<<

Int. J. Engng Ed. Vol. 22, No. 1, pp. 35±44, 2006 0949-149X/91 $3.00+0.00 Printed in Great Britain. # 2006 TEMPUS Publications.

The Descent of Biological *

JOEL L. CUELLO Department of Agricultural and Biosystems Engineering, The University of Arizona, 507 Shantz Building, Tucson, AZ 85721, USA. E-mail: [email protected] The genealogy of , spanning a period of at least four millennia, shows that Biological Engineering is descended from the intersections of various disciplines that originate from three ancient pillars of knowledge, including the practices of engineering and and the discipline of philosophy. The descent of Biological Engineering through the ages flowed from the demise of Teleology and from the triumph of Mechanism, making Biological Engineering a thoroughgoing mechanistic discipline, no different in this respect from all the other modern engineering disciplines. It is the mechanistic of Biological Engineering that enables the basic technical activity of Biological Engineering, engineering design, to be successfully accom- plished. The genealogy of Biological Engineering also underscores that, based on historical evolution, precedes Biological Engineering. Based on the disciplinary hierarchy, however, Biomedical Engineering falls under the rubric of the broader, more inclusive, Biological Engineering. Keywords: biomedical engineering; biological engineering

INTRODUCTION ANCIENT BEGINNINGS: THE ADVENT OF TELEOLOGY THE VENERABLE Encyclopaedia Britannica defines `Bioengineering' or Biological Engineering The genealogy of the various disciplines that led as `the application of engineering knowledge to eventually to the melding of engineering and biol- fields of medicine and ' and lists its applica- ogy in the 20th century covers a time span of at tion areas as `Medical Engineering, Agricultural least four millennia, dating from as far back as Engineering, , , circa 3000 BC. At around this time, three pillars of Human Factors Engineering, and Bioenvironmen- knowledge served as foundation stones for the tal Engineering' [1]. Cuello [2, 3] defined Biological gradual rise of the modern sciences and the sub- Engineering as the engineering discipline whose sequent, or perhaps inexorable, convergence of science base is biology, in the same way that engineering and biology. These three pillars were civil and have the ancient practices of engineering and medicine (physics), has electricity plus the discipline of philosophy. Figure 1 illus- (physics), and has chemistry trates the genealogy of Biological Engineering, as their science bases, respectively. Operationally, showing the significant intersections of the various Cuello [4] defined Biological Engineering as the relevant disciplines leading to its genesis. optimization of a task or set of tasks performed by Medicine and engineering in ancient times were or upon a biological system through application of patently not scientific disciplines. While ancient the engineering design process. This operational engineering was part trial-and-error and part definition establishes the basic precept that, similar handed-down knowledge [6], ancient medicine to all other engineering disciplines, Biological En- was part trial-and-error and a large part super- gineering focuses on the engineering design process stition [1]. The first practicing on record as its basic technical activity across its application was Imhotep, who was chief minister for the domains [4, 5]. Today the Institute of Biological Egyptian pharaoh Zoser around 2750 BC and Engineering defines Biological Engineering as `the was credited with building one of the first pyra- biology-based engineering discipline that inte- mids of Egypt, the Step Pyramid at Saqqarah [7]. It grates sciences with engineering in the advance- is noteworthy, if also surprising, that the first ment and application of fundamental concepts of practicing on record was also Imhotep, biological systems from molecular to ecosystem who also served as court physician at the time [7]. levels.' The aim of this paper is to trace the descent Since the earliest practicing engineer and the earl- or lineage of Biological Engineering through time iest practicing physician in recorded history were from its various disciplinary sources, seeking the same person, one might imagine that only a insights into its fundamental philosophical short time would elapse before engineering and foundations. medicine would merge to give rise to Biomedical Engineering. As it happens, more than four thou- sand years had to pass before such disciplinary fusion would occur. * Accepted 22 August 2005. The march of ancient engineering and medicine

35 36 J. Cuello

Fig. 1. The genealogy of Biological Engineering. through the ages toward their modern scientific the sciences of (biology) and physics. incarnations necessitated prior, if not contempora- Existing specimens of mathematics older than neous, advances in the field of natural philosophy, the renowned Egyptian papyri, such as the Rhind and specifically in its branches of mathematics and Papyrus (17th century BC) in the British Museum The Descent of Biological Engineering 37 and the Golenishchev Papyrus (19th century BC) vain' [9]. To him, things do not happen at in the Moscow Museum of Fine Arts, are found randomÐas in the random coming together and among the surviving clay tablets of Mesopotamian separation of atomsÐbut always with an end in scribes dating from the Sumerian kingdoms of the view. And this end, to Aristotle, is the final cause, 3rd millennium BC and the Babylonian regimes of the reason for things happening [8]. Couching his the 2nd millennium BC [1]. These tablets show argument in terms of his concepts of `potentiality' that the Babylonians devised a versatile numeral and `actuality', Aristotle explained that `Actuality system, developed computational methods and is to potency as that which is building is to that solutions for linear and quadratic problems, and which is capable of being built . . . and that which established geometric relations such as that has been shaped out of matter to matter' [9]. between the hypotenuse and the two legs of a Aristotle concluded that things develop toward right triangle, now commonly known as the an end. Thus, the embryo chick in its egg is Pythagorean theorem, more than a thousand potentially a rooster, a block of stone is potentially years before the Greeks used it [1]. There is also a statue, etc. His concept was thoroughly teleo- evidence that a crude form of surveying and logical (i.e. the end governs the means) [8]. As such, elementary mathematics came into use in Egypt he could conclude that `the man is prior to the boy as early as 3000 BC [6]. Pythagoras (530 BC) and and the human being to the seed; for the one Euclid (300 BC) would contribute significantly in already has its form and the other has not, and advancing the mathematics of classical antiquity because everything that comes to be moves [8]. towards a principle, i.e. an end (for that for the Elemental knowledge of physiology can be sake of which a thing is, is its principle, and traced back to ancient Egyptian papyri pertaining the becoming is for the sake of the end), and the to medical subjects. One contains anatomical actuality is the end, and it is for the sake of this descriptions (1600 BC) and another indicates that that the potency is acquired' [9]. the importance of the heart had been recognized Aristotle's second central dogma was that `All [1]. Alcmaeon, a Greek philosopher in the 6th substance appears to signify that which is indivi- century BC, was the first recorded physiologist to dual' [9]. Describing `individual' as `the individual have practiced dissection of human bodies for man or horse,' Aristotle defines substance (the research purposes [1]. He dissected the brain, individual) to be irreducible [8]. Thus, Aristotle optic nerves and the eye, and concluded that the could not understand how the random movement `seat of sensations is the brain' [8]. Herophilus (4th of `billiard-ball' atoms could account for the century BC) also dissected human cadavers and biological phenomena he had directly observedÐ advanced significantly [1]. Alcmaeon, namely, the ordered sequential processes of Herophilus and also Hippocrates, a Greek physi- , the structure and function of animals, cian in the 5th century BC who emphasized the the similarity of parent and offspring, etc. [8]. effects of food, occupation and especially climate Since Aristotle, as those of his predecessors like in causing disease [1], helped bridge physiology Plato, aspired to a philosophy that constituted a into the practice of medicine. comprehensive world system [8], he applied his Physics had its early beginnings in the field of dogmas both to physics and biology. Consistent astronomy. As early as 1800 BC, Babylonian with his theories he applied to biology, Aristotle astronomers worked toward the accurate predic- described motion, which he considered to be the tion of astronomical phenomena, especially the datum with which physicists were concerned above first appearance of the new moon [1]. Their work all else, also in terms of potentiality and actuality. represented one of the earliest systematic, scientific A body in motion is first potentially and then treatments of the physical world. A notable mile- actually at the finishing line [8]. Thus, from the stone in the development of the physics of classical 4th century BC, both biology and physics fell antiquity occurred, however, when Leucippus (430 captive to the battling philosophies of Democri- BC) and later his pupil Democritus (420 BC), tean Mechanism and Aristotelian Teleology. For theorizing on the nature of matter, advanced the mechanism, the means governs the end. Mechan- philosophy of atomism [8]. They posited that ism posits that a given response by a living or a matter is composed of `an infinite number of non-living entity is the necessary result of sequence [atoms] and they are invisible owing to the small- of causes originating from the entity's physical ness of their bulk. They move in the void and by structure and chemical constitution [10, 11]. For their coming together they effect coming into teleology, mechanism's antithesis, the end governs being, and by their separation passing away' [9]. the means. Teleology (Gk. teleologia: telos, teleos, This early, if rudimentary, mechanistic view of an end ‡ logia, doctrine, science or theory) [12] matter, however, clashed violently with the philo- postulates that a given response by a living or a sophy of one of antiquity's most prominent and non-living entity is drawn out of or elicited from influential figures, Aristotle [8]. Aristotle attacked the entity by an end, a goal or a purpose. Some the atomic theory of matter, declaring that, `There definitions of teleology imply that a teleological are some who make chance the cause of both these entity possesses intrinsic purposivenessÐthat is, heavens and of all the worlds' [9]. Aristotle's first the entity `desires some goal, and is behaving in a central dogma was that `Nature does nothing in manner it believes appropriate to the attainment of 38 J. Cuello it' [13]. While teleology has been historically asso- the qualitative Aristotelian orthodoxy [8]. Indeed ciated with vitalism, or the doctrine of vital (spiri- his mathematical approach enabled Galileo to take tual) forces, its modern definition eschews those on Aristotle's physics of motion, culminating in connotations [14, 10]. Isaac Newton establishing one of the laws of the Owing to Aristotle's coherent theories and his new physics, providing that `Everything proceeds vast influence, achieved in part through the school at rest or in rectilinear motion unless acted upon that he founded in Athens, the Lyceum, his tele- by a force' [9]. Newton's first law finally delivered logical biology and physics (which included his the coup de grace to Aristotle's spurious formula- false analysis of motion requiring that `everything tion that `Everything that is in motion must be that is in motion must be moved by something' [9]) moved by something.' gained widespread acceptance until the 16th cent- After Galileo and before Newton there was the ury [8]. Their more subtle forms, mixed with the Roman Catholic priest Pierre Gassendi, who in vitalistic or mystical concepts of spirit and 1649 revisited and revived the atomism of Leucip- essences, however, would continue to linger and pus and Democritus. To make the theory, which would not be completely extirpated from the had long been branded atheistic, acceptable to the natural sciences until the end of the 19th century. Roman church, he asserted that atoms were in the beginning made by God and that they were endowed with a certain impetus by which they OUT OF QUANDARY: are compelled to move until the end of time [8]. THE ASCENT OF MECHANISM Indeed, it was quite probable that Gassendi's revival of atomism influenced Newton's assump- There was a brief shining moment in classical tion of material bodies being composed of particles antiquity, even during the powerful reign of or corpuscles. Thus, it was the triumvirate of Aristotelian physics, when mathematics, science Galileo, Newton and Gassendi that promptly and engineering blended together harmoniously provided a clear path for the physics of the 17th and even in a very modern way. Archimedes century to escape the clutches of the moribund (287±212 BC), a proteÂge of King Hieron of Syra- Aristotelian teleology and to follow the lead of a cuse (c. 270±215 BC), laid the theoretical founda- reinvigorated mechanism. tions for hydrostatics and mechanics through his For biology, the escape from teleology toward application of mathematics in the treatment of mechanism was provided also during the 17th physical phenomena. Indeed, his mechanistic century by the landmark works of Paul Harvey achievement helped him design ships, foremost of and Rene Descartes. Harvey, through his elegant which was a 400-foot-long combination warship, and extensive experimentations, described for the merchant and pleasure vessel, which eventually first time in his 1628 publication, On the Motion of was given to the ruler of Egypt, Ptolemy Phila- the Heart and Blood, the hydraulic understanding dephos (285±246 BC) [7]. What the work of of the cardiovascular system, confirming that the Archimedes underscored, though perhaps not heart is a muscle, that its most important function publicly evident at the time, was that his reliance is to pump blood into blood vessels, and that blood on mathematics obviated any need for him to actually circulates within the body [11]. The appeal to an Aristotelian final cause. mechanistic model by Harvey, who today is Approximately 18 centuries later, Galileo Galilei accorded the honor of being the founder of adopted the same mathematical approach that modern physiology, would later help falsify the Archimedes employed, insisting that `the book long-held vitalistic concept that food was [of nature] cannot be understood unless one first converted into blood in the liver and that some learns to comprehend the language and read the of the blood was carried to the heart to receive a letters of which it is composed. It is written in the quantity of vital spirit [11]. language of mathematics and its characters are In the 1630s, following Harvey's important triangles, circles and other geometrical figures, work, Descartes formulated a thoroughly mechan- without which it is humanly impossible to under- istic conception for the biological system [8]. stand a single word of it; without these one Owing to his dichotomous metaphysical belief wanders in a labyrinth' [15]. Galileo was firm in that `the soul . . . is entirely distinct from the believing that only the application of mathematics body,' he postulated that the activities of the could provide an escape from the quandary of body could be treated solely as the activities of a scholastic arguments [8]. Without appealing to a piece of intricate machinery, necessitating no need final cause and ignoring the vitalistic concepts of of any concept (teleology, vitalism) which could spirit and essences, he treated external bodies only not be equally well applied to the process of non- in terms of `sizes, shapes, numbers and slow or living entities [8]. Such a mechanistic approach swift motion.' This was revolutionary in the 17th guided Descartes methodically in his various inves- century, since it succeeded in starting to divest tigations, leading to his numerous contributions in science of teleology and of the then conventional the physiology of the nervous system and the scholastic concern with the subjective notions of physiology of motion, among other fields. And spirit and essences, and since Galileo's decidedly though the actual theories of Descartes concerning mathematical philosophy contrasted starkly with animal movement were soon discarded, his The Descent of Biological Engineering 39 mechanistic approach continued to endure, REINVENTING MEDICINE AND bestowing on him the honor of having `opened ENGINEERING: THE TRIUMPH OF up a road to the mechanical theory of these MECHANISM processes, which has been followed by all his successors' [16]. In the field of neurophysiology, As the winds of mechanism blew over the `the modern view has in principle departed but domains of the physical sciences in the 19th cent- little from the lead that Descartes gave it' [17]. ury, it was perhaps inevitable that they were also Descartes was expressly followed by those who carried over into the biological realm. With the came after him in the second half of the 17th establishment of chemistry, the propitious time for century, including William Croone and the math- the full implementation of the mechanistic ematician and physicist Giovanni Borelli, both of program that Descartes envisioned for biology in whom studied muscular contractions mechanisti- the 17th century finally arrived. The publication of cally, considering the body exclusively as `a kind of Animal Chemistry by Justus Liebig in 1813 machine or automaton' [8]. Croone's and Borelli's commenced the crossover of mechanistic chemistry iatrophysics or iatromechanics further advanced into the provinces of physiology and medicine. In the influence of mechanism in biology [8]. the process, Liebig ushered in the science of - One more advance, however, was necessary to ic chemistry, the harbinger of today's enable the dominance of mechanistic philosophy in and [8]. Employing his meticu- both physics and biology to transpire: the devel- lous and quantitative analytical chemistry, Liebig opment of the science of the inorganics, chemistry. established the chemical composition of the foods Starting with Robert Boyle, who in 1660 attributed consumed by animals and the constituents of many the `spring' or compressibility of the air to his animal tissues, body fluids and excretory materials philosophy that `the air is nothing but a congeries [19]. His extensive data led him to the conclusion or heap of small and (for the most part) of flexible that, `In the animal body, the food is the fuel; with particles. . . ' to Priestly's discovering oxygen in a proper supply of oxygen we obtain the heat given 1774, and on to Lavoiser's quantitative experi- out during its oxidation or combustion' [19]. Thus, ments in 1789 showing that oxygen is consumed realizing that the body constitutes a form of during animal respiration and is substituted by biochemical machinery, Liebig finally explored carbon dioxide in the respired air, the new science successfully what for a long time had been terra of chemistry was inaugurated and began to be incognita to mechanistic explicationsÐthe source revolutionized [8]. And using his own conceptual of animal heat [8]. His data confirmed that `the models of atoms at the beginning of the 19th mutual action between the elements of the food century, John Dalton successfully accounted for and the oxygen conveyed by the circulation of the the characteristics of gas solubility, which had been blood to every part of the animal body is the described earlier by Henry (now known as Henry's source of animal heat' [19]. Law) in terms of their constituent atoms [8]. Other physiological processes, including neuro- Dalton also showed that the partial pressures of physiology and animal homeostasis, which gases could be attributed to their atomic constitu- remained shrouded in mystery for ages and ents. And, more importantly, Dalton realized that which earlier necessitated the invocation of tele- the observations made earlier by other chemists, ology or vitalism, eventually yielded to completely which came to be known as the law of multiple mechanistic explanations [8]. The early works by proportions, could be explained if it was supposed Galvani (c. 1791), Volta (c. 1792) and Metteuci that the chemical elements were in fact atomic in (c. 1840), linking electromagnetism and neuro- nature and that combinations were produced by physiology, culminated with Du Bois Reymond atomic combinations [8]. Dalton published his establishing in 1848 the physical (mechanistic) major work, A New System of Chemical Philo- basis for the nerve impulse [8]. Helmholtz later sophy, in 1808, and the completed foundations of successfully showed, in 1850, that frog nerve mechanistic philosophy for the natural sciences conducted an impulse at a rate of approximately were subsequently irrevocably established. 30 m/s, confirming Du Bois Reymond's vision of a A far-reaching consequence of the works on purely nonteleological (mechanistic) nervous motion by Galileo in 1632 and by Newton in sytem [8]. And Claude Bernard (c. 1850) opened 1687 and of the establishment of chemistry at the the way to the mechanistic understanding of dawn of the 19th century was that scientists began animal thermoregulation, showing that `the calori- to understand that they could fully account for and fic function proper to warm-blooded animals is explain physical phenomena without appealing to due to a perfecting of the nervous mechanism, an Aristotelian final cause or its associated concept which, by incessant compensation, maintains a of vitalism. An efficient or prior (or mechanistic) practically fixed temperature in the internal en- cause was all that was necessary. This realization vironment' [8]. Thus, Bernard correctly identified later prompted Helmholtz to acknowledge that the cybernetic-control mechanism employed by the `the task of physical science is finally to reduce nervous system in the regulation of body tempera- all the phenomena of nature to forces of attraction ture long before the concept of feedback-control and repulsion, the intensity of which is dependent mechanism was fully understood in the 20th upon the mutual distance of material bodies . . .' [18]. century. 40 J. Cuello

And, ultimately, Schwann's theory (1839), Meanwhile, electrical engineering, which emerged Darwin's theory of evolution (1859), the perfection in 1864 when the Scottish physicist James Maxwell of the atomic theory in the 20th century by J. J. summarized the basic laws of electricity in mathe- Thomson (discovery of electrons, 1897), Ruther- matical form, became in demand with the rise in ford (electrons orbit around nucleus, 1911), Bohr the practical applications of electricity, including (quantized orbits, 1913), de Broglie (electron Alexander Graham Bell's telephone in 1876, waves, 1923) and Schroedinger (wave mechanics, Thomas Edison's incandescent lamp in 1878 and 1926) as well as the discovery of the structure of the latter's first central generating plant in New DNA by Watson and Crick (1953), among others, York city in 1882 [1]. The American Institute of paved the way for a thoroughly mechanistic Electrical was founded in 1884 [21]. approach in deciphering the complex biochemical The collision course between modern engineer- processes that lead to biological self-assembly (or ing and biology began with the ushering of the morphopoiesis). And while today's understanding Industrial Revolution into the agricultural farms of morphopoiesis remains far from complete, it is beginning in the latter part of the 19th century, nonetheless established that its processes do not leading to the emergence of modern agricultural appeal to any teleology. engineering [21]. ( is as As for engineering, Archimedes emerged easily old as the agricultural industry. Its heritage dates from the long lines of mostly obscure military and from farm implements, structures, and the post- civil engineers from ancient Egypt, Greece, China harvest processes invented by ancient civiliza- and Rome as the archetypal engineer-scientistÐ tions.) The American Society of Agricultural Engi- the harbinger of today's modern engineers who neers was founded in 1907 [21], galvanizing the seamlessly combine science and mathematics in application of engineering to `the problems of engineering design [7]. Centuries had to pass biological production and to the external opera- before the rightful successors of Archimedes tions and environment that influence this produc- appeared in a small coterie of scientist-engineers tion' [1]. Indeed, modern Agricultural Engineering in France at the beginning of the 17th century, in the broadest sense is the first bioengineering the foremost members of which were Pitot discipline. Finally, chemical engineering also mate- (1695±1771), the inventor of the pitot tube, and rialized toward the end of the 19th century, Charles Coulomb (1736±1806), a pioneer in the brought into existence by the demands of the study of electricity and magnetism [7]. But manufacture of chemicals and the development although one of the first engineering schools in of the petroleum industry, whose novel technical the world, Ecole Nationale des Ponts et ChausseÂes challenges at the time could not be met by the (National School of Bridges and Highways), traditional chemist or mechanical engineer [1]. The opened in France in 1747, providing engineering American Institute of Chemical Engineers was with a stronger mathematical and scientific foun- established in 1908 [21]. dation [7], it was not until 1847 that `the beginning Thus, around the middle of the 20th century, the of a truly rational and scientific design in . . . mortal combat between mechanism and teleology, engineering' occurred, marked with the publica- which lasted for over two millennia, finally reached tion of Squire Whipple's first treatise on stresses in its irrevocable deÂnouement, with mechanism pilla- trusses [20]. This was followed in 1853 by De ging from the vanquished teleology the latter's Sazilly's analysis of dam design. Since 1847, engin- treasured possessionsÐnamely, the sciences of eering `design passed out of the hands of the physics and biology and the practice of medicine. practical man into the hands of those with scien- The stage was set for the melding of engineering tific training' [20]. From the 19th century to the and biology to finally occur. present, the indispensability of quantitative physi- cal principles to respectable engineering design has become simply axiomatic. THE RISE OF BIOMEDICAL ENGINEERING The development of modern engineering both led to and was spurred on by the formation of Organized discussions on the founding of the professional engineering societies. France's Corps new discipline of biomedical engineering must de Ponts et ChausseÂes (Bridge and Highway have taken place as early as 1947, as suggested Corps) was established in 1716, while Great by the first published Digest (book of abstracts) of Britain's Society of Civil Engineers was founded the Annual Conference on Engineering in Medi- by John Smeaton, the first man to call himself a cine and Biology held in Chicago, IL, in 1962, civil engineer, in 1771 [7]. After this society's which was billed the 15th of such annual confer- dissolution in 1792, some young British engineers ences. The 15th annual conference was sponsored formed the Institution of Civil Engineers in 1818 by the American Institute of Electrical Engineers [7]. And as the Industrial Revolution in Great and by the Instrument Society of America (ISA). Britain transpired in the 19th century, providing For the 17th annual conference held in 1964 in impetus to the development of machinery of all Cleveland, OH, the Joint Committee on Engineer- types, mechanical engineers came to be recognized ing in Medicine and Biology participated as co- and founded the Institution of Mechanical sponsor, in addition to the Institute of Electrical Engineers in Birmingham, England, in 1847 [1]. and Electronics Engineers (IEEE) and the ISA. The Descent of Biological Engineering 41

The American Society of Mechanical Engineers Case Institute of Technology in Cleveland, OH, (ASME) became a participant in 1965 for the which established a clear divide between Bioengi- 18th annual conference, and the American Insti- neering and Medical Engineering in their programs tute of Chemical Engineers (AIChE) became a [25]. Further, defining `Bioengineering' as `the participant in 1967 for the 20th annual conference. application of the knowledge gained by a cross- The following year, in 1968, the Biomedical En- fertilization of engineering and the biological gineering Society (BMES) was founded. It is sciences so that both will be more fully utilized noteworthy that the Biological Engineering for the benefit of man,' the Engineers Joint Coun- Society in the United Kingdom was founded in cil Committee on Engineering Interactions with 1960, though their first conference was not held Biology and Medicine indicated that Bioengi- until 1970. neering is a part of at least six disciplines; The Alliance for Engineering in Medicine and namely, `Medical Engineering, Environment Biology became the official sponsor of the Annual Engineering, Agricultural Engineering, Conference on Engineering in Medicine and Biol- Bionics, Engineering, and Human ogy beginning in 1970. That year the Alliance was Factors Engineering' [26]. Errett Albritton [27] of composed of 18 organizations, including IEEE, the National Institutes of Health (NIH) also ASME, ISA, AIChE and the American Society ascribed a broad domain for Bioengineering for (ASEE). For the 1971 research, including `Biological Systems,' `Eco- conference, the Alliance grew to 21 organizations, logical Systems,' `Prostheses,' `Transducers,' which included the American Society of Agricul- `Laboratory Instrumentation,' and `Bionics.' tural Engineers (ASAE). In 1978, ASME's Bio- The predominant interest in the 1960s and the engineering Division, in cooperation with the Heat 1970s, however, remained the establishment of a Transfer Division, held its first conference on decidedly Biomedical-Engineering discipline as Advances in Bioengineering in San Francisco, opposed to the more general field of Biological CA. The following year, in 1979, the Engineering Engineering. Indeed, even the resolve of the in Medicine and Biology Society (EMBS), a group academic institutions mentioned above to keep formed within IEEE, held its first annual confer- an explicit distinction between Biomedical Engin- ence in Denver, CO. Meanwhile, the Annual eering and Bioengineering buckled over time. Conference on Engineering in Medicine and Today, the Case School of Engineering at Case Biology as sponsored by the Alliance would Western Reserve University only offers Biomedical continue in existence until 1984, when it published Engineering, while the School of Engineering at its last proceedings for the 37th annual conference. the University of Santa Clara offers neither one. Marquette University in Milwaukee, WI, was Meanwhile, at around the same time that enthu- probably the first academic institution to have siasm for Biomedical Engineering was rising in the established a program in Biomedical Engineering, 1940s, interest in the application of engineering dating back to 1953 [22]. A survey conducted and principles to fermentation processesÐa significant published by the Medical Electronics News in 1966 impetus to the conception of a broader biological showed that as many as 37 American academic engineeringÐwas also mounting [28]. The institutions offered programs in Biomedical En- American Chemical Society (ACS) established its gineering at various levels [23]. By the end of the Fermentation Section in 1947. The section was 1970s, Biomedical Engineering had become an later granted a permanent division status within established academic discipline and profession. ACS in 1963, with its name changed to the Divi- sion of Microbial Chemistry and Technology. (The division's name was changed in 1976 to Microbial THE EMERGENCE OF BIOLOGICAL and Biochemical Technology Division, and again ENGINEERING in 1989 to Biochemical Technology Division [28].) In 1966, the American Institute of Chemical Even as Biomedical Engineering was coalescing Engineers chartered its Food, Pharmaceutical & into a defined discipline in the 1960s, there was Bioengineering Division in support of its interests some recognition that Biomedical Engineering was in both fermentation-related engineering and in reality a sub-discipline of a larger umbrella biomedical engineering [29]. discipline, i.e. Bioengineering or Biological Engin- And while IEEE and ASME, among other eering. For instance, the School of Engineering at professional organizations, were endeavoring in the University of Santa Clara in Santa Clara, CA, the 1960s to establish the Biomedical Engineering which in 1966 had both undergraduate and grad- discipline, or perhaps a discipline that was Bio- uate programs in Bioengineering, proposed that medical Engineering with some Biological Engin- the term `Bioengineering' be used in the broad eering included, a small group within the American sense, `including all aspects of engineering and Society of Agricultural Engineers was also at work biology as they are integrated to form a single attempting to advance a more broad-based discip- discipline', so that `Medical Engineering,' `Medical line of Biological Engineering. This group helped Electronics,' and `Biomathematics' then logically form a Bioengineering Committee within ASAE in denote sub-specialties of `Bioengineering' [24]. The 1966 [21]. Also around this time, the Agricultural same sentiment was echoed in the same year by the Engineering Department at North Carolina State 42 J. Cuello

University modified its name to `Biological and of the physicochemical sciences [11]. The purpose Agricultural Engineering Department', to reflect of provincialism is to secure for biological systems its interest in biological engineering [21]. Sibling a `foundation of certainty,' as invoked by Francis departments at Mississippi State University and Crick, who asserted that `the ultimate aim of the Rutgers University followed suit not long after [21]. modern movement in biology is in fact to explain Although discussions within ASAE in regard to all biology in terms of physics and chemistry. biological engineering surfaced as early as 1937 There is very good reason for this. Since the [21], no significant official actions were taken by chemistry and the relevant parts of physics . . . ASAE to facilitate the establishment of the discip- together with our empirical knowledge of chemis- line within its confines over the next five decades. try, appears to provide us with a ``foundation of The late 1980s, however, saw numerous Agri- certainty'' on which to build biology. In just the cultural Engineering departments in the United same way Newtonian mechanics . . . provides States individually reworking their curricula and foundation for, say, mechanical engineering' [31]. programs toward the broader Biological Engineer- The same idea was earlier expressed by Smart [32], ing discipline, and including the term `Biological articulating that `If it is asked whether biology can Engineering' or variations thereof in their depart- be made an exact science the answer is ``No more ment names and/or academic programs. ASAE's and no less'' than technology. If by ``exact science'' first official action on the matter came in 1993, is meant one with strict laws and unitary theories when it formally revised its name from `The of its own, then the search for an exact [biological American Society of Agricultural Engineers system] science is a wild-goose chase. We do not (ASAE)' to `ASAE: The Society for the Engineer- have laws and theories of electronics and chemical ing of Agricultural, Food and Biological Systems.' engineering, and engineers do not worry about this By 1995, as many as 30 out of 49 Agricultural lack. They see that their subjects get scientific Engineering academic departments had included exactness from the application of the sciences of `Biological Engineering' or variations thereof in physics and chemistry . . . There are no laws of their department names [30]. Also in 1995, the biology [or biological system] for the same reason Institute of Biological Engineering was formally that there are no special ``laws of engineering''.' established within ASAE. Five years later, in 2000, Second, the mechanistic (and also provincialis- IBE amicably gained independence from ASAE, tic) philosophy of biological engineering enables and a Biological Engineering Division was offi- the basic technical activity of Biological Engineer- cially formed within ASAE. Today, IBE is the ing, engineering design, to be successfully accom- engineering society that represents exclusively plished. Since the accomplishment of the biological engineering in its broadest sense. Mean- engineering design process requires the forging of while, ASAE, two years before its centennial explanatory (functional) and predictive (quant- celebration, officially revised its name in 2005 to itative) relationships among relevant design `American Society of Agricultural and Biological variables, it follows that the successful accomplish- Engineers (ASABE)'. ment of the basic technical activity of biological engineering hinges upon the establishment of such explanatory and predictive relationships among EPILOGUE relevant design variables in biological systems [4, 5]. (It is noteworthy that, in failing to establish The descent of biological engineering betrays the relationships in biological systems that are at least following insights into this still fledgling discipline. predictive, if not also explanatory, then there First, clearly descending from the intersections of would potentially be no authentic engineering thoroughgoing mechanistic disciplines, biological design and there would potentially be no authentic engineering is also in itself a clearly thoroughgoing biological engineering, at least in the modern sense mechanistic discipline, not at all teleological. of engineering [4, 5].) The mechanistic (and also Hence, biological engineering treats biological provincialistic) philosophy of biological engineer- systems, to which it employs the engineering ing `unlocks' or points directly to specific technical design process, as exclusively mechanistic systems. principles and tools that can be used to forge As such, biological engineering, just like all other relationships in biological systems that are at engineering disciplines, borrows and relies on the least predictive, if not also explanatory, enabling fundamental laws of physics and chemistry in the successful accomplishment of the basic treating biological systems in a predictive and technical activity of biological engineering [4, 5]. explanatory manner, and does not possess its And third, based on historical evolution, Bio- own fundamental laws which are unique from medical Engineering precedes Biological Engineer- those of physics and chemistry nor from those ing. Based on disciplinary hierarchy, however, which the other engineering disciplines employ. Biomedical Engineering falls under the rubric of In short, mechanism breeds provincialismÐthe the broader, more inclusive, Biological Engineering. philosophy postulating that biology (or the bio- Thus, at the beginning of the 21st century, logical system) is a province of the physico- Biomedical Engineering has emerged as estab- chemical sciences and that the advancement of lished, both as a defined discipline and as a biology hinges upon its application of the methods differentiated profession. Attaining to such an The Descent of Biological Engineering 43 established state is perhaps the most pressing as it strives to grow and flourish in the new century challenge that now faces Biological Engineering and into the future.

REFERENCES

1. Encyclopaedia Britannica, 15th ed., Encyclopaedia Britannica, Inc., Chicago, IL (1994). 2. J. L. Cuello, Toward a new engineering order, Agricultural Engineering, 73(6) (1992), pp. 17±19. 3. J. L. Cuello, Choosing biological engineering, Agricultural Engineering, 74(2) (1993), pp. 24±26. 4. J. L. Cuello, An Operational Approach to Systematic Development of a Proposed Framework for Biological Engineering Curriculum, Proceedings of the Institute of Biological Engineering, IBE Publications, Athens, GA (1998a). 5. J. L. Cuello, Mechanism and Provincialism: Two Philosophical Movements Shaping Biological Engineering, Proceedings of the Institute of Biological Engineering, IBE Publications, Athens, GA (1998b). 6. C. J. Merdinger, through the ages, Part I, in C. J. Merdinger (ed.), The Military Engineer, XLIV (297) (1952a). 7. J. Rae and R. Volti, The Engineer in History, Peter Lang, New York, NY (1993). 8. C. U. M. Smith, The Problem of Life: An Essay in the Origins of Biological Thought, John Wiley & Sons, New York, NY (1976). 9. R. M. Hutchins (ed.), Encyclopaedia Britannica, Great Books of the Western World, Encyclopaedia Britannica, Inc., Chicago, IL (1952). 10. R. J. Faber, Clockwork Garden, On the Mechanistic Reduction of Living Things, University of Massachusetts Press, Amherst, MA (1986). 11. A. Rosenberg, The Structure of Biological Science, Press Syndicate of the University of Cambridge, New York, NY (1985). 12. V. Neufeldts and D. B. Guralnik (eds.), Webster's New World Dictionary, third college edition, Simon & Schuster, New York, NY (1988). 13. R. Taylor, Purposeful and non-purposeful behavior: A rejoinder, Philosophy of Science, 17(4) (1950). 14. A. Rosenblueth, N. Wiener and J. Bigelow, Behavior, purpose and teleology, Philosophy of Science, 10(1) (1943), pp. 18±24. 15. G. de Santillana, Dialogue of the Great World Systems, trans. by Thomas Salusbury, 1661 (1953). 16. T. H. Huxley, On the hypothesis that animals are automata and its history, in Collected Essays, Vol. 1 (1898); MacMillan, London (1874). 17. J. H. Woodger, Biological Principles: A Critical Study, Routledge and Kegan Paul, London (1967). 18. H. Helmholtz, Ueber der Erhaltung der Kraft, trans. by J. Tyndall, in W. F. Magie (ed.), A Source Book in Physics (1935); McGraw-Hill, New York, NY (1847). 19. W. Gregory (trans.), Justus Liebig's Animal Chemistry, London (1842). 20. C. J. Merdinger, Civil engineering through the ages, Part II, in C. J. Merdinger (ed.), The Military Engineer, XLIV (298) (1952b). 21. R. E. Stewart, Seven decades that changed America: A History of the American Society of Agricultural Engineers, 1907±1977, ASAE, St. Joseph, MI (1979). 22. A. Sances, Jr., Biomedical Engineering: A Collaborative Program, Marquette University and Marquette School of Medicine, Proceedings of the 8th International Conference on Medical and Biological Engineering and the 22nd Annual Conference on Engineering in Medicine and Biology, The Conference Committee for the 8th ICMBE and 22nd ACEMB (1969). 23. J. N. Martin, Biomedical Engineering Education, Rambach Publications Division, Pittsburgh, PA (1966). 24. R. C. Dorf and J. D. Mandell, Bioengineering at the University of Santa Clara, Proceedings of the Annual Conference on Engineering in Medicine and Biology, The Conference Committee for the 19th ACEMB (1966). 25. R. E. Bolz, Survey of biomedical engineering courses and curricula: Case Institute of Technology, in J. A. Martin (ed.), Biomedical Engineering Education, Rambach Publications Division, Pittsburgh, PA (1966). 26. R. M. Arthur, Bioengineering education, in J. A. Martin (ed.), Biomedical Engineering Education, Rambach Publications Division, Pittsburgh, PA (1966). 27. E. C. Albritton, What is Bioengineering ?, Proceedings of the Annual Conference on Engineering in Medicine and Biology, The Conference Committee for the 19th ACEMB (1966). 28. American Chemical Society, History of the Biochemical Technology Division (2001) (http:// calvin.biotech.wisc.edu/ACS_BIOT/division/histor.html). 29. American Institute of Chemical Engineers, Food Pharmaceutical & Bioengineering Division (2001) (http://www.aiche.org/mag/divisions/divdtl.asp). 30. J. L. Cuello, Faces of Change, Part IIÐResource: Engineering and Technology for a Sustainable World, ASAE, St. Joseph, MI (1995). 31. F. Crick, Of Molecules and Men, University of Washington Press, Seattle, WA (1966). 32. J. J. C. Smart, Philosophy and Scientific Realism, Routledge and Kegan Paul, London (1963).

Joel L. Cuello is an Associate Professor in the Department of Agricultural and Biosystems Engineering at The University of Arizona in Tucson, Arizona, U.S.A, where he has been teaching and conducting research since 1995. In 1994, he was a U.S. National Research Council Research Associate at NASA John F. Kennedy Space Center in Cape Canaveral, 44 J. Cuello

Florida. He received his Ph.D. and M.S. in Agricultural and Biological Engineering from The Pennsylvania State University in 1994 and 1990, respectively; his second M.S. in Plant Physiology also from Penn State in 1999; and his B.S. in Agricultural Engineering from The University of the Philippines at Los Banos in 1984. His two-pronged research on Biological Engineering and Controlled-Environment Engineering currently includes nano-scale bio- sensors, chemical production from cell cultures, hydroponic systems and plant lighting systems.