Material Conditional (P. 37/41) Take the Sentence If That Monkey Is Friendly, Then It Is Safe to Play with It

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Material Conditional (P. 37/41) Take the Sentence If That Monkey Is Friendly, Then It Is Safe to Play with It Introduction to Deductive Logic Summer 2004 31 Material Conditional (p. 37/41) Take the sentence If that monkey is friendly, then it is safe to play with it. This is a compound of That monkey is friendly and That monkey is safe to play with. Let us symbolize these as ‘F’ and ‘S’ respectively. We introduce into SL the symbol ‘’ to represent truth-functional uses of ‘if . then . ’ in English. We thus symbolize our sentence as F S. Sentences of SL of the form P Q are called material conditionals. P (the sentence on the left of the connective) is called the antecedent and Q (the sentence on the right) is called the consequent of P Q. ‘’ is called “the hook” or “the horseshoe”. Introduction to Deductive Logic Summer 2004 32 Material Conditional Continued Material conditionals have the following truth-table: P Q P Q T T T T F F F T T F F T They are false when their antecedent is true and their consequent is false, and true otherwise. The conditions for a material conditional being false are clear enough. “If Brian v. is in this room, then he is a student in Introduction to Deductive Logic” is pretty clearly false, just because I am in the room, but am not an Intro Logic student. What someone who says “If Brian v. is in this room, then he is a student in Introduction to Deductive Logic” is trying to rule out is just that I am in the room and not a student. If what they are trying to rule out does not obtain, then what they have said is true. (Given the assumptions of truth-functionality and exactly two truth-values, every sentence having exactly one.) Introduction to Deductive Logic Summer 2004 33 Material Conditional Continued The text does not introduce sentences of the form P Q directly. Instead, it suggests that we paraphrase our original sentence as: Either it is not the case that that monkey is friendly or that monkey is safe to play with. And then symbolize it as: ~F S. Only then does the text introduce 'F S' as an abbreviation of '~F S'. Thus, the text introduces P Q as an abbreviation for ~P Q as a way of helping to motivate its truth-table: ~P Q is false if and only if ~P is false and Q is false. So ~P Q is false if and only if P is true and Q is false. And, you will note, these are exactly the truth-conditions we gave for P Q. Introduction to Deductive Logic Summer 2004 34 Material Conditional Continued So, why does the text take the detour? Consider the “Paradoxes of the Material Conditional”: If 2+2=9 then my name is Brian. If baboons are reptiles then the president of the USA is a potato. If grass is green then sky is blue. If we symbolize these as T B, etc., then the each come out as true sentences of SL, given the state of the world and the truth-table for ''. (We've not yet really introduced our full semantics, so this is a bit sloppy, but fine for now.) Many people feel uncomfortable with the claim that these sentences are true. (After all, logically speaking, the colour of grass and the sky have nothing to do with each other.) The presentation in the text tries to hide this, by first offering the translation in terms of negation and disjunction. The hope is that you will find the translation plausible and thus accept the somewhat counter-intuitive consequences as following from the translation. Introduction to Deductive Logic Summer 2004 35 Material Conditional Continued This seems dishonest. If you are bothered by the “paradoxes,” you could just as easily react by rejecting the translation of English “If . then . .”'s into the negation/disjunction form. Fortunately we can do better. Recall that we are doing truth- functional logic. We thus must read “If . then . .” as a truth- function. Say I promise you: If you don't take the final exam, then you will fail the course. (We can symbolize this as D F.) When have I broken my promise? Well, say you don't take the final and yet you pass. Pretty clearly, my promise has been broken. What if you don't take the final and you fail the course? Well, I've kept my promise! And what if you do take the final? Well, whether you pass or fail the course, I haven't broken my promise, have I? So, if we look at P Q as a promise that “if P is true, then Q is true”, then if P is false, the promise is kept, no matter the truth-value of Q. Introduction to Deductive Logic Summer 2004 36 Material Conditional Continued Here is another approach. What would prove the English sentence: If Jane is in the library, then she is studying to be false? Clearly Jane's being in the library and not studying. And, if it is not false, it is true. (We are assuming that every sentences is either true or false.) If Jane is there and studying, it has to be true —it is no good to say that maybe she is sometimes there without studying, etc. because we are doing truth-functional logic. But if the only circumstances where our sentence (we can symbolize it as L S) is false is when she is in the library and not studying, then it has to be true, no matter what else obtains (under our assumptions of bivalenent truth and truth- functionality.) Introduction to Deductive Logic Summer 2004 37 Material Conditional Continued: One more approach: with our Jane in the library example, we have given clear justification of some of the table as follows: P Q P Q T T T T F F F T T F F T What can we say to justify the other two values? They cannot both get false, otherwise we would have conjunction. But if either of the false antecedent cases get true, it would seem that they both should. (Given that the antecedent fails to obtain, what difference to the truth of the truth- functional conditional should the truth-value of the consequent make?) Introduction to Deductive Logic Summer 2004 38 Material Conditional Continued: Not all English conditionals are plausibly seen as truth-functional. Consider If these crystals are salt then they will dissolve in water. This sentence is plausibly construed as making a causal claim — it is claiming that being crystals of salt is connected (beyond a merely truth-functional connection) to dissolving in water. If we symbolize it as S D we are giving it a symbolization that is true if the crystals in question are not salt. But then S ~D would also be true. But only one of the two English conditionals: If these crystals are salt then they will dissolve in water and If these crystals are salt then they will not dissolve in water is true. Something has been lost. Introduction to Deductive Logic Summer 2004 39 Material Conditional Continued: Other Conditionals Forms in English: Mary is in this room only if Mary is interested in logic. We can paraphrase this as If Mary is in this room then Mary is interested in logic. Ferrets are docile unless they are frightened. We can paraphrase this as If it is not the case that ferrets are frightened then ferrets are docile. Introduction to Deductive Logic Summer 2004 40 Material Biconditional (p. 42/45) Consider Koalas are quadrupeds if and only if they have four legs. We can paraphrase this as Both (if koalas are quadrupeds then they have four legs) and (if koalas have four legs then they are quadrupeds). We can symbolize this as (Q F) & (F Q). We introduce the symbol ‘’ into SL to capture this truth- functional relationship. ‘’ is called “the triple bar”. We can thus symbolize our sentence as Q F. Sentences of SL of the form P Q are called material biconditionals. Introduction to Deductive Logic Summer 2004 41 Material Biconditional Continued: A material biconditional is true if and only both sentences on either side of the ‘’ have the same truth-value. Thus, material biconditionals have the following truth-table: P Q P Q T T T T F F F T F F F T Introduction to Deductive Logic Summer 2004 42 The Vocabulary of SL (p. 62/69) We have now introduced all of the elements of our language SL. The formal syntax of our language is fairly simple. The “lexicon” is as follows: Sentence letters of SL: { A, B, . , Z, A1, B1, . , Z1, A2, B2, . , Z2, . } Connectives of SL: { ~, &, , , } The punctuation marks of SL: { (, ) } Next, we define Sentence of SL. Introduction to Deductive Logic Summer 2004 43 Definition of Sentence of SL (p. 63/70) 1. Every sentence letter is a sentence. 2. If P is a sentence then ~P is a sentence. 3. If P and Q are sentences, then (P & Q ) is a sentence. 4. If P and Q are sentences, then (P Q ) is a sentence. 5. If P and Q are sentences, then (P Q ) is a sentence. 6. If P and Q are sentences, then (P Q ) is a sentence. 7. Nothing else is a sentence. We can refer to sentences of SL as SL-sentences and, more generally, to sentences of some logical language L as L- sentences. A Convention If R is a sentence by one of clauses 3-6 we may drop the outer pair of parentheses.
Recommended publications
  • Gibbardian Collapse and Trivalent Conditionals
    Gibbardian Collapse and Trivalent Conditionals Paul Égré* Lorenzo Rossi† Jan Sprenger‡ Abstract This paper discusses the scope and significance of the so-called triviality result stated by Allan Gibbard for indicative conditionals, showing that if a conditional operator satisfies the Law of Import-Export, is supraclassical, and is stronger than the material conditional, then it must collapse to the material conditional. Gib- bard’s result is taken to pose a dilemma for a truth-functional account of indicative conditionals: give up Import-Export, or embrace the two-valued analysis. We show that this dilemma can be averted in trivalent logics of the conditional based on Reichenbach and de Finetti’s idea that a conditional with a false antecedent is undefined. Import-Export and truth-functionality hold without triviality in such logics. We unravel some implicit assumptions in Gibbard’s proof, and discuss a recent generalization of Gibbard’s result due to Branden Fitelson. Keywords: indicative conditional; material conditional; logics of conditionals; triva- lent logic; Gibbardian collapse; Import-Export 1 Introduction The Law of Import-Export denotes the principle that a right-nested conditional of the form A → (B → C) is logically equivalent to the simple conditional (A ∧ B) → C where both antecedentsare united by conjunction. The Law holds in classical logic for material implication, and if there is a logic for the indicative conditional of ordinary language, it appears Import-Export ought to be a part of it. For instance, to use an example from (Cooper 1968, 300), the sentences “If Smith attends and Jones attends then a quorum *Institut Jean-Nicod (CNRS/ENS/EHESS), Département de philosophie & Département d’études cog- arXiv:2006.08746v1 [math.LO] 15 Jun 2020 nitives, Ecole normale supérieure, PSL University, 29 rue d’Ulm, 75005, Paris, France.
    [Show full text]
  • Glossary for Logic: the Language of Truth
    Glossary for Logic: The Language of Truth This glossary contains explanations of key terms used in the course. (These terms appear in bold in the main text at the point at which they are first used.) To make this glossary more easily searchable, the entry headings has ‘::’ (two colons) before it. So, for example, if you want to find the entry for ‘truth-value’ you should search for ‘:: truth-value’. :: Ambiguous, Ambiguity : An expression or sentence is ambiguous if and only if it can express two or more different meanings. In logic, we are interested in ambiguity relating to truth-conditions. Some sentences in natural languages express more than one claim. Read one way, they express a claim which has one set of truth-conditions. Read another way, they express a different claim with different truth-conditions. :: Antecedent : The first clause in a conditional is its antecedent. In ‘(P ➝ Q)’, ‘P’ is the antecedent. In ‘If it is raining, then we’ll get wet’, ‘It is raining’ is the antecedent. (See ‘Conditional’ and ‘Consequent’.) :: Argument : An argument is a set of claims (equivalently, statements or propositions) made up from premises and conclusion. An argument can have any number of premises (from 0 to indefinitely many) but has only one conclusion. (Note: This is a somewhat artificially restrictive definition of ‘argument’, but it will help to keep our discussions sharp and clear.) We can consider any set of claims (with one claim picked out as conclusion) as an argument: arguments will include sets of claims that no-one has actually advanced or put forward.
    [Show full text]
  • Three Ways of Being Non-Material
    Three Ways of Being Non-Material Vincenzo Crupi, Andrea Iacona May 2019 This paper presents a novel unified account of three distinct non-material inter- pretations of `if then': the suppositional interpretation, the evidential interpre- tation, and the strict interpretation. We will spell out and compare these three interpretations within a single formal framework which rests on fairly uncontro- versial assumptions, in that it requires nothing but propositional logic and the probability calculus. As we will show, each of the three intrerpretations exhibits specific logical features that deserve separate consideration. In particular, the evidential interpretation as we understand it | a precise and well defined ver- sion of it which has never been explored before | significantly differs both from the suppositional interpretation and from the strict interpretation. 1 Preliminaries Although it is widely taken for granted that indicative conditionals as they are used in ordinary language do not behave as material conditionals, there is little agreement on the nature and the extent of such deviation. Different theories tend to privilege different intuitions about conditionals, and there is no obvious answer to the question of which of them is the correct theory. In this paper, we will compare three interpretations of `if then': the suppositional interpretation, the evidential interpretation, and the strict interpretation. These interpretations may be regarded either as three distinct meanings that ordinary speakers attach to `if then', or as three ways of explicating a single indeterminate meaning by replacing it with a precise and well defined counterpart. Here is a rough and informal characterization of the three interpretations. According to the suppositional interpretation, a conditional is acceptable when its consequent is credible enough given its antecedent.
    [Show full text]
  • False Dilemma Wikipedia Contents
    False dilemma Wikipedia Contents 1 False dilemma 1 1.1 Examples ............................................... 1 1.1.1 Morton's fork ......................................... 1 1.1.2 False choice .......................................... 2 1.1.3 Black-and-white thinking ................................... 2 1.2 See also ................................................ 2 1.3 References ............................................... 3 1.4 External links ............................................. 3 2 Affirmative action 4 2.1 Origins ................................................. 4 2.2 Women ................................................ 4 2.3 Quotas ................................................. 5 2.4 National approaches .......................................... 5 2.4.1 Africa ............................................ 5 2.4.2 Asia .............................................. 7 2.4.3 Europe ............................................ 8 2.4.4 North America ........................................ 10 2.4.5 Oceania ............................................ 11 2.4.6 South America ........................................ 11 2.5 International organizations ...................................... 11 2.5.1 United Nations ........................................ 12 2.6 Support ................................................ 12 2.6.1 Polls .............................................. 12 2.7 Criticism ............................................... 12 2.7.1 Mismatching ......................................... 13 2.8 See also
    [Show full text]
  • Material Conditional Cnt:Int:Mat: in Its Simplest Form in English, a Conditional Is a Sentence of the Form “If Sec
    int.1 The Material Conditional cnt:int:mat: In its simplest form in English, a conditional is a sentence of the form \If sec . then . ," where the . are themselves sentences, such as \If the butler did it, then the gardener is innocent." In introductory logic courses, we earn to symbolize conditionals using the ! connective: symbolize the parts indicated by . , e.g., by formulas ' and , and the entire conditional is symbolized by ' ! . The connective ! is truth-functional, i.e., the truth value|T or F|of '! is determined by the truth values of ' and : ' ! is true iff ' is false or is true, and false otherwise. Relative to a truth value assignment v, we define v ⊨ ' ! iff v 2 ' or v ⊨ . The connective ! with this semantics is called the material conditional. This definition results in a number of elementary logical facts. First ofall, the deduction theorem holds for the material conditional: If Γ; ' ⊨ then Γ ⊨ ' ! (1) It is truth-functional: ' ! and :' _ are equivalent: ' ! ⊨ :' _ (2) :' _ ⊨ ' ! (3) A material conditional is entailed by its consequent and by the negation of its antecedent: ⊨ ' ! (4) :' ⊨ ' ! (5) A false material conditional is equivalent to the conjunction of its antecedent and the negation of its consequent: if ' ! is false, ' ^ : is true, and vice versa: :(' ! ) ⊨ ' ^ : (6) ' ^ : ⊨ :(' ! ) (7) The material conditional supports modus ponens: '; ' ! ⊨ (8) The material conditional agglomerates: ' ! ; ' ! χ ⊨ ' ! ( ^ χ) (9) We can always strengthen the antecedent, i.e., the conditional is monotonic: ' ! ⊨ (' ^ χ) ! (10) material-conditional rev: c8c9782 (2021-09-28) by OLP/ CC{BY 1 The material conditional is transitive, i.e., the chain rule is valid: ' ! ; ! χ ⊨ ' ! χ (11) The material conditional is equivalent to its contrapositive: ' ! ⊨ : !:' (12) : !:' ⊨ ' ! (13) These are all useful and unproblematic inferences in mathematical rea- soning.
    [Show full text]
  • Exclusive Or from Wikipedia, the Free Encyclopedia
    New features Log in / create account Article Discussion Read Edit View history Exclusive or From Wikipedia, the free encyclopedia "XOR" redirects here. For other uses, see XOR (disambiguation), XOR gate. Navigation "Either or" redirects here. For Kierkegaard's philosophical work, see Either/Or. Main page The logical operation exclusive disjunction, also called exclusive or (symbolized XOR, EOR, Contents EXOR, ⊻ or ⊕, pronounced either / ks / or /z /), is a type of logical disjunction on two Featured content operands that results in a value of true if exactly one of the operands has a value of true.[1] A Current events simple way to state this is "one or the other but not both." Random article Donate Put differently, exclusive disjunction is a logical operation on two logical values, typically the values of two propositions, that produces a value of true only in cases where the truth value of the operands differ. Interaction Contents About Wikipedia Venn diagram of Community portal 1 Truth table Recent changes 2 Equivalencies, elimination, and introduction but not is Contact Wikipedia 3 Relation to modern algebra Help 4 Exclusive “or” in natural language 5 Alternative symbols Toolbox 6 Properties 6.1 Associativity and commutativity What links here 6.2 Other properties Related changes 7 Computer science Upload file 7.1 Bitwise operation Special pages 8 See also Permanent link 9 Notes Cite this page 10 External links 4, 2010 November Print/export Truth table on [edit] archived The truth table of (also written as or ) is as follows: Venn diagram of Create a book 08-17094 Download as PDF No.
    [Show full text]
  • An Introduction to Formal Logic
    forall x: Calgary An Introduction to Formal Logic By P. D. Magnus Tim Button with additions by J. Robert Loftis Robert Trueman remixed and revised by Aaron Thomas-Bolduc Richard Zach Fall 2021 This book is based on forallx: Cambridge, by Tim Button (University College Lon- don), used under a CC BY 4.0 license, which is based in turn on forallx, by P.D. Magnus (University at Albany, State University of New York), used under a CC BY 4.0 li- cense, and was remixed, revised, & expanded by Aaron Thomas-Bolduc & Richard Zach (University of Calgary). It includes additional material from forallx by P.D. Magnus and Metatheory by Tim Button, used under a CC BY 4.0 license, from forallx: Lorain County Remix, by Cathal Woods and J. Robert Loftis, and from A Modal Logic Primer by Robert Trueman, used with permission. This work is licensed under a Creative Commons Attribution 4.0 license. You are free to copy and redistribute the material in any medium or format, and remix, transform, and build upon the material for any purpose, even commercially, under the following terms: ⊲ You must give appropriate credit, provide a link to the license, and indicate if changes were made. You may do so in any reasonable manner, but not in any way that suggests the licensor endorses you or your use. ⊲ You may not apply legal terms or technological measures that legally restrict others from doing anything the license permits. The LATEX source for this book is available on GitHub and PDFs at forallx.openlogicproject.org.
    [Show full text]
  • Conditional Heresies *
    CONDITIONAL HERESIES * Fabrizio Cariani and Simon Goldstein Abstract The principles of Conditional Excluded Middle (CEM) and Simplification of Disjunctive Antecedents (SDA) have received substantial attention in isolation. Both principles are plausible generalizations about natural lan- guage conditionals. There is however little discussion of their interaction. This paper aims to remedy this gap and explore the significance of hav- ing both principles constrain the logic of the conditional. Our negative finding is that, together with elementary logical assumptions, CEM and SDA yield a variety of implausible consequences. Despite these incom- patibility results, we open up a narrow space to satisfy both. We show that, by simultaneously appealing to the alternative-introducing analysis of disjunction and to the theory of homogeneity presuppositions, we can satisfy both. Furthermore, the theory that validates both principles re- sembles a recent semantics that is defended by Santorio on independent grounds. The cost of this approach is that it must give up the transitivity of entailment: we suggest that this is a feature, not a bug, and connect it with recent developments of intransitive notions of entailment. 1 Introduction David Lewis’s logic for the counterfactual conditional (Lewis 1973) famously invalidates two plausible-sounding principles: simplification of disjunctive antecedents (SDA),1 and conditional excluded middle (CEM).2 Simplification states that conditionals with disjunctive antecedents entail conditionals whose antecedents are the disjuncts taken in isolation. For instance, given SDA, (1) en- tails (2). *Special thanks to Shawn Standefer for extensive written comments on a previous version of this paper and to anonymous reviewers for Philosophy and Phenomenological Research and the Amsterdam Colloquium.
    [Show full text]
  • Forall X: an Introduction to Formal Logic 1.30
    University at Albany, State University of New York Scholars Archive Philosophy Faculty Books Philosophy 12-27-2014 Forall x: An introduction to formal logic 1.30 P.D. Magnus University at Albany, State University of New York, [email protected] Follow this and additional works at: https://scholarsarchive.library.albany.edu/ cas_philosophy_scholar_books Part of the Logic and Foundations of Mathematics Commons Recommended Citation Magnus, P.D., "Forall x: An introduction to formal logic 1.30" (2014). Philosophy Faculty Books. 3. https://scholarsarchive.library.albany.edu/cas_philosophy_scholar_books/3 This Book is brought to you for free and open access by the Philosophy at Scholars Archive. It has been accepted for inclusion in Philosophy Faculty Books by an authorized administrator of Scholars Archive. For more information, please contact [email protected]. forallx An Introduction to Formal Logic P.D. Magnus University at Albany, State University of New York fecundity.com/logic, version 1.30 [141227] This book is offered under a Creative Commons license. (Attribution-ShareAlike 3.0) The author would like to thank the people who made this project possible. Notable among these are Cristyn Magnus, who read many early drafts; Aaron Schiller, who was an early adopter and provided considerable, helpful feedback; and Bin Kang, Craig Erb, Nathan Carter, Wes McMichael, Selva Samuel, Dave Krueger, Brandon Lee, Toan Tran, and the students of Introduction to Logic, who detected various errors in previous versions of the book. c 2005{2014 by P.D. Magnus. Some rights reserved. You are free to copy this book, to distribute it, to display it, and to make derivative works, under the following conditions: (a) Attribution.
    [Show full text]
  • Form and Content: an Introduction to Formal Logic
    Connecticut College Digital Commons @ Connecticut College Open Educational Resources 2020 Form and Content: An Introduction to Formal Logic Derek D. Turner Connecticut College, [email protected] Follow this and additional works at: https://digitalcommons.conncoll.edu/oer Recommended Citation Turner, Derek D., "Form and Content: An Introduction to Formal Logic" (2020). Open Educational Resources. 1. https://digitalcommons.conncoll.edu/oer/1 This Book is brought to you for free and open access by Digital Commons @ Connecticut College. It has been accepted for inclusion in Open Educational Resources by an authorized administrator of Digital Commons @ Connecticut College. For more information, please contact [email protected]. The views expressed in this paper are solely those of the author. Form & Content Form and Content An Introduction to Formal Logic Derek Turner Connecticut College 2020 Susanne K. Langer. This bust is in Shain Library at Connecticut College, New London, CT. Photo by the author. 1 Form & Content ©2020 Derek D. Turner This work is published in 2020 under a Creative Commons Attribution- NonCommercial-NoDerivatives 4.0 International License. You may share this text in any format or medium. You may not use it for commercial purposes. If you share it, you must give appropriate credit. If you remix, transform, add to, or modify the text in any way, you may not then redistribute the modified text. 2 Form & Content A Note to Students For many years, I had relied on one of the standard popular logic textbooks for my introductory formal logic course at Connecticut College. It is a perfectly good book, used in countless logic classes across the country.
    [Show full text]
  • © Cambridge University Press Cambridge
    Cambridge University Press 978-0-521-89957-4 - Handbook of Practical Logic and Automated Reasoning John Harrison Index More information Index (x, y) (pair), 594 ---, 618 − (negation of literal), 51 -/, 617 − (set difference), 594 //, 617 C− (negation of literal set), 181 ::, 616 ∧ (and), 27 </, 617 ∆0 formula, 547 <=/, 617 ∆1-definable, 564 =/, 617 ⊥ (false), 27 @, 616 ⇔ (iff), 27 #install printer,22 ⇒ (implies), 27 0-saturation, 91 ∩ (intersection), 594 1-consistent, 554 ¬ (not), 27 1-saturation, 91 ∨ (or), 27 3-CNF, 79 Π1-formula, 550 3-SAT, 79 Σ1-formula, 550 (true), 27 Abel, 6 ∪ (union), 594 abelian, 287 ◦ (function composition), 596 abstract syntax, 12 ∂ (degree), 355 abstract syntax tree, 12 ∅ (empty set), 594 abstract type, 469 ≡ (congruent modulo), 594 AC (associative–commutative), 285 ∈ (set membership), 594 AC (Axiom of Choice), 144 κ-categorical, 245 accumulator, 611 → (maps to), 595 Ackermann reduction, 254 | (divides), 593 ad hoc polymorphism, 612 |= (logical consequence), 40, 130 Add,14 |=M (holds in M), 130 add 0, 565 ℘ (power set), 598 add assum, 480 ⊂ (proper subset), 594 add assum’, 497 → (sequent), 471 add default, 436 \ (set difference), 594 add suc, 565 ⊆ (subset), 594 adequate set (of connectives), 46 × (Cartesian product), 594 adjustcoeff, 342 → (function space), 595 AE fragment, 309 → (reduction relation), 258 aedecide, 310 →∗ (reflexive transitive closure of →), 258 affine transformation, 417 →+ (transitive closure of →), 258 affirmative negative rule,81 (provability), 246, 470, 474 afn dlo, 335 {1, 2, 3} (set enumeration),
    [Show full text]
  • The Logic of Conditionals1
    THE LOGIC OF CONDITIONALS1 by Ernest Adams University of California, Berkeley The standard use of the propositional calculus ('P.C.') in analyzing the validity of inferences involving conditionals leads to fallacies, and the problem is to determine where P.C. may be 'safely' used. An alternative analysis of criteria of reasonableness of inferences in terms of conditions of justification r a t h e r than truth of statements is pro- posed. It is argued, under certain restrictions, that P. C. may be safely used, except in inferences whose conclusions are conditionals whose antecedents are incompatible with the premises in the sense that if the antecedent became known, some of the previously asserted premises would have to be withdrawn. 1. The following nine 'inferences' are all ones which, when symbol- ized in the ordinary way in the propositional calculus and analyzed truth functionally, are valid in the sense that no combination of truth values of the components makes the premises true but the conclusion false. Fl. John will arrive on the 10 o'clock plane. Therefore, if J o h n does not arrive on the 10 o'clock plane, he will arrive on the 11 o'clock plane. F2. John will arrive on the 10 o'clock plane. Therefore, if John misses his plane in New York,' he will arrive on the 10 o'clock plane. F3. If Brown wins the election, Smith will retire to private life. Therefore, if Smith dies before the election and Brown wins it, Smith will retire to private life. F4. If Brown wins the election, Smith will retire to private life.
    [Show full text]