Revision by Conditionals: from Hook to Arrow

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Revision by Conditionals: from Hook to Arrow Proceedings of the 17th International Conference on Principles of Knowledge Representation and Reasoning (KR 2020) Main Track Revision by Conditionals: From Hook to Arrow Jake Chandler1 , Richard Booth2 1La Trobe University 2Cardiff University [email protected], [email protected] Abstract conditional belief. In Section 3, we outline and discuss our proposal regarding (B). Subsection 3.1 presents the basic The belief revision literature has largely focussed on the issue idea, according to which computing the result of a revi- of how to revise one’s beliefs in the light of information re- garding matters of fact. Here we turn to an important but com- sion by a Ramsey Test conditional can be derived by min- paratively neglected issue: How might one extend a revision imal modification, under constraints, of the outcome of a operator to handle conditionals as input? Our approach to this revision by its corresponding material conditional. Our key question of ‘conditional revision’ is distinctive insofar as it technical contribution is presented in Subsection 3.2, where abstracts from the controversial details of how to revise by we prove that this minimal change under constraints can be factual sentences. We introduce a ‘plug and play’ method for achieved by means of a simple and familiar transformation. uniquely extending any iterated belief revision operator to the Subsection 3.3 outlines some interesting general properties conditional case. The flexibility of our approach is achieved of the proposal. These strengthen, in a plausible manner, by having the result of a conditional revision by a Ramsey the aforementioned constraints presented in (Kern-Isberner Test conditional (‘arrow’) determined by that of a plain re- 1999) and are of independent interest. Subsection 3.4 con- vision by its corresponding material conditional (‘hook’). It is shown to satisfy a number of new constraints that are of siders the upshot of pairing our proposal regarding (B) with independent interest. some well-known suggestions regarding how to tackle (A). Finally, in Section 4, we compare the suggestion made with existing work on the topic noting some important shortcom- 1 Introduction ings of the latter. We close the paper in Section 5 with a The past three decades have witnessed the development of number of questions for future research. a substantial, if inconclusive, body of work devoted to the Due to space limitations, only a couple of the more im- issue of belief revision, namely portant proofs have been provided, in Section 6. A version (A) determining the impact of a local change in belief on of the paper containing all proofs can be accessed online at both (i) the remainder of one’s prior beliefs and (ii) http://arxiv.org/abs/2006.15811. one’s prior conditional beliefs (‘Ramsey Test condi- tionals’). 2 Revision Surprisingly, however, very little has been done to this date The beliefs of an agent are represented by a belief state. Such on the question of conditional belief revision, that is states will be denoted by upper case Greek letters Ψ; Θ;:::. We denote by S the set of all such states. Each state de- (B) determining the impact of a local change in condi- termines a belief set, a consistent and deductively closed tional beliefs on both (i) and (ii). set of sentences, drawn from a finitely generated proposi- Furthermore, nearly all of the few proposals to tackle is- tional, truth-functional language L, equipped with the stan- sue (B), namely (Hansson 1992), (Boutilier and Goldszmidt dard connectives ⊃, ^, _, and :. We denote the belief set 1993), and (Nayak et al. 1996), have typically rested on associated with state Ψ by [Ψ]. Logical equivalence is de- somewhat contentious assumptions about how to approach noted by ≡ and the set of classical logical consequences of (A). (A noteworthy exception to this (Kern-Isberner 1999), Γ ⊆ L by Cn(Γ), with > denoting an arbitrary propositional who introduced a number of plausible general postulates tautology. The set of propositional worlds will be denoted by governing revision by conditionals whose impact on revision W and the set of models of a given sentence A by [[A]]. simpliciter remains fairly modest. More on these below.) The operation of revision ∗ returns the posterior state Ψ ∗ In this paper, we consider the prospects of providing a A that results from an adjustment of Ψ to accommodate the ‘plug and play’ solution to issue (B) that is independent of inclusion of the consistent input A in its associated belief the details of how to address (A). Its remainder is organ- set, in such a way as to maintain consistency of the resulting ised as follows. First, in Section 2, we present some standard belief set. background on problem (A), introducing along the way the The beliefs resulting from single revisions are conve- well-known notion of a Ramsey Test conditional or again niently representable by a conditional belief set [Ψ]c, which 233 Proceedings of the 17th International Conference on Principles of Knowledge Representation and Reasoning (KR 2020) Main Track ∗ 4 4 can be viewed as encoding the agent’s rules of inference over (C14) If x; y 2 [[A]] then x Ψ∗A y iff x Ψ y L in state Ψ. It is defined via the Ramsey Test: ∗ 4 4 (C24) If x; y 2 [[:A]] then x Ψ∗A y iff x Ψ y (RT) For all A; B 2 L, A) B 2 [Ψ]c iff B 2 [Ψ ∗ A] ∗ (C34) If x 2 [[A]], y 2 [[:A]] and x ≺Ψ y, then We shall call Lc the minimal extension of L that additionally x ≺Ψ∗A y ∗ 4 includes all sentences of the form A) B, with A; B 2 L. (C44) If x 2 [[A]], y 2 [[:A]] and x Ψ y, then We shall call sentences of the form A ) B ‘conditionals’ x 4Ψ∗A y and sentences of the form A ⊃ B ‘material conditionals’. We shall say that a sentence of the form A) B is consistent Importantly, while there appears to be a degree of consen- just in case A ^ B is consistent (later in the paper, we shall sus that these postulates should be strengthened, there is no explicitly disallow revisions by inconsistent conditionals). agreement as to how this should be done. Popular options Conditional belief sets are constrained by the AGM pos- include the principles respectively associated with the oper- tulates of (Alchourron,´ Gardenfors,¨ and Makinson 1985; ators of natural revision ∗N (Boutilier 1996), restrained revi- Darwiche and Pearl 1997) (henceforth ‘AGM’). Given these, sion ∗R (Booth and Meyer 2006) and lexicographic revision ∗ (Nayak, Pagnucco, and Peppas 2003), semantically de- [Ψ]c corresponds to a consistency-preserving rational con- L sequence relation, in the sense of (Lehmann and Magi- fined as follows: dor 1992). Equivalently, it is representable by a total pre- Definition 1. The operators ∗N, ∗R and ∗L are such that: order (TPO) 4Ψ of worlds, such that A ) B 2 [Ψ]c iff x 4Ψ∗ A y iff (1) x 2 min(4Ψ; [[A]]), or (2) x; y2 = min(4Ψ; A ) ⊆ B (Grove 1988; Katsuno and Mendel- N min(4Ψ; [[A]]) and x 4Ψ y zon 1991).J NoteK thatJ AK 2 [Ψ] iff >) A 2 [Ψ]c or equiva- 4 4 4 lently iff min( Ψ;W ) ⊆ [[A]]. x Ψ∗RA y iff (1) x 2 min( Ψ; [[A]]), or (2) x; y2 = Following convention, we shall call principles presented min(4Ψ; [[A]]) and either (a) x ≺Ψ y or (b) x ∼Ψ y in terms of belief sets ‘syntactic’, and call ‘semantic’ those and (x 2 [[A]] or y 2 [[:A]]) principles couched in terms of TPOs, denoting the latter by x 4 y iff (1) x 2 [[A]] and y 2 [[:A]], or (2) 4 Ψ∗LA subscripting the corresponding syntactic principle with ‘ ’. (x 2 [[A]] iff y 2 [[A]]) and x 4Ψ y. Due to space considerations and for ease of exposition, we will largely restrict our focus to a semantic perspective on The suitability of all three operators, which we will group our problem of interest. here under the heading of ‘elementary revision operators’ The AGM postulates do not entail that one’s conditional (Chandler and Booth 2019), has been called into question. beliefs are determined by one’s beliefs—in the sense that, Indeed, they assume that a state Ψ can be identified with its corresponding TPO 4Ψ and that belief revision functions if [Ψ] = [Θ], then [Ψ]c = [Θ]c—and there is widespread consensus that such determination would be unduly restric- map pairs of TPOs and sentences onto TPOs. (For this rea- tive, with (Hansson 1992) providing supporting arguments. son, we will sometimes abuse language and notation and A fortiori, one should not identify conditional beliefs with speak, for instance, of the lexicographic revision of a TPO beliefs in the corresponding material conditional. That said, rather than of a state.) But this assumption has been criti- cised as implausible, with (Booth and Chandler 2017) pro- there does remain a connection between A) B 2 [Ψ]c and A ⊃ B 2 [Ψ]. The following is well known: viding a number of counterexamples. Accordingly, (Booth and Chandler 2018; Booth and Proposition 1. Given AGM, (a) if A ) B 2 [Ψ] , then c Chandler 2020) propose a strengthening of the DP postulates A ⊃ B 2 [Ψ], but (b) the converse does not hold. that is weak enough to avoid an identification of states with Indeed, (a) is simply equivalent, given (RT), to the AGM TPOs and is consistent with the characteristic postulates of postulate of Inclusion, according to which [Ψ ∗ A] ⊆ both ∗R and ∗L (albeit not of ∗N).
Recommended publications
  • Gibbardian Collapse and Trivalent Conditionals
    Gibbardian Collapse and Trivalent Conditionals Paul Égré* Lorenzo Rossi† Jan Sprenger‡ Abstract This paper discusses the scope and significance of the so-called triviality result stated by Allan Gibbard for indicative conditionals, showing that if a conditional operator satisfies the Law of Import-Export, is supraclassical, and is stronger than the material conditional, then it must collapse to the material conditional. Gib- bard’s result is taken to pose a dilemma for a truth-functional account of indicative conditionals: give up Import-Export, or embrace the two-valued analysis. We show that this dilemma can be averted in trivalent logics of the conditional based on Reichenbach and de Finetti’s idea that a conditional with a false antecedent is undefined. Import-Export and truth-functionality hold without triviality in such logics. We unravel some implicit assumptions in Gibbard’s proof, and discuss a recent generalization of Gibbard’s result due to Branden Fitelson. Keywords: indicative conditional; material conditional; logics of conditionals; triva- lent logic; Gibbardian collapse; Import-Export 1 Introduction The Law of Import-Export denotes the principle that a right-nested conditional of the form A → (B → C) is logically equivalent to the simple conditional (A ∧ B) → C where both antecedentsare united by conjunction. The Law holds in classical logic for material implication, and if there is a logic for the indicative conditional of ordinary language, it appears Import-Export ought to be a part of it. For instance, to use an example from (Cooper 1968, 300), the sentences “If Smith attends and Jones attends then a quorum *Institut Jean-Nicod (CNRS/ENS/EHESS), Département de philosophie & Département d’études cog- arXiv:2006.08746v1 [math.LO] 15 Jun 2020 nitives, Ecole normale supérieure, PSL University, 29 rue d’Ulm, 75005, Paris, France.
    [Show full text]
  • Glossary for Logic: the Language of Truth
    Glossary for Logic: The Language of Truth This glossary contains explanations of key terms used in the course. (These terms appear in bold in the main text at the point at which they are first used.) To make this glossary more easily searchable, the entry headings has ‘::’ (two colons) before it. So, for example, if you want to find the entry for ‘truth-value’ you should search for ‘:: truth-value’. :: Ambiguous, Ambiguity : An expression or sentence is ambiguous if and only if it can express two or more different meanings. In logic, we are interested in ambiguity relating to truth-conditions. Some sentences in natural languages express more than one claim. Read one way, they express a claim which has one set of truth-conditions. Read another way, they express a different claim with different truth-conditions. :: Antecedent : The first clause in a conditional is its antecedent. In ‘(P ➝ Q)’, ‘P’ is the antecedent. In ‘If it is raining, then we’ll get wet’, ‘It is raining’ is the antecedent. (See ‘Conditional’ and ‘Consequent’.) :: Argument : An argument is a set of claims (equivalently, statements or propositions) made up from premises and conclusion. An argument can have any number of premises (from 0 to indefinitely many) but has only one conclusion. (Note: This is a somewhat artificially restrictive definition of ‘argument’, but it will help to keep our discussions sharp and clear.) We can consider any set of claims (with one claim picked out as conclusion) as an argument: arguments will include sets of claims that no-one has actually advanced or put forward.
    [Show full text]
  • Three Ways of Being Non-Material
    Three Ways of Being Non-Material Vincenzo Crupi, Andrea Iacona May 2019 This paper presents a novel unified account of three distinct non-material inter- pretations of `if then': the suppositional interpretation, the evidential interpre- tation, and the strict interpretation. We will spell out and compare these three interpretations within a single formal framework which rests on fairly uncontro- versial assumptions, in that it requires nothing but propositional logic and the probability calculus. As we will show, each of the three intrerpretations exhibits specific logical features that deserve separate consideration. In particular, the evidential interpretation as we understand it | a precise and well defined ver- sion of it which has never been explored before | significantly differs both from the suppositional interpretation and from the strict interpretation. 1 Preliminaries Although it is widely taken for granted that indicative conditionals as they are used in ordinary language do not behave as material conditionals, there is little agreement on the nature and the extent of such deviation. Different theories tend to privilege different intuitions about conditionals, and there is no obvious answer to the question of which of them is the correct theory. In this paper, we will compare three interpretations of `if then': the suppositional interpretation, the evidential interpretation, and the strict interpretation. These interpretations may be regarded either as three distinct meanings that ordinary speakers attach to `if then', or as three ways of explicating a single indeterminate meaning by replacing it with a precise and well defined counterpart. Here is a rough and informal characterization of the three interpretations. According to the suppositional interpretation, a conditional is acceptable when its consequent is credible enough given its antecedent.
    [Show full text]
  • False Dilemma Wikipedia Contents
    False dilemma Wikipedia Contents 1 False dilemma 1 1.1 Examples ............................................... 1 1.1.1 Morton's fork ......................................... 1 1.1.2 False choice .......................................... 2 1.1.3 Black-and-white thinking ................................... 2 1.2 See also ................................................ 2 1.3 References ............................................... 3 1.4 External links ............................................. 3 2 Affirmative action 4 2.1 Origins ................................................. 4 2.2 Women ................................................ 4 2.3 Quotas ................................................. 5 2.4 National approaches .......................................... 5 2.4.1 Africa ............................................ 5 2.4.2 Asia .............................................. 7 2.4.3 Europe ............................................ 8 2.4.4 North America ........................................ 10 2.4.5 Oceania ............................................ 11 2.4.6 South America ........................................ 11 2.5 International organizations ...................................... 11 2.5.1 United Nations ........................................ 12 2.6 Support ................................................ 12 2.6.1 Polls .............................................. 12 2.7 Criticism ............................................... 12 2.7.1 Mismatching ......................................... 13 2.8 See also
    [Show full text]
  • Material Conditional Cnt:Int:Mat: in Its Simplest Form in English, a Conditional Is a Sentence of the Form “If Sec
    int.1 The Material Conditional cnt:int:mat: In its simplest form in English, a conditional is a sentence of the form \If sec . then . ," where the . are themselves sentences, such as \If the butler did it, then the gardener is innocent." In introductory logic courses, we earn to symbolize conditionals using the ! connective: symbolize the parts indicated by . , e.g., by formulas ' and , and the entire conditional is symbolized by ' ! . The connective ! is truth-functional, i.e., the truth value|T or F|of '! is determined by the truth values of ' and : ' ! is true iff ' is false or is true, and false otherwise. Relative to a truth value assignment v, we define v ⊨ ' ! iff v 2 ' or v ⊨ . The connective ! with this semantics is called the material conditional. This definition results in a number of elementary logical facts. First ofall, the deduction theorem holds for the material conditional: If Γ; ' ⊨ then Γ ⊨ ' ! (1) It is truth-functional: ' ! and :' _ are equivalent: ' ! ⊨ :' _ (2) :' _ ⊨ ' ! (3) A material conditional is entailed by its consequent and by the negation of its antecedent: ⊨ ' ! (4) :' ⊨ ' ! (5) A false material conditional is equivalent to the conjunction of its antecedent and the negation of its consequent: if ' ! is false, ' ^ : is true, and vice versa: :(' ! ) ⊨ ' ^ : (6) ' ^ : ⊨ :(' ! ) (7) The material conditional supports modus ponens: '; ' ! ⊨ (8) The material conditional agglomerates: ' ! ; ' ! χ ⊨ ' ! ( ^ χ) (9) We can always strengthen the antecedent, i.e., the conditional is monotonic: ' ! ⊨ (' ^ χ) ! (10) material-conditional rev: c8c9782 (2021-09-28) by OLP/ CC{BY 1 The material conditional is transitive, i.e., the chain rule is valid: ' ! ; ! χ ⊨ ' ! χ (11) The material conditional is equivalent to its contrapositive: ' ! ⊨ : !:' (12) : !:' ⊨ ' ! (13) These are all useful and unproblematic inferences in mathematical rea- soning.
    [Show full text]
  • Exclusive Or from Wikipedia, the Free Encyclopedia
    New features Log in / create account Article Discussion Read Edit View history Exclusive or From Wikipedia, the free encyclopedia "XOR" redirects here. For other uses, see XOR (disambiguation), XOR gate. Navigation "Either or" redirects here. For Kierkegaard's philosophical work, see Either/Or. Main page The logical operation exclusive disjunction, also called exclusive or (symbolized XOR, EOR, Contents EXOR, ⊻ or ⊕, pronounced either / ks / or /z /), is a type of logical disjunction on two Featured content operands that results in a value of true if exactly one of the operands has a value of true.[1] A Current events simple way to state this is "one or the other but not both." Random article Donate Put differently, exclusive disjunction is a logical operation on two logical values, typically the values of two propositions, that produces a value of true only in cases where the truth value of the operands differ. Interaction Contents About Wikipedia Venn diagram of Community portal 1 Truth table Recent changes 2 Equivalencies, elimination, and introduction but not is Contact Wikipedia 3 Relation to modern algebra Help 4 Exclusive “or” in natural language 5 Alternative symbols Toolbox 6 Properties 6.1 Associativity and commutativity What links here 6.2 Other properties Related changes 7 Computer science Upload file 7.1 Bitwise operation Special pages 8 See also Permanent link 9 Notes Cite this page 10 External links 4, 2010 November Print/export Truth table on [edit] archived The truth table of (also written as or ) is as follows: Venn diagram of Create a book 08-17094 Download as PDF No.
    [Show full text]
  • An Introduction to Formal Logic
    forall x: Calgary An Introduction to Formal Logic By P. D. Magnus Tim Button with additions by J. Robert Loftis Robert Trueman remixed and revised by Aaron Thomas-Bolduc Richard Zach Fall 2021 This book is based on forallx: Cambridge, by Tim Button (University College Lon- don), used under a CC BY 4.0 license, which is based in turn on forallx, by P.D. Magnus (University at Albany, State University of New York), used under a CC BY 4.0 li- cense, and was remixed, revised, & expanded by Aaron Thomas-Bolduc & Richard Zach (University of Calgary). It includes additional material from forallx by P.D. Magnus and Metatheory by Tim Button, used under a CC BY 4.0 license, from forallx: Lorain County Remix, by Cathal Woods and J. Robert Loftis, and from A Modal Logic Primer by Robert Trueman, used with permission. This work is licensed under a Creative Commons Attribution 4.0 license. You are free to copy and redistribute the material in any medium or format, and remix, transform, and build upon the material for any purpose, even commercially, under the following terms: ⊲ You must give appropriate credit, provide a link to the license, and indicate if changes were made. You may do so in any reasonable manner, but not in any way that suggests the licensor endorses you or your use. ⊲ You may not apply legal terms or technological measures that legally restrict others from doing anything the license permits. The LATEX source for this book is available on GitHub and PDFs at forallx.openlogicproject.org.
    [Show full text]
  • Conditional Heresies *
    CONDITIONAL HERESIES * Fabrizio Cariani and Simon Goldstein Abstract The principles of Conditional Excluded Middle (CEM) and Simplification of Disjunctive Antecedents (SDA) have received substantial attention in isolation. Both principles are plausible generalizations about natural lan- guage conditionals. There is however little discussion of their interaction. This paper aims to remedy this gap and explore the significance of hav- ing both principles constrain the logic of the conditional. Our negative finding is that, together with elementary logical assumptions, CEM and SDA yield a variety of implausible consequences. Despite these incom- patibility results, we open up a narrow space to satisfy both. We show that, by simultaneously appealing to the alternative-introducing analysis of disjunction and to the theory of homogeneity presuppositions, we can satisfy both. Furthermore, the theory that validates both principles re- sembles a recent semantics that is defended by Santorio on independent grounds. The cost of this approach is that it must give up the transitivity of entailment: we suggest that this is a feature, not a bug, and connect it with recent developments of intransitive notions of entailment. 1 Introduction David Lewis’s logic for the counterfactual conditional (Lewis 1973) famously invalidates two plausible-sounding principles: simplification of disjunctive antecedents (SDA),1 and conditional excluded middle (CEM).2 Simplification states that conditionals with disjunctive antecedents entail conditionals whose antecedents are the disjuncts taken in isolation. For instance, given SDA, (1) en- tails (2). *Special thanks to Shawn Standefer for extensive written comments on a previous version of this paper and to anonymous reviewers for Philosophy and Phenomenological Research and the Amsterdam Colloquium.
    [Show full text]
  • Forall X: an Introduction to Formal Logic 1.30
    University at Albany, State University of New York Scholars Archive Philosophy Faculty Books Philosophy 12-27-2014 Forall x: An introduction to formal logic 1.30 P.D. Magnus University at Albany, State University of New York, [email protected] Follow this and additional works at: https://scholarsarchive.library.albany.edu/ cas_philosophy_scholar_books Part of the Logic and Foundations of Mathematics Commons Recommended Citation Magnus, P.D., "Forall x: An introduction to formal logic 1.30" (2014). Philosophy Faculty Books. 3. https://scholarsarchive.library.albany.edu/cas_philosophy_scholar_books/3 This Book is brought to you for free and open access by the Philosophy at Scholars Archive. It has been accepted for inclusion in Philosophy Faculty Books by an authorized administrator of Scholars Archive. For more information, please contact [email protected]. forallx An Introduction to Formal Logic P.D. Magnus University at Albany, State University of New York fecundity.com/logic, version 1.30 [141227] This book is offered under a Creative Commons license. (Attribution-ShareAlike 3.0) The author would like to thank the people who made this project possible. Notable among these are Cristyn Magnus, who read many early drafts; Aaron Schiller, who was an early adopter and provided considerable, helpful feedback; and Bin Kang, Craig Erb, Nathan Carter, Wes McMichael, Selva Samuel, Dave Krueger, Brandon Lee, Toan Tran, and the students of Introduction to Logic, who detected various errors in previous versions of the book. c 2005{2014 by P.D. Magnus. Some rights reserved. You are free to copy this book, to distribute it, to display it, and to make derivative works, under the following conditions: (a) Attribution.
    [Show full text]
  • Form and Content: an Introduction to Formal Logic
    Connecticut College Digital Commons @ Connecticut College Open Educational Resources 2020 Form and Content: An Introduction to Formal Logic Derek D. Turner Connecticut College, [email protected] Follow this and additional works at: https://digitalcommons.conncoll.edu/oer Recommended Citation Turner, Derek D., "Form and Content: An Introduction to Formal Logic" (2020). Open Educational Resources. 1. https://digitalcommons.conncoll.edu/oer/1 This Book is brought to you for free and open access by Digital Commons @ Connecticut College. It has been accepted for inclusion in Open Educational Resources by an authorized administrator of Digital Commons @ Connecticut College. For more information, please contact [email protected]. The views expressed in this paper are solely those of the author. Form & Content Form and Content An Introduction to Formal Logic Derek Turner Connecticut College 2020 Susanne K. Langer. This bust is in Shain Library at Connecticut College, New London, CT. Photo by the author. 1 Form & Content ©2020 Derek D. Turner This work is published in 2020 under a Creative Commons Attribution- NonCommercial-NoDerivatives 4.0 International License. You may share this text in any format or medium. You may not use it for commercial purposes. If you share it, you must give appropriate credit. If you remix, transform, add to, or modify the text in any way, you may not then redistribute the modified text. 2 Form & Content A Note to Students For many years, I had relied on one of the standard popular logic textbooks for my introductory formal logic course at Connecticut College. It is a perfectly good book, used in countless logic classes across the country.
    [Show full text]
  • © Cambridge University Press Cambridge
    Cambridge University Press 978-0-521-89957-4 - Handbook of Practical Logic and Automated Reasoning John Harrison Index More information Index (x, y) (pair), 594 ---, 618 − (negation of literal), 51 -/, 617 − (set difference), 594 //, 617 C− (negation of literal set), 181 ::, 616 ∧ (and), 27 </, 617 ∆0 formula, 547 <=/, 617 ∆1-definable, 564 =/, 617 ⊥ (false), 27 @, 616 ⇔ (iff), 27 #install printer,22 ⇒ (implies), 27 0-saturation, 91 ∩ (intersection), 594 1-consistent, 554 ¬ (not), 27 1-saturation, 91 ∨ (or), 27 3-CNF, 79 Π1-formula, 550 3-SAT, 79 Σ1-formula, 550 (true), 27 Abel, 6 ∪ (union), 594 abelian, 287 ◦ (function composition), 596 abstract syntax, 12 ∂ (degree), 355 abstract syntax tree, 12 ∅ (empty set), 594 abstract type, 469 ≡ (congruent modulo), 594 AC (associative–commutative), 285 ∈ (set membership), 594 AC (Axiom of Choice), 144 κ-categorical, 245 accumulator, 611 → (maps to), 595 Ackermann reduction, 254 | (divides), 593 ad hoc polymorphism, 612 |= (logical consequence), 40, 130 Add,14 |=M (holds in M), 130 add 0, 565 ℘ (power set), 598 add assum, 480 ⊂ (proper subset), 594 add assum’, 497 → (sequent), 471 add default, 436 \ (set difference), 594 add suc, 565 ⊆ (subset), 594 adequate set (of connectives), 46 × (Cartesian product), 594 adjustcoeff, 342 → (function space), 595 AE fragment, 309 → (reduction relation), 258 aedecide, 310 →∗ (reflexive transitive closure of →), 258 affine transformation, 417 →+ (transitive closure of →), 258 affirmative negative rule,81 (provability), 246, 470, 474 afn dlo, 335 {1, 2, 3} (set enumeration),
    [Show full text]
  • The Logic of Conditionals1
    THE LOGIC OF CONDITIONALS1 by Ernest Adams University of California, Berkeley The standard use of the propositional calculus ('P.C.') in analyzing the validity of inferences involving conditionals leads to fallacies, and the problem is to determine where P.C. may be 'safely' used. An alternative analysis of criteria of reasonableness of inferences in terms of conditions of justification r a t h e r than truth of statements is pro- posed. It is argued, under certain restrictions, that P. C. may be safely used, except in inferences whose conclusions are conditionals whose antecedents are incompatible with the premises in the sense that if the antecedent became known, some of the previously asserted premises would have to be withdrawn. 1. The following nine 'inferences' are all ones which, when symbol- ized in the ordinary way in the propositional calculus and analyzed truth functionally, are valid in the sense that no combination of truth values of the components makes the premises true but the conclusion false. Fl. John will arrive on the 10 o'clock plane. Therefore, if J o h n does not arrive on the 10 o'clock plane, he will arrive on the 11 o'clock plane. F2. John will arrive on the 10 o'clock plane. Therefore, if John misses his plane in New York,' he will arrive on the 10 o'clock plane. F3. If Brown wins the election, Smith will retire to private life. Therefore, if Smith dies before the election and Brown wins it, Smith will retire to private life. F4. If Brown wins the election, Smith will retire to private life.
    [Show full text]