Hegel-Aesthetics Sep

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Hegel-Aesthetics Sep pdf version of the entry Hegel’s Aesthetics http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/sum2010/entries/hegel-aesthetics/ Hegel's Aesthetics from the Summer 2010 Edition of the First published Tue Jan 20, 2009; substantive revision Tue Dec 15, 2009 Stanford Encyclopedia G.W.F. Hegel's aesthetics, or philosophy of art, forms part of the extraordinarily rich German aesthetic tradition that stretches from J.J. of Philosophy Winckelmann's Thoughts on the Imitation of the Painting and Sculpture of the Greeks (1755) and G.E. Lessing's Laocoon (1766) through Immanuel Kant's Critique of the Power of Judgment (1790) and Friedrich Schiller's Letters on the Aesthetic Education of Man (1795) to Friedrich Nietzsche's Birth of Tragedy (1872) and (in the twentieth century) Martin Edward N. Zalta Uri Nodelman Colin Allen John Perry Heidegger's The Origin of the Work of Art (1935–6) and T.W. Adorno's Principal Editor Senior Editor Associate Editor Faculty Sponsor Aesthetic Theory (1970). Hegel was influenced in particular by Editorial Board Winckelmann, Kant and Schiller, and his own thesis of the “end of art” http://plato.stanford.edu/board.html (or what has been taken to be that thesis) has itself been the focus of close Library of Congress Catalog Data attention by Heidegger and Adorno. Hegel's philosophy of art is a wide ISSN: 1095-5054 ranging account of beauty in art, the historical development of art, and Notice: This PDF version was distributed by request to mem- the individual arts of architecture, sculpture, painting, music and poetry. It bers of the Friends of the SEP Society and by courtesy to SEP contains distinctive and influential analyses of Egyptian art, Greek content contributors. It is solely for their fair use. Unauthorized sculpture, and ancient and modern tragedy, and is regarded by many as distribution is prohibited. To learn how to join the Friends of the one of the greatest aesthetic theories to have been produced since SEP Society and obtain authorized PDF versions of SEP entries, Aristotle's Poetics. please visit https://leibniz.stanford.edu/friends/ . 1. Hegel's Knowledge of Art Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy 2. Hegel's Texts and Lectures on Aesthetics Copyright c 2010 by the publisher The Metaphysics Research Lab 3. Art, Religion and Philosophy in Hegel's System Center for the Study of Language and Information 4. Kant, Schiller and Hegel on Beauty and Freedom Stanford University, Stanford, CA 94305 5. Art and Idealization Hegel’s Aesthetics Copyright c 2010 by the author 6. Hegel's Systematic Aesthetics or Philosophy of Art Stephen Houlgate 6.1 Ideal Beauty as such All rights reserved. 6.2 The Particular Forms of Art Copyright policy: https://leibniz.stanford.edu/friends/info/copyright/ 6.3 The System of the Individual Arts 1 Hegel’s Aesthetics Stephen Houlgate 7. Conclusion individual works of art—to such an extent, indeed, that his aesthetics Bibliography constitutes, in Kai Hammermeister's words, “a veritable world history of Hegel's Collected Works art” (Hammermeister, 24). English Translations of Key Texts by Hegel Transcripts of Hegel's Lectures on Aesthetics Hegel read both Greek and Latin (indeed, he wrote his diary partly in Secondary Literature in English Latin from the age of fourteen); he also read English and French. He was Secondary Literature in German thus able to study the works of Homer, Aeschylus, Sophocles, Euripides, Other Relevant Works Virgil, Shakespeare and Molière in the original languages. He never Other Internet Resources travelled to Greece or Italy, but he did undertake several long journeys Related Entries from Berlin (where he was appointed Professor in 1818) to Dresden (1820, 1821, 1824), the Low Countries (1822, 1827), Vienna (1824) and Paris (1827). On these journeys he saw Raphael's Sistine Madonna and 1. Hegel's Knowledge of Art several paintings by Correggio (in Dresden), Rembrandt's Night Watch (in Amsterdam), the central section of the van Eyck brothers' Adoration Hegel's Phenomenology of Spirit (1807) contains chapters on the ancient of the Lamb (in Ghent)—the wing panels were at that time in Berlin—and Greek “religion of art” (Kunstreligion) and on the world-view presented “famous items by the noblest masters one has seen a hundred times in in Sophocles' Antigone and Oedipus the King. His philosophy of art copper engravings: Raphael, Correggio, Leonardo da Vinci, Titian” (in proper, however, forms part of his philosophy (rather than Paris) (Hegel: The Letters, 654). He liked to visit the theatre and opera, phenomenology) of spirit. The Phenomenology can be regarded as the both on his travels and in Berlin, and he was acquainted with leading introduction to Hegel's philosophical system. The system itself comprises singers, such as Anna Milder-Hauptmann (who sang in the first three parts: logic, philosophy of nature, and philosophy of spirit, and is set production of Beethoven's Fidelio in 1814), as well as the composer Felix out (in numbered paragraphs) in Hegel's Encyclopaedia of the Mendelssohn-Bartholdy (whose revival of J.S. Bach's St Matthew Passion philosophical Sciences (1817, 1827, 1830). The philosophy of spirit is in Hegel attended in March 1829). Hegel was also on close personal terms turn divided into three sections: on subjective, objective and absolute with Goethe and knew his drama and poetry especially well (as he did spirit. Hegel's philosophy of art or “aesthetics” constitutes the first sub- those of Friedrich Schiller). section of his philosophy of absolute spirit, and is followed by his philosophy of religion and his account of the history of philosophy. Adorno complains that “Hegel and Kant [ … ] were able to write major aesthetics without understanding anything about art” (Adorno, 334). This Hegel's philosophy of art provides an a priori derivation—from the very may or may not be true of Kant, but it is clearly quite untrue of Hegel: he concept of beauty itself—of various forms of beauty and various had an extensive knowledge and a good understanding of many of the individual arts. In marked contrast to Kant, however, Hegel weaves into great works of art in the Western tradition. Nor was Hegel's knowledge his philosophical study of beauty numerous references to and analyses of and interest restricted to Western art: he read (in translation) works of individual works of art—to such an extent, indeed, that his aesthetics Indian and Persian poetry, and he saw at first hand works of Egyptian art 2 Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Summer 2010 Edition 3 Hegel’s Aesthetics Stephen Houlgate Indian and Persian poetry, and he saw at first hand works of Egyptian art extent (if at all) Hotho did in fact distort Hegel's account of art. It should in Berlin (Pöggeler 1981, 206–8). Hegel's philosophy of art is thus an a also be noted that Gethmann-Siefert's own interpretation of Hegel's priori derivation of the various forms of beauty that, pace Adorno, is aesthetics has been called into question (see Houlgate 1986a). informed and mediated by a thorough knowledge and understanding of Nevertheless Gethmann-Siefert is right to encourage readers with a individual works of art from around the world. knowledge of German to consult the published transcripts, since they contain a wealth of important material, and in some cases material that is 2. Hegel's Texts and Lectures on Aesthetics missing from the Hotho edition (such as the brief reference to Caspar David Friedrich in the 1820/21 lectures [VÄ, 192]). Hegel's published thoughts on aesthetics are to be found in pars. 556–63 of the 1830 Encyclopaedia. Hegel also held lectures on aesthetics in Hegel's philosophy of art has provoked considerable debate since his Heidelberg in 1818 and in Berlin in 1820/21 (winter semester), 1823 and death in 1831. Does he believe that only Greek art is beautiful? Does he 1826 (summer semesters), and 1828/29 (winter semester). Transcripts of hold that art comes to an end in the modern age? The answers one gives Hegel's lectures made by his students in 1820/21, 1823 and 1826 have to such questions should, however, be offered with a degree of caution, now been published (though no English translations of these transcripts for, sadly, there is no fully worked out philosophy of art by Hegel that are yet available) (see Bibliography). In 1835 (and then again in 1842) was officially endorsed by Hegel himself. The paragraphs in the one of Hegel's students, Heinrich Gustav Hotho, published an edition of Encyclopaedia are written by Hegel, but they are very brief and Hegel's lectures on aesthetics based on a manuscript of Hegel's (now lost) condensed and were intended to be supplemented by Hegel's lectures; the and a series of lecture transcripts. This is available in English as: G.W.F. transcripts of the lectures are written by students of Hegel (some taken Hegel, Aesthetics. Lectures on Fine Art, trans. T.M. Knox, 2 vols. down in class, some compiled afterwards from notes taken in class); and (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1975). Most of the secondary literature on the “standard” edition of Hegel's lectures is actually a work put together Hegel's aesthetics (in English and German) makes reference to Hotho's by Hegel's student, Hotho (albeit using a manuscript by Hegel himself). edition. Yet according to one of the leading specialists on Hegel's There is, therefore, no definitive edition of Hegel's fully developed aesthetics, Annemarie Gethmann-Siefert, Hotho distorted Hegel's thought aesthetic theory that would trump all others and settle all debate. in various ways: he gave Hegel's account of art a much stricter systematic structure than Hegel himself had given it, and he supplemented Hegel's 3.
Recommended publications
  • Hegel and Marx on Alienation a Thesis Submitted to the Graduate School of Social Sciences of Middle East Technical University By
    HEGEL AND MARX ON ALIENATION A THESIS SUBMITTED TO THE GRADUATE SCHOOL OF SOCIAL SCIENCES OF MIDDLE EAST TECHNICAL UNIVERSITY BY SEVGİ DOĞAN IN PARTIAL FULFILLMENT OF THE REQUIREMENTS FOR THE DEGREE OF MASTER OF ARTS IN THE DEPARTMENT OF PHILOSOPHY FEBRUARY 2008 Approval of the Graduate School of (Name of the Graduate School) Prof. Dr. Sencer Ayata Director I certify that this thesis satisfies all the requirements as a thesis for the degree of Master of Arts. Prof. Dr. Ahmet İnam Head of Department This is to certify that we have read this thesis and that in our opinion it is fully adequate, in scope and quality, as a thesis for the degree of Master of Arts of Philosophy. Assist. Prof. Dr. Barış Parkan Supervisor Examining Committee Members Assist. Prof. Dr. Barış Parkan (METU, PHIL) Assist. Prof. Dr. Elif Çırakman (METU, PHIL) Assist. Prof. Dr. Çetin Türkyılmaz (Hacettepe U., PHIL) I hereby declare that all information in this document has been obtained and presented in accordance with academic rules and ethical conduct. I also declare that, as required by these rules and conduct, I have fully cited and referenced all material and results that are not original to this work. Name, Last name: Sevgi Doğan Signature : iii ABSTRACT HEGEL AND MARX ON ALIENATION Doğan, Sevgi M.A., Department of Philosophy Supervisor: Assist. Prof. Barış Parkan February 2008, 139 pages Is alienation a process of self-discovery or is it a loss of reality? The subject of this thesis is how alienation is discussed in Hegel and Marx’s philosophies in terms of this question.
    [Show full text]
  • Cultural Naturalism and the Market God David Timothy Denenny Southern Illinois University Carbondale, [email protected]
    Southern Illinois University Carbondale OpenSIUC Theses Theses and Dissertations 12-1-2018 Cultural Naturalism and the Market God David Timothy Denenny Southern Illinois University Carbondale, [email protected] Follow this and additional works at: https://opensiuc.lib.siu.edu/theses Recommended Citation Denenny, David Timothy, "Cultural Naturalism and the Market God" (2018). Theses. 2464. https://opensiuc.lib.siu.edu/theses/2464 This Open Access Thesis is brought to you for free and open access by the Theses and Dissertations at OpenSIUC. It has been accepted for inclusion in Theses by an authorized administrator of OpenSIUC. For more information, please contact [email protected]. CULTURAL NATURALISM AND THE MARKET GOD by David Denenny B.A. Eastern Washington University, 2015 A Thesis Submitted in Partial Fulfillment of the Requirements for the Master of Arts Degree Department of Philosophy in the Graduate School Southern Illinois University Carbondale December 2018 Copyright by David Denenny, 2018 All Rights Reserved THESIS APPROVAL CULTURAL NATURALISM AND THE MARKET GOD by David Denenny A Thesis Submitted in Partial Fulfillment of the Requirements for the degree of Master of Arts in the field of Philosophy Approved by: Kenneth William Stikkers, Chair Randall Auxier Alfred Frankowski Graduate School Southern Illinois University Carbondale November 8, 2018 AN ABSTRACT OF THE THESIS OF David Denenny, for the Master of Arts degree in Philosophy, presented on November 8, 2018, at Southern Illinois University Carbondale. TITLE: CULTURAL NATURALISM AND THE MARKET GOD MAJOR PROFESSOR: Dr. Kenneth William Stikkers This work employs John Dewey's cultural naturalism to explore how and why the orthodox economic tradition functions as a religious faith.
    [Show full text]
  • Machine Automation and the Critique of Abstract Labor in Hegel's Mature
    Georgia State University ScholarWorks @ Georgia State University Philosophy Theses Department of Philosophy 12-12-2018 Machine Automation and the Critique of Abstract Labor in Hegel’s Mature Social Theory Matthew J. Delhey Follow this and additional works at: https://scholarworks.gsu.edu/philosophy_theses Recommended Citation Delhey, Matthew J., "Machine Automation and the Critique of Abstract Labor in Hegel’s Mature Social Theory." Thesis, Georgia State University, 2018. https://scholarworks.gsu.edu/philosophy_theses/248 This Thesis is brought to you for free and open access by the Department of Philosophy at ScholarWorks @ Georgia State University. It has been accepted for inclusion in Philosophy Theses by an authorized administrator of ScholarWorks @ Georgia State University. For more information, please contact [email protected]. MACHINE AUTOMATION AND THE CRITIQUE OF ABSTRACT LABOR IN HEGEL’S MATURE SOCIAL THEORY by MATTHEW J. DELHEY Under the Direction of Sebastian Rand, PhD ABSTRACT This thesis examines Hegel’s critique of abstract labor in the Philosophy of Right and the sections on objective spirit in the Encyclopaedia. Against both Frederick Neuhouser’s and Marxist interpretations, I argue that abstract labor, for Hegel, characterizes the specific kind of mechanical labor undertaken in the nineteenth-century factory. Such repetitive labor, Hegel claims, leads to the deadening (Abstumpfung) of the worker through the deforming of her ethical subjectivity, a social pathology he hopes will be resolved by machine automation. By developing two key aspects of Hegel’s social theory—that labor produces ethical subjectivity or education (Bildung) and that this education is the central locus of civil society’s ethicality—I argue that we ought to understand Hegel’s hope for machine automation as a critique of those forms of labor which prevent the worker’s rational participation in the totality of the labor process and thus fail to actualize her social freedom.
    [Show full text]
  • Hegel 250—Too Late?
    HEGEL 250—TOO LATE? Ljubljana 2020 HEGEL 250—TOO LATE? ANALECTA Publisher: Društvo za teoretsko psihoanalizo Publishing board: Miran Božovič, Mladen Dolar, Rado Riha, Alenka Zupančič (president), Slavoj Žižek Edited by Mladen Dolar Copyedited by Tanja Dominko and Eric Powell Cover Design by AOOA Layout by Klemen Ulčakar Printed by Ulčakar Grafika First Edition Circulation 200 Ljubljana 2020 This publication has been co-published in partnership with the Goethe-Institut Ljubljana. CIP - Kataložni zapis o publikaciji Narodna in univerzitetna knjižnica, Ljubljana 1Hegel G.W.F.(082) HEGEL 250 - too late? / [edited by Mladen Dolar]. - 1st ed. - Ljubljana : Društvo za teoretsko psihoanalizo : Goethe-Institut, 2020. - (Zbirka Analecta) (Problemi ; let. 58, 11-12) (Problemi International ; 2020, 4) ISBN 978-961-6376-94-5 (Društvo za teoretsko psihoanalizo) COBISS.SI-ID 61238531 Table of Contents Hegel Reborn: A Brief Introduction to HEGEL 250—TOO LATE? Árpád-Andreas Sölter. 5 Hegel’s Time! Ana Jovanović, Bara Kolenc, Urban Šrimpf, Goran Vranešević. 9 Nadia Bou Ali and Ray Brassier After Too Late: The Endgame of Analysis. 11 Mladen Dolar What’s the Time? On Being Too Early or Too Late in Hegel’s Philosophy. 31 Luca Illetteratti Nature’s Externality: Hegel’s Non-Naturalistic Naturalism. .51 Zdravko Kobe The Time of Philosophy: On Hegel’s Conception of Modern Philosophy . 73 Bara Kolenc Is It Too Late?. 91 Christian Krijnen “What, if Anything, Has Not Been Called Philosophizing?” On the Relevance of Hegel’s Conception of a Philosophical History of Philosophy. 119 Gregor Moder What Is To Be Done: On the Theatricality of Power. 143 Nadia Bou Ali and Ray Brassier Sebastian Rödl Thinking Nothing .
    [Show full text]
  • Kierkegaard, Literature, and the Arts
    Kierke gaard, Literature, and the Arts Engraving, ca. 1837, by Carl Strahlheim showing the Gendarmenmarkt in Berlin, with what was then the Schauspielhaus, or Theater (center)— now the concert house of the Konzerthausorchester Berlin— flanked by the German Cathedral (left) and the French Cathedral (right). Pictured in the background to the immediate right of the theater is the building, still standing today, in which Kierkegaard lodged during his four stays in Berlin, in 1841– 42, 1843, 1845, and 1846. It was there, as noted by a plaque outside, that Kierkegaard wrote the first drafts of Either/Or, Repetition, and Fear and Trembling. Kierkegaard, Literature, and the Arts Edited by Eric Ziolkowski northwestern university press evanston, illinois Northwestern University Press www.nupress.northwestern.edu Copyright © 2018 by Northwestern University Press. Published 2018. All rights reserved. Printed in the United States of America 10 9 8 7 6 5 4 3 2 1 Library of Congress Cataloging- in- Publication Data Names: Ziolkowski, Eric Jozef, 1958– editor. Title: Kierkegaard, literature, and the arts / edited by Eric Ziolkowski. Description: Evanston, Illinois : Northwestern University Press, 2018. | Includes index. Identifiers: LCCN 2017029795 | ISBN 9780810135970 (cloth : alk. paper) | ISBN 9780810135963 (pbk. : alk. paper) | ISBN 9780810135987 (e-book) Subjects: LCSH: Kierkegaard, Søren, 1813–1855. | Kierkegaard, Søren, 1813– 1855—Aesthetics. | Literature—Philosophy. | Music and philosophy. | Art and philosophy. | Performing arts—Philosophy. Classification: LCC B4377 .K4558 2018 | DDC 198.9—dc23 LC record available at https://lccn.loc.gov/2017029795 Except where otherwise noted, this book is licensed under a Creative Commons Attribution-NonCommercial-NoDerivatives 4.0 International License. To view a copy of this license, visit http://creativecommons.org/licenses/by-nc-nd/4.0/.
    [Show full text]
  • PHILOSOPHY and RELIGION in GERMAN IDEALISM Studies in German Idealism
    PHILOSOPHY AND RELIGION IN GERMAN IDEALISM Studies in German Idealism Series Editor: Reinier Munk, Leiden University and Vrije Universiteit Amsterdam, The Netherlands Advisory Editorial Board: Frederick Beiser, Syracuse University, U.S.A. George di Giovanni, McGill University, Montreal, Canada Helmut Holzhey, University of Zürich, Switzerland Detlev Pätzold, University of Groningen, The Netherlands Robert Solomon, University of Texas at Austin, Texas, U.S.A. VOLUME 3 PHILOSOPHY AND RELIGION IN GERMAN IDEALISM Edited by WILLIAM DESMOND Catholic University of Louvain ERNST-OTTO ONNASCH Vrije Universiteit Amsterdam and PAUL CRUYSBERGHS Catholic University of Louvain KLUWER ACADEMIC PUBLISHERS NEW YORK, BOSTON, DORDRECHT, LONDON, MOSCOW eBook ISBN: 1-4020-2325-1 Print ISBN: 1-4020-2324-3 ©2005 Springer Science + Business Media, Inc. Print ©2004 Kluwer Academic Publishers Dordrecht All rights reserved No part of this eBook may be reproduced or transmitted in any form or by any means, electronic, mechanical, recording, or otherwise, without written consent from the Publisher Created in the United States of America Visit Springer's eBookstore at: http://ebooks.springerlink.com and the Springer Global Website Online at: http://www.springeronline.com This book is dedicated to Ludwig Heyde (†) CONTENTS Preface ix WILLIAM DESMOND, ERNST-OTTO ONNASCH and PAUL CRUYSBERGHS Introduction xi WALTER JAESCHKE Philosophy of Religion after the Death of God 1 MARTIN MOORS Kant on Religion in the Role of Moral Schematism 21 DANIEL BREAZEALE “Wishful Thinking.” Concerning Fichte’s Interpretation of the Postulates of Reason in his Versuch einer Kritik aller Offenbarung (1792) 35 LUDWIG HEYDE (†) The Unsatisfied Enlightenment. Faith and Pure Insight in Hegel’s Phenomenology of Spirit 71 STEPHEN HOULGATE Religion, Morality and Forgiveness in Hegel’s Philosophy 81 SANDER GRIFFIOEN The Finite does not Hinder.
    [Show full text]
  • 1 the Authority of Conceptual Analysis in Hegelian
    1 The Authority of Conceptual Analysis in Hegelian Ethical Life [Forthcoming in An Ethical Modernity? Hegel’s Concept of Ethical Life Today – Its Limits and Potential. Eds. Tereza Matějčková and Jiři Chotaš (Brill). Please cite published version] W. Clark Wolf 1. Introduction1 There is among many philosophers a recurring attraction to the idea of philosophy as conceptual analysis: namely, that philosophy has as its aim the clear explication of the central terms governing ordinary and scientific thought. This idea can be traced back even to Plato’s Socrates, who at least initially used dialogues to draw out clearer definitions from his interlocuters of key terms such as virtue, knowledge, and justice. For Plato, at least at one stage, such explication can result in genuine and deep knowledge, even if this is only a more explicit and recollected form of a knowledge that was once merely implicit; he used the concept of forms (eidé) to say what the object of such knowledge is. For later thinkers, especially linguistically minded philosophers of the twentieth century, the attraction of the ‘conceptual conception’ of philosophy was not to credit philosophy with a distinct form of knowledge as much as to distinguish its activity from empirical science. Philosophy was to be regarded not as a first-order inquiry into a special set of rational objects, but a second-order determination of meanings in support of the claims of first- 1 The present version of this paper benefitted from comments and discussion with fellow participants at the conference in Prague. I would especially like to thank Paul Cobben, David James, and Christian Krijnen for valuable discussion.
    [Show full text]
  • And Art's Modernity
    Proceedings of the European Society for Aesthetics Volume 11, 2019 Edited by Connell Vaughan and Iris Vidmar Jovanović Published by the European Society for Aesthetics esa Proceedings of the European Society for Aesthetics Founded in 2009 by Fabian Dorsch Internet: http://proceedings.eurosa.org Email: [email protected] ISSN: 1664 – 5278 Editors Connell Vaughan (Technological University Dublin) Iris Vidmar Jovanović (University of Rijeka) Editorial Board Adam Andrzejewski (University of Warsaw) Pauline von Bonsdorff (University of Jyväskylä) Daniel Martine Feige (Stuttgart State Academy of Fine Arts) Tereza Hadravová (Charles University, Prague) Vitor Moura (University of Minho, Guimarães) Regina-Nino Mion (Estonian Academy of Arts, Tallinn) Francisca Pérez Carreño (University of Murcia) Karen Simecek (University of Warwick) Elena Tavani (University of Naples) Publisher The European Society for Aesthetics Department of Philosophy University of Fribourg Avenue de l’Europe 20 1700 Fribourg Switzerland Internet: http://www.eurosa.org Email: [email protected] Proceedings of the European Society for Aesthetics Volume 11, 2019 Edited by Connell Vaughan and Iris Vidmar Jovanović Table of Contents Lydia Goehr [Keynote Paper] Painting in Waiting Prelude to a Critical Philosophy of History and Art ................................................................ 1 Lucas Amoriello (Non)Identity: Adorno and the Constitution of Art ...... 31 Claire Anscomb Photography, Digital Technology, and Hybrid Art Forms ...................................................................................................
    [Show full text]
  • Hegel's Modal Ontological Argument
    THE CATHOLIC UNIVERSITY OF AMERICA Hegel’s Modal Ontological Argument A DISSERTATION Submitted to the Faculty of the School of Philosophy Of The Catholic University of America In Partial Fulfillment of the Requirements For the Degree Doctor of Philosophy © Copyright All Rights Reserved By David Pensgard Washington, D.C. 2019 Hegel’s Modal Ontological Argument David Pensgard, PhD Director: Antón Barba-Kay, PhD A recent trend in Hegel scholarship has recognized an irreducibly metaphysical component. Unlike traditional metaphysical views, this trend, sometimes referred to as the revised metaphysical view, accepts significant Kantian influence on Hegel, but also sees a rebuttal and counter-critique. Such a Hegel avoids the excesses of traditional metaphysics, including ontotheological speculation, but does not avoid metaphysics altogether. To extend this effort to understand Hegel’s metaphysics, without suggesting an argument for the existence of God, I here point to Hegel’s ontological argument as the one, indispensable interpretational key that he himself has provided for this purpose. Unfortunately, this argument is not only hard to detect because of the way Hegel presents it, but it is also difficult to accept because it takes a very unexpected form; it is a deduction in the ordinary sense. Perhaps without exception, scholars today think that Hegel could not possibly be using a deduction because deductive logic is considered to be antithetical to his project. It is true that Hegel criticized logic’s traditional practice for being dogmatic, and he did detect oppositional themes within the method of deduction itself, but Hegel neither condemned nor abandoned deduction. Instead, he worked to redeem it by purging its practice of two errors: presupposition and finitude.
    [Show full text]
  • Hegel on the Modern Arts Pdf, Epub, Ebook
    HEGEL ON THE MODERN ARTS PDF, EPUB, EBOOK Benjamin Rutter | 298 pages | 12 Feb 2015 | CAMBRIDGE UNIVERSITY PRESS | 9781107499669 | English | Cambridge, United Kingdom Hegel on the Modern Arts PDF Book But the precise text of the lectures that Hegel read out is lost. Kant had thought that the aesthetic impulse enables us to sense a kind of harmony implicit in the world between the purposes of morality and those of reason. Of the third part, which is larger than both the others combined, being the treatment of all the Arts in detail, I have given all the important definitions and fundamental ideas, omitting, as was needful, the minute illustrations of the same, and the properly technical part, which, too, can be found elsewhere"--Preface. The question of freedom sits at the forefront of this text, alongside the relation between art and the spirit. Password Please enter your Password. For Greenberg, inspired by Hegel, art was progressing, moving towards, striving towards a perfection in which it had to shed all elements that were impure, such as dimension and representation, until it art evolved into pure abstraction. Author : George R. As a synthesis, Romantic art must be independent and begins to exist on its own. Hegel's Aesthetics further situates his arguments in the intense philosophizing about art among his contemporaries, including Kant, Lessing, Herder, Schelling, and the Schlegel brothers. Hegel does not get involved in any particular movement or style or work of art, but, that said, he was very definite about the kind of art where Beauty could be found.
    [Show full text]
  • Property, Useand Value in Hegel's Philosophy of Right
    CHAPTER 2 Property, Use and Value in Hegel's Philosophy of Right Stephen Houlgate Hegel is aware that it is only in the modern world, with the emergence of civil society, that 'the freedom of property has been recognized here and there as a principle' (PR § 62R).' Nonetheless, he contends, property is made necessary by the very idea of freedom itself The purpose of this essay is to explain why this is the case by tracing the logic that leads in Hegel's Philosophy of Right from freedom, through right, to property and its use. I conclude by briefly comparing Hegel and Marx on the topic of 'value'. FreeWill and Right The first task is to explain why freedom, or the free will, must give itself the form of right (Recht). What Hegel calls 'intelligence' is the knowing of what is (PM § 465). Will, in contrast, seeks to realize, and realizes, its subjective aims in the external world. It is, therefore, the activity of giving objective 'existence' (Existenz) to the content of its aims (PR § 8; PM § 469).2 Insofar as will actively objectifies itself in this way, it is 'self-determining' and free. Initially, however, its aims are determined by nature, rather than by itself: they are its immediately given needs, drives and inclinations. Accordingly, Hegel maintains, will is at first not fully free, but free only implicitly or 'in itself' (an sich) (PR §§ IO-II; PM §§ 471-475). Will is, however, explicitly free, or free 'for itself', insofar as it dis- tinguishes itself in thought from its given drives and inclinations and understands itself to be the power to choose which aims it will realize: the , See also PR § 18zA, and VRP 3: 565, 641.
    [Show full text]
  • KOYRÉ, KOJÈVE, and MALABOU SPECULATE on HEGELIAN TIME Rory Jeffs
    PARRHESIA NUMBER 15 • 2012 • 35-53 THE FUTURE OF THE FUTURE: KOYRÉ, KOJÈVE, AND MALABOU SPECULATE ON HEGELIAN TIME Rory Jeffs … will there and can there be a future after the supposed end of history…. beyond ‘absolute knowledge’? — Jacques Derrida1 The relationship between Hegel’s speculative idealist philosophy and time has a long and complicated history. Since his death in 1831, Hegel’s name has inspired a range of interpretations and speculations about what his philosophy entails. In 1946, the Russian-born French Hegelian Alexandre Kojève speculated: [I]t may be that, in fact the future of the world, and therefore the meaning of the present and the significance of the past, depend, in the final analysis, on the way in which the Hegelian writings are interpreted today.2 Half a century later as we entered the twenty-first century, Catherine Malabou speculated that the future of Hegel depended on how we read the future in Hegel’s philosophy.3 And more recently, Slavoj Žižek in his own typically speculative manner, claimed that even after decades of anti-Hegelian sentiment and a wilful forgetting of Hegel, “Hegel’s century will be the twenty-first.”4 On the surface, such statements seem to place undue importance on Hegel and may confirm the conventional suspicion of him as an all-encompassing philosopher. However, there is also the implication that the future itself, or to loosely paraphrase Malabou, “the future of the future” is what is at stake. Hegel’s value then would be to act as a guide to working out and potentially saving the time of the future itself from insignificance, repetition, or a “levelling down”.5 Žižek may have also intimated something, that Hegel’s time, or future, is yet-to-come—which raises the question of what could have delayed Hegel’s true arrival? I will examine in this article one possible response to such a question that THE FUTURE OF THE FUTURE concerns how the riddle of Hegelian temporality plagued the twentieth-century French reading of Hegel.
    [Show full text]