The Point Mass As a Model for Epistemic Representation

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

The Point Mass As a Model for Epistemic Representation Dipartimento di Scienze Pure e Applicate Corso di Dottorato di Ricerca in Scienze di Base e Applicazioni Ph.D. Thesis THE POINT MASS AS A MODEL FOR EPISTEMIC REPRESENTATION. A HISTORICAL & EPISTEMOLOGICAL APPROACH Tutor: Candidate: Chiar.mo Prof. Vincenzo Fano Dott.ssa Antonella Foligno Curriculum Scienze della Complessità Ciclo XXX – A. A. 2016/2017 Settore Scientifico Disciplinare: M-FIL/02 To Martina and Giada If our highly pointed Triangles of the Soldier class are formidable, it may be readily inferred that far more formidable are our Women. For, if a Soldier is a wedge, a Woman is a needle; being, so to speak, all point, at least at the two extremities. Add to this the power of making herself practically invisible at will, and you will perceive that a Female, in Flatland, is a creature by no means to be trifled with. But here, perhaps, some of my younger Readers may ask how a woman in Flatland can make herself invisible. This ought, I think, to be apparent without any explanation. However, a few words will make it clear to the most unreflecting. Place a needle on the table. Then, with your eye on the level of the table, look at it side-ways, and you see the whole length of it; but look at it end-ways, and you see nothing but a point, it has become practically invisible. Just so is it with one of our Women. When her side is turned towards us, we see her as a straight line; when the end containing her eye or mouth – for with us these two organs are identical – is the part that meets our eye, then we see nothing but a highly lustrous point; but when the back is presented to our view, then – being only sublustrous, and, indeed, almost as dim as an inanimate object – her hinder extremity serves her as a kind of Invisible Cap. [E. A. Abbott, Flatland. A Romance in Many Dimensions, 1882] Mathematical truth, unlike a mathematical construction, is not something I can hope to find by introspection. It does not exist in my mind. A mathematical theory, like any other scientific theory is a social product. It is created and developed by the dialectical interplay of many minds, not just one mind. When we study the history of mathematics we do not find a mere accumulation of new definitions, new techniques, and new theorems. Instead, we find a repeated refinement and sharpening of old concepts and old formulations, gradually rising standard of rigor, and an impressive secular increase in generality and depth. Each generation of mathematicians rethinks the mathematics of the previous generation, discarding what was faddish or superficial or false and recasting what is still fertile into new and sharper form. [N. D. Goodman 1979, p. 545] Table of Contents Introduction 1 Chapter 1 Models for Scientific Representation 11 1. 1 The Structure of Scientific Theories 18 1. 2 Models and Model-Building Practice 31 1. 3 One Model for many purposes 41 Chapter 2 Ancient Mathematics 60 2. 1 A General Introduction to Ancient Mathematics: the methods and tools of Greek mathematicians 60 2. 2 The standard Euclidean geometry 65 2. 3 Towards a Heuristic tradition 78 2. 4 Archimedes and the Centres of Gravity 82 2. 5 The Method of Mechanical Theorems 90 2. 6 Floating Centres of Gravity 104 Chapter 3 The Renaissance Turns 109 3. 1 The ‘Restoration’ 113 3. 2 The rediscovery of Archimedes in the ‘School of Urbino’ 129 3. 3 Mathematical Humanism in the Renaissance 138 3. 4 Federico Commandino, Head of the Urbino School 140 3. 4. 1 The new Centre of Gravity 145 3. 5 Francesco Maurolico 151 3. 6 The Scientia de Ponderibus 155 3. 7 Guidobaldo del Monte: the new Archimedes? 162 3. 7. 1 Guidobaldo the Natural Philosopher 174 3. 8 Luca Valerio: the turn towards the mathematical analysis of physical states of affairs 187 Chapter 4 From Galileo to the Modern Turns 196 4. 1 Galileo Galilei: a Bridge to the Modern Mathematical Physics 203 4. 2 The Modern Turns 232 4. 2. 1 Hobbes: Abstraction and Idealization as Acts of Mind 234 4. 2. 2 Newton 242 4. 2. 3 Euler, Rational Mechanics and the Algebraic Representation of Physics 252 Conclusions 264 References 270 Acknowledgements 305 Introduction Any casual philosopher of science writing in the twentieth century cannot help but showcase the recurrent presence of Newton’s science of mechanics in introducing her diverging views on the nature of (physical) science. Newton’s Principia embodies a powerful and coherent research program for linking mathematical representations with real-world structures. A crucial passage where Newton himself expresses clearly what he is up to in his Principia occurs in a scholium to section 11 of the first book: In mathematics we are to investigate the quantities of forces with their proportions consequent upon any conditions supposed; then, when we enter upon physics [my emphasis], we compare those proportions with the phenomena of Nature, that we may know what conditions [or laws] of those forces answer to the several kinds of attractive bodies. And, this preparation being made, we argue more safely, concerning the physical species, causes and proportions of the forces.1 The first two books of his treatise deal with forces treated abstractly; they contain purely mathematical exercises in determining the implications of the laws of motion under different conditions. The investigation of all sorts of systematic relations which occur in physical phenomena is constructed by the means of mathematical models,2 which function as instruments of theoretical measurement, and which in turn allow the determination of parameters that characterise forces from parameters that characterise motion. In a later stage, or what Newton describes as “enter[ing] upon physics”, these models are put to use in the third book to measure the characteristics of the forces that can be found in our solar system. 1 Newton (1687) 1726, p. 218. In mathesi investigandae sunt virium quantitates et rationes illae, quae ex conditionibus quibuscunque positis consequentur: deinde, ubi in physicam descenditur conferendae sunt hac rationes cum phaenomenis; ut innotescat quaenam virium conditiones singulis corporum attractivorum generis competant. Et tum demum de virium speciebus, causis et rationibus physicistutius disputare licebit. 2 Hereafter, the terms ‘mathematical model’ and ‘mathematical object’ are used interchangeably. 1 This powerful methodology has the scope to function as an example for emphasising how the world could be formally defined with mathematical models, which can additionally be used for deductive reasoning, simplifying computations and mathematical proofs. Moreover, these models can also be used in physics for representational, explicative and predictive purposes. Examples of them include numbers, equations, functions, relations, and so on. Geometry too has its own mathematical objects, such as points, lines, planes, and solid figures. The philosophy of science deals with the ontological commitments relating to the nature of those objects. Are they mind-dependent objects arbitrarily produced by the scientific community for practical and speculative purposes? Or are they rather mind- independent objects, which have their own autonomy and existence? The fact that mathematics represents the best way we have today of representing the world in which we are embedded, allows us to use those objects – no matter what is the nature of their existence – as a model for representing physical phenomena in the natural world. They are also considered to be useful for mathematical manipulation and clarification, but they represent only idealized states which, strictly speaking, do not exist ontologically. To clarify this point, I suggest to the reader an example, which will also be the case study throughout the research presented in this dissertation. Let us look at the point mass3 as a mathematical entity which is used as a model for epistemic representational purposes of the phenomena under observation. First, let me define this entity with reference to its current definition taken from modern rational mechanics.4 3 The term ‘point mass’ can be found in the literature under several different expressions, including ‘material point’, ‘mass point’, ‘point particle’ and ‘point charge’. Hereafter the terms ‘material point’ and ‘point mass’ will be used synonymously in order to indicate either small bodies or their mathematical idealizations with the geometrically unextended point, or a point of a continuum model of matter. Of course the smallness in question refers to the extension of the space considered; for instance at the astronomical scale, the planets could be considered as punctiform. Moreover, I think that the expression ‘material point’ is not anachronistic, because it helps to refer to the materiality of the object, whilst at the same time the term ‘point mass’ is appropriate because of its explicit reference to mass. 4 The term ‘rational mechanics’ is used here in distinction from the mere mechanics of the past, in order to ensure that when we speak about modern mechanics, we are aware that statics, dynamics and kinematics 2 The material point – regarding its kinematic aspects (i.e. position, trajectory, velocity, acceleration, etc.) – could be considered as a geometrical point. However, under the action of a force it still should be considered as a natural body. Using this schematic representation it might be possible, on the one hand, to obtain the fundamental dynamic laws which underlie its behaviour; but on the other hand the material point’s dynamics will give us the fundamentals of mechanics. Therefore the laws of motion of any kind of body could be established just considering that body as an aggregate of material points.5 In this respect, the point mass is a theoretical and abstract entity which has dimensions that can be considered negligible when compared to a problem under examination.
Recommended publications
  • Vocabulary of PHILOSOPHY Vocabulary of PHILOSOPHY Version 1.1 (Last Updated : Apr
    - Institute for scientific and technical information - Vocabulary of PHILOSOPHY Vocabulary of PHILOSOPHY Version 1.1 (Last updated : Apr. 05, 2018) This resource contains 4435 entries grouped into 89 collections. Controlled vocabulary used for indexing bibliographical records for the "Philosophy" FRANCIS database (1972-2015, http://pascal-francis.inist.fr/ ). This vocabulary is browsable online at: https://www.loterre.fr Legend • Syn: Synonym. • →: Corresponding Preferred Term. • FR: French Preferred Term. • DE: German Preferred Term. • SC: Semantic Category. • DO: Domain. • URI: Concept's URI (link to the online view). This resource is licensed under a Creative Commons Attribution 4.0 International license: LIST OF ENTRIES List of entries English French Page • 10th century Xe siècle 176 • 11th - 13th centuries XIe - XIIIe siècles 176 • 11th century XIe siècle 176 • 12th -13th centuries XIIe - XIIIe siècles 176 • 12th century XIIe siècle 176 • 13th - 14th centuries XIIIe - XIVe siècles 176 • 13th - 15th centuries XIIIe - XVe siècles 176 • 13th century XIIIe siècle 176 • 14th - 15th centuries XIVe - XVe siècles 176 • 14th - 16th centuries XIVe - XVIe siècles 176 • 14th - 17th centuries XIVe - XVIIe siècles 176 • 14th century XIVe siècle 176 • 15th - 17th centuries XVe - XVIIe siècles 176 • 15th century XVe siècle 176 • 1656-1658 1656-1658 176 • 16th - 17th centuries XVIe - XVIIe siècles 176 • 16th - 18th centuries XVIe - XVIIIe siècles 176 • 16th - 20th centuries XVIe - XXe siècles 176 • 16th century XVIe siècle 176 • 1735-1985 1735-1985
    [Show full text]
  • John Pecham on Life and Mind Caleb G
    University of South Carolina Scholar Commons Theses and Dissertations 2014 John Pecham on Life and Mind Caleb G. Colley University of South Carolina - Columbia Follow this and additional works at: https://scholarcommons.sc.edu/etd Part of the Philosophy Commons Recommended Citation Colley, C. G.(2014). John Pecham on Life and Mind. (Doctoral dissertation). Retrieved from https://scholarcommons.sc.edu/etd/ 2743 This Open Access Dissertation is brought to you by Scholar Commons. It has been accepted for inclusion in Theses and Dissertations by an authorized administrator of Scholar Commons. For more information, please contact [email protected]. JOHN PECHAM ON LIFE AND MIND by Caleb Glenn Colley ! Bachelor of Arts Freed-Hardeman !University, 2006 Bachelor of Science Freed-Hardeman !University, 2006 Master of Liberal Arts ! Faulkner University, 2009 ! ! Submitted in Partial Fulfillment of the Requirements For the Degree of Doctor of Philosophy in Philosophy College of Arts and Sciences University of South Carolina 2014 Accepted by: Jeremiah M.G. Hackett, Major Professor Jerald T. Wallulis, Committee Member Heike O. Sefrin-Weis, Committee Member Gordon A. Wilson, Committee Member Lacy Ford, Vice Provost and Dean of Graduate Studies ! ! ! ! ! ! ! ! ! ! ! ! ! ! ! ! ! ! ! ! ! ! ! ! ! ! © Copyright by Caleb Glenn Colley, 2014 All Rights !Reserved. !ii ! ! ! ! DEDICATION To my parents, who have always encouraged and inspired me. Et sunt animae vestrae quasi mea. ! ! ! ! ! ! ! ! ! ! ! ! ! ! ! ! !iii ! ! ! ACKNOWLEDGEMENTS A number of people have spent generous amounts of time and energy to assist in the preparation of this dissertation. Professor Girard J. Etzkorn, the editor of Pecham’s texts, is not listed as a committee member, but he read my manuscript in its early form and made many helpful suggestions.
    [Show full text]
  • 3 Al-Farabi, Avicenna, and Averroes in Hebrew: Remarks on the Indirect Transmission of Arabic-Islamic Philosophy in Medieval Judaism
    3 Al-FArAbi, AvicennA, And Averroes in Hebrew: remArks on tHe indirect trAnsmission oF ArAbic-islAmic PHilosophy in medievAl JudAism James T. Robinson erhaps as early as the eighth century, in the Islamic East, the traditional Sanskrit tales about the Buddha’s enlightenment—about his recognition of his own mortality and training with an ascetic monk—were translated into Persian and Arabic. The Arabic version, entitled Bilawhar wa-Būdhāsaf, then served as Pthe basis for renderings into Georgian, Greek, Latin, Hebrew, and a long list of European vernacular languages.1 These renderings were, more often than not, not straightforward translations but adaptations, often introducing significant modifications into the frame narrative. The Greek version, for example, transformed Bilawhar—an ascetic teacher—into Barlaam, a saintly Christian monk, and his disciple Budasaf or Yudasaf—the Buddha—into Joasaph or Josaphat, a saintly Christian Neophyte.2 The Hebrew version is no less surprising than the Greek, when Bilawhar be- comes not a Jewish sage but a Neoplatonic philosopher, and his 1 For the Arabic and Persian versions, see D. Gimaret (1972); D. Gimaret (1971). See also S. M. Stern and S. Walzer (1971). For the Georgian and Greek versions, see: D. M. Lang (1957), idem (1966); John Damascene (1914). The Hebrew version was edited by A. M. Habermann (1951), with extensive apparatus and commentary. For the vernacular versions, see most recently the studies of the German and English versions: S. Calomino (1990); K. Ikegami (1999). 2 In fact, both Barlaam and Joasaph/Josaphat became Christian saints. 60 The Judeo-Christian-Islamic Heritage final lesson to his young disciple is not a lesson in religious prac- tice but an introduction to neoplatonic metaphysics, based on the Arabic versions of Plotinus—namely, that complex of texts associated with the Theology of Aristotle.3 This is one example of the indirect transmission of Greek and Arabic philosophy in medieval Judaism.
    [Show full text]
  • A Study on University Education of Medieval European Mathematicians 1K
    International Journal of Pure and Applied Mathematics Volume 116 No. 22 2017, 265-273 ISSN: 1311-8080 (printed version); ISSN: 1314-3395 (on-line version) url: http://www.ijpam.eu Special Issue ijpam.eu A Study on University Education of Medieval European Mathematicians 1K. Rejikumar and 2C.M. Indukala 1Deptment of Mathematics, N.S.S. College, Pandalam, Kerala, India. [email protected] 2University of Kerala, Palayam, Thiruvananthapuram, Kerala, India. [email protected] Abstract Higher educational institutions in a country play an important role in the cultural transformation of people. Its role in the coordination and strengthening of new knowledge and its proper dissemination in the community is an important factor in the development of any country. In this paper we compare the importance of role played by higher educational institutions in the development of Kerala School of Mathematics and European School of Mathematics. Key Words:Kerala school of mathematics, european school of mathematics, institutions of higher learning. 265 International Journal of Pure and Applied Mathematics Special Issue 1. Introduction The word university is originated from the Latin word “Universitas”, means the whole, the world or the universe. Before Universities were established, the main centers for education were monastic schools. Because of the increasing necessity for acquisition of knowledge, there happened the migration of cathedral schools to large cities. At the early stage Universities were consisted of a group of individuals assembled at some available spaces such as church or homes. Gradually Universities were established in secluded buildings and teachers were granted remuneration [1]. This paper deals with a cursory overview on the education details of eminent European scholars who made significant contributions in mathematics and other fields of interest during the period from 1300 to 1700.
    [Show full text]
  • GALILEO CREATION and COSMOGONY a Study on the Interplay Between Galileo’S Science of Motion and the Creation Theme [M-STO/05, M-FIL/06]
    DOCTORAL DISSERTATION GALILEO CREATION AND COSMOGONY A Study on the Interplay between Galileo’s Science of Motion and the Creation Theme [M-STO/05, M-FIL/06] Ph.D. Candidate Ph.D. Coordinator IVAN MALARA Prof. ANDREA PINOTTI Registration number: R11933 JOINT PH.D. SUPERVISORS Università degli Studi di Milano Prof. LUCA BIANCHI Doctoral course in Philosophy and Human Sciences – XXXIII Cycle Prof. ELIO NENCI (Dipartimento di Filosofia “Piero Martinetti”) Gent Universiteit Prof. MAARTEN VAN DYCK Academic Year 2019/2020 È chiaro che il pensiero dà fastidio anche se chi pensa è muto come un pesce anzi è un pesce e come pesce è difficile da bloccare perché lo protegge il mare Com’è profondo il mare LUCIO DALLA, Com’è profondo il mare (1977) Non ’mbrischiare a calia ca ’nzudda (Calabrian saying) Table of contents Abstract English .........................................................................................................VII Italian ..........................................................................................................VIII Dutch.............................................................................................................IX Introduction .............................................................................................................XI PART ONE: CREATION I. Anno 1607: Galileo and Castelli 1. Galileo in 1607..............................................................................................3 2. Castelli in 1607. The epistulae Cavenses.......................................................
    [Show full text]
  • NICOLA POLLONI Gundissalinus and Avicenna
    NICOLA POLLONI Gundissalinus and Avicenna : Some Remarks on an Intricate Philosophical Connection Dominicus Gundissalinus is a peculiar figure in the twelfth-century cultural landscape. Born in the Iberian Peninsula between 1115 and 1125, he received his philosophical education in Chartres possibly under Thierry of Chartres and William of Conches as many traces in his original productions indicate1. At least since 1148, Gundissalinus was archdeacon of Cuéllar, a village not far from Segovia, where supposedly he was resident until 11612. Then, he moved to Toledo, where he was based from 1162. This fact is to be linked to the presence, in the Castilian town, of the Jewish philosopher Abraham ibn Daud. As pointed out by Bertolacci3, Ibn Daud’s translation of the prologue to Avicenna’s Liber sufficientiae — i.e., the Kitāb al-Šifāʾ — is to be seen as an invitation to the Toledan archbishop, John II, to sponsor and support a series of translations into Latin of Avicenna’s work. As a result, Gundissalinus arrived in Toledo, his presence probably required there by the same archbishop with the purpose of collaborating with Ibn Daud on the ‘Avicenna project’, the first accomplishment of which was the Latin translation of Avicenna’s De anima, realized before 11664. 1 SISMEL. EDIZIONI DEL GALLUZZO Cf. N. HÄRING, Thierry of Chartres and Dominicus Gundissalinus, « Mediaeval Studies », 26, 1964, pp. 271-286 ; K. M. FREDBORG, The Latin Rhetorical Commentaries by Thierry of Chartres, Pontifical Institute of Medieval Studies, Toronto 1988 ; EAD., The Dependence of Petrus Helias’ Summa super Priscianum on William of Conches’ Glosae super Priscianum, « Cahiers de l’Institut du Moyen Âge grec et latin », 11, 1973, pp.
    [Show full text]
  • Knowledge, Freedom, and Brotherly Love: Homosociality and the Accademia Dei Lincei Mario Biagioli Special Cluster: Gender and Early-Modern Science
    Copyright © 1995, The Johns Hopkins University Press and the Society for Literature and Science. All rights reserved. Configurations 3.2 (1995) 139-166 ../toc Knowledge, Freedom, and Brotherly Love: Homosociality and the Accademia dei Lincei Mario Biagioli Special Cluster: Gender and Early-Modern Science The Accademia dei Lincei, often considered the earliest of scientific organizations, was established in 1603 by Federico Cesi, a young Roman aristocrat who was soon to become prince of San Polo and Sant'Angelo, duke of Aquasparta, and marquis of Monticelli. 1 After a period of very limited activity, which lasted until 1609, the academy quickly revived its membership and visibility, and by 1611 it included prestigious figures like Galileo and Giovanbattista della Porta. Its ranks continued to increase until 1625, when it listed thirty-two members, most of them located in Rome, Naples, and Florence. 2 The Lincei became an important reference point in the fledgling Italian philosophical community and played a relevant role in Galileo's later career, but it collapsed shortly after the prince's death in 1630. Cesi left behind a vast, elaborate, and well-documented academic project that usually bore little more than a family resemblance to the [End Page 139] actual academy. This essay analyzes the gender dimensions of Cesi's project and traces them into some aspects of the academy's historical record. Unlike all other seventeenth-century scientific academies that excluded women from their membership without making that ban explicit or providing reasons for their policies, the Lincei's oath stated that the academy was a "philosophical army" whose recruits were exclusively male.
    [Show full text]
  • 19Chronology of Works in Aesthetics and Philosophy Of
    Chronology of 19 Works in Aesthetics and Philosophy of Art Darren Hudson Hick Notes on Selection This chronology, as with this Companion as a whole, focuses on those works that contribute to the Western tradition of aesthetics, and, beginning in the twentieth century, in the analytic current of thought within that tradition (as opposed to the Continental one). As with the history of Western philosophy in general, the study of philosophical problems in art and beauty dates back to the ancient period, and is infl uenced by the major philosophical and cultural move- ments through the centuries. Much of what survives from the ancient to the post-Hellenistic period does so in fragments or references. In cases where only fragments or references exist, and where dating these is especially problematic, the author or attributed author and (where available) his dates of birth and death are listed. Where works have not survived even as fragments, these are not listed. As well, much of what sur- vives up to the medieval period is diffi cult to date, and is at times of disputable attribution. In these cases, whatever information is available is listed. Aesthetics in the period between the ancients and the medievals tends to be dominated by adherence to Platonic, Aristotelian, and other theories rooted in the ancient period, and as such tends to be generally lacking in substantive the- oretical advancements. And while still heavily infl uenced by ancient thinking, works from the medieval period tend also to be heavily infl uenced by religious thinking, and so many issues pertaining to art and aesthetics are intertwined with issues of religion as “theological aesthetics.” Movements in art theory and aes- thetics in the Renaissance, meanwhile, were largely advanced by working artists, and so tend to be couched in observational or pedagogical approaches, rather than strictly theoretical ones.
    [Show full text]
  • The Beginnings of Medieval Romance: Fact and Fiction, 1150-1220
    The Beginnings of Medieval Romance Up to the twelfth century writing in the western vernaculars dealt almost exclusively with religious, historical and factual themes, all of which were held to convey the truth. The second half of the twelfth century saw the emergence of a new genre, the romance, which was consciously conceived as fictional and therefore allowed largely to break free from traditional presuppositions. Dennis Green explores how and why this happened, and examines this period of crucial importance for the birth of the romance and the genesis of medieval fiction in the vernacular. Although the crucial innovative role of writers in Germany is Green’s main concern, he also takes Latin, French and Anglo-Norman literature into account. This study offers a definition of medieval fictionality in its first formative period in the twelfth century, and underlines the difficulties encountered in finding a place for the fictional romance within earlier literary traditions. d. h. green is Schroder¨ Professor Emeritus of German at the University of Cambridge. He is a Fellow of Trinity College, Cambridge, and of the British Academy. He is the author of The Carolingian Lord (1965), The Millstatter¨ Exodus (1966), Approaches to Wolfram von Eschenbach (1978), Irony in the Medieval Romance (1979), The Art of Recognition in Wolfram’s Parzival (1982), Medieval Listening and Reading (1994) and Language and History in the Early Germanic World (1998). This Page Intentionally Left Blank CAMBRIDGE STUDIES IN MEDIEVAL LITERATURE General editor Alastair Minnis,
    [Show full text]
  • APPENDIX: SUPPLEMENT 1980 to "HUSSERL in ENGLAND" This
    APPENDIX: SUPPLEMENT 1980 TO "HUSSERL IN ENGLAND" This Supplement, written after the reprinting ofthe original article was already at the galley stage, is the result of an odd repetition ofthe circumstances which necessitated the Postscript 1969 after the unexpected arrival of the Freiburg Diary 1928 by W. R Boyce Gibson at the Husserl Archives in Louvain in 1969.1 Only this time, the information that, thanks to the efforts of Professor Cyril Welch of Mount Allison University, became available to me is even more authentie and of greater significance than the Diary for supplementing and correcting the story of Husserl's visit to England, for it comes from the letters of Edmund Husserl and his wife Malvine. Winthrop Bell, the Canadian addressee of these 23 letters and postcards from 1919 to 1925, was one of Husserl's earliest Anglo-American students (after William Ernest Hocking who had spent only two months in Göttingen in 1902). Bell had come to Husserl after a year's graduate study at Harvard and then at Cambridge, England - a fact which mayaIso explain Husserl's hope to enlist hirn as his" mentor" and assistant during his visit to England in 1922. Bell had left Cambridge for health reasons to go to Leipzig, where he first learned about Husserl. So he transferred to Göttingen, where he stayed on from 1911 to 1914. There he had just completed his German Ph.D. thesis, at Husserl's urging on "Eine kritische Untersuchung der Erkenntnistheorie von J osiah Royce"2 when W orld War I broke out, leading to Bell' s internment in Ruhleben near Berlin.
    [Show full text]
  • Some Considerations on the Role of the Mediaeval Postulates to Base Scientific Cognition on Mathematics*
    O R G A N O N 8 (1971) AUTEURS ET PROBLÈMES Małgorzata Frankowska-Terlecka (Poland) SOME CONSIDERATIONS ON THE ROLE OF THE MEDIAEVAL POSTULATES TO BASE SCIENTIFIC COGNITION ON MATHEMATICS* One day I reached for a book in the hope that it might drag me away from the problems of the mediaeval science. The theme awoke my inter­ est tremendously and I was affected even stronger at once by the way the subject had been treated by the author. But the book did not divert me from my work. On the contrary: the problems of my work drew nearer, and the longer I read the book, the more I felt as if it were writ­ ten for the specific purpose of helping me to deal with my work better than heretofore. Actually, of course, the author of the book 1 intended simply to meet the needs of students and teachers of mathematics—to aid the former in the development of their own potentialities and to show the latter how to develop most effectively the abilities of their students. The third aim of the author, certainly not the least in importance, has been to rouse the curiosity of those who are interested in methods lead­ ing to original inventions and discoveries. I am neither a student nor a teacher of mathematics but I am deeply interested in the ars inveniendi, not only in the literal sense of this expression as the art of making scien­ tific discoveries, but also in a more general sense — as the art of correct reasoning, as the skill of most adroitly approaching all questions, as the ability to resolve problems—not only mathematical problems.
    [Show full text]
  • The Fate of the Flying Man Medieval Reception of Avicenna’S Thought Experiment
    OUP CORRECTED PROOF – FINAL, 9/5/2015, SPi The Fate of the Flying Man Medieval Reception of Avicenna’s Thought Experiment Juhana Toivanen 1. INTRODUCTION Thought experiments are nowadays an important part of philosophical discourse. They are used to illuminate theoretical arguments and to reveal philosophically significant features of an argument or a problem in a way that aspires to precision. Although the phrase ‘thought experiment’ itself is quite recent, the use of imagined counterfactual cases which are designed to have a role in philosophical argument can be traced back to Antiquity, and the technique was widely employed in the Middle Ages.1 One of the most well-known medieval thought experiments is the so-called ‘flying man’ of Avicenna. The flying man is an imaginary person whose senses do not provide any input but who nevertheless admits his own existence, or the existence of his soul. Avicenna’s idea was that this thought experiment helps us to understand that the soul is not identical to the body but an immaterial entity. Modern scholarship has discussed the Latin reception of this thought experiment to some extent,2 but there are a couple of issues that have not 1 For the role of thought experiments in the history of Western philosophy, see Katerina Ierodiakonou and Sophie Roux (eds), Thought Experiments in Methodological and Historical Contexts, History of Science and Medicine Library 19 (Leiden: Brill, 2011), 1–142. 2 Dag Nikolaus Hasse, Avicenna’s De anima in the Latin West: The Formation of a Peripatetic Philosophy of the Soul, 1160–1300 (London: The Warburg Institute, 2000), 80–92 and 236; Deborah J.
    [Show full text]