Let's Reappraise Carnapian Inductive Logic!

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Let's Reappraise Carnapian Inductive Logic! View metadata, citation and similar papers at core.ac.uk brought to you by CORE provided by Kent Academic Repository Let's Reappraise Carnapian Inductive Logic! Thesis submitted in fulfilment of the requirements of the degree of Doctor of Philosophy in Philosophy School of European Culture and Languages, University of Kent Teddy Groves Total word count: 77523 2 Acknowledgements I am very grateful to Maria Groves, Liam Kofi Bright, Hykel Hosni, Gilbert Harman, Richard Pettigrew, Pavel Janda, Jason Konek, Andr´eCarus, Michael Wilde, Ruth Hibbert, Matthew Wittingham, James Angove for their very gen- erous help with and comments on this thesis. I would also like to thank Jon Williamson, J¨urgenLandes and David Corfield for their excellent PhD supervision. The research that led to this thesis was generously funded by the Arts and Humanities Research Council as part of the project From Objective Bayesian Epistemology to Inductive Logic. Finally, I am very grateful to Brigitte Parakenings and Brigitta Arden for help- ing me to access archival material. All such material inside is quoted by per- mission of the University of Pittsburgh. All rights reserved. 3 4 Contents 1 Introduction9 1.1 Reappraising Carnap.........................9 1.2 Structure............................... 11 1.3 Limitations of this analysis..................... 17 2 Carnapian inductive logic 19 2.1 Introduction.............................. 19 2.2 Historical sketch........................... 20 2.2.1 Related programmes..................... 21 2.3 The methodology of scientific research programmes........ 22 2.3.1 Lakatos's methodology.................... 22 2.3.2 The question of truth-directedness............. 23 2.4 Hard core commitments....................... 25 2.4.1 Explication.......................... 26 2.4.2 Systems of inductive logic.................. 28 2.4.3 Tolerance........................... 33 2.4.4 Summary of Carnapian inductive logic's hard core.... 36 2.5 Other components.......................... 36 2.5.1 Protective belt........................ 37 2.5.2 Negative heuristic...................... 37 2.5.3 Positive heuristic....................... 38 2.6 How Carnapian inductive logic developed............. 39 2.6.1 Less restrictive systems of inductive logic......... 39 2.6.2 Different interpretative requirements............ 40 2.6.3 Families of predicates.................... 40 2.6.4 Measure-theoretic reformulation.............. 41 2.6.5 Versatility........................... 41 2.7 Carnapian inductive logic was progressive............. 43 2.8 Discussion............................... 47 2.9 Additional interpretative points................... 49 2.9.1 Blank slate situations.................... 49 2.9.2 The term `logic'....................... 56 2.9.3 Probability1 .......................... 59 5 6 CONTENTS 3 Critiques 63 3.1 Introduction.............................. 63 3.2 Lakatos's critique........................... 63 3.2.1 Historical background.................... 64 3.2.2 Lakatos's argument...................... 65 3.2.3 Why Lakatos was mistaken................. 67 3.2.4 Why did Lakatos go wrong?................. 68 3.2.5 Summary........................... 71 3.3 Grue, projectability and instantial relevance............ 71 3.3.1 Historical background.................... 71 3.3.2 The objection......................... 72 3.3.3 Artificiality.......................... 73 3.3.4 Carnapian inductive logic can formalise assumptions about projectability......................... 74 3.3.5 Why has grue been such a big issue?............ 76 3.4 Salmon on partial entailment.................... 79 3.4.1 Hume's principle....................... 79 3.4.2 Learning from experience.................. 80 3.4.3 Salmon's argument...................... 80 3.4.4 Responses to Salmon's objection.............. 81 3.5 Other critiques of Carnapian inductive logic............ 83 3.5.1 Universal hypotheses..................... 83 3.5.2 Constant exchangeability.................. 84 3.5.3 Reliability in the limit.................... 87 3.6 Discussion............................... 90 3.6.1 Why were there so many critiques?............. 91 3.6.2 What next?.......................... 92 4 Subjective Bayesian inductive logic 93 4.1 Introduction.............................. 93 4.1.1 Inductive logic and epistemology.............. 94 4.1.2 Subjective Bayesian epistemology.............. 95 4.1.3 Subjective Bayesian inductive logic............. 98 4.2 Probabilistic necessity........................ 100 4.2.1 Betting arguments...................... 101 4.2.2 Cox's axiomatic argument.................. 107 4.2.3 Accuracy arguments..................... 111 4.2.4 Are the different arguments for probabilistic necessity mu- tually reinforcing?...................... 123 4.2.5 Conclusion: probabilistic necessity has not yet been es- tablished........................... 129 4.3 Probabilistic sufficiency....................... 129 4.3.1 Grue-based arguments.................... 130 4.3.2 Dominance-avoidance.................... 132 4.3.3 Howson's logical argument.................. 133 4.3.4 Probabilistic sufficiency has not been established..... 139 CONTENTS 7 4.4 Which kind of inductive logic is best?............... 139 4.4.1 Philosophical comparison.................. 139 4.4.2 Methodological comparison................. 140 4.4.3 Conclusion.......................... 141 5 Objective Bayesianism 143 5.1 Introduction.............................. 143 5.2 Objective Bayesian epistemology.................. 144 5.2.1 Norms of rational belief................... 144 5.2.2 Are the norms justified?................... 146 5.2.3 Methods of representing evidence.............. 146 5.3 Objective Bayesian inductive logic................. 148 5.3.1 Scope for formalising different inductive assumptions... 150 5.3.2 Evidence about physical probabilities........... 151 5.3.3 Evidence about relevance.................. 152 5.3.4 Conclusion.......................... 157 5.4 The assimilative approach...................... 159 5.4.1 Objective Bayesian epistemology as a system of inductive logic.............................. 160 5.4.2 Advantages of the assimilative approach.......... 162 5.4.3 Problem: unconnectedness.................. 165 5.4.4 Assessment of the assimilative approach.......... 166 5.5 Conclusion.............................. 167 6 An application 169 6.1 Introduction.............................. 169 6.2 Statistical model-choice....................... 170 6.2.1 Statistical models....................... 170 6.2.2 Gelman and Shalizi's arguments.............. 170 6.3 The Carnapian account....................... 173 6.4 Advantages of the Carnapian account............... 177 6.4.1 Technical fruitfulness..................... 177 6.4.2 Philosophical foundations.................. 179 6.4.3 Conclusion.......................... 182 7 Conclusion 185 7.1 The current state of the reappraisal................. 185 7.1.1 Historical reappraisal..................... 185 7.1.2 Substantive reappraisal................... 186 7.2 The case for ongoing reappraisal.................. 188 7.2.1 Reassessing the context of Carnapian inductive logic... 188 7.2.2 Carnap's conception of logic................. 189 7.2.3 Other ways of evaluating research programmes...... 190 7.2.4 Carrying out the assimilative approach........... 190 7.2.5 Imprecise probability..................... 191 7.2.6 Double-counting....................... 193 8 CONTENTS 7.3 Conclusion.............................. 193 Chapter 1 Introduction 1.1 Reappraising Carnap Sometimes the scholarly community comes to realise that it should have a second look at an old idea. Sometimes circumstances change so that the old idea acquires extra salience. Sometimes, for one reason or another, it turns out that an old idea had not previously been understood correctly. When this happens and the old idea is re-examined, prompting a change in the general consensus as to its nature and importance, a reappraisal has taken place. In recent times scholars of twentieth century philosophy have begun to recon- sider their views about the German philosopher Rudolf Carnap and the `logical positivist' movement that he championed. Carnap and the other logical pos- itivists had previously been understood as continuing the tradition of British empiricists such as Locke, who sought to establish that sensory experience was the foundation of all human knowledge. Lately, works such as Friedman(1999) and Richardson(1998) have argued convincingly that the logical positivists were not primarily interested in this foundational project, and that their work is better understood in the context of Austro-German neo-Kantianism. Logi- cal positivism had been thought of as an apolitical movement, if not one with reactionary tendencies: a well-informed activist once commented \I cant see anything progressive. coming out of positivism. It just seems to exclude it completely." Chomsky et al.(1988). Recent scholarship, for example Carus (2010) and Yap(2010), has revealed that many of the logical positivists saw their work as part of an emancipatory social project and that that their ideas can make interesting and useful contributions to current such projects. Close examination of the historical record has also overthrown the previous view that the positivists held academic activities other than physics in disregard. For example, Galison(1990) and Potochnik and Yap(2006) unearth connections between the logical positivists and the Bauhaus movement. 9 10 CHAPTER 1. INTRODUCTION This sustained rethinking of Carnap's place in
Recommended publications
  • Abraham Kaplan Papers 0054
    http://oac.cdlib.org/findaid/ark:/13030/c86q1z11 No online items Abraham Kaplan Papers 0054 California State Polytechnic University, Pomona. Special Collections and Archives 3801 West Temple Avenue Pomona, CA 91768 [email protected] 909-869-3775 Abraham Kaplan Papers 0054 0054 1 Title: Abraham Kaplan Papers Creator: Kaplan, Abraham, 1918-1993 Identifier/Call Number: 0054 Contributing Institution: California State Polytechnic University, Pomona. Special Collections and Archives Language of Material: English Physical Description: 17 boxes Date (inclusive): 1942-1989 Abstract: Abraham Kaplan (1918-1993) was a philosopher, an author and an educator. His collection contains correspondence, articles, lectures, speeches, book manuscripts, subject files, notes, and printed matter pertaining to his writings and academic career. Conditions Governing Access Advance notice required for access. Conditions Governing Use Unpublished manuscripts are protected by copyright. Permission to publish, quote, or reproduce must be secured from the repository and the copyright holder. Preferred Citation [Box/folder# or item name], Abraham Kaplan Papers, Collection no. 0054, University Archives, Special Collections and Archives, University Library, California State Polytechnic University, Pomona. Immediate Source of Acquisition The collection was transferred to the University Archives by Professor of Philosophy James Manley in 2001. Biographical / Historical Abraham Kaplan (1918-1993) was an American philosopher with a long and distinguished career. He was born June 11, 1918 to parents Joseph J. (a Rabbi) and Chava (Lerner) Kaplan in Odessa, Ukraine. Kaplan and his family immigrated to the United States in 1923 and he became a naturalized citizen in 1930. A student of philosopher Bertrand Russell, he graduated from the College of St.
    [Show full text]
  • Rudolf Carnap Papers, 1920-1968
    http://oac.cdlib.org/findaid/ark:/13030/tf7q2nb520 No online items Finding Aid for the Rudolf Carnap papers, 1920-1968 Processed by UCLA Library Special Collections staff; machine-readable finding aid created by Caroline Cubé UCLA Library Special Collections UCLA Library Special Collections staff Room A1713, Charles E. Young Research Library Box 951575 Los Angeles, CA 90095-1575 Email: [email protected] URL: http://www.library.ucla.edu/libraries/special/scweb/ © 1998 The Regents of the University of California. All rights reserved. Note Arts and Humanities --PhilosophyHistory --History, University of California --History, UC Los AngelesGeographical (By Place) --University of California --University of California Los Angeles Finding Aid for the Rudolf Carnap 1029 1 papers, 1920-1968 Finding Aid for the Rudolf Carnap papers, 1920-1968 Collection number: 1029 UCLA Library Special Collections UCLA Library Special Collections staff Los Angeles, CA Contact Information UCLA Library Special Collections staff UCLA Library Special Collections Room A1713, Charles E. Young Research Library Box 951575 Los Angeles, CA 90095-1575 Telephone: 310/825-4988 (10:00 a.m. - 4:45 p.m., Pacific Time) Email: [email protected] URL: http://www.library.ucla.edu/libraries/special/scweb/ Processed by: UCLA Library Special Collections staff, 1998 Encoded by: Caroline Cubé Online finding aid edited by: Josh Fiala, June 2002 © 1998 The Regents of the University of California. All rights reserved. Descriptive Summary Title: Rudolf Carnap papers, Date (inclusive): 1920-1968 Collection number: 1029 Creator: Carnap, Rudolf, 1891-1970 Extent: 56 boxes (28 linear ft.) Repository: University of California, Los Angeles. Library Special Collections.
    [Show full text]
  • On the Origins of Carnap's Aufbau from Reductive Empiricism to The
    The publication of this book was supported by the Student Union of ELTE University and the Student Union of the Faculty of Humanities at ELTE University. Published by the Philosophy Workshop of Eötvös József Collegium Budapest, 2016 Director of publication: Dr. László Horváth Edited by Megyer Gyöngyösi, Zsolt Kapelner, Zsófia Ádám, István Faragó-Szabó Cover design by Hunor Gyöngyösi Designed by Zsófia Machó isbn © 2016 Philosophy Workshop of Eötvös József Collegium © The authors On the Origins of Carnap’s Aufbau From reductive empiricism 13 to the Geisteswissenschaften Ádám Tamás Tuboly Rudolf Carnap’s Der logische Aufbau der Welt is considered to be the magnum opus of (early) analytic philosophy. Contrary to this analytic tradition stands, as the saying goes, everything else – the so called continental philosophies. It has been highlighted recently, however, that the contexts of the Aufbaudiffer radically from the usual received view. In order to obtain a better picture of (the influences of) the Aufbau, I will present in Sect. 1 the received view which characterizes the book as a reductive empiricist, foundationalist and phenomenalist work. In Sect. 2 I will show step-by-step that this view is mistaken and the influences on the Aufbau could be located around Neo-Kantianism, the philosophy of Husserl and the human sciences [Geisteswissenschaften]. The contribution of this paper is connected to these approaches and argues for a different and currently unanalyzed and mainly ignored aspect of Carnap’s work, namely his theory of geistige Gegenstände. After all, I will claim that the motivations and continental roots of the Aufbau are just much deeper than it is usually thought.
    [Show full text]
  • Michigan State University 1956
    AN INVESTIGATION OF THE DISTINCTION BETWEEN HISTQRY AND SCIENCE Thesis Ice II“ Dogma OI M. A. MICHIGAN STATE UNIVERSITY Rolf A. George 1956 AH INVESTIGATION OF THE DISTIHUTIOH BE JESH HISTORY AND SCIEHCE A'EEBIS Submitted to the College of Science and Arts of Michigan State University of Agriculture and Applied Science in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of HAS”ER OF ARTS Department of PhilOSOphy 1950 15-23515 1 i,"' and"? hub." 'fj“"r"'| ‘iCAL;.CJ-4l—I‘JUIJ"~L‘J.LQ“L The author wisIes to express his grateful thanks to Professors Henry 8. Leonard and Lewis K. Zerby for their help and encouragement throughout the course of this investigation. r'1 ' "-T :‘1 ‘. ‘1 M-":? rm“ z ‘ lejr‘“ .LAULLLI (JL‘ Ubulpulo Introductory Jote I4 he Referential Ambiguity of "History” #- Hominai'sm and Realism Concerning "Philo- sophy of history” Science and History mhe Ontologies of Science and history History and Epistemology: Preliminaries History and Epistemology I listory and epistemology II History an Epistemology III p; History 9.) nd Value History and Unified Science An Attempt to Define ”Statement of History" Iindelband's Theory Concernine 0 Subjects and Predicates Concluding hemarhs Footnotes Bibliography Ah II‘EDTIGATION OF THE DISTINCTION BBTJEEN HISTORY AND SCIENCE Introductory hote The purpose of this paper is twofold: On the one hand, it is to discuss some attempts that have been made to find criteria for the discrimination of science from history. On the other hand, it is to offer, tentatively, one such criter- io.. The paper begins by discussing the ambiguity of the word "history," and pointing out some difficulties that have ensued from neglecting this ambiguity.
    [Show full text]
  • Carnap on the Mind-Body Problem and Non-Classical Reductionism
    Carnap on the Mind-Body Problem and Non-Classical Reductionism Christian J. Feldbacher-Escamilla Autumn 2020 Motivation Introduction Observation: We often find a gap of dealing with traditional philosophical topics within analytic philosophy. Examples: • Metaphysics: elimination ) Kripke's essentialism • Ethics: meta-ethics ) Frankena's analytic normative ethics . • Philosophy of Mind: mind-body pseudo-problem ) Feigl's rehabilita- tion In this talk we focus on the mind-body problem \gap" in analytic philosophy. Carnap on the Mind-Body Problem 1 / 28 Motivation Introduction Ad gap: \[I]t was the papers by Smart and Feigl that introduced the mind- body problem as a mainstream metaphysical Problematik of ana- lytical philosophy, and launched the debate that has continued to this day" (Kim 2000, p.1) This expresses the widely held view that the current debate on the mind- body problem in analytic philosophy began during the 1950s at two distinct sources: • in the US deriving from Herbert Feigl's writings (particularly 1958) • in Australia related to writings by J.J.C. Smart (particularly 1959) Carnap on the Mind-Body Problem 2 / 28 Motivation Introduction Recent interest in this field: (Kim 2003), (Heidelberger 2003), (Crawford forthcoming) Brings to the fore: Feigl was important, but relied heavily on Schlick and Carnap. Schlick: double-language theory (some form of \epistemic" identity theory) Carnap: revision of views due to his discussions with Carnap Carnap on the Mind-Body Problem 3 / 28 Motivation Introduction Feigl was important, because of . • . his propaganda for Logical Positivism: A New Movement in Euro- pean Philosophy (published 1931, in the Journal of Philosophy), • .
    [Show full text]
  • Carnap, Reichenbach and the Great Intellectual Migration. Part II: Hans Reichenbach.” Journal for the History of Analytical Philosophy 8(11): 24–47
    Journal for the History of Analytical Philosophy Coming to America: Carnap, Reichenbach and the Volume 8, Number 11 Great Intellectual Migration. Editor in Chief Part I: Rudolf Carnap Audrey Yap, University of Victoria Sander Verhaegh Editorial Board Annalisa Coliva, UC Irvine In the years before the Second World War, Rudolf Carnap and Henry Jackman, York University Hans Reichenbach emigrated to the United States, escaping the Frederique Janssen-Lauret, University of Manchester quickly deteriorating political situation on the continent. Once Kevin C. Klement, University of Massachusetts in the U. S., the two significantly changed the American philo- Consuelo Preti, The College of New Jersey sophical climate. This two-part paper reconstructs Carnap’s and Marcus Rossberg, University of Connecticut Reichenbach’s surprisingly numerous interactions with Ameri- Anthony Skelton, Western University can academics in the decades before their move in order to explain Mark Textor, King’s College London the impact of their arrival in the late 1930s. Building on archival Richard Zach, University of Calgary material of several key players and institutions, I take some first steps toward answering the question why logical empiricism be- Editors for Special Issues came so successful in the United States after the War. This first Sandra Lapointe, McMaster University part reconstructs Carnap’s development between 1923, when he Alexander Klein, McMaster University first visited New York, and 1936, when he was offered a position Review Editors at the University of Chicago. I describe Carnap’s first substantive Sean Morris, Metropolitan State University of Denver contacts with American philosophers as well as the events lead- Sanford Shieh, Wesleyan University ing up to his decision to emigrate.
    [Show full text]
  • Building a New Thursday Circle Carnap and Frank in Prague
    Building a New Thursday Circle Carnap and Frank in Prague Adam Tamas Tuboly Institute of Philosophy, Hungarian Academy of Sciences; University of Pécs, Pécs, Hungary [email protected] 1 Building a New Thursday Circle Carnap and Frank in Prague1 1. Introduction When Carnap wrote a short intellectual autobiography for Marcel Boll in March 1933, he mentioned two things about Prague: (1) that he became a professor at the German University in 1931, and (2) that he worked on his Logische Syntax der Sprache until 1933.2 These things are well known. Carnap spent, however, five long years in Prague, just like he did before in Vienna: so, one might ask, whether (1) and (2) indeed sufficiently characterize his Prague- period. Philipp Frank (1949, 45), who was there for almost twenty years when Carnap arrived, wrote that “[f]rom 1931 on we [i.e. Frank and Carnap] had in this way a new center of ‘scientific world conception’ at the University of Prague.” This seems to be much more than what Carnap claimed. Actually Carnap might have had great expectations regarding Prague: the First Conference on the Epistemology of the Exact Sciences, where the Vienna Circle made public its manifesto, was organized by Frank there in 1929; five years later in 1934 the Preliminary Conference of the International Congresses for the Unity of Science was hosted again in Prague. As Jan Sebestik (1994, 205) claimed, “Prague has always been one of the important European centres of learning and of science, and it has often been the forerunner of vast currents or movements, both intellectual and political.” The city also had a long tradition of scientifically oriented philosophical thinking: through Bernard Bolzano, members of the Brentano-School (such as Anton Marty, Tomáš G.
    [Show full text]
  • Christian Damböck Editor In Uences on the Aufbau Vienna Circle Institute Yearbook
    Vienna Circle Institute Yearbook Christian Damböck Editor In uences on the Aufbau Vienna Circle Institute Yearbook Institut ‘Wiener Kreis’ Society for the Advancement of the Scientifi c World Conception Volume 18 Series Editor Friedrich Stadler , Univ. of Vienna & Inst. Vienna Circle , Wien , Austria Advisory Editorial Board Jacques Bouveresse, Collège de France, Paris, France Martin Carrier, University of Bielefeld, Germany Nancy Cartwright, London School of Economics, UK Richard Creath, Arizona State University, USA Massimo Ferrari, University of Torino, Italy Michael Friedman, Stanford University, USA Maria Carla Galavotti, University of Bologna, Italy Peter Galison, Harvard University, USA Malachi Hacohen, Duke University, USA Rainer Hegselmann, University of Bayreuth, Germany Michael Heidelberger, University of Tübingen, Germany Don Howard, University of Notre Dame, USA Paul Hoyningen-Huene, University of Hanover, Germany Clemens Jabloner, Hans-Kelsen-Institut, Vienna, Austria Anne J. Kox, University of Amsterdam, The Netherlands Martin Kusch, University of Vienna, Austria James G. Lennox, University of Pittsburgh, USA Juha Manninen, Helsinki Collegium for Advanced Studies, Finland Thomas Mormann, University of Donostia/San Sebastián, Spain Edgar Morscher, University of Salzburg, Austria Kevin Mulligan, Université de Genève, Switzerland Elisabeth Nemeth, University of Vienna, Austria Julian Nida-Rümelin, University of Munich, Germany Ilkka Niiniluoto, University of Helsinki, Finland Otto Pfersmann, Université Paris I Panthéon – Sorbonne, France Miklós Rédei, London School of Economics, UK Alan Richardson, University of British Columbia, CDN Gerhard Schurz, University of Düsseldorf, Germany Peter Schuster, University of Vienna, Austria Karl Sigmund, University of Vienna, Austria Hans Sluga, University of California at Berkeley, USA Elliott Sober, University of Wisconsin, USA Antonia Soulez, Université de Paris 8, France Wolfgang Spohn, University of Konstanz, Germany Thomas E.
    [Show full text]
  • Sinn/Bedeutung and Intension/Extension in Gödel's Max
    Sinn/Bedeutung and Intension/Extension in Gödel’s Max Phil IX Gabriella Crocco To cite this version: Gabriella Crocco. Sinn/Bedeutung and Intension/Extension in Gödel’s Max Phil IX. Kurt Gödel: Philosopher-Scientist, Aix-en-Provence (Presses Universitaires de Provence), Presses Universitaires de Provence, pp.127-153., 2016. hal-01473413 HAL Id: hal-01473413 https://hal.archives-ouvertes.fr/hal-01473413 Submitted on 23 Feb 2017 HAL is a multi-disciplinary open access L’archive ouverte pluridisciplinaire HAL, est archive for the deposit and dissemination of sci- destinée au dépôt et à la diffusion de documents entific research documents, whether they are pub- scientifiques de niveau recherche, publiés ou non, lished or not. The documents may come from émanant des établissements d’enseignement et de teaching and research institutions in France or recherche français ou étrangers, des laboratoires abroad, or from public or private research centers. publics ou privés. Sinn/Bedeutung and Intension/Extension in Gödel’s Max Phil IX Gabriella Crocco Aix-Marseille University, CEPERC, UMR 7304 CNRS, France Introduction On 18th November 1942 P.A. Schilpp, the editor of the famous series The library of living Philosophers, asked Gödel to contribute to the volume in honour of Bertrand Russell. The volume was planned for the fall or early winter of 1943, and Schilpp suggested that Gödel’s essay should take the title “Russell’s mathematical logic”. 1 Gödel sent a first manuscript on the 17th of May 1943, and the revised version on the 28th of September. On the same day that he had been asked to contribute the essay, the 18th of November 1942, Gödel began a new philosophical notebook, the Max Phil IX.
    [Show full text]
  • Hans Reichenbach
    [Forthcoming in the Journal for the History of Analytical Philosophy] Coming to America: Carnap, Reichenbach and the Great Intellectual Migration Part II: Hans Reichenbach Sander Verhaegh Tilburg University Ich habe das Gefühl, dass gerade Amerika mit seinem Sinn für das konkrete und technische mehr Verständnis haben müsste für meine naturwissenschaftliche Philosophie als Europa, wo noch immer die mystisch-metaphysischen Spekulationen als die wahre Philosophie angesehen werden. ⎯ Reichenbach to Sidney Hook, January 31, 1935 II.1. Introduction In the late-1930s, Rudolf Carnap and Hans Reichenbach, arguably the two most prominent scientific philosophers of their time, emigrated to the United States, escaping the increasingly perilous situation on the continent. Once in the U.S., the two significantly changed the American philosophical landscape. In this two-part paper, I reconstruct Carnap’s and Reichenbach’s surprisingly numerous interactions with American scholars throughout the 1920s and 1930s in order to better explain the transformation of analytic philosophy in the years before and after the Second World War. In the first part of this paper, I reconstructed Carnap’s contacts with American philosophers throughout the 1920s and 1930s. In this second part, I focus on Reichenbach’s interactions with the American philosophical community before he moved to the United States. I argue that some of Reichenbach’s work from the mid-1930s⎯ in particular Experience and Prediction (1938)⎯ can be better understood if we take into account the context in which it was written. This paper is structured as follows. After an overview of Reichenbach’s ignorance about Anglophone philosophy in the first stages of his academic career (§II.2), I reconstruct his ‘American turn’ in the early 1930s, focusing especially on the reception of his philosophy by a group of New York philosophers (§II.3).
    [Show full text]
  • Carnap and the Ontology of Mathematics
    Carnap and the Ontology of Mathematics Benjamin Marschall Darwin College, University of Cambridge February 2020 This thesis is submitted for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy. Declaration This thesis is the result of my own work and includes nothing which is the out- come of work done in collaboration except as declared in the Preface and speci- fied in the text. It is not substantially the same as any that I have submitted, or, is being concurrently submitted for a degree or diploma or other qualification at the University of Cambridge or any other University or similar institution except as declared in the Preface and specified in the text. I further state that no sub- stantial part of my thesis has already been submitted, or, is being concurrently submitted for any such degree, diploma or other qualification at the University of Cambridge or any other University or similar institution except as declared in the Preface and specified in the text. It does not exceed the prescribed word limit for the relevant Degree Committee. Abstract Carnap and the Ontology of Mathematics Benjamin Marschall In this thesis I investigate Rudolf Carnap’s philosophy of mathematics. Most philosophers assume that the nature of mathematics raises deep philosophical questions, which call for theories about how we manage to know about and interact with abstract objects. Carnap’s position, in contrast, is deflationary: he aims to show that we can take mathematics at face value without having to answer questions about the metaphysical status of mathematical objects. If Carnap is right, there is thus no need for a philosophy of mathematics as it is usually understood at all.
    [Show full text]
  • Reply to Critics of Philosophical Analysis in the Twentieth Century
    Scott Soames Reply to Critics of Philosophical Analysis in the Twentieth Century: Christopher Pincock, Thomas Hurka, Michael Kremer, and Paul Horwich Pacific Division Meetings of the American Philosophical Association Portland, Oregon March 25, 2006 Volume 1 Reply to Christopher Pincock and Thomas Hurka Pincock Chris Pincock is offended that I presumed to write a historical overview of analytic philosophy without filling it with scholarly detail provided by specialists. Instead of relying on them, I simply read the works of leading philosophers and tried to figure out for myself what they were up to. Didn’t I know that this is impossible? I myself point out in the Epilogue that the history of philosophy is now a specialized discipline. How, Pincock wonders, could I have failed to recognize the implications of this lesson for my own project? Don’t try this at home! Read the original works, if you must, but don’t dare say anything about the views you find – let alone evaluate them by contemporary standards -- unless you first vet your remarks with those in the archives. History isn’t easy, you know! On the contrary, Pincock tells us, “the overriding lesson of work in the history of analytic philosophy is that history is hard.” Conveying that lesson should, he tells us, be the main goal of any historical introduction to the subject. “Above all,” he says, “I would hope that the reader would finish reading such a book with an appreciation of the difficulties inherent in the study of the history of philosophy.” This, I submit, is self-serving nonsense.
    [Show full text]