<<

Philosophy of Science Association

How to Remain (Reasonably) Optimistic: Scientific Realism and the "Luminiferous Ether" Author(s): John Worrall Source: PSA: Proceedings of the Biennial Meeting of the Philosophy of Science Association, Vol. 1994, Volume One: Contributed Papers (1994), pp. 334-342 Published by: The University of Chicago Press on behalf of the Philosophy of Science Association Stable URL: http://www.jstor.org/stable/193038 Accessed: 17/05/2010 09:34

Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of JSTOR's Terms and Conditions of Use, available at http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp. JSTOR's Terms and Conditions of Use provides, in part, that unless you have obtained prior permission, you may not download an entire issue of a journal or multiple copies of articles, and you may use content in the JSTOR archive only for your personal, non-commercial use.

Please contact the publisher regarding any further use of this work. Publisher contact information may be obtained at http://www.jstor.org/action/showPublisher?publisherCode=springer.

Each copy of any part of a JSTOR transmission must contain the same copyright notice that appears on the screen or printed page of such transmission.

JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide range of content in a trusted digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and facilitate new forms of scholarship. For more information about JSTOR, please contact [email protected].

Springer, The University of Chicago Press, Philosophy of Science Association are collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend access to PSA: Proceedings of the Biennial Meeting of the Philosophy of Science Association.

http://www.jstor.org How to Remain (Reasonably) Optimistic: Scientific Realism and the "Luminiferous Ether"

John Worrall

London School of Economics

1. Laudan on the "Non-Referring"but Empirically Successful "Optical Ether"

In the course of his forceful (1981) attack on "convergent realism", LarryLaudan attemptedto turn an influential pro-realistconsideration on its head. Scientific realists have wondered how a theory could enjoy the sort of empirical predictive success ex- hibited by presently accepted theories in the "mature"sciences, and yet be radically wrong in what it claims is going on "behind"the empirical phenomena. If nothing like the electrons and other particles postulated by currentphysics exists, how can the theo- ries that there are such things have made the great range of successful predictions that they do about phenomena observed in particle accelerators and the like? Laudandi- rects such realists to the history of science and to a list of "once successful" theories which are "(by present lights) non-referring"-a list of successful theories which gave a "central"role to notions that, according to theories we accept now, do not exist (1981, 26). He supposes, apparentlyquite reasonably, that, whatever account of"ap- proximate truth"the realist relies on (and, notoriously, there is as yet no generally ac- cepted formal account on offer), that account will entail that a theory involving central terms with no referentcannot be "approximatelytrue". (But see section 4.) He claims, then, that, in view of the history of science, this realist consideration is self-defeating. If, as the realist recommends, we hold that presently accepted theories (in the "mature" sciences) are approximatelytrue, then it follows that these earlier theories were radi- cally false, despite their predictive success. The empirical success of presently accept- ed theories can, then, hardly be used as an argumentfor their approximatetruth.

Laudan's argument seems especially strong because it hits, not at particularrealist arguments, but directly at the realist's general, underlying intuitions. Laudan himself later described his (1981) as having

challenged the intuitions which motivate the realist enterprise by arguing .. that many (now discredited) scientific theories of earlier eras exhibited an impres- sive sort of empirical support, arguably no different in kind from that enjoyed by many contemporaryphysical theories. Yet we now believe that many of those earlier theories profoundly mischaracterized the way the world really is. More specifically, we now believe that there is nothing in the world which even

PSA 1994, Volume 1, pp. 334-342 Copyright ? 1994 by the Philosophy of Science Association 335 approximately answers to the central explanatory entities postulated by a great many successful theories of the past (1984, 157)

Laudan's argument is, however, only as strong as the quality of his historical exam- ples of "once successful but (by present lights) nonreferring"theories. Some of the entries on his list (which he insisted could be extended "ad nauseam") are in fact strikingly unimpressive. He must have been working with some very loose notion of scientific "success" in order to count, for example, the vapid, truly etherial, conjec- tures of Hartley and LeSage even as having "enjoyed some measure of empirical suc- cess" (1981, 27). The argument needs examples of theories which were successful in the genuinely predictive sense. We know that any theory can be made to have correct empirical consequences by "writing those consequences into" it; the cases that have traditionally induced realist-inclinations in even the most hard-headedare cases of theories, designed with one set of data in mind, that have turned out to predict entirely unexpectedly some furthergeneral phenomenon. Laudan himself gives special em- phasis to the one item on his list that seems unambiguously to fit this bill - Fresnel's theory of light and its associated elastic-solid "luminiferous ether".

It would be difficult to argue that Fresnel's theory counts as "immature"science; and impossible to deny that it was impressively successful predictively. Aside from the much-rehearsedcase of the light spot at the centre of the shadow of a small opaque disc (for the real story of this case see my 1989), Fresnel's theory of the wave surface inside biaxial crystals turnedout to predict the existence of internal and external coni- cal refraction. Fresnel never realised that these latter predictions follow from his theo- ry; and the phenomena themselves were not even thought of, let alone known to occur, until, after Fresnel's death, they were derived from the theory by William Rowan Hamilton (1833) and confirmed experimentally by HumphreyLloyd (1833).

So there is at least one theory on Laudan's list that was unambiguously successful. And, so Laudan asserts, that theory "centrally"involved a notion denied any real ref- erent by theories subsequently accepted in science. Within Fresnel's theory "the opti- cal ether functioned centrally in explanations of reflection, refraction, interference, double refraction, diffraction, and "(1981,27); but Maxwell's theory and then the General Theory of Relativity entail that there is just no such thing as Fresnel's elastic optical ether. According to these later theories, light "in fact" con- sists of vibrations of the electromagnetic field, a field which is "sui generis", explicit- ly not a manifestation of the contortions of some underlying material medium. (As is well known, Maxwell himself tried hard to produce a "mechanical model" for the field-that is, to explain the field in terms of some underlying material medium. But his failure in this attempt, and the failure of his contemporaries and successors, led to the acceptance of what might be called the "mature"version of Maxwell's theory- a theory that sees the field as a "primitive"part of the furnitureof the universe.)

The case of Fresnel's theory of the elastic ether poses, then, via Laudan's argu- ment, a sharp challenge for the realist-a primafacie strong historical reason to be "pessimistic" about the likely fate of currently accepted theories. Two realist respons- es to the challenge are possible: (i) deny that the ether played a "central"role in Fresnel's theorising, and (ii) deny that the ether has in fact been rejected by later sci- ence. Both of these strategies have found interesting particularinstantiations in the recent literature-in Hardinand Rosenberg (1982) and in Kitcher (1992). Both ac- counts see the two, apparentlyquite different, strategies as in fact closely interrelated.

I argue (in sections 2 and 3 respectively) that neither realist strategy succeeds. Each does, however, point to importantfeatures of the logical relationship between 336 Fresnel's theory and the theories that later replaced it. In section 4 I argue that, when that logical relationship is properly described and its consequences fully drawn out, although this case of a theory-shift is inconsistent with scientific realism as normally construed, it "confirms" a view that has been called structural realism. This was first developed by Poincar6 (and is very different from the sort of anti-realismthat is usu- ally attributedto him). In fact, Poincar--who fully anticipated the "pessimistic in- duction" argument-used exactly this historical case of the shift from Fresnel's elastic ether to Maxwell's electromagnetic field theory as the chief illustrationof his general view of the aim and status of theories. Structuralrealism encourages an optimistic in- duction from the history of theory-change in science, but an optimistic induction con- cerning the discovery of mathematical structure ratherthan individual ontology.

2. Did the "Luminiferous Ether" Really Play a Central Role in the Success of Fresnel's Theory?

It can't, I think, sensibly be denied that Fresnel believed in the the ether as a real, material medium. He refers to such a material medium explicitly (and in explicitly "realist"terms) at various points in his scientific work. For example, in his famous (1818) "Prize Memoir" on diffraction, he characterisedthe general problem of diffrac- tion as follows : "Given the intensities and the relative positions of any number of systems of light of the same , propagatingin the same direction, to determine the intensity of the vibrations resulting from the concourse of these differ- ent systems, that is to say, the velocity of the oscillations of the molecules of the ether" (248). In his (1822, 136) he stated that the properties of polarised light are sim- ply explained on his theory "by supposing that, in light waves, the oscillations of the molecules of the ether are executed at right angles to the rays".

It doesn't however follow that the ether played a "centralrole" in his theory. Indeed the standard view in history of science-following Whittaker'sinfluential treatment-is that Fresnel's account of ether-dynamics, was pure window-dressing: whatever Fresnel's own beliefs, the heuristic impetus for his theoretical work came from mathematical considerations-the mechanical-dynamical considerations at- tached themselves only later, only unsuccessfully and certainly without any indepen- dent empirical success. Charting Fresnel's route to his theory of the wave-surface in birefringentcrystals, Whittakerremarked (1951,119):

Having ... arrived at his result by reasoning of a purely geometrical character, [Fresnel] now devised a dynamical scheme to suit it.

(A similar claim that Fresnel's ether played no "generative"role in the development of his theory of polarisation is made in Buchwald 1989.) No realist should advocate a "realist attitude"towards all theoreticalclaims-even theoreticalclaims within successful theories. Some play no effective role and are, in Kitcher's (1992) terminology, "presuppositional". (Newton's assumptionthat the cen- tre of mass of the universe is at absolute rest is surely a case in point.) If the standard story were correct, then the realist would be justified in claiming that, since the material ether was a "merely presuppositionalposit", and since he holds no brief for such no- tions, the eventual rejection of that materialether representsno threatto his position.

The claim that the ether was "central"figures as a bald, unsubstantiatedassertion in Laudan's paper unaccompanied by either analysis or argument. Nonetheless it is, I believe, correct or at any rate correct enough to block this escape route for the realist. I cannot argue the case fully here, but detailed analysis (forthcoming) shows that the 337 suggestion that the material ether was an idle component in Fresnel's system is signif- icantly misleading. Whittakerclaims, for example, that "geometrical reasoning" led the way in Fresnel's development of the wave surface in birefringent crystals. However, this "geometrical reasoning" itself did not spring from nowhere, but was based on Hooke's law, Huygens's principle, the principle of superposition ("coexis- tence of small movements") and other assumptions of a general mechanical kind. Moreover, although Fresnel's extension to cover all crystals of Huygens's famous sphere/spheroidconstruction for the two refracted beams can be characterisedmathe- matically as a process of putting two equations together (by introducing three parame- ters for Huygens's two), that process was in turn undoubtedly guided by Fresnel's "re- alist" belief that there could only be one light-carrying medium and the "natural"as- sumption that, in the general case, the coefficients of elasticity of that medium in the three orthogonal directions in space will be different. Fresnel did get some important heuristic mileage out of certain general mechanical-dynamical ideas concerning some sort of mechanical medium with some sort of vibrating parts.

Whittakerand others are, I believe, wrong: Fresnel did not first operate geometri- cally and only later "interpret"his theory dynamically. Rather than two separate stages, Fresnel was, I think, working all the time with a mix of basic mechanical ideas, mathematics and known experimental results. (This is surely generally true in theoret- ical physics.) He arrived at an account of light as a wave motion in a mechanical medium possessing certain general properties in accord with the known principles of dynamics. This account was dramaticallysuccessful empirically. He (and his succes- sors) made various attempts to strengthen the account into a fully-fledged dynamical theory in which everything would follow from a "natural","unified" account of the forces operating on the ether particles. These attempts were, however, immediately re- futed (or if you prefer, immediately ran into some notable and stubbornanomalies).

The problems with the attempts to strengthen the theory of the wave surface into a fully-fledged dynamical theory of the ether are well-known: the most famous being the problem of the longitudinal wave. Although Fresnel continued to talk about the etherial "fluid" even after he became convinced that the oscillations of the medium are transverse to the direction of propagation of the wave, he was fully aware that transversalitymeant that the medium had to have resistance to shear (and this makes it, at least according to later terminology, unambiguously an elastic solid). "Ordinary"elastic solids are resistant both to shear and to compression, and hence transmit both transverse and longitudinal waves. Fresnel took it that his and Arago's experimental results on the interference of polarised light establish that no longitudi- nal component plays any role in optical effects. What happens to the longitudinal wave in the elastic solid ether? Fresnel simply hypothesised it away. He assumed that the ether must be infinitely (or "near infinitely") resistant to compression so that the longitudinal wave travels at infinite or "near infinite" velocity and so can some- how be ignored. Unfortunately hypothesising the longitudinal wave away once is not enough: even when you have got, or rather have given yourself, a purely , it ought on mechanical principles to develop a longitudinal component again whenever it meets the boundaryof a medium of a different optical density. So you have to keep on hypothesising away such longitudinal components. That is, you have to keep on violating the laws of mechanics.

The intractablityof this and other problems and their role in leading eventually to a replacementtheory is what lies behind Whittaker'streatment (and those of Hardinand Rosenberg and of Kitcher). But this representsillicit use of hindsight:there was, of course, no reason to believe back in 1821, say, that those problems would prove in- tractable. There certainly was reason in 1821 (when Fresnel completed his paper on the 338 form of the wave-surface in biaxial crystals) to regardthe ether as problematic. But-as is now generally recognised following the work of Kuhn, Lakatosand others-the high- est-level, most interestingparts of theoreticalscience are invariablyproblematic, when examined closely. If the realist is in the business of advocatinga realist attitudeonly to- ward entirely unproblematictheories, then realism is indeed restrictedin scope.

If my claims about Fresnel's theoretical work are at all correct, then the realist still faces a threat from this case, and cannot convincingly hide behind the problems that Fresnel's basic theory of the ether undoubtedly faced. The elastic-solid ether played a problematic, but nonetheless somewhat positive role, so the realist had better have something positive to say about it.

3. Was Fresnel Talking about Electromagnetic Waves all Along?

Hardin and Rosenberg (1982) make the, at first glance audacious, claim that the "something positive" the realist can say about the ether is that, contrary to Laudan, we still believe it to exist: the realist can justifiably view Fresnel as talking about the electromagnetic field all along when he used the term "ether". They concede (p.611) that this account of reference "severs it from the detailed beliefs of' Fresnel. Indeed, this is hardly a question of detail: Fresnel could scarcely have believed that he was referring to an entity which was first thought of only some decades after his death! Hardin and Rosenberg point out-citing the problems faced by the elastic ether -that various features of Fresnel's accounts of optical phenomena undoubtedly sit more easily with Maxwell's field theory than with his own notion of an elastic solid. And they argue (613-4) that, given this and given the "continuity of causal role" stretching from Fresnel's ether to Maxwell's field and beyond, a realist can reasonably regard Fresnel as referring to the electromagnetic field when he used the term "ether":

Looking back across the range of theories from Fresnel to Einstein, we see a constant causal role being played in all of them; that causal role we now as- cribe to the electromagnetic field. One permissible strategy of the realist is to let reference follow causal role. It seems not unreasonable,then, for realists to say that 'ether' referred to the electromagnetic field all along.

But in fact, the causal role is only "constant"if we ignore certain inconvenient fea- tures of the earlier theory: for example, the elastic solid ether ought to have had the ef- fect of slowing down the planets as they moved through it. If we are allowed to be similarly selective in other cases, there seems equally to be a "constantcausal role" be- tween, say, Aristotle's notion of a body's desire to be in its naturalplace and Einstein's notion of a body moving along a geodesic in curved space-time; or between the seven- teenth century notion of a witch and twentieth century notions of sufferers from mental illnesses of various kinds. If it is "not unreasonable... for realists to say that 'ether' re- ferred to the electromagnetic field all along", it seems equally to fail to be unreason- able to say that "desire for its naturalplace" refers to "necessity to move along a geodesic" or to say that "witch" (sometimes) refers to "suffererfrom certain kinds of mental illness". The causal role in explaining certain kinds of "odd" behaviour that was attributedin the seventeenth century to a person's being a witch is certainly now attributedto mental afflictions of various kinds. Laudan makes much the same point in his (1984)-taking it to be a severe embarrassmentfor Hardinand Rosenberg's ac- count (whether or not it really is an embarrassmentwill be considered in section 4).

Philip Kitcher's (1993) treatmentof this issue has a similar theme, though with in- teresting variations. Kitcher concedes that Fresnel's term "ether"fails to refer, but suggests (1993, 147) that Fresnel's tokens of the term "light wave" nonetheless do 339 refer. Fresnel undoubtedly believed that such waves were waves in his elastic medium but, so Kitcher claims, since Fresnel's "dominantintention" was "thatof talking about the wavelike features of light, however they happen to be realized", it is reasonable, in view of what science now tells us, to take tokens of that term (or perhaps most of them) as "genuinely refer[ring] to electromagnetic waves of high "(146).

So far as the ether itself is concerned, Kitcher asks if "the schemata employed by Fresnel and other wave theorists of the early and middle nineteenth century contain ineliminable commitments to the ether?"; and, concluding that they do not, infers that "[t]he ether is a prime example of a presuppositional posit" (1993, 149). I have sug- gested that the ether was in fact a problematic, but certainly non-idle notion in Fresnel's approach. Fresnel got real heuristic assistance from ideas of a general me- chanical kind. But are those ideas nonetheless "eliminable"? Can't the principle of superposition, Hooke's law and the other assumptions that Fresnel used be cut off from their original mechanical bearings and be re-clothed in the terms of some other theoretical framework?

If this is a question about logical possibilities ratherthan possibilities practically available to Fresnel and his contemporaries,then the answer is of course "yes". But if "ineliminability"requires that there be no other theory that explains the phenomenaat issue then no theory, no theoretical notion, is ineliminable. In cases such as this one where we are considering a theory that was later replaced, no recourseneed be had to ab- stract ideas about "underdetermination"in orderto establish this: the replacingtheory it- self forms a constructiveproof of the "eliminability"of the earlierone. Maxwell's theo- ry of the electromagneticfield shows that the role that Fresnel believed could only be played by a materialmedium can also be played by the field. A realistcommitted to a realist attitudetoward only ineliminable notions faces no problemfrom the history of science, but then he has no position to defend. In orderto count as any sort of realism, a position must entail something positive about Fresnel's ether despite its "eliminability". 4. Fresnel and Maxwell: the Ether, the Field and "StructuralRealism"

The above remarks notwithstanding, there is in much that I agree with in the posi- tions of Hardin and Rosenberg and of Kitcher. Both accounts point to importantfea- tures of the relationship between Fresnel's ether theory and its successors. However neither account gets this relationship quite right because each seeks to defend a stronger version of realism than is, I believe, really defensible.

It is, so the realist wants to claim, vastly improbable that a theory should score the sort of extensive empirical success scored by presently accepted theories in the "ma- ture sciences" and yet not have somehow "latched on to" how things are "underneath" the empirical phenomena. To defend this intuitive claim against cases of theory- change, the realist needs to show that, from the point of view of the later theory, the fundamental claims of the earlier theory (in so far as they played integral roles in that theory's empirical success) were-though false-nonetheless in some clear sense "approximately correct". He needs to show that, from the point of view of the later theory, we can still explain the success enjoyed by the earlier one.

A naturalassumption is that such an explanation requires a demonstrationeither that the parts of the earlier theory rejected by the later one were redundantor that no real "rejection"was involved (but only a "re-description"). However, in this particu- lar historical case at least, the most straightforwardand least revisionary account of the explanation of the success of the earlier theory provided by its successor fits nei- ther of those patterns. 340

For convenience (and temporarily)freeze the history of science at the point where the "mature"(non-medium-based) version of Maxwell's theory had been accepted. From that vantage point, there is an easy explanation of the success of Fresnel's elas- tic-ether theory of light-one which requires no Whiggish "reinterpretation"of Fresnel's thought. From the later point of view, Fresnel clearly misidentified the na- ture of light, but his theory nonetheless accurately described not just light's observ- able effects but also its structure. There is no elastic-solid ether of the kind Fresnel's theory (problematically but nonetheless importantly) involved; but there is an electro- magnetic field. The field is not underpinnedby a mechanical ether and in no clear sense "approximates"it. Similarly there are no "light waves" in Fresnel's sense, since these were supposed to consist of motions of material ether-particles. Nonetheless disturbances in Maxwell's field do obeyformally similar (in fact, and unusually, mathematically identical) laws to some of those obeyed by the "materially"entirely different elastic disturbances in a mechanical medium.

Unless-surely very much in the spirit of anti-realism-we think of these theoreti- cal notions as characterisedby their observable effects, then we have to allow that Fresnel's most basic ontological claim that the vibrations making up light are vibra- tions of real material ether particles subject to elastic restoring forces was entirely wrong. A displacement currentin a sui generis electromagnetic field and a mechani- cal vibration transmittedfrom particle to particle are more like "chalk and cheese" than are real chalk and cheese. But if Fresnel was as wrong as he could have been about what oscillates, he was right, not just about the optical phenomena, but right also that those phenomena depend on the oscillations of something or other at right angles to the light. His theory was more than empirically adequate, but less than true; instead it was structurally correct. There is an important"carry-over" from Fresnel to Maxwell, one at a "higher"level than the merely empirical, but it is a carry over of structure ratherthan content. Both Fresnel's and Maxwell's theories make the pas- sage of light consist of wave forms transmittedfrom place to place, forms obeying the same mathematics. Hence, although the periodic changes which the two theories postulate are ontologically of radically different sorts-in one material particles change position, in the other field strengths change-there is nonetheless a structural, mathematical continuity between the two theories.

All this is reflected in the fact that if you perform the following meta-level opera- tion on Fresnel's theory you "turnit into" a genuine sub-theory of Maxwell's:

Go through Fresnel's theory and, wherever he talks about a molecule of the ether's being forced away from its equilibrium position, replace that talk by talk of a forced change in the electromagnetic field strength.

(Another way to put this is that if you go throughFresnel's theory and replace the no- tion of a molecule's being forced from its equilibriumposition by a theory-neutralterm such as "optical disturbance"; and then reinterpret"optical disturbance"as "forced vi- brationof the electromagneticfield" then what you get is a sub-theory of Maxwell.)

Nothing "Whiggish" is being perpetratedhere: I do not assert-indeed I explicitly deny-that this is what Fresnel's theory "really" amounted to "all along". What you get as a result of this process is not Fresnel's theory but a structurallyidenticalfac- simile of it. But it's the fact that this facsimile is entailed by the later theory that ex- plains why, from the vantage point of the later theory, the empirical predictive success of Fresnel's theory was no lucky accident. 341 This account, in terms of the "ontological" falsity, but structuralcorrectness of Fresnel's theory, might appear insufficiently different from those of Hardinand Rosenberg and of Philip Kitcher to justify the fuss. But let's think through what their claims that Fresnel was "really" talking about the field or waves in it "all along" really mean. If those claims mean just that the entity that "really"plays the causal role in producing a given range of phenomena that Fresnel attributedto a highly attenuated elastic medium is-according to the science of the later nineteenth century- the elec- tromagnetic field, then it is of course no more than the truth. (Just in the same sense that Aristotle was-according to twentieth century science-referring to bodies mov- ing along geodesics in spacetime when he talked about bodies seeking their natural place.) But the conditional characterof such judgments is, of course, crucial. The judgments are always theory-dependent. If we ask in turn what is the "real"referent of Maxwell's term "electromagnetic field", the question can again only be answered within the context of the theories accepted at some given time. The answer according to currently accepted theories is a quantum field carrying probability waves-a notion radically different from anything envisaged by Maxwell himself, perhapseven more radically different from it (if we can make sense of such comparisons) than Maxwell's own notion of field is from Fresnel's notion of the elastic ether. (It seems to be a his- torical accident -of no more than conventional significance-that science happens to continue to use the word "field" whereas, on the whole, it has droppedthe term "ether".) Since the "continuity of causal role" to which Hardinand Rosenberg appeal now extends beyond Maxwell, presumably they must allow that what Fresnel was re- ally "really"referring to "all along" was the quantumfield carryingprobability waves. Or rather -since this theory may of course itself eventually be replaced-that we don't know what the real "real referent"of Fresnel's notion the "ether"is. What we do know is that there was a certain structuralor syntactic continuity between the theories of Fresnel and Maxwell (and again-though this time involving the "correspondence principle"-between Maxwell's and the quantumtheory of "the"field).

It was exactly this point that Poincare had in mind when he said that both Fresnel's notion of an elastic vibration and Maxwell's notion of displacement currentare

merely names of the images we substituted for the real objects which Nature will hide for ever from our eyes (1905, 162)

Poincar6 insisted that adopting this view

cannot be said [to amount to] reducing physical theories to simple practical recipes [i.e. to instrumentalism]; [Fresnel's] equations express relations, and if the equations remain true [better; "are preserved in the later theory"], it because the relations preserve their reality ....The true relations ....are the only reality we can attain. (ibid)

Poincare did not think of himself as proposing a restriction of a strongerview about theories and their relation to the world, but ratheras pointing out that, in view of the fact that in science we can never "get outside" of our theories but only view reality through those theories we currently accept, this structuralversion is the only view (the only version of "realism") that makes any sense.

If the switch from Fresnel to Maxwell is typical (and I have given no reason in this paper to think it is), then-against the currently fashionable "pessimistic induc- tion"-there are (inductive) grounds for optimism, optimism that science is progress- ing towards a correct account of the universe, but that progress is at the structural, ratherthan the "ontological" level. If Poincare is correct, then any feeling that this is 342 less optimism than we could reasonably expect is based on a surely mistaken (but eas- ily adopted) view that we can somehow have direct access to the furnitureof the uni- verse, unmediated by our theories.

References

Buchwald, J.Z. (1989), The Rise of the WaveTheory of Light. Chicago and London: University of Chicago Press.

Fresnel, A.J. (1818), "Memoire Couronne sur la Diffraction" (page references to the reprintedversion in Fresnel Oeuvres Completes, I, Paris 1865).

?______. (1822), De la Lumiere. (page references to the reprintedversion in Fresnel Oeuvres Completes, I, Paris 1865).

Hamilton, W.R. (1833), "Essay on the Theory of Systems of Rays", Transactions of the Royal Irish Academy 17, 1833, 1.

Hardin, C.L. and Rosenberg, A. (1982), "In Defence of Convergent Realism", Philosophy of Science 49: 604-615

Kitcher, P. (1993), The Advancementof Science. Oxford and New York:Oxford University Press.

Laudan, L. (1981), "A Confutation of Convergent Realism", Philosophy of Science 48: 19-49.

_ _ _ _ _ . (1984), "Realism without the Real", Philosophy of Science 51, 156-62.

Lloyd, H. (1833), "On the Phenomena exhibited by Light in its passage along the axes of Biaxial Crystals", Transactions of the Royal Irish Academy 17, 145.

Poincare, H. ([1905] 1952), Science and Hypothesis. Originally published as Science et Hypothese (Paris:). New York: Dover.

Whittaker,E.T. (1951), A History of the Theories of Aether and Electricity. The Classical Theories. London: Thomas Nelson.

Worrall,J. (1989), "Fresnel, Poisson and the White Spot: the Role of Successful Predictions in the Acceptance of Scientific Theories" in D.Gooding et al (eds): The Uses of Experiment.Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.