Etiek En Toeskouerskap Deur Die Lens Van Michael Haneke Se Amour
Total Page:16
File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb
LitNet Akademies Jaargang 15, Nommer 2, 2018, ISSN 1995-5928 Verantwoordelike rolprentvervaardiging: etiek en toeskouerskap deur die lens van Michael Haneke se Amour Dian Weys Dian Weys, onafhanklike navorser Opsomming Aangesien ons moderne samelewing deur die media oorweldig word, stel Michael Haneke voor dat filmmakers ‘n verantwoordelikheid het om gehore aan te moedig om aan ‘n film se betekenisskeppingproses deel te neem, veral wanneer dit kom by die uitbeelding van geweld. Wat behels hierdie verantwoordelikheid? Stanley Cavell verduidelik dat, omdat toeskouers tydens die filmkykproses onsigbaar is, film ‘n beroep op ons moderne begeerte doen, nie vir mag oor die wêreld nie, maar eerder die wens om nie mag nodig te hê nie en om nie die laste van ‘n ander te dra nie. Dit is ‘n probleem, glo ek, veral wanneer iemand anders se werklike swaarkry en lyding as bronmateriaal gebruik word, omdat filmmakers dié werklike ervaring wederregtelik in besit neem vir vermaaklikheidsonthalwe. Indien die filmkykproses ons kwytskeld daarvan om die laste van die wêreld te dra en dus verligting bied van die opneem van verantwoordelikheid, argumenteer ek dat ons nie mag wens om nie die laste van iemand anders te dra nie. Ons is, soos Emmanuel Levinas argumenteer, verantwoordelik vir mekaar. Hoe poog Haneke om, tegnies gewys, sy gehore bewus te maak van hierdie verantwoordelikheid? Judith Butler sê dat ‘n begrip van verantwoordelikheid net bereik kan word wanneer ‘n ek-heid die perke van selfkennis erken. Daarom, indien ons, soos Butler sê, net bewus kan raak van die ondeursigtigheid eie aan ons menswees wanneer ons gekonfronteer word met die ondeursigtigheid van ‘n ander, argumenteer ek dat Haneke, deur sy fragmentariese aanslag ten opsigte van die beeld, redigering en klank, sy gehoor in verwantskap plaas met ‘n film wat hul met die perke van hul selfkennis konfronteer. Sodoende word sy filmgehoor in staat gestel om ‘n etiese posisie in te neem. Ek gebruik Amour regdeur my bespreking om Haneke se verantwoordelikheid as filmregisseur te illustreer, naamlik om sy gehoor nie net met die onverhaalbaarheid van ‘n ander se swaarkry te konfronteer nie, maar ook om sy gehoor tot verantwoording te roep. Trefwoorde: Amour; Butler, Judith; Cavell, Stanley; etiek; Haneke, Michael; Levinas, Emmanuel; verantwoordelike rolprentvervaardiging 16 LitNet Akademies Jaargang 15, Nommer 2, 2018, ISSN 1995-5928 Abstract Responsible filmmaking: ethics and spectatorship through the lens of Michael Haneke’s Amour An established theme in the films of Michael Haneke is the role, influence and ubiquity of the media in modern society. Before a screening of Benny’s video in 1995, Haneke (2010:579) explained how the sheer mass of media has resulted in a situation where the ―absolute equivalency of all the contents stripped of their reality ensures the universal fictionality of anything shown‖, turning the spectator into ―spineless consumer[s] of empty, interchangeable forms‖. In a world oversaturated with various forms of media, Haneke addresses the responsibility of the filmmaker: How do I give the viewer the chance to recognize this loss of reality and his implication in it, thus emancipating him from being a victim of the medium to its potential partner? The question is not: ―What am I allowed to show?‖ but rather: ―What chance do I give the viewer to recognize what it is I am showing?‖ How does Haneke‘s position influence his own approach to filmmaking, especially when the film in question, Amour, is based on the real pain and suffering of one of Haneke‘s own family members? Is there not a danger of appropriating the real suffering of another for entertainment‘s sake? In response to Haneke‘s address and the problem of representing violence, this article is guided by two broad questions in order to explore and formulate the responsibility of the filmmaker. Firstly, in the context of the ubiquity of the media, why is it important to make films responsibly and, secondly, how does Haneke assume his responsibility as a filmmaker for both his subject matter and his audience? Guided by the work of Stanley Cavell, Emmanuel Levinas and Judith Butler, I use Haneke‘s film Amour as a lens through which to address these two broad questions, after which I return to Haneke‘s call to give the viewer the chance to ―recognize‖ what is shown. I illustrate how Haneke‘s responsibility as a filmmaker enables the audience to recognise the opacity of someone else‘s pain and suffering, which, in effect, enables them to respond to Anne‘s suffering on their own terms and become responsible for the viewing situation. To answer the first question, I focus on two specific scenes in Amour to illustrate, firstly, the invisible position of the spectator and, secondly, how the spectator‘s invisibility relieves him or her of responsibility during the act of viewing. I explore the ontology of film by drawing from the work of Stanley Cavell, who theorises that a photograph is not a replica, copy, surface or handmade version of reality, but rather that a photograph is manufactured, and that what is manufactured is ―an image of the world‖ (1979:20). If film, according to Cavell (1979:72), is ―a succession of automatic world projections‖, how does the manufacturedness of film, which presents an image of the world (instead of the world itself), influence or position its audience? After the opening scene of Amour, when the police break into the Laurents‘ apartment and find Anne‘s decomposing body, Haneke holds a long shot of a filling auditorium as spectators settle down for a piano recital. This reflexive scene reflects our own, the film audience‘s, position. Similar to the audience watching a piano recital, we, too, are going to watch a production: we are going to watch a film that will show how the woman from the previous scene died. There is, however, a great difference between us and 17 LitNet Akademies Jaargang 15, Nommer 2, 2018, ISSN 1995-5928 the audience of the piano recital. The piano player is in the presence of the audience and vice versa. While the world of the film is present to us, however, we, as the audience of Amour, are not present to it – the world of the film does not know that we are watching it. In other words, as Cavell (1979:24) says, the film ―screens [us] from the world it holds – that is, makes [us] invisible‖. By permitting us to view the world unseen, Cavell (1979:40) argues that the act of viewing satisfies a deep, modern desire, which is ―not a wish for power over creation, [...] but a wish not to need power, not to have to bear its burdens‖. If the act of viewing relieves us of responsibility, then I argue that, on the contrary, we cannot wish not to bear the burdens of another, because we are responsible for one another. In keeping with Cavell‘s revisionist approach, I turn to Emmanuel Levinas, who argues that ethics is the ―calling into question of my spontaneity by the presence of the Other‖ (1969:43), which, for him, is signalled by the approach of the face. When Georges and Anne have breakfast the next morning, Anne becomes unresponsive and suffers a stroke. Georges tries to get her attention, takes her face into his hands and draws her closer. The approach of the face, for Levinas (in Kearney 1986:23–4), is ―the most basic mode of responsibility‖, which signifies that we are endlessly and boundlessly responsible for one another. I use Georges‘s responsibility towards Anne as a metaphor of Haneke‘s responsibility towards his audience, since both take responsibility for her: Georges in the ways in which he takes care of her and Haneke by way of representation. Since our responsibility for one another is, according to Levinas, formed pre-ontologically, I argue that we usurp the place of the Other when we watch films that are generated at the cost of real, horrific and violent experiences that provide material for our viewing pleasure. If our responsibility for one another is formed pre- ontologically, then our responsibility cannot be suspended during the act of viewing. How does Haneke assume responsibility for both the representation of Anne‘s suffering and his (invisible) audience and, by implication, make his audience responsible in return? To answer the broad second question, I draw from Haneke‘s own article in which he outlines his approach to filmmaking in terms of editing, image and sound, and from the work of Judith Butler. Butler argues that a theory of subject formation that ―acknowledges the limits of self- knowledge can serve a conception of ethics and, indeed, responsibility‖ (2005:19). Since an acknowledgement of the opacity of a subject is a prerequisite for responsibility, how does Haneke, through his use of editing, image and sound, imbue Anne‘s suffering with opacity and, thereby, admit that he cannot represent Anne‘s suffering in its totality? Haneke‘s approach to editing and images departs from standard Hollywood practices or, as Mark Cousins terms it, closed romantic realism. With average shot lengths that are up to ten times longer than those of mainstream films, and with Anne‘s slow deterioration being shown in fragments, interspersed with pauses and rests, Haneke eschews clarity and lucidity and, instead, opts for an opaque representation. Furthermore, while most films use music to prescribe the audience with specific emotions, Haneke avoids a non-diegetic soundtrack. When he uses diegetic music, however, Haneke ruptures the music mid-note. In addition, his use of silences and off-screen spaces enables the audience to imagine Anne‘s suffering for themselves. All of these aspects imbue her suffering with opacity and, in effect, encourage the audience to take a part in the film‘s meaning-making process.