Fisiología Y Ética

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Fisiología Y Ética UNIVERSIDAD DE VALLADOLID Fisiología y ética Fundamentos fisiológicos de la psicología moral en Galeno de Pérgamo Liliana Cecilia Molina González Investigación dirigida por el Prof. Dr. Alfredo Marcos Martínez 2012 D OCTORADO EN LÓGICA Y FILOSOFÍA DE LA CIENCIA Para los pequeños enormes, Antonio y Violeta, para su padre, en ellos. [2] Contenido Abreviaturas usadas 5 Introducción 7 Cap. 1. El platonismo matizado de Galeno 21 1. Medicina y retórica 27 1.1. Cármides 27 1.2. Gorgias 35 1.3. Fedro 41 2. Dualismo, inmortalidad y tripartición 46 2.1. Dualismo e inmortalidad 46 2.2. Tripartición e inmortalidad 61 3. El platonismo matizado de Galeno 66 3.1. La formación del médico y las pautas metodológicas de la investigación 67 3.2. Ventajas de un modelo tripartito del alma 76 Cap. 2. El modelo médico-filosófico de Galeno sobre el alma y la crítica de Crisipo en De Placitis Hippocratis et Platonis (PHP) 82 1. Contexto de discusión en PHP: el debate sobre la sede del hêgemonikon 107 1.1. Exigencias epistemológicas e investigación anatomo-fisiológica 110 2. Dos modelos de alma divergentes 123 2.1. Entendiendo a Crisipo 123 2.1.1. El modelo de Crisipo sobre el alma según los testimonios de PHP 134 2.2. Entendiendo a Galeno 150 3. Conclusiones 169 Cap. 3. Filosofía moral y Dietética. Las facultades del alma siguen los temperamentos del cuerpo (QAM) 175 1. Las tesis 193 2. Fundamentación 218 2.1. Antecedentes 218 [3] 2.2. La propuesta de Galeno. Presupuestos que justifican la identificación entre krâsis y facultades del alma 224 2.2.1. Sobre el arte 235 2.2.2. Sobre los humores 236 2.2.3. Sobre las mezclas (Temp.), Sobre la mejor constitución de los cuerpos (Opt. Corp. Const.) y Sobre la buena constitución (Bon. Hab.) 238 2.2.4. La aplicación de la teoría humoral para establecer las causas de las enfermedades del alma racional 245 2.2.4.1. Sobre los lugares afectados 245 2.2.4.2. Sobre las enfermedades y sus síntomas 249 2.3. Retornando a “Quod animi mores” 251 3. Conclusiones 256 3.1. ¿Responde Galeno en QAM la cuestión sobre la ousia del alma? 256 3. 2. ¿Elimina Galeno la filosofía moral en pos de la defensa acérrima de la medicina dietética? 258 Cap. 4. Diagnóstico y tratamiento de las pasiones y los errores del alma de cada uno: dietética del alma y medicina preventiva 263 1. Contexto filosófico de los escritos morales de Galeno 263 1.1 La filosofía como forma de vida, práctica y entrenamiento en la comprensión de los errores morales 267 2. Los tratados morales de Galeno 272 2.1. Diagnóstico y tratamiento de las pasiones del alma de cada uno 282 2.1.1 Galeno: tipos de pasiones y sus causas. Medidas terapéuticas y el significativo papel de la parte irascible del alma 284 2.1.2. Séneca y Galeno. Ephedreia (vigilancia), ascesis (ejercitación) y enseñanzas (dogmata) como medidas para disminuir la fuerza de las pasiones en el alma 294 2.2. Diagnóstico y tratamiento de los errores del alma de cada uno 297 2.2.1. Contexto crítico: la discusión con las sectas 300 2.2.2 Contexto argumentativo. Errores morales, tipos de errores según su causa; y la relación entre error propio y falsa opiniones 302 2.2.3. Utilidad del método demostrativo. El enfoque profiláctico de Pecc. Dig. 309 3. Conclusiones 313 Anexos Diagnóstico y tratamiento de las pasiones propias del alma de cada uno 328 Diagnóstico y tratamiento de los errores del alma de cada uno 358 Conclusiones 383 Bibliografía 397 [4] Abreviaturas usadas∗ *Obras de Galeno Citamos en este caso, las traducciones disponibles consultadas en esta investigación. PHP. De Placitis Hippocratis et Platones. Sobre las opiniones comunes de Hipócrates y Platón (De Lacy, 2005). Opt. Doct. Qoud Optimus Medicus sit quoque Philosophus. Que el mejor médico es también filósofo. (Martínez, 2002); (Singer, 1997). Prop. Plac. De Propiis Placitis. Sobre mis propias opiniones. (Martínez, 2002). Lib. Prop. De Libris Propiis. Sobre mis propios libros. (Martínez, 2002). Ord. Lib. Prop. De Ordine Librorum Propriorum. Sobre el orden de mis propios libros. (Martínez, 2002). Ars Med. Ars Medica. Art of Medicine. (Singer, 1997). QAM. Quod Animi Mores Corporis Temperamenta Sequuntur. Las facultades del alma siguen los temperamentos del cuerpo. (Zaragoza G, 2003); (Singer, 1997); (Barras, Birchler, Morand, 1995) Nat. Fac. De naturalibus Facultatibus. Las facultades naturales. (Zaragoza G., 2003). Aff. Dig. De proprium Animi Cuiuslibet Affectuum Dignotione et Curatione. Diagnóstico y curación de las pasiones del alma de cada uno; (Barras, Birchler, Morand, 1995); (Singer, 1997) y (Harkins, 1963). Pecc. Dig. De Animi Cuiuslibet Peccatorum Dignotione et Curatione. Diagnóstico y curación de los errores del alma de cada uno; (Barras, Birchler, Morand, 1995) ; (Singer, 1997) y (Harkins, 1963). Temp. De Temperamentis. Sobre las mezclas. (Singer, 1997). Opt. Corp. Const. De Optima Corporis Nostri. La mejor constitución de nuestro cuerpo. (Singer, 1997). Bon. Hab. De Bono Habitu. (Singer, 1997). Loc. Aff. De Locis Affectis. Sobre la localización de las enfermedades. (Andrés Aparicio, 1997). ∗Solamente en el caso de las obras de Galeno citamos las traducciones usadas. Y utilizamos las abreviaturas con que son citados los tratados de Galeno, tal como se reseñan en el apéndice I de Hankinson (2008). En el caso de los tratados Aff. Dig. y Pecc. Dig. hemos hecho nuestra propia traducción al español con base en el texto griego y en las versiones disponibles en la lengua francesa e inglesa; y la hemos insertado como anexo al final de este trabajo. Para los tratados médicos, los diálogos de Platón y las obras de Aristóteles, hemos consultado las traducciones disponibles en la edición de Gredos. Y utilizamos las abreviaturas usadas por Liddell, H.; Scott, R. (comp.) and Jones, H. S. (rev.) (1996), (eds.), A Greek-English Lexicon. Oxford, Clarendon Press. No incluimos abreviaturas de los diálogos de Platón ni de los tratados médicos consultados en este trabajo. En ese caso simplemente usamos el nombre completo de la obra citada. [5] Hum. De humoribus. Sobre los humores (Grant, 2000). Caus. Symp. De symptomatum causis. De las causas de las enfermedades (Johnston, 2006). Symp. Diff. De symptomatum differentiis. De las diferencias de los síntomas (Johnston, 2006). *Obras de Aristóteles PA. Partes de los animales GA. Generación de los animales de An. Sobre el alma EN. Ética a Nicómaco GC. Generación y Corrupción PN. Tratados breves de historia natural [6] Introducción 1. Justificación y estado de la cuestión Hace cuatro décadas, aproximadamente, los historiadores de la filosofía comienzan a interesarse en la obra del médico Galeno de Pérgamo (I-II de nuestra era) ; entre las primeras publicaciones al respecto podemos citar, por ejemplo, Rise and decline of Galenism de Temkin Owsei (1970) y los diferentes artículos publicados por el profesor García Ballester.1 Actualmente no se duda de la relevancia de su obra para la historia de la medicina, ni de la importancia doxográfica y filosófica de los tratados en que Galeno discute, críticamente, con una amplia gama de planteamientos filosóficos y médicos: el mejor ejemplo es su escrito sobre las opiniones de Hipócrates y Platón, que resulta relevante para estudiar las primeras doctrinas estoicas sobre el alma y las pasiones.2 Quienes pretenden justificar la importancia filosófica de Galeno buscan identificar, principalmente, la influencia de la tradición filosófica en su investigación médica sobre la naturaleza del alma y su relación con el cuerpo;3 y evaluar la novedad y pertinencia de su método experimental para las discusiones filosóficas sobre la naturaleza.4 Galeno se apoya en conocimientos anatómicos para explicar empíricamente la estructura y funcionamiento del alma;5 y su doctrina fisiológica sobre el pneuma 1 Los más relevantes: “Soul and body, Disease of the Soul and disease of the body in Galen´s Medical Thought”, en: Manuli e Vegetti (1988); “Galen as a medical practitioner. Problems in diagnosis”. En: Nutton (1981). Y su libro Galen and Galenism (2002). 2 Cfr. Tieleman (1996 y 2003). 3 Entre este grupo de investigadores podemos citar a García Ballester (1969), con sus artículos: “La `Psique` en el somaticismo médico de la antigüedad: la actitud de Galeno” (1969), y “La utilización de Platón y Aristóteles en los escritos tardíos de Galeno de Pérgamo” (1971). Y, por otro lado, a De Lacy (1972), “Galen´s Platonism”; Frede, M., “On Galen´s Epistemology” y Moraux, P. “Galien comme Philosophe. La philosophie de la nature”, en Nutton (1981); y a Piegaud, “Le platonisme de Galien”, una sección de “La psychopathologie des médecins (Piegaud, 1981); Donini, “Motivi filosofici in Galeno” (Donini, 1980) y “Galeno e la Filosofia” (Donini, 1992); Hankinson, “Anatomy of the Soul” (Hankinson, 1991); y Desideri, “Galeno come intellecttuale” (Desideri, P., 2000). 4 Cfr. al respecto los artículos compendiados en Hankinson (ed.) (2008), cfr. especialmente: “Psychology” (Donini); “Anatomy” (Rocca), “Philosophy of nature” (Hankinson), “Epistemology” (Hankinson), “Logic” (Morison), “Methodology” (Tieleman) y “Physiology” (Debru A.). 5 En Galeno “alma” es el conjunto de las funciones o facultades de un cuerpo viviente organizado. Justamente porque vemos esas facultades (respiración, nutrición, sensación, pensamiento), no dudamos de su existencia. Para Galeno “alma” es el concepto con que los filósofos designan la causa de dichas facultades; pero el médico busca demostrar que estas facultades tienen su principio (archê) en partes diferentes del cuerpo. El principio epistemológico tras este planteamiento es que todo sucede por una causa y las causas de estas actividades “naturales” o “del alma” son diferentes. Para intentar demostrarlo, Galeno investiga la fisiología del cuerpo y hace experimentos anatómicos para identificar la estructura causal de las actividades de un cuerpo viviente. Por esta razón hablamos de una investigación fisiológica [7] como instrumento del alma, le permite establecer diferencias entre las facultades anímicas.
Recommended publications
  • Emotions, Demons, and Moral Ability
    Chapter 2 Emotions, Demons, and Moral Ability This chapter deals with TriTrac’s relationship to ancient theories of emotions (πάθη) and cognition. What role do emotions play within the mechanisms of the mind? In ancient time, emotions were not only thought to be a cognitive matter, but very much a bodily matter, too;1 they were also closely intertwined with ethics and morality.2 As the famous philosopher-physician Galen stated plainly, the doctrine of virtues was thought to follow necessarily from the doc- trine of the emotions.3 Nonetheless, early Christian attitudes to emotions has been a somewhat neglected topic4 until fairly recently,5 while TriTrac’s rela- tion to ancient theories on emotions remains to be explored, especially from the perspective of their importance for ethical considerations. In this chapter, we explore the role that emotion, or passion,6 plays in TriTrac from the per- spective of ancient debates concerning the composition of the human mind and the cognitive apparatus. We also have reason to explore the connection between ancient theories of emotions and demonology. But first, a short look 1 See, for example, Carlin A. Barton, Roman Honor: The Fire in the Bones (Berkeley: University of California Press, 2001), 1–4; Sorabji, Emotion, 17–29. 2 See, for example, John T. Fitzgerald, “The Passions and Moral Progress: An Introduction”, in Passions and Moral Progress in Greco-Roman Thought, ed. John T. Fitzgerald (London and New York: Routledge, 2008), 1–25. 3 Galen, On the Opinions of Hippocrates and Plato V.6.1. For a work that recognizes the central importance of the body for early Christian social structures, although the focus on cognition and emotions is not discussed to any great extent, see Peter Brown, The Body and Society: Men, Women, and Sexual Renunciation in Early Christianity (New York: Columbia University Press, 1988).
    [Show full text]
  • Dispassionate Passions
    c Peter King, in Reason and Emotion in Medieval and Early Modern Philosophy DISPASSIONATE PASSIONS I want to trace the Hellenistic origins and mediæval career of the idea that there can be emotions that do not have the disagreeable baggage with which ordinary emotions travel — emotions that are neither turbulent nor disruptive, emotions that lack any somatic component, emotions that are the product of reason rather than opposed to it: in a word, dispassionate passions of the soul. The mediæval motivation behind the idea of dispassionate passions is not far to seek. It is a fundamental article of faith that immaterial beings such as God and His angels, as well as postmortem human souls, enjoy bodiless bliss in Heaven as the highest state of which they are capable. Hence the transports of delight experienced there must be independent of the body; they are the final fulfillment of rational nature, not its annulment, and they contribute to a stable and settled state of eternal blessedness. Yet while the mediæval motivation for adopting dispassionate passions seems clear, such reasons of faith do not apply to the Stoics. More pressing, the doctrine itself stands in need of clarification. How could passions be dispassionate, emotions unemotional, feelings unfelt? Our sources for early and middle Stoicism permit us to have a clear view of the main outlines of the doctrine of dispassionate passions in the Hellenis- tic period, though not about the motivation behind it, despite its being one of the aspects of Stoicism heavily criticized in Antiquity (§). Mediæval philoso- phers tried to transplant the doctrine of dispassionate passions from its Stoic origins to different philosophical environments: Augustine into Platonism (§), Aquinas into Aristotelianism (§).
    [Show full text]
  • But Were They Talking About Emotions? Affectus, Affectio and the History of Emotions
    Haskell, Y., Champion, M., Ruys, J., & Garrod, R. (2016). But were they talking about emotions? Affectus, affectio and the history of emotions. Rivista Storica Italiana, CXXVIII(II), 521-543. http://www.edizioniesi.it/rivistastoricaitaliana/index.php?id=2016 Peer reviewed version Link to publication record in Explore Bristol Research PDF-document This is the author accepted manuscript (AAM). The final published version (version of record) is available online via ESI at http://www.edizioniesi.it/rivistastoricaitaliana/data/uploads/indici/2016_2.pdf. Please refer to any applicable terms of use of the publisher. University of Bristol - Explore Bristol Research General rights This document is made available in accordance with publisher policies. Please cite only the published version using the reference above. Full terms of use are available: http://www.bristol.ac.uk/red/research-policy/pure/user-guides/ebr-terms/ But Were They Talking about Emotions? Affectus, affectio and the History of Emotions It is well recognized that a history of emotions must account for the fact that the term ‘emotions’ is itself a modern construction.1 The question arises then, if medieval and early modern people talked about a concept that is recognizably similar to our ‘emotions’ (although this itself may be in dispute), what terminology did they use to describe these affective states that were partly volitional, partly cognitive, and (for some at least) necessarily physiological? Attention has centred on the Latin terms affectus (pl. affectūs) and affectio (pl.
    [Show full text]
  • Captain Cook's Antimony Cup, Vesalius, VII, 2, 62 - 64, 2001
    Vol. VII, Nr 2 December 2001 Official journal of the International Society for the History of Medicine Vesalius Revue officielle de la Societe Internationale d'Histoire de la Medecine Acta Internationalia Historiae Medicinae EDITORS - EDITEURS EDITORIAL BOARD Thierry Appelboom COMITE DE REDACTION Editorial John Cule John Blair Athanasios Diamandopoulos ASSOCIATE EDITORS Gary Ferngren EDITEURS ASSOCIES A perusal of the proposed programme for the 38th John Ford Chester Burns International Congress on the History of Medicine, to Alain Lellouch Samuel Kottek be held in Istanbul between 1-6 September 2002, Alfredo Musajo-Somma Regis Olry Jean-Pierre Tricot YnezViole O'Neill gives much food for thought in these troubled times. Bruce Parker The programme includes an invitation to come to the MANAGING EDITOR John Pearn Congress, extended by its President, Professor Nil COORDINATION Robin Price Diana Gasparon Hans Schadewaldt Sari. In this she described Istanbul as a gateway Alain Segal between the East and West, a city that has attracted REVIEW EDiTOR Michel Thiery David Wright many people for centuries. Sue Weir Image conjured up by the words East and West, have ADDRESS -ADRESSE JOURNAL SUBSCRIPTION changed markedly in the last two or three months of Secretariat "Vesalius" ABONNEMENT A LA REVUE Medical Museum this year. Such images at present include all the 808 route de Lennik 2 issues per year - 2 numeros par an horrors of modern and of old fashioned violence. With Annual rate : 50 Eur B - 1070 Brussels, Belgium such visions, we need the perspective that history can Phone : 32 / 2 / 555.34.31 Each issue : 25 Eur Fax : 32 / 2 / 555.34.71 Free to ISHM members offer to reassure us that, in more favourable circum­ e-mail: dgasparo© ulb.ac.be stances, different cultures can interact in a positive rather than a destructive way.
    [Show full text]
  • Cicero on the Philosophy of Religion
    CICERO ON THE PHILOSOPHY OF RELIGION: DE NATURA DEORUM AND DE DIVINATIONE. A Dissertation Presented to the Faculty of the Graduate School of Cornell University in Partial Fulfillment of the Requirements for the Degree of Doctor of Philosophy by John Patrick Frederick Wynne January 2008 CICERO ON THE PHILOSOPHY OF RELIGION: DE NATURA DEORUM AND DE DIVINATIONE. John Patrick Frederick Wynne, Ph. D. Cornell University, 2008 Cicero wrote de Natura Deorum (dND), de Divinatione (Div.) and de Fato (Fat.) in succession and describes the latter two as continuations of the first. I argue that the three dialogues form a trilogy, in which Cicero as author indicates a stance on the material he presents (but that too little of the fragmentary Fat. remains to be useful for my purposes). There are much-debated attributions of preferences to Cicero’s propriae personae at the conclusions of dND and Div.; I take these preferences to express Cicero’s authorial stance. I examine relevant parts of the speeches to which they react and, first, make philosophical interpretations of each (often comparing other sources for Hellenistic thought) and, second, pay attention to the interaction of Cicero’s characterization of each speaker with the arguments the speaker gives. I find that Balbus in dND advocates the avoidance of superstition and the reform of religious beliefs in line with Stoic physics and that Cotta has a strong commitment to traditional Roman religious views consistent with his sceptical epistemology. Cotta’s scepticism is elusive in its details but perhaps yields a kind of fideism. I find that Quintus Cicero’s advocacy in Div.
    [Show full text]
  • God, Emotion and Impassibility
    Durham E-Theses God, emotion and impassibility Scrutton, Anastasia Philippa How to cite: Scrutton, Anastasia Philippa (2008) God, emotion and impassibility, Durham theses, Durham University. Available at Durham E-Theses Online: http://etheses.dur.ac.uk/1930/ Use policy The full-text may be used and/or reproduced, and given to third parties in any format or medium, without prior permission or charge, for personal research or study, educational, or not-for-prot purposes provided that: • a full bibliographic reference is made to the original source • a link is made to the metadata record in Durham E-Theses • the full-text is not changed in any way The full-text must not be sold in any format or medium without the formal permission of the copyright holders. Please consult the full Durham E-Theses policy for further details. Academic Support Oce, Durham University, University Oce, Old Elvet, Durham DH1 3HP e-mail: [email protected] Tel: +44 0191 334 6107 http://etheses.dur.ac.uk University of Durham God, Emotion and Impassibility Volume one of two Anastasia Philippa Scrutton PhD 2008 Abstract The current theological climate presents two extremes in speaking of the emotional life of God: Passibilism, which affirms the fullness of God's emotional life, and impassibilism, which (claiming fidelity to traditional orthodox Christianity) asserts that God cannot experience emotions. Likewise, contemporary philosophy of emotion is characterised by the extremes of cognitive views of emotion on the one hand, and non-cognitive, physiological or `feelings' views on the other. In this thesis I argue for a more nuanced account of both impassibility and emotion.
    [Show full text]
  • THE CATHOLIC UNIVERSITY of AMERICA Passions, Virtue, And
    THE CATHOLIC UNIVERSITY OF AMERICA Passions, Virtue, and Moral Growth in John of Apamea’s Dialogues on the Soul A DISSERTATION Submitted to the Faculty of the School of Theology and Religious Studies Of The Catholic University of America In Partial Fulfillment of the Requirements For the Degree Doctor of Philosophy By Rodrigue J. Constantin Washington, D.C. 2020 Abstract Passions, Virtue, and Moral Growth in John of Apamea’s Dialogues on the Soul Rodrigue J. Constantin, Ph.D. Director: Paul J. Scherz, Ph.D. Virtue cultivation is an under-researched topic in theological virtue ethics. Moreover, little attention is given in virtue ethics to vice and its impact on virtue cultivation. In this dissertation, I respond to this lacuna by examining the role of the removal of evil passions in moral growth in the Dialogues on the Soul, whose author, John of Apamea, is a fifth-century ascetic who has introduced the discussion of passions in Syriac Christianity. For John, moral growth occurs in three stages: somaticity, psychicality, and pneumaticity. I argue that, for John, the gradual healing from evil passions facilitates one’s moral progress from one stage to another. After examining John’s theological anthropology, in the first chapter, I explore his views on the relationship of the body and the soul with the passions in chapters two and three. In chapter four, I focus on the morality of the passions, that is, whether the passions in themselves are good or evil, and to what degree one is morally responsible for them. I, then, reconstruct, in chapter five, a list of the passions and their variations in the Dialogues on the Soul, as well as the structure of the passions as stirrings that are intimately connected to thoughts.
    [Show full text]
  • Final Thesis Dec 2018
    Department of Classics Royal Holloway University of London Epictetus on Human Suffering (Ταράσσει τοὺς ἀνθρώπους οὐ τὰ πράγματα, ἀλλὰ τὰ περὶ τῶν πραγμάτων δόγματα) By Edward James Humphreys Thesis submitted for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy PhD THESIS December 2018 Epictetus on Human Suffering Edward James Humphreys Page 1 of 223 Epictetus on Human Suffering Edward James Humphreys Page 2 of 223 Declaration of Authorship I, Edward James Humphreys, hereby declare that this thesis and the work presented in it is entirely my own. Where I have consulted the work of others, this is always clearly stated. Signed: Date: 23rd December 2018 © copyright by Edward James Humphreys 2011-2018. All Rights Reserved Epictetus on Human Suffering Edward James Humphreys Page 3 of 223 Epictetus on Human Suffering Edward James Humphreys Page 4 of 223 Abstract This thesis considers Epictetus’ response to human suffering with regard to its broader meaning. This encompasses not only what Buddhism refers to as ordinary suffering, but also what they call suffering caused by change and by the conditioned mind, all of which manifest at different levels of consciousness, in different forms and from the very gross to the very subtle. In considering Epictetus’ response we shall consider suffering as a universally occurring and unending dissatisfaction with life - a ‘dis-ease’ that exists as part of our human condition and formative learning experience of life. This thesis takes a fresh look at Epictetus by reframing his thinking and response to suffering. First, the Buddhist model known as the Four Noble Truths (cattāri ariyasaccāni) is used as a systematic basis for discussing Epictetus.
    [Show full text]
  • Platonic and Stoic Passions in Philo of Alexandria Loren Kerns George Fox University, [email protected]
    Digital Commons @ George Fox University George Fox Evangelical Seminary 2013 Platonic and Stoic Passions in Philo of Alexandria Loren Kerns George Fox University, [email protected] Follow this and additional works at: http://digitalcommons.georgefox.edu/gfes Part of the Christianity Commons, and the Church History Commons Recommended Citation Kerns, Loren, "Platonic and Stoic Passions in Philo of Alexandria" (2013). George Fox Evangelical Seminary. Paper 6. http://digitalcommons.georgefox.edu/gfes/6 This Dissertation is brought to you for free and open access by Digital Commons @ George Fox University. It has been accepted for inclusion in George Fox Evangelical Seminary by an authorized administrator of Digital Commons @ George Fox University. Kings College London Platonic and Stoic Passions in Philo of Alexandria A Dissertation submitted to The School of Arts and Humanities In Candidacy for the Degree of Doctor of Philosophy Department of Theology and Religious Studies By Loren Kerns London, United Kingdom July 2013 Copyright by Loren Kerns, 2013 All rights reserved. Abstract Philo of Alexandria forged his theory of the soul and its passions while expositing the meaning of Torah. Though writing as a Jewish teacher and disciple of Moses, his biblical reflections display a strong orientation toward Middle-Platonic philosophy. On the topic of the soul and its passions, however, Philo also exhibits significant Stoic influence. The introduction notes Philo’s apparent incompatible use of both the complex Platonic and the monistic Stoic psychological models. After assessing the degree to which Philo understood 'passion' to be a type of Stoic impulse or opinion (chapter one), chapter two demonstrates that Philo consistently drew upon the Stoics’ depiction of all passions as irrational, excessive, and unnatural.
    [Show full text]
  • Targeting Emotion in Early Stoicism
    Binghamton University The Open Repository @ Binghamton (The ORB) The Society for Ancient Greek Philosophy Newsletter 12-28-2002 Targeting Emotion in Early Stoicism Scott M. Rubarth Rollins College, [email protected] Follow this and additional works at: https://orb.binghamton.edu/sagp Part of the Ancient History, Greek and Roman through Late Antiquity Commons, Ancient Philosophy Commons, and the History of Philosophy Commons Recommended Citation Rubarth, Scott M., "Targeting Emotion in Early Stoicism" (2002). The Society for Ancient Greek Philosophy Newsletter. 353. https://orb.binghamton.edu/sagp/353 This Article is brought to you for free and open access by The Open Repository @ Binghamton (The ORB). It has been accepted for inclusion in The Society for Ancient Greek Philosophy Newsletter by an authorized administrator of The Open Repository @ Binghamton (The ORB). For more information, please contact [email protected]. Targeting Emotion in Early Stoicism Scott M. Rubarth, Rollins College Presented to the Society for Ancient Greek Philosophy at the 2002 meeting with the Eastern Division of the American Philosophical Association, in Philadelphia The Stoic sage is a cold, heartless being who would not grieve over the loss of a beloved companion or child. Unmoved, unemotional, uncaring, the sage is an ethical and emotional monstrosity hiding behind the pretension of the so-called virtues of detachment and austerity. That, at least, is how many who study Stoic ethics perceive the sage in regard to his/her emotional life. 1 In this paper I will argue that this conception of the Stoic theory of emotion and passion is misleading; emotions, in fact, are central to Stoic ethics and apatheia should not be confused with the contemporary idea of apathy or emotional flatness.
    [Show full text]
  • Schedule of Meetings for Affiliated Groups
    144TH APA ANNUAL MEETING ABSTRACTS WASHINGTON STATE CONVENTION CENTER January 3-6, 2013 Seattle, WA ii PREFACE The abstracts in this volume appear in the form submitted by their authors without editorial intervention. They are arranged in the same order as the Annual Meeting Program. An index by name at the end of the volume is provided. This is the thirty first volume of Abstracts published by the Association in as many years, and suggestions of improvements in future years are welcome. Again this year, the Program Committee has invited affiliated groups holding sessions at the Annual Meeting to submit abstracts for publication in this volume. The following groups have published abstracts this year. AFFILIATED GROUPS American Association for Neo-Latin Studies American Classical League American Society of Greek and Latin Epigraphy American Society of Papyrologists Eta Sigma Phi Friends of Numismatics International Plutarch Society International Society for Neoplatonic Studies Lambda Classical Caucus Medieval Latin Studies Group Society for Ancient Greek Philosophy Society for Ancient Medicine and Pharmacy Society for Ancient Mediterranean Religions Society for Late Antiquity Women’s Classical Caucus The Program Committee thanks the authors of these abstracts for their cooperation in making the timely production of this volume possible. 2012 ANNUAL MEETING PROGRAM COMMITTEE MEMBERS Joseph Farrell, Chair Christopher A. Faraone Kirk Freudenburg Maud Gleason Corinne O. Pache Adam D. Blistein (ex officio) Heather H. Gasda (ex officio) iii iv
    [Show full text]
  • 1 Ancient Theories
    Cambridge University Press 978-1-107-48084-1 — Generations of Feeling Barbara H. Rosenwein Excerpt More Information 1 Ancient theories We begin with Cicero (d. 43 bce). To be sure, long before his time many theories of the emotions had been elaborated, particularly within the Stoic and Epicurean philosophies of the Hellenistic era.1 Cicero drew on these traditions when he wrote on emotions for the Latinate audience of the Roman West. Medieval people inherited his writings. But they read them through Christian lenses. Christianity, which became the official religion of the Roman Empire in the 380s, radically transformed ancient ideas about the emotions. To get a clear idea of some of the most important of those changes, we will focus in the second part of this chapter on Saint Augustine’s reconsideration of the Ciceronian canon. Augustine (d. 430), perhaps the most influential of the Western Church Fathers, read Cicero on the emotions and reoriented the discussion. Armed with the theories and the vocabularies of Augustine and Cicero, we will be ready to look at some early medieval emotional communities in Chapter 2. In addition, the writings of Cicero and Augustine discussed here exerted an enormous influence on later emotional communities, especially those of the twelfth century and beyond, as we shall see in Chapter 4 and those thereafter. Cicero’s somber, “Stoic” emotions While Cicero expressed many emotions in his writings, we are here interested in his theoretical works on the topic, particularly the Tusculan Disputations and Laelius on Friendship. Both were written near the end of Cicero’s life, the first in 45 and the second in 44 bce.
    [Show full text]