[Dear Carnap, Dear Van]

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

[Dear Carnap, Dear Van] [Dear Carnap, Dear Van] http://content.cdlib.org.oca.ucsc.edu/xtf/view?docId=ft0c60030x&chunk... Preferred Citation: Quine, W.V., and Rudolf Carnap Dear Carnap, Dear Van: The Quine-Carnap Correspondence and Related Work. Berkeley, CA: University of California Press, c1990 1990. http://ark.cdlib.org/ark:/13030/ft0c60030x/ [Dear Carnap, Dear Van] The Quine-Carnap Correspondence and Related Work W.V. Quine and Rudolf Carnap UNIVERSITY OF CALIFORNIA PRESS Berkeley · Los Angeles · Oxford © 1991 The Regents of the University of California Preferred Citation: Quine, W.V., and Rudolf Carnap Dear Carnap, Dear Van: The Quine-Carnap Correspondence and Related Work. Berkeley, CA: University of California Press, c1990 1990. http://ark.cdlib.org/ark:/13030/ft0c60030x/ ― vii ― [PREFACE] This volume is designed for two distinct audiences. The first of these includes a growing band of researchers who recognize that Quine and Carnap are historically very important and that the more we understand of their controversy the firmer our grasp will be of various central issues in the theory of knowledge and in philosophy more generally. This audience needs as much exact information about the manuscripts as can be provided to serve as a basis for its own research. A second and equally important audience is made up of students (both undergraduate and graduate), interested laymen, and a good many professional philosophers for whom the issues and events of the Carnap-Quine controversy are not matters of regular study. What is essential for this audience is a clear, readable text, unburdened by massive scholarly paraphernalia, and an introduction that lays out the essential philosophic and biographical facts along with a guide to their interpretation. Fortunately, it is possible to meet the needs of both audiences in a single volume. For the first group I have tried to reproduce as much of the character of the original manuscripts as possible: spellings, marginalia, corrections, and so on. For the second group, the information concerning marginalia, corrections, and so forth beyond the original text is reserved to footnotes. This allows a student, for example, to read and follow the basic text without drowning in the scholarly details. I have very occasionally intruded editorial notes and corrections into the text and set off such insertions by means of angle brackets ('<','>'). This is to distinguish these insertions from Carnap's and Quine's material in parentheses or square brackets. That text will have the misspellings of the original, but that should 1 of 343 11/13/2007 10:29 PM [Dear Carnap, Dear Van] http://content.cdlib.org.oca.ucsc.edu/xtf/view?docId=ft0c60030x&chunk... ― viii ― not impair its readability. Besides, it often adds to the charm. Not only does this policy of preserving the "mistakes" conform to standard practice in the editing of scientific manuscripts, it is specifically endorsed by Quine for this project. Where it seemed to me that a reader might mistake an original error for a printer's error, I have inserted '<sic >' in the text. It was generally unnecessary to indicate what would be the corrected expression. I realize that the line is vague between those errors that require notation and those that do not. But vague distinctions are often valuable, and in this case the gain in utility seemed to outweigh the apparent loss of neatness. The text has been proofread repeatedly, so one should assume that residual errors were in the original. The point of this, and of standard practice more generally, is to preserve as much of the character of and information about the original text as possible. It is the very features that editors tend to clean up that often provide evidence of the writer's mood, attentiveness to the issue, estimation of the recipient, or mastery of the language. For this reason it is often desirable to preserve every detail (short of photocopying), such as original pagination, information on whether the document is handwritten, the author's own corrections, and so on. All of this can be valuable in its place, but here the intended audience is wider than just advanced scholars seeking minute clues. Thus, where Carnap or Quine himself makes a correction in his own text, it is printed here in the corrected form with no notation. However, if the recipient makes a correction, this is noted. This becomes especially important in those letters resulting from the practice that Quine and Carnap adopted for a while of writing in each other's language, correcting the letters received for style and grammar, and returning the corrected copy to its author. The originals are still clear enough to be understood, so those are printed here intact, but the recipient's corrections are duly noted in the footnotes. Marginalia are also reported in the footnotes, and their location is indicated in the margin of the main text. Since Quine often composed his reply in the margins or on the back of Carnap's letters, the marginalia are sometimes cumbersome. In order to minimize the volume of footnotes, however, I have omitted information concerning the original pagination and the physical character of the documents. More- ― ix ― over, as is customary, I have rendered underscored material in italics. I have also translated those letters (and passages) which were written in German. This would not have been necessary in a purely scholarly text, but it is provided for students and others who need it. There might have been a question of whether to include both the English and German versions. Since the number of German letters is small, however, both parts of the intended audience could be accommodated without unreasonably compromising either part's needs simply by printing both versions. Thus, letters always appear in their original language first, followed if necessary by a translation into English. Both versions will have the same letter number, for example, 7. But the translation's number will be followed by an 'e', for example, 7.e. It remains, finally, to say a few words about the sources of the documents: their provenance if you will. The "Lectures on Carnap" are taken from a carbon copy in the possession of Quine. Presumably it dates from when the lectures were delivered publicly in the fall of 1934. From that carbon copy, however, a number of pages were missing, removed, no doubt, for some more pressing philosophic business. Happily, a photocopy of the missing pages was supplied by Burton Dreben. There is another lecture entitled "Logical Positivism" which is part of the carbon copy and whose pages are numbered consecutively with the first three. It is not reprinted here for several reasons. First, it was not part of the original series of lectures but was instead given at Radcliffe College on December 17, 1934. In those days Radcliffe lectures were given separately from those at Harvard. Second, the lecture is of an entirely different kind because it is intended for an undergraduate audience. Third and last, the text is incomplete; what starts out as a full written text peters out into a series of lecture notes. The sources for the correspondence are more complicated. Both Quine and Carnap tended to keep both sides of their correspondence. This means that there are often two copies of a letter from which to choose. Wherever possible I have used the original text, noting the changes in the copy. Carnap's letters—that is, those letters and copies in Carnap's possession—passed on his death to his daughter, Hanneliese Carnap Thost. She in turn sold the let- ― x ― ters along with Carnap's library, manuscripts, and other material to the University of Pittsburgh in 1974. The Carnap Collection is enormous, including about ten thousand letters. While Carnap kept 2 of 343 11/13/2007 10:29 PM [Dear Carnap, Dear Van] http://content.cdlib.org.oca.ucsc.edu/xtf/view?docId=ft0c60030x&chunk... everything or seems to have tried to, most of his correspondence with Quine is absent from the material that was sold to the University of Pittsburgh. Why? We do not know. It could have been lost during one of Carnap's many moves; it could have been loaned to someone for some philosophic purpose; it could just unaccountably have been lost. Fortunately, the overwhelming bulk of this material appears in Quine's collection, so it has not been lost to posterity. While Quine has graciously provided copies of his correspondence with Carnap to the Carnap Collection, for this volume I worked directly from the originals which are still in the files in Quine's Emerson Hall office. Are there letters between Carnap and Quine of which we have no copy? Of course. The letters we do have make that plain. Perhaps some of those missing letters may eventually turn up. I certainly hope they do. But in the meantime, we can be reasonably sure that we have the vast majority of the letters that were written, certainly enough to trace the development of their relationship both intellectual and personal. The letters are interrupted in this volume by Carnap's reply to Quine: "Quine on Analyticity." This is transcribed and translated from a shorthand manuscript in the Rudolf Carnap Collection at the University of Pittsburgh. The transcription is by Richard Nollan. Unfortunately there is no entirely satisfactory place to print the paper within this volume. Placing it before or after the correspondence takes it far out of its natural chronological order. Including it within the correspondence would be misleading, for there is no evidence that Quine ever saw the paper. To avoid these difficulties, I have divided the correspondence into two (rather unequal) parts: (1) up through the publication of "Two Dogmas of Empiricism" and (2) thereafter.
Recommended publications
  • Abraham Kaplan Papers 0054
    http://oac.cdlib.org/findaid/ark:/13030/c86q1z11 No online items Abraham Kaplan Papers 0054 California State Polytechnic University, Pomona. Special Collections and Archives 3801 West Temple Avenue Pomona, CA 91768 [email protected] 909-869-3775 Abraham Kaplan Papers 0054 0054 1 Title: Abraham Kaplan Papers Creator: Kaplan, Abraham, 1918-1993 Identifier/Call Number: 0054 Contributing Institution: California State Polytechnic University, Pomona. Special Collections and Archives Language of Material: English Physical Description: 17 boxes Date (inclusive): 1942-1989 Abstract: Abraham Kaplan (1918-1993) was a philosopher, an author and an educator. His collection contains correspondence, articles, lectures, speeches, book manuscripts, subject files, notes, and printed matter pertaining to his writings and academic career. Conditions Governing Access Advance notice required for access. Conditions Governing Use Unpublished manuscripts are protected by copyright. Permission to publish, quote, or reproduce must be secured from the repository and the copyright holder. Preferred Citation [Box/folder# or item name], Abraham Kaplan Papers, Collection no. 0054, University Archives, Special Collections and Archives, University Library, California State Polytechnic University, Pomona. Immediate Source of Acquisition The collection was transferred to the University Archives by Professor of Philosophy James Manley in 2001. Biographical / Historical Abraham Kaplan (1918-1993) was an American philosopher with a long and distinguished career. He was born June 11, 1918 to parents Joseph J. (a Rabbi) and Chava (Lerner) Kaplan in Odessa, Ukraine. Kaplan and his family immigrated to the United States in 1923 and he became a naturalized citizen in 1930. A student of philosopher Bertrand Russell, he graduated from the College of St.
    [Show full text]
  • Rudolf Carnap Papers, 1920-1968
    http://oac.cdlib.org/findaid/ark:/13030/tf7q2nb520 No online items Finding Aid for the Rudolf Carnap papers, 1920-1968 Processed by UCLA Library Special Collections staff; machine-readable finding aid created by Caroline Cubé UCLA Library Special Collections UCLA Library Special Collections staff Room A1713, Charles E. Young Research Library Box 951575 Los Angeles, CA 90095-1575 Email: [email protected] URL: http://www.library.ucla.edu/libraries/special/scweb/ © 1998 The Regents of the University of California. All rights reserved. Note Arts and Humanities --PhilosophyHistory --History, University of California --History, UC Los AngelesGeographical (By Place) --University of California --University of California Los Angeles Finding Aid for the Rudolf Carnap 1029 1 papers, 1920-1968 Finding Aid for the Rudolf Carnap papers, 1920-1968 Collection number: 1029 UCLA Library Special Collections UCLA Library Special Collections staff Los Angeles, CA Contact Information UCLA Library Special Collections staff UCLA Library Special Collections Room A1713, Charles E. Young Research Library Box 951575 Los Angeles, CA 90095-1575 Telephone: 310/825-4988 (10:00 a.m. - 4:45 p.m., Pacific Time) Email: [email protected] URL: http://www.library.ucla.edu/libraries/special/scweb/ Processed by: UCLA Library Special Collections staff, 1998 Encoded by: Caroline Cubé Online finding aid edited by: Josh Fiala, June 2002 © 1998 The Regents of the University of California. All rights reserved. Descriptive Summary Title: Rudolf Carnap papers, Date (inclusive): 1920-1968 Collection number: 1029 Creator: Carnap, Rudolf, 1891-1970 Extent: 56 boxes (28 linear ft.) Repository: University of California, Los Angeles. Library Special Collections.
    [Show full text]
  • BIO MEYERSON CH13.Pdf
    La chute dans l’oubli Bernadette Bensaude-Vincent, Eva Telkes-Klein To cite this version: Bernadette Bensaude-Vincent, Eva Telkes-Klein. La chute dans l’oubli. Les identités multiples d’Emile Meyerson, éditions Champion, 2016, 978-2-7453-3110-6. hal-01496887 HAL Id: hal-01496887 https://hal.archives-ouvertes.fr/hal-01496887 Submitted on 28 Mar 2017 HAL is a multi-disciplinary open access L’archive ouverte pluridisciplinaire HAL, est archive for the deposit and dissemination of sci- destinée au dépôt et à la diffusion de documents entific research documents, whether they are pub- scientifiques de niveau recherche, publiés ou non, lished or not. The documents may come from émanant des établissements d’enseignement et de teaching and research institutions in France or recherche français ou étrangers, des laboratoires abroad, or from public or private research centers. publics ou privés. CHAPITRE 13 LA CHUTE DANS L’OUBLI Meyerson s’éteint en 1933, peu après la sortie de son petit livre sur la physique quantique, sans enfants, sans élèves. Qui peut alors assumer l’énorme travail de diffusion de sa pensée auquel il s’est adonné sans relâche, en entretenant un réseau de correspondants et de disciples ? Faute de relais institutionnels, son œuvre est livrée aux initiatives individuelles et voyage au gré des événements et des modes intellectuelles. En 1992, Jean Largeault publie un article intitulé : « Émile Meyerson, philosophe oublié1 ». Comment peut-on « oublier » une œuvre aussi importante, déjà connue, largement diffusée ? Meyerson a-t-il été simplement oublié, ou plutôt éclipsé, activement effacé de la mémoire? Et une fois disparu de l’avant- scène de la philosophie des sciences, sur quel mode est-il encore lu aujourd’hui ? Dans sa patrie d’adoption, durant les décennies qui suivent sa mort, Meyerson est durablement effacé de la scène épistémologique, cependant sa pensée circule et fait son chemin à l’étranger, en particulier aux Etats-Unis où elle affleure dans le courant qui professionnalise l’histoire et la philosophie des sciences au cours des années 1960.
    [Show full text]
  • Download Report 2010-12
    RESEARCH REPORt 2010—2012 MAX-PLANCK-INSTITUT FÜR WISSENSCHAFTSGESCHICHTE Max Planck Institute for the History of Science Cover: Aurora borealis paintings by William Crowder, National Geographic (1947). The International Geophysical Year (1957–8) transformed research on the aurora, one of nature’s most elusive and intensely beautiful phenomena. Aurorae became the center of interest for the big science of powerful rockets, complex satellites and large group efforts to understand the magnetic and charged particle environment of the earth. The auroral visoplot displayed here provided guidance for recording observations in a standardized form, translating the sublime aesthetics of pictorial depictions of aurorae into the mechanical aesthetics of numbers and symbols. Most of the portait photographs were taken by Skúli Sigurdsson RESEARCH REPORT 2010—2012 MAX-PLANCK-INSTITUT FÜR WISSENSCHAFTSGESCHICHTE Max Planck Institute for the History of Science Introduction The Max Planck Institute for the History of Science (MPIWG) is made up of three Departments, each administered by a Director, and several Independent Research Groups, each led for five years by an outstanding junior scholar. Since its foundation in 1994 the MPIWG has investigated fundamental questions of the history of knowl- edge from the Neolithic to the present. The focus has been on the history of the natu- ral sciences, but recent projects have also integrated the history of technology and the history of the human sciences into a more panoramic view of the history of knowl- edge. Of central interest is the emergence of basic categories of scientific thinking and practice as well as their transformation over time: examples include experiment, ob- servation, normalcy, space, evidence, biodiversity or force.
    [Show full text]
  • On the Origins of Carnap's Aufbau from Reductive Empiricism to The
    The publication of this book was supported by the Student Union of ELTE University and the Student Union of the Faculty of Humanities at ELTE University. Published by the Philosophy Workshop of Eötvös József Collegium Budapest, 2016 Director of publication: Dr. László Horváth Edited by Megyer Gyöngyösi, Zsolt Kapelner, Zsófia Ádám, István Faragó-Szabó Cover design by Hunor Gyöngyösi Designed by Zsófia Machó isbn © 2016 Philosophy Workshop of Eötvös József Collegium © The authors On the Origins of Carnap’s Aufbau From reductive empiricism 13 to the Geisteswissenschaften Ádám Tamás Tuboly Rudolf Carnap’s Der logische Aufbau der Welt is considered to be the magnum opus of (early) analytic philosophy. Contrary to this analytic tradition stands, as the saying goes, everything else – the so called continental philosophies. It has been highlighted recently, however, that the contexts of the Aufbaudiffer radically from the usual received view. In order to obtain a better picture of (the influences of) the Aufbau, I will present in Sect. 1 the received view which characterizes the book as a reductive empiricist, foundationalist and phenomenalist work. In Sect. 2 I will show step-by-step that this view is mistaken and the influences on the Aufbau could be located around Neo-Kantianism, the philosophy of Husserl and the human sciences [Geisteswissenschaften]. The contribution of this paper is connected to these approaches and argues for a different and currently unanalyzed and mainly ignored aspect of Carnap’s work, namely his theory of geistige Gegenstände. After all, I will claim that the motivations and continental roots of the Aufbau are just much deeper than it is usually thought.
    [Show full text]
  • Michigan State University 1956
    AN INVESTIGATION OF THE DISTINCTION BETWEEN HISTQRY AND SCIENCE Thesis Ice II“ Dogma OI M. A. MICHIGAN STATE UNIVERSITY Rolf A. George 1956 AH INVESTIGATION OF THE DISTIHUTIOH BE JESH HISTORY AND SCIEHCE A'EEBIS Submitted to the College of Science and Arts of Michigan State University of Agriculture and Applied Science in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of HAS”ER OF ARTS Department of PhilOSOphy 1950 15-23515 1 i,"' and"? hub." 'fj“"r"'| ‘iCAL;.CJ-4l—I‘JUIJ"~L‘J.LQ“L The author wisIes to express his grateful thanks to Professors Henry 8. Leonard and Lewis K. Zerby for their help and encouragement throughout the course of this investigation. r'1 ' "-T :‘1 ‘. ‘1 M-":? rm“ z ‘ lejr‘“ .LAULLLI (JL‘ Ubulpulo Introductory Jote I4 he Referential Ambiguity of "History” #- Hominai'sm and Realism Concerning "Philo- sophy of history” Science and History mhe Ontologies of Science and history History and Epistemology: Preliminaries History and Epistemology I listory and epistemology II History an Epistemology III p; History 9.) nd Value History and Unified Science An Attempt to Define ”Statement of History" Iindelband's Theory Concernine 0 Subjects and Predicates Concluding hemarhs Footnotes Bibliography Ah II‘EDTIGATION OF THE DISTINCTION BBTJEEN HISTORY AND SCIENCE Introductory hote The purpose of this paper is twofold: On the one hand, it is to discuss some attempts that have been made to find criteria for the discrimination of science from history. On the other hand, it is to offer, tentatively, one such criter- io.. The paper begins by discussing the ambiguity of the word "history," and pointing out some difficulties that have ensued from neglecting this ambiguity.
    [Show full text]
  • Carnap on the Mind-Body Problem and Non-Classical Reductionism
    Carnap on the Mind-Body Problem and Non-Classical Reductionism Christian J. Feldbacher-Escamilla Autumn 2020 Motivation Introduction Observation: We often find a gap of dealing with traditional philosophical topics within analytic philosophy. Examples: • Metaphysics: elimination ) Kripke's essentialism • Ethics: meta-ethics ) Frankena's analytic normative ethics . • Philosophy of Mind: mind-body pseudo-problem ) Feigl's rehabilita- tion In this talk we focus on the mind-body problem \gap" in analytic philosophy. Carnap on the Mind-Body Problem 1 / 28 Motivation Introduction Ad gap: \[I]t was the papers by Smart and Feigl that introduced the mind- body problem as a mainstream metaphysical Problematik of ana- lytical philosophy, and launched the debate that has continued to this day" (Kim 2000, p.1) This expresses the widely held view that the current debate on the mind- body problem in analytic philosophy began during the 1950s at two distinct sources: • in the US deriving from Herbert Feigl's writings (particularly 1958) • in Australia related to writings by J.J.C. Smart (particularly 1959) Carnap on the Mind-Body Problem 2 / 28 Motivation Introduction Recent interest in this field: (Kim 2003), (Heidelberger 2003), (Crawford forthcoming) Brings to the fore: Feigl was important, but relied heavily on Schlick and Carnap. Schlick: double-language theory (some form of \epistemic" identity theory) Carnap: revision of views due to his discussions with Carnap Carnap on the Mind-Body Problem 3 / 28 Motivation Introduction Feigl was important, because of . • . his propaganda for Logical Positivism: A New Movement in Euro- pean Philosophy (published 1931, in the Journal of Philosophy), • .
    [Show full text]
  • Carnap, Reichenbach and the Great Intellectual Migration. Part II: Hans Reichenbach.” Journal for the History of Analytical Philosophy 8(11): 24–47
    Journal for the History of Analytical Philosophy Coming to America: Carnap, Reichenbach and the Volume 8, Number 11 Great Intellectual Migration. Editor in Chief Part I: Rudolf Carnap Audrey Yap, University of Victoria Sander Verhaegh Editorial Board Annalisa Coliva, UC Irvine In the years before the Second World War, Rudolf Carnap and Henry Jackman, York University Hans Reichenbach emigrated to the United States, escaping the Frederique Janssen-Lauret, University of Manchester quickly deteriorating political situation on the continent. Once Kevin C. Klement, University of Massachusetts in the U. S., the two significantly changed the American philo- Consuelo Preti, The College of New Jersey sophical climate. This two-part paper reconstructs Carnap’s and Marcus Rossberg, University of Connecticut Reichenbach’s surprisingly numerous interactions with Ameri- Anthony Skelton, Western University can academics in the decades before their move in order to explain Mark Textor, King’s College London the impact of their arrival in the late 1930s. Building on archival Richard Zach, University of Calgary material of several key players and institutions, I take some first steps toward answering the question why logical empiricism be- Editors for Special Issues came so successful in the United States after the War. This first Sandra Lapointe, McMaster University part reconstructs Carnap’s development between 1923, when he Alexander Klein, McMaster University first visited New York, and 1936, when he was offered a position Review Editors at the University of Chicago. I describe Carnap’s first substantive Sean Morris, Metropolitan State University of Denver contacts with American philosophers as well as the events lead- Sanford Shieh, Wesleyan University ing up to his decision to emigrate.
    [Show full text]
  • Building a New Thursday Circle Carnap and Frank in Prague
    Building a New Thursday Circle Carnap and Frank in Prague Adam Tamas Tuboly Institute of Philosophy, Hungarian Academy of Sciences; University of Pécs, Pécs, Hungary [email protected] 1 Building a New Thursday Circle Carnap and Frank in Prague1 1. Introduction When Carnap wrote a short intellectual autobiography for Marcel Boll in March 1933, he mentioned two things about Prague: (1) that he became a professor at the German University in 1931, and (2) that he worked on his Logische Syntax der Sprache until 1933.2 These things are well known. Carnap spent, however, five long years in Prague, just like he did before in Vienna: so, one might ask, whether (1) and (2) indeed sufficiently characterize his Prague- period. Philipp Frank (1949, 45), who was there for almost twenty years when Carnap arrived, wrote that “[f]rom 1931 on we [i.e. Frank and Carnap] had in this way a new center of ‘scientific world conception’ at the University of Prague.” This seems to be much more than what Carnap claimed. Actually Carnap might have had great expectations regarding Prague: the First Conference on the Epistemology of the Exact Sciences, where the Vienna Circle made public its manifesto, was organized by Frank there in 1929; five years later in 1934 the Preliminary Conference of the International Congresses for the Unity of Science was hosted again in Prague. As Jan Sebestik (1994, 205) claimed, “Prague has always been one of the important European centres of learning and of science, and it has often been the forerunner of vast currents or movements, both intellectual and political.” The city also had a long tradition of scientifically oriented philosophical thinking: through Bernard Bolzano, members of the Brentano-School (such as Anton Marty, Tomáš G.
    [Show full text]
  • Christian Damböck Editor In Uences on the Aufbau Vienna Circle Institute Yearbook
    Vienna Circle Institute Yearbook Christian Damböck Editor In uences on the Aufbau Vienna Circle Institute Yearbook Institut ‘Wiener Kreis’ Society for the Advancement of the Scientifi c World Conception Volume 18 Series Editor Friedrich Stadler , Univ. of Vienna & Inst. Vienna Circle , Wien , Austria Advisory Editorial Board Jacques Bouveresse, Collège de France, Paris, France Martin Carrier, University of Bielefeld, Germany Nancy Cartwright, London School of Economics, UK Richard Creath, Arizona State University, USA Massimo Ferrari, University of Torino, Italy Michael Friedman, Stanford University, USA Maria Carla Galavotti, University of Bologna, Italy Peter Galison, Harvard University, USA Malachi Hacohen, Duke University, USA Rainer Hegselmann, University of Bayreuth, Germany Michael Heidelberger, University of Tübingen, Germany Don Howard, University of Notre Dame, USA Paul Hoyningen-Huene, University of Hanover, Germany Clemens Jabloner, Hans-Kelsen-Institut, Vienna, Austria Anne J. Kox, University of Amsterdam, The Netherlands Martin Kusch, University of Vienna, Austria James G. Lennox, University of Pittsburgh, USA Juha Manninen, Helsinki Collegium for Advanced Studies, Finland Thomas Mormann, University of Donostia/San Sebastián, Spain Edgar Morscher, University of Salzburg, Austria Kevin Mulligan, Université de Genève, Switzerland Elisabeth Nemeth, University of Vienna, Austria Julian Nida-Rümelin, University of Munich, Germany Ilkka Niiniluoto, University of Helsinki, Finland Otto Pfersmann, Université Paris I Panthéon – Sorbonne, France Miklós Rédei, London School of Economics, UK Alan Richardson, University of British Columbia, CDN Gerhard Schurz, University of Düsseldorf, Germany Peter Schuster, University of Vienna, Austria Karl Sigmund, University of Vienna, Austria Hans Sluga, University of California at Berkeley, USA Elliott Sober, University of Wisconsin, USA Antonia Soulez, Université de Paris 8, France Wolfgang Spohn, University of Konstanz, Germany Thomas E.
    [Show full text]
  • Sinn/Bedeutung and Intension/Extension in Gödel's Max
    Sinn/Bedeutung and Intension/Extension in Gödel’s Max Phil IX Gabriella Crocco To cite this version: Gabriella Crocco. Sinn/Bedeutung and Intension/Extension in Gödel’s Max Phil IX. Kurt Gödel: Philosopher-Scientist, Aix-en-Provence (Presses Universitaires de Provence), Presses Universitaires de Provence, pp.127-153., 2016. hal-01473413 HAL Id: hal-01473413 https://hal.archives-ouvertes.fr/hal-01473413 Submitted on 23 Feb 2017 HAL is a multi-disciplinary open access L’archive ouverte pluridisciplinaire HAL, est archive for the deposit and dissemination of sci- destinée au dépôt et à la diffusion de documents entific research documents, whether they are pub- scientifiques de niveau recherche, publiés ou non, lished or not. The documents may come from émanant des établissements d’enseignement et de teaching and research institutions in France or recherche français ou étrangers, des laboratoires abroad, or from public or private research centers. publics ou privés. Sinn/Bedeutung and Intension/Extension in Gödel’s Max Phil IX Gabriella Crocco Aix-Marseille University, CEPERC, UMR 7304 CNRS, France Introduction On 18th November 1942 P.A. Schilpp, the editor of the famous series The library of living Philosophers, asked Gödel to contribute to the volume in honour of Bertrand Russell. The volume was planned for the fall or early winter of 1943, and Schilpp suggested that Gödel’s essay should take the title “Russell’s mathematical logic”. 1 Gödel sent a first manuscript on the 17th of May 1943, and the revised version on the 28th of September. On the same day that he had been asked to contribute the essay, the 18th of November 1942, Gödel began a new philosophical notebook, the Max Phil IX.
    [Show full text]
  • Hans Reichenbach
    [Forthcoming in the Journal for the History of Analytical Philosophy] Coming to America: Carnap, Reichenbach and the Great Intellectual Migration Part II: Hans Reichenbach Sander Verhaegh Tilburg University Ich habe das Gefühl, dass gerade Amerika mit seinem Sinn für das konkrete und technische mehr Verständnis haben müsste für meine naturwissenschaftliche Philosophie als Europa, wo noch immer die mystisch-metaphysischen Spekulationen als die wahre Philosophie angesehen werden. ⎯ Reichenbach to Sidney Hook, January 31, 1935 II.1. Introduction In the late-1930s, Rudolf Carnap and Hans Reichenbach, arguably the two most prominent scientific philosophers of their time, emigrated to the United States, escaping the increasingly perilous situation on the continent. Once in the U.S., the two significantly changed the American philosophical landscape. In this two-part paper, I reconstruct Carnap’s and Reichenbach’s surprisingly numerous interactions with American scholars throughout the 1920s and 1930s in order to better explain the transformation of analytic philosophy in the years before and after the Second World War. In the first part of this paper, I reconstructed Carnap’s contacts with American philosophers throughout the 1920s and 1930s. In this second part, I focus on Reichenbach’s interactions with the American philosophical community before he moved to the United States. I argue that some of Reichenbach’s work from the mid-1930s⎯ in particular Experience and Prediction (1938)⎯ can be better understood if we take into account the context in which it was written. This paper is structured as follows. After an overview of Reichenbach’s ignorance about Anglophone philosophy in the first stages of his academic career (§II.2), I reconstruct his ‘American turn’ in the early 1930s, focusing especially on the reception of his philosophy by a group of New York philosophers (§II.3).
    [Show full text]