Inspiration and Τέχνη: Divination in Plato's

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Inspiration and Τέχνη: Divination in Plato's AARON LANDRY | 85 Inspiration INTRODUCTION and Τέχνη: In Plato’s Ion, inspiration functions in con- Divination in tradistinction to technē.1 Since Ion’s rhapso- dic expertise does not stand up to Socrates’ Plato’s Ion epistemological critique, his performances of Homer cannot stem from knowledge, but from elsewhere, from divine inspiration. The two are presented as a strict disjunction. Yet in both cases there is an appeal to divination. If rhapsody, and poetry by extension, cannot synthesize the two, why does Socrates seem 2 Aaron Landry to think that divination can? This puzzle has Humber College caused quite a bit of consternation about the 3 [email protected] value and subject matter of the dialogue. In particular, it is unclear what Socrates thinks about the nature of poetic and rhapsodic ins- piration. In this essay, I will argue that divi- nation constitutes an alternate, and improved, framework for Ion to model his expertise on. By clarifying the role and scope of divination in the Ion, I aim to show that Socrates’ disjunctive account – inspiration or technē – can actually be integrated. In so doing, I argue that there are in fact positive philosophical theses latent ABSTRACT in the dialogue. In part I, I rehearse the contrasting accoun- In Plato’s Ion, inspiration functions in ts of divination in the dialogue. In the first argumentative exchange, divination is refe- contradistinction to technē. Yet, paradoxically, in both cases, there is an appeal to divination. renced as a paradigmatic technē. The seer is I interrogate this in order to show how these best equipped to speak about the contrasting two disparate accounts can be accommodat- depictions of divination given by Homer and ed. Specifically, I argue that Socrates’ appeal Hesiod. When Ion fails to meet Socrates’ ques- to Theoclymenus at Ion 539a-b demonstrates tioning, the argument changes direction. Ion’s that Plato recognizes the existence of intuitive ability is now the result of divine inspiration; seers who defy his own distinction between again, Socrates cites divination as akin to what possession and technical divination. Such seers Ion purportedly experiences. provide an epistemic model for Ion; that he does In part II, I interrogate the final reference to not notice this confirms he is not an exemplary divination, which occurs when Socrates appeals rhapsode. to the Homeric Epics. Ostensibly, Socrates is trying to show Ion that the best person to judge Keywords: Ancient Philosophy; Plato; Ion. literary depictions of a technē is a practitioner http://dx.doi.org/10.14195/2183-4105_14_6 86 | Inspiration and Τέχνη: Divination in Plato’s Ion AARON LANDRY | 87 of that technē. In each case, and for slightly like Theoclymenus and Diotima, together different reasons, I show that Socrates fails with Socrates’ daimonion, complicate affairs to do justice to Homer. It is not that Socrates and carve out space for visionaries who always is only engaged in eristic with Ion, but that a retain their nous. deeper philosophical point lurks in the back- ground. Divination is Socrates’ final example and is quoted twice – first, Theoclymenus’ vi- PART I: TWO REFERENCES TO sion of the suitors’ destruction, and second, a DIVINATION bird omen appearing to the Trojans. I argue that Theoclymenus is what I call an ‘intuitive The first reference to divination occurs at seer’ in that he can simultaneously practice his the beginning of the dialogue. Ion’s specialty technē and claim to be divinely inspired. In is Homer, but can perform the works of other other words, he is a model for Ion to emulate. poets (531a)?7 Since Homer and Hesiod often In part III, I sketch a related, but funda- engage with the same subject matter, Socrates mentally distinct, account of divination offered reasons that he who can recite the former can by Brickhouse and Smith 1993. They too are also recite the latter. He urges Ion to consider interested in the relationship between technē those subjects like the seer’s art (mantikēs), and inspiration. Their account claims that the upon which Homer and Hesiod disagree (531b). technē of a possessed seer like the Pythia con- Which person can speak better about divina- sists of knowing how to enter into an inspired tion – Ion or a seer? Ion replies that it would state. Once in this state, the god who possesses be the seer. In fact, Socrates explicitly connec- the seer takes over and the seer can no longer ts Ion and divination by asking “Suppose you be thought of as in control of his or her thou- [Ion] were a diviner…” (ei de su ēstha mantis) ghts, utterances, and actions. 4 In contrast, and (531b7), wouldn’t you be the person best equi- drawing on Diotima in the Symposium, I argue pped to explain the similarities and differences that intuitive seers are simultaneously divinely between the two poets? inspired and self-aware. They are able to re- The second reference to divination occurs flect and interpret their own divinations. I will in the famous magnet section (533d-534e). Ion argue that intuitive seers like Theoclymenus cannot explain his ability to perform Homer. and Diotima cannot be explained according to Socrates introduces a new concept – a divine the model proposed by Brickhouse and Smith.5 power (theia de dunamis) – in strong contrast to There is both a narrow and broad purpo- technē.8 Like the power of the magnet, Ion, toge- se for developing this interpretive possibility ther with the epic poets, is divinely possessed. in the Ion. From a dramaturgical perspective, Not only does the magnet attract the iron ring, Theoclymenus and seers like him offer Ion an it implants power into the ring itself, thereby epistemic alternative on which to model his enabling the ring to pull other rings. Similarly, purported expertise. His failure confirms that the Muse inspires Homer, who in turn inspires he is not an exemplary rhapsode.6 More broadly Ion, who is finally able to enchant his audien- construed, this serves to blur the distinction ce. Although Socrates introduces the concept of between having a technē and being divinely inspiration, specified as the rhapsode’s complete inspired. When this distinction usually crops lack of nous (ho nous mēketi en autō enē) (534b4- up, it is immediately undermined. But seers 5), Ion heartily subscribes to it. 86 | Inspiration and Τέχνη: Divination in Plato’s Ion AARON LANDRY | 87 For Socrates, if a person is in possession of The first example is chariot driving. So- their intellect, they are unable to create poetry crates prompts Ion to quote what Nestor tells or sing prophecy. The particularity of Ion’s ex- his son about turning post in the chariot race pertise is the best evidence that he is inspired during Patroclus’ funeral: by the Muse. According to Socrates, what ha- ppens to Ion is analogous to “prophets and go- Lean yourself over on the smooth-planed dly seers” (tois khrēsmōdois kai tois mantesi tois chariot just to the left of the pair. Then the theiois) (534d2) in the sense that no one thinks horse on the right – goad him shout him it is the seers themselves who divine.9 Rather, on, easing the reins with your hands. At it is the gods who use the seer as a medium.10 the post let your horse on the left stick ti- Note, furthermore, that Socrates connects seers ght to the turn so you seem to come right with prophets (khrēsmōdois), which etymolo- to the edge, with the hub of your welded gically means ‘singer of oracles’.11 wheel. But escape cropping the stone… In the next section, I examine the final por- (Iliad 23.335-340 qtd. at 537a8-b6,) trayal of divination in conjunction with the other technai discussed – chariot driving, medicine, κλινθῆναι δέ, φησί, καὶ αὐτὸς ἐυξέστῳ and fishing. My aim is to see how each example ἐνὶ δίφρῳ ἦκ᾽ ἐπ᾽ ἀριστερὰ τοῖιν: ἀτὰρ functions in the Homeric Epics. In the case of τὸν δεξιὸν ἵππον κένσαι ὁμοκλήσας, divination, I argue that Theoclymenus is best εἶξαί τέ οἱ ἡνία χερσίν. ἐν νύσσῃ δέ τοι conceptualized as an intuitive seer, someone who ἵππος ἀριστερὸς ἐγχριμφθήτω, ὡς ἄν experiences visions but nevertheless remains self τοι πλήμνη γε δοάσσεται ἄκρον ἱκέσθαι -aware. This is important because it serves as a κύκλου ποιητοῖο: λίθου δ᾽ ἀλέασθαι potential model for individuals like Ion. ἐπαυρεῖν. For Socrates, an expert in chariot driving PART II: THE HOMERIC is better able to interpret this passage than QUOTATIONS Homer, or a performer of the Homeric epi- cs like Ion. Undoubtedly, chariot driving, Socrates’ use of Homer is perplexing, due in like automobile driving, requires skill. But large part to his claim that a literary depiction does it qualify as a technē? In fact, Nestor of a technē requires the relevant practitioner initially qualifies his instruction by stating to adequately judge it. What about aesthetic that Zeus and Poseidon have ‘taught’ (edi- expertise? In what follows, I rehearse Socrates’ daxan) his son every form of chariot driving quotations as they function in the Homeric tex- and that there is no need for his ‘instruction’ ts. I show that each example, when considered (didaskemen). in context, does not support Socrates’ claim. In Nevertheless, Nestor goes on to say that An- each case, there is a slightly different problem tilochos’ horse is slower than the other racers, with Socrates’ argument. This serves to open and that he must therefore use his ‘cunning’ up alternate interpretations to what Socrates (mētis) if he is to be successful. It is in this overtly states. In the case of divination, the context that he offers advice on how best to final example, I stress its affinity with the kind round the post.
Recommended publications
  • PLATO's SYMPOSIUM J
    50 ccn~ PLATO'S SYMPOSIUM j - - -- ________j e Library of Liberal Arts PLATO'S SYMPOSIUM Tran lated by BENJAMIN JOWETT With an Introduction by FULTON H. ANDERSON Professor of Philosophy, University of Toronto THE LIBERAL ARTS PRESS NEW YORK CONTENTS SELECTED BIBLIOGRAPHY .. .... ................................... ......... ... ........... 6 EDITOR'S INTRODUCTION ................... ............................................. 7 SYMPOSIUM APOLLODORUS 13 THE SPEECH OF PHAEDRUS ...... .......................... .......................... .. 19 THE SPEECH OF PAU ANIAS ................. ... ................................. ... .. 21 THE SPEECH OF ERYXIMACHUS 27 THE SPEECH OF ARISTOPHAN E .. ............................... .................. 30 THE SPEECH OF AGATHON ............ .............................................. .. 35 THE SPEECH OF SocRATES ................................ .. ................... ..... .. 39 THE SPEECH OF ALCIBIADES ................. ............... ... ........... ...... .... .. 55 8 PLATO INTROD CTION 9 crescendo, and culminates in the report by Socrates on wi dom and epistemology, upon all of which the Symposium ha bearing, learned from the "wi e" woman Diotima. are intertwined, we m ay set down briefly a few of the more general The dialogue i a "reported" one. Plato himself could not have principles which are to be found in it author's many-sided thought. been present at the original party. (What went on there was told The human soul, a cording to Plato, is es entially in motion. time and time again about Athens.) He was a mere boy when it It is li fe and the integration of living functions. A dead soul is a con­ took place. Nor could the narrator Apollodorus have been a guest; _lladiction in terms. Man throughout his whole nature is erotically he was too young at the time. The latter got his report from motivated. His "love" or desire i manifest in three mutually in­ Aristodemus, a guest at the banquet.
    [Show full text]
  • The Historicity of Plato's Apology of Socrates
    Loyola University Chicago Loyola eCommons Master's Theses Theses and Dissertations 1946 The Historicity of Plato's Apology of Socrates David J. Bowman Loyola University Chicago Follow this and additional works at: https://ecommons.luc.edu/luc_theses Part of the Classical Literature and Philology Commons Recommended Citation Bowman, David J., "The Historicity of Plato's Apology of Socrates" (1946). Master's Theses. 61. https://ecommons.luc.edu/luc_theses/61 This Thesis is brought to you for free and open access by the Theses and Dissertations at Loyola eCommons. It has been accepted for inclusion in Master's Theses by an authorized administrator of Loyola eCommons. For more information, please contact [email protected]. This work is licensed under a Creative Commons Attribution-Noncommercial-No Derivative Works 3.0 License. Copyright © 1946 David J. Bowman !HE HISTORICITY OP PLATO'S APOLOGY OF SOCRATES BY DA.VID J. BOWJWf~ S.J• .l. !BESIS SUBMITTED Ilf PARTIAL FULFILIJIE.NT OF THB: R}gQUIRE'IIENTS POR THE DEGREE OF IIA.STER OF ARTS Ill LOYOLA UlfiVERSITY JULY 1946 -VI'fA. David J. Bowman; S.J•• was born in Oak Park, Ill1no1a, on Ma7 20, 1919. Atter b!a eleaentar7 education at Ascension School# in Oak Park, he attended LoJola AcademJ ot Chicago, graduat1DS .from. there in June, 1937. On September 1, 1937# he entered the Sacred Heart Novitiate ot the SocietJ ot Jesus at Milford~ Ohio. Por the tour Jear• he spent there, he was aoademicallJ connected with Xavier Univeraitr, Cincinnati, Ohio. In August ot 1941 he tranaterred to West Baden College o.f Lorol& Universit7, Obicago, and received the degree ot Bachelor o.f Arts with a major in Greek in Deo.aber, 1941.
    [Show full text]
  • Plato's Symposium: the Ethics of Desire
    Plato’s Symposium: The Ethics of Desire FRISBEE C. C. SHEFFIELD 1 Contents Introduction 1 1. Ero¯s and the Good Life 8 2. Socrates’ Speech: The Nature of Ero¯s 40 3. Socrates’ Speech: The Aim of Ero¯s 75 4. Socrates’ Speech: The Activity of Ero¯s 112 5. Socrates’ Speech: Concern for Others? 154 6. ‘Nothing to do with Human AVairs?’: Alcibiades’ Response to Socrates 183 7. Shadow Lovers: The Symposiasts and Socrates 207 Conclusion 225 Appendix : Socratic Psychology or Tripartition in the Symposium? 227 References 240 Index 249 Introduction In the Symposium Plato invites us to imagine the following scene: A pair of lovers are locked in an embrace and Hephaestus stands over them with his mending tools asking: ‘What is it that you human beings really want from each other?’ The lovers are puzzled, and he asks them again: ‘Is this your heart’s desire, for the two of you to become parts of the same whole, and never to separate, day or night? If that is your desire, I’d like to weld you together and join you into something whole, so that the two of you are made into one. Look at your love and see if this is what you desire: wouldn’t this be all that you want?’ No one, apparently, would think that mere sex is the reason each lover takes such deep joy in being with the other. The soul of each lover apparently longs for something else, but cannot say what it is. The beloved holds out the promise of something beyond itself, but that something lovers are unable to name.1 Hephaestus’ question is a pressing one.
    [Show full text]
  • On the Arrangement of the Platonic Dialogues
    Ryan C. Fowler 25th Hour On the Arrangement of the Platonic Dialogues I. Thrasyllus a. Diogenes Laertius (D.L.), Lives and Opinions of Eminent Philosophers 3.56: “But, just as long ago in tragedy the chorus was the only actor, and afterwards, in order to give the chorus breathing space, Thespis devised a single actor, Aeschylus a second, Sophocles a third, and thus tragedy was completed, so too with philosophy: in early times it discoursed on one subject only, namely physics, then Socrates added the second subject, ethics, and Plato the third, dialectics, and so brought philosophy to perfection. Thrasyllus says that he [Plato] published his dialogues in tetralogies, like those of the tragic poets. Thus they contended with four plays at the Dionysia, the Lenaea, the Panathenaea and the festival of Chytri. Of the four plays the last was a satiric drama; and the four together were called a tetralogy.” b. Characters or types of dialogues (D.L. 3.49): 1. instructive (ὑφηγητικός) A. theoretical (θεωρηµατικόν) a. physical (φυσικόν) b. logical (λογικόν) B. practical (πρακτικόν) a. ethical (ἠθικόν) b. political (πολιτικόν) 2. investigative (ζητητικός) A. training the mind (γυµναστικός) a. obstetrical (µαιευτικός) b. tentative (πειραστικός) B. victory in controversy (ἀγωνιστικός) a. critical (ἐνδεικτικός) b. subversive (ἀνατρεπτικός) c. Thrasyllan categories of the dialogues (D.L. 3.50-1): Physics: Timaeus Logic: Statesman, Cratylus, Parmenides, and Sophist Ethics: Apology, Crito, Phaedo, Phaedrus, Symposium, Menexenus, Clitophon, the Letters, Philebus, Hipparchus, Rivals Politics: Republic, the Laws, Minos, Epinomis, Atlantis Obstetrics: Alcibiades 1 and 2, Theages, Lysis, Laches Tentative: Euthyphro, Meno, Io, Charmides and Theaetetus Critical: Protagoras Subversive: Euthydemus, Gorgias, and Hippias 1 and 2 :1 d.
    [Show full text]
  • ION: Plato's Defense of Poetry Critical Introduction We
    ION: Plato's defense of poetry Critical Introduction We occasionally use a word as a position marker. For example, the word 'Plato' is most often used to mark an anti-poetic position in the "old quarrel" between philosophy and poetry. Occasionally that marker is shifted slightly, but even in those cases it does not shift much. So, W.K.C. Guthrie in his magisterial History of Greek Philosophy1 can conclude [Plato] never flinched from the thesis that poets, unlike philosophers, wrote without knowledge and without regard to the moral effect of their poems, and that therefore they must either be banned or censored (Vol IV, 211). Generally, studies of individual dialogues take such markers as their interpretative horizon. So, Kenneth Dorter,2 who sees the importance of the Ion as "the only dialogue which discusses art in its own terms at all" (65) begins his article with the statement There is no question that Plato regarded art as a serious and dangerous rival to philosophy—this is a theme that remains constant from the very early Ion to the very late Laws (65). Even in those very rare instances where the marker is itself brought into question, as Julius Elias' Plato's Defence of Poetry3 attempts to do, the one dialogue in which Plato picks up poetry (rather than rhetoric) on its own account and not in an explicitly political or educational setting—the Ion—is overlooked entirely or given quite short shrift. Elias, after a two paragraph summary of the dialogue says "almost anybody could defend poetry better than Ion; we must look elsewhere for weightier arguments and worthier opponents" (6) and does not refer to the dialogue again in his book.
    [Show full text]
  • Leto As Mother: Representations of Leto with Apollo and Artemis in Attic Vase Painting of the Fifth Century B.C
    https://publications.dainst.org iDAI.publications ELEKTRONISCHE PUBLIKATIONEN DES DEUTSCHEN ARCHÄOLOGISCHEN INSTITUTS Dies ist ein digitaler Sonderdruck des Beitrags / This is a digital offprint of the article Lavinia Foukara Leto as Mother: Representations of Leto with Apollo and Artemis in Attic Vase Painting of the Fifth Century B.C. aus / from Archäologischer Anzeiger Ausgabe / Issue Seite / Page 63–83 https://publications.dainst.org/journals/aa/2027/6626 • urn:nbn:de:0048-journals.aa-2017-1-p63-83-v6626.5 Verantwortliche Redaktion / Publishing editor Redaktion der Zentrale | Deutsches Archäologisches Institut Weitere Informationen unter / For further information see https://publications.dainst.org/journals/aa ISSN der Online-Ausgabe / ISSN of the online edition 2510-4713 ISSN der gedruckten Ausgabe / ISSN of the printed edition Verlag / Publisher Ernst Wasmuth Verlag GmbH & Co. Tübingen ©2019 Deutsches Archäologisches Institut Deutsches Archäologisches Institut, Zentrale, Podbielskiallee 69–71, 14195 Berlin, Tel: +49 30 187711-0 Email: [email protected] / Web: dainst.org Nutzungsbedingungen: Mit dem Herunterladen erkennen Sie die Nutzungsbedingungen (https://publications.dainst.org/terms-of-use) von iDAI.publications an. Die Nutzung der Inhalte ist ausschließlich privaten Nutzerinnen / Nutzern für den eigenen wissenschaftlichen und sonstigen privaten Gebrauch gestattet. Sämtliche Texte, Bilder und sonstige Inhalte in diesem Dokument unterliegen dem Schutz des Urheberrechts gemäß dem Urheberrechtsgesetz der Bundesrepublik Deutschland. Die Inhalte können von Ihnen nur dann genutzt und vervielfältigt werden, wenn Ihnen dies im Einzelfall durch den Rechteinhaber oder die Schrankenregelungen des Urheberrechts gestattet ist. Jede Art der Nutzung zu gewerblichen Zwecken ist untersagt. Zu den Möglichkeiten einer Lizensierung von Nutzungsrechten wenden Sie sich bitte direkt an die verantwortlichen Herausgeberinnen/Herausgeber der entsprechenden Publikationsorgane oder an die Online-Redaktion des Deutschen Archäologischen Instituts ([email protected]).
    [Show full text]
  • Download Scans
    12e JAARGANG 1e KWARTAAL 1947 PHILOSOPHIA R·EFORMATA ORGA,AN VAN DE VEREENIGING VOOR CALVI NISTISCHE W!JSBEGEERTE ONDER REDACTIEVA~J DR J. BOHATEC DR J. H. DIEMER DR H. DO 0 YEW EERD DR H. G. STOKER DR C. VAN TIL DR D. H. TH. VOLLENHOVEN UITGAVE J.H. KOK N.V KAMPEN HOOFOREDACTEUR: Prof. Dr H. DOOYE"\VEERD, Or anje Nassaulaan 13, Al\iSTERDAl\I-ZUID REDACTIELEDEN: Dr J. BOf-IATEC, \VEENEN Dr J. H. DIEMER, GnO?\IXGE:\ Dr H. G. STOKER, POTCIIEFSTTIOO:\1 ­ Dr C. V.A..l~ TIL, PHILADELPHIA - Dr D. H. TIl. 'VOLLENIIO\'EN, Al\ISTETIDAI\1 Secretariaat: Dr .1. P. A. Mekkes, Waalsdorperweg 245, 's Gravenhage INHOUDSOPGAVE pag. OXTWERP ENER AESTHETICA OP GROXDSLAG DER \VIJSBEGEERTE DER \VETSIDEE, II, door H. R. ROOK.l\lAAKER 1 OPVOEDI:"JG, ONDER\VIJS, SCI-lOOLVERBAKD, I, door DR K J. POPMA. .......... 36 CALYIXISME EN VOLKEKRECHT, door DR J R. STEL- LINGA •............ .. 42 ONTWERP ENER AESTHETICA OP GRONDSLAG DER WIJSBEGEERTE DER WETSIDEE DOOR H. R. ROOKMAAKER. § 10. Stijl en schoonheid aan niet-aesthetisch gequalificeerde structuren. Schoonheid aan natuurdingen is een stijlloze schoonheid 53), immers, deze schoonheid is gefundeerd in de leidende functie van het (in één van de natuurzijden gequalificeerde) ding en dus niet in de (historische) beheersende vorming. Aan alle structureel in de historische functie ge- fundeerde objectieve dingstructuren kunnen we echter stijl herkennen; het ding is immers tot stand gekomen in een menselijke vormingsarbeid.. Stijl is dus geen „privilege" voor kunstwerken, voor aesthetisch-gequa- lificeerde dingen. Zo merken we schoonheid, stijl op aan sociaal-ge- qualificeerde structuren als stoelen, glaswerk, wasbakken etc.
    [Show full text]
  • The Rationality of Plato's Theory of Good and Evil
    Wilfrid Laurier University Scholars Commons @ Laurier Theses and Dissertations (Comprehensive) 1979 The Rationality of Plato’s Theory of Good and Evil Allan A. Davis Wilfrid Laurier University Follow this and additional works at: https://scholars.wlu.ca/etd Part of the Philosophy Commons Recommended Citation Davis, Allan A., "The Rationality of Plato’s Theory of Good and Evil" (1979). Theses and Dissertations (Comprehensive). 1508. https://scholars.wlu.ca/etd/1508 This Thesis is brought to you for free and open access by Scholars Commons @ Laurier. It has been accepted for inclusion in Theses and Dissertations (Comprehensive) by an authorized administrator of Scholars Commons @ Laurier. For more information, please contact [email protected]. ABSTRACT Plato has been called the "father of rational theology." This thesis is an attempt to examine in the light of contemporary Platonic scholarship five of Plato's essentially religious doctrines insofar as they support the idea that Plato's theory of good and evil is rational. Chapters 1 and 2 examine the plausibility of Plato's theory of knowledge. Chapter 3 states briefly his theory of Forms, while Chapter 4 attempts to give this doctrine credence by analysing those aspects of it which seem least convincing. Chapters 5 and 6 consider Plato's theory of soul and conclude that, although some of his beliefs in this area lack credibility, his interpretation of the nature and function of soul is basically plausible. Chapters 7 and 8 examine the rationality of Plato's Idea of the Good. Chapter 9 sketches his notion of balance and proportion and, in conclusion, Chapter 10 attempts to show how this theory provides an underlying credibility not only to all the theories discussed but also to Plato's theory of good and evil in its entirety.
    [Show full text]
  • An Apology of Euripides: Defending the Poets
    [Expositions 11.1 (2017) 118–137] Expositions (online) ISSN: 1747–5376 An Apology of Euripides: Defending the Poets MARLENE K. SOKOLON Concordia University One of the main prosecutors of Socrates on charges of impiety and corruption in 399 B.C.E. was the poet Miletus. In Plato’s version of his Apology (22b), Socrates defends himself by pointing out that poets are merely inspired and their audiences are better at explaining their poems.1 This critique of poetry is found and developed across Plato’s corpus, especially in the Republic (604b– 608d) where Socrates ends the ancient quarrel by exiling the poets from the city and philosophic education. This banishment, however, unleashed a new quarrel as to the meaning of Socrates’ critique of poetry, especially in light of his generous use of poetic elements in Plato’s dialogues. Generally, this debate has examined whether Socrates’ critique is ironic from the philosopher’s perspective. In contrast, this analysis takes up Socrates’ explicit challenge in the Republic (607e) for a defender (prostatēs) to give apology of poetry demonstrating that it is not simply pleasant but beneficial to regimes and human life. Offering two of Euripides’ plays in defense—Suppliant Women and Ion—the article investigates Euripides’ poetic contribution to understanding two enduring questions of political philosophy: what is the best regime; and what is the role of myth in political origin. Importantly, Euripides provides a serious account of such questions and reveals that a poetic education may be not only beneficial, but essential in any democratic regime. Socrates’ Critique of the Poets In Plato’s Apology, Socrates’ critique of the poets appears in the context of his defense against his old accusers.
    [Show full text]
  • Reading Penelope and Molly: an Intertextual Analysis
    Reading Penelope and Molly: An Intertextual Analysis A thesis submitted to the Miami University Honors Program in partial fulfillment of the requirements for University Honors By Michelle L. Mitchell May 2004 Oxford, OH ii Abstract Reading Penelope and Molly: An Intertextual Analysis by Michelle L. Mitchell This thesis takes an intertextual approach to Homer’s Odyssey and James Joyce’s Ulysses. Intertextual analysis goes beyond examining the ways Joyce adopts Homer’s themes and characters in his own modern epic to also consider the ways in which a reading of Ulysses can affect one’s understanding of the Odyssey. Examining the reader’s role in the production and consumption of texts allows for a more realistic examination of how texts are actually processed. The focus of my interetextual analysis of both works is on the representation of women, particularly Penelope and Molly Bloom. iii iv An Intertextual Analysis of the Representations of Women in Homer’s Odyssey and Joyce’s Ulysses by Michelle L. Mitchell Approved by: _____________________________________, Advisor Judith de Luce _____________________________________, Reader Madelyn Detloff _____________________________________, Reader Kathleen Johnson Accepted by: _____________________________________, Director, University Honors Program v vi Acknowledgements Many thanks to my advisor, Judith de Luce, for her encouragement and guidance. Thanks also to Madelyn Detloff and Kathleen Johnson, my readers, for their suggestions. I would also like to thank the Office for the Advancement of
    [Show full text]
  • Penelope, Odysseus, and the Teleologies of the Odyssey
    Putting an End to Song: Penelope, Odysseus, and the Teleologies of the Odyssey Emily Hauser Helios, Volume 47, Number 1, Spring 2020, pp. 39-69 (Article) Published by Texas Tech University Press DOI: https://doi.org/10.1353/hel.2020.0001 For additional information about this article https://muse.jhu.edu/article/765967 [ Access provided at 28 Dec 2020 07:35 GMT from University of Washington @ Seattle ] Putting an End to Song: Penelope, Odysseus, and the Teleologies of the Odyssey EMILY HAUSER Abstract Book 1 of the Odyssey presents us with the first bard-figure of the poem, singing what in many ways is an analogue to the Odyssey with “the return of the Greeks”; yet when Penelope appears, it is to attempt to put an end to his song. I use this scene as a starting point to suggest that Penelope is deeply implicated in narrative endings in the Odyssey. Looking at the end or τέλος of the poem through a system- atic study of its “closural allusions,” I argue that a teleological analysis of Penelope’s character in relation to endings may both resolve some of the issues in her inter- pretation thus far, and open up new avenues for the reading of the Odyssey as a poem informed by endings. I. Introduction Penelope’s first appearance in the Odyssey (1.325–144) is to make a request of Phe- mius the bard, who is singing the tale of the Greeks’ return from Troy, the Ἀχαιῶν νόστος (1.326). Phemius’s song of the Greek νόστος (return), of course, mirrors the plot of the Odyssey itself, which has opened only a few hundred lines before with the plea to the Muse to sing of Odysseus and his companions’ return (νόστος, 1.5) from Troy.1 Penelope, however, interrupts the narrative flow and asks the bard to cease singing because of the pain his tale is causing her (1.340–342): ‘ταύτης δ᾽ ἀποπαύε᾽ ἀοιδῆς λυγρῆς, ἥ τέ μοι αἰεὶ ἐνὶ στήθεσσι φίλον κῆρ τείρει .
    [Show full text]
  • Artemis Und Der Weg Der Frauen Von Der Geburt Bis Zur Mutterschaft Am Beispiel Von Kulten Auf Der Peloponnes
    ARTEMIS UND DER WEG DER FRAUEN VON DER GEBURT BIS ZUR MUTTERSCHAFT AM BEISPIEL VON KULTEN AUF DER PELOPONNES INAUGURAL-DISSERTATION ZUR ERLANGUNG DER DOKTORWÜRDE DER PHILOSOPHISCHEN FAKULTÄT I DER JULIUS-MAXIMILIANS-UNIVERSITÄT WÜRZBURG VORGELEGT VON MARIA GENNIMATA AUS THESSALONIKI (WÜRZBURG 2006) ERSTGUTACHTER: PROFESSOR DR. U. SINN ZWEITGUTACHTER: PROFESSORIN DR. R. LINDNER (†) TAG DES KOLLOQUIUMS: 18.07.2006 INHALT Vorwort ..................................................................................................................................... 7 Abkürzungsverzeichnis ........................................................................................................... 11 Einleitung – Forschungsstand ................................................................................................. 17 Methodischer Ansatz............................................................................................................... 33 I. BEISTAND DER ARTEMIS VON DER GEBURT BIS ZUR MUTTERSCHAFT: FUNKTIONS- EPIKLESEN JENSEITS DER PELOPONNES 1. GEBURT UND WOCHENBETT 1.1. Chitone, Kithone................................................................................................. 45 1.1.1. Literarische und epigraphische Belege ................................................... 45 1.1.2. Die rituelle Praxis der Kleiderweihe ....................................................... 47 1.2. Dynatera ............................................................................................................. 48 1.3. Eileithyia............................................................................................................
    [Show full text]