Carnap, Reichenbach and the Great Intellectual Migration.Part II

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Carnap, Reichenbach and the Great Intellectual Migration.Part II Journal for the History of Analytical Philosophy Coming to America: Carnap, Reichenbach and the Volume 8, Number 11 Great Intellectual Migration. Editor in Chief Part II: Hans Reichenbach Audrey Yap, University of Victoria Sander Verhaegh Editorial Board Annalisa Coliva, UC Irvine In the late 1930s, a few years before the start of the Second Henry Jackman, York University World War, a small number of European philosophers of sci- Frederique Janssen-Lauret, University of Manchester ence emigrated to the United States, escaping the increasingly Kevin C. Klement, University of Massachusetts perilous situation on the continent. Among the first expatriates Consuelo Preti, The College of New Jersey were Rudolf Carnap and Hans Reichenbach, arguably the most Marcus Rossberg, University of Connecticut influential logical empiricists of their time. In this two-part pa- Anthony Skelton, Western University per, I reconstruct Carnap’s and Reichenbach’s surprisingly nu- Mark Textor, King’s College London merous interactions with American academics in the decades Richard Zach, University of Calgary before their move in order to explain the impact of their arrival in the late 1930s. This second part traces Reichenbach’s devel- Editors for Special Issues opment and focuses on his frequent interactions with American Sandra Lapointe, McMaster University academics throughout the 1930s. I show that Reichenbach was Alexander Klein, McMaster University quite ignorant about developments in Anglophone philosophy Review Editors in the first stages of his career but became increasingly focused Sean Morris, Metropolitan State University of Denver on the United States from the late 1920s onwards. I reconstruct Sanford Shieh, Wesleyan University Reichenbach’s efforts to find a job across the Atlantic and show that some of his English publications—most notably Experience Design and Layout and Prediction—were attempts to change the American narrative Daniel Harris, Hunter College about logical empiricism. Whereas U. S. philosophers identified Kevin C. Klement, University of Massachusetts scientific philosophy with the views of the Vienna Circle, Re- ichenbach aimed to market his probabilistic philosophy of sci- ISSN: 2159-0303 ence as a subtler alternative. jhaponline.org © 2020 Sander Verhaegh Coming to America: Carnap, Reichenbach This part is structured as follows: after an overview of Re- and the Great Intellectual Migration. ichenbach’s ignorance about Anglophone philosophy in the first Part II: Hans Reichenbach stages of his academic career (2), I reconstruct his “American turn” in the early 1930s, focusing especially on the reception of his philosophy by a group of New York philosophers (3). Sander Verhaegh Next, I describe the increasing tensions between Reichenbach and the Vienna Circle (4) and—after an intermezzo reconstruct- ing Reichenbach’s first attempts to find a position in the United Ich habe das Gefühl, dass gerade Amerika mit seinem Sinn für das States (5–6)—I outline his efforts to correct the American narra- konkrete und technische mehr Verständnis haben müsste für meine tive about the role the Vienna Circle played in the development naturwissenschaftliche Philosophie als Europa, wo noch immer die of scientific philosophy (7, 9). In the final sections, I reconstruct mystisch-metaphysischen Spekulationen als die wahre Philosophie angesehen werden. how Reichenbach finally found a job with the help of Charles Morris, who, I show, played a crucial role in the development of Reichenbach to Sidney Hook, 31 January 1935 scientific philosophy in the United States (8, 10) and I conclude this two-part paper with a discussion of the ways in which the 1. Introduction story of Carnap’s and Reichenbach’s turn to America sheds new light on the development of logical empiricism. In the late 1930s, Rudolf Carnap and Hans Reichenbach, ar- guably the two most prominent logical empiricists of their time, emigrated to the United States, escaping the increasingly per- 2. Early insularity ilous situation on the continent. Once in the U. S., the two significantly changed the American philosophical landscape. In the first phase of his academic career, Reichenbach appears In this two-part paper, I reconstruct Carnap’s and Reichen- to have been largely ignorant about Anglophone developments bach’s surprisingly numerous interactions with American schol- in the philosophy of science. In debates about the philosophical ars throughout the 1920s and 1930s in order to better explain the implications of relativity theory, the focal point of his writings transformation of analytic philosophy in the years before and af- throughout the 1920s, Reichenbach almost exclusively concen- ter the Second World War. In the first part of this paper (Verhaegh trated on German interlocutors such as Moritz Schlick, Ernst 2020), I reconstructed Carnap’s contacts with American philoso- Cassirer, and Hermann Weyl, who had all published influen- phers throughout the 1920s and 1930s. In this second part, I focus tial analyses of Einstein’s theory of relativity in the late 1910s 2 on Reichenbach’s interactions with the American philosophical and early 1920s. Although there was a significant literature community before he moved to the United States. I argue that Archives of Scientific Philosophy, the Charles Morris’ Records of the Unity of some of Reichenbach’s work from the mid-1930s, in particular Science Movement (USM), the papers of Moritz Schlick at the Wiener Kreis Experience and Prediction (1938a), can be better understood if we Archiv in Haarlem (MSP), and the University of Chicago Archives (UCA). take into account the context in which it was written.1 Transcriptions and translations are mine unless indicated otherwise. 2 1 See, e.g., Schlick (1917), Cassirer (1921), Weyl (1923), and, for a reconstruc- The present paper is based on material from the Hans Reichenbach Papers tion, Ryckman (2005). (hereafter, HRP) and the Rudolf Carnap Papers (hereafter, RCP) at Pittsburgh’s Journal for the History of Analytical Philosophy vol. 8 no. 11 [24] on relativity theory in the United States (e.g., Carmichael 1912; work of Charles Sanders Peirce, who had already been develop- Tolman 1917) and in Great Britain (e.g., Robb 1914; Eddington ing a frequency theory of probability in the late 19th century. In 1918), he cited no contemporary Anglophone philosophers or fact, it was not until the mid-1930s, when he had just published scientists in Relativitätstheorie und Erkenntnis apriori (1920), the his Wahrscheinlichkeitslehre (1935b), that Reichenbach discovered book in which Reichenbach first explicated his “method of logi- that his theory was “just in the line of [Peirce’s] thought” (Re- cal analysis”, arguing that it is the task of philosophy to classify ichenbach to Hook, 19 October 1935, HRP, 013-46-72).5 and order the fundamental assumptions of scientific theories. Reichenbach’s parochialism was not unique. At the time, many Reichenbach’s ignorance about the Anglophone world is even German philosophers almost exclusively focused on internal, more evident in his second book, Axiomatik der relativistischen Germanophone debates—a situation that often annoyed their Raum-Zeit-Lehre (1924), which applies this method by develop- American contemporaries. The New York philosopher Sidney ing an axiomatization of relativity theory. The book completely Hook, for example, aptly described the problem in a report about ignores the work of Alfred Arthur Robb, a Cambridge mathe- his year in Europe: matician who had constructed a similar axiomatization about What impresses the foreign student . is . [t]he insularity of ten years before (Robb 1914). Whereas Reichenbach devised an German philosophy . epitomized in the naïve declaration of one axiom system which assumed “the relation of cause and effect” Privat-dozent that the history of philosophy . since Kant is the as a primitive term (1956, 25), Robb had developed a relativistic history of German philosophy . Whitehead, Dewey and San- geometry on a purely causal basis, a view that has been dubbed tayana, are hardly names . William James seems to be the only the “causal theory of space-time” (Winnie 1977). Unlike Weyl, American philosopher who is known—and he is more often ‘re- who cited Robb’s work in his influential Spanish lectures (1923, futed’ than read. I have heard many refutations of pragmatism in 8), Reichenbach seems to have been unaware that a comparable Germany. Most of them were variations on the theme that man is 3 born to something higher than merely to fill his stomach. (Hook system had already been developed. 1930, 146) Also in his early work on probability, the fundamental theme of his philosophy throughout his career, Reichenbach was surpris- Nor was this shortsightedness restricted to the Schulphilosophen, ingly ignorant about Anglophone developments. Although John often accused of navel-gazing by scientific philosophers. When Maynard Keynes had made significant contributions to probabil- Ernest Nagel first visited a meeting of the Unity of Science move- ity theory in the early 1920s, Reichenbach appears to have been ment in the mid 1930s, for example, he was surprised to learn unaware of Keynes’ work until the latter’s Treatise on Probabil- that the attendants had no knowledge of Peirce’s philosophy. ity was translated into German.4 Nor did Reichenbach cite the In a report about the conference, Nagel wondered whether this testified “the provincialism of their reading habits” or the “inac- 3 See also Glymour and Eberhardt (2016): “Reichenbach’s apparent unfamil- cessibility
Recommended publications
  • Abraham Kaplan Papers 0054
    http://oac.cdlib.org/findaid/ark:/13030/c86q1z11 No online items Abraham Kaplan Papers 0054 California State Polytechnic University, Pomona. Special Collections and Archives 3801 West Temple Avenue Pomona, CA 91768 [email protected] 909-869-3775 Abraham Kaplan Papers 0054 0054 1 Title: Abraham Kaplan Papers Creator: Kaplan, Abraham, 1918-1993 Identifier/Call Number: 0054 Contributing Institution: California State Polytechnic University, Pomona. Special Collections and Archives Language of Material: English Physical Description: 17 boxes Date (inclusive): 1942-1989 Abstract: Abraham Kaplan (1918-1993) was a philosopher, an author and an educator. His collection contains correspondence, articles, lectures, speeches, book manuscripts, subject files, notes, and printed matter pertaining to his writings and academic career. Conditions Governing Access Advance notice required for access. Conditions Governing Use Unpublished manuscripts are protected by copyright. Permission to publish, quote, or reproduce must be secured from the repository and the copyright holder. Preferred Citation [Box/folder# or item name], Abraham Kaplan Papers, Collection no. 0054, University Archives, Special Collections and Archives, University Library, California State Polytechnic University, Pomona. Immediate Source of Acquisition The collection was transferred to the University Archives by Professor of Philosophy James Manley in 2001. Biographical / Historical Abraham Kaplan (1918-1993) was an American philosopher with a long and distinguished career. He was born June 11, 1918 to parents Joseph J. (a Rabbi) and Chava (Lerner) Kaplan in Odessa, Ukraine. Kaplan and his family immigrated to the United States in 1923 and he became a naturalized citizen in 1930. A student of philosopher Bertrand Russell, he graduated from the College of St.
    [Show full text]
  • CAUSATION Chapter 4 Humean Reductionism
    CAUSATION Chapter 4 Humean Reductionism – Analyses in Terms of Nomological Conditions Many different accounts of causation, of a Humean reductionist sort, have been advanced, but four types are especially important. Of these, three involve analytical reductionism. First, there are approaches which start out from the general notion of a law of nature, then define the ideas of necessary, and sufficient, nomological conditions, and, finally, employ the latter concepts to explain what it is for one state of affairs to cause another. Secondly, there are approaches that employ subjunctive conditionals, either in an attempt to give a purely counterfactual analysis of causation (David Lewis, 1973 and 1979), or as a supplement to other notions, such as that of agency (Georg von Wright, 1971). Thirdly, there are approaches that employ the idea of probability, either to formulate a purely probabilistic analysis (Hans Reichenbach, 1956; I. J. Good, 1961 and 1962; Patrick Suppes, 1970; Ellery Eells, 1991; D. H. Mellor, 1995) - where the central idea is that a cause must, in some way, make its effect more likely -- or as a supplement to other ideas, such as that of a continuous process (Wesley Salmon, 1984). Finally, a fourth approach involves the idea of offering, not an analytic reduction of causation, but a contingent identification of causation, as it is in this world, with a relation whose only constituents are non- causal properties and relations. One idea, for example, is that causal processes can be identified with continuous processes in which relevant quantities are conserved (Wesley Salmon, 1997 and 1998; Phil Dowe, 2000a and 2000b).
    [Show full text]
  • Discovery and the Rationality of Science
    Loyola University Chicago Loyola eCommons Dissertations Theses and Dissertations 1985 Discovery and the Rationality of Science William S. Hill Loyola University Chicago Follow this and additional works at: https://ecommons.luc.edu/luc_diss Part of the Philosophy Commons Recommended Citation Hill, William S., "Discovery and the Rationality of Science" (1985). Dissertations. 2434. https://ecommons.luc.edu/luc_diss/2434 This Dissertation is brought to you for free and open access by the Theses and Dissertations at Loyola eCommons. It has been accepted for inclusion in Dissertations by an authorized administrator of Loyola eCommons. For more information, please contact [email protected]. This work is licensed under a Creative Commons Attribution-Noncommercial-No Derivative Works 3.0 License. Copyright © 1985 William S. Hill DISCOVERY AND THE RATIONALITY OF SCIENCE by Wiliam S. Hill A Dissertation Submitted to the Faculty of the Graduate School of Loyola University of Chicago in Partial Fulfillment of the Requirements for the Degree of Doctor of Philosophy August 1985 TABLE OF CONTENTS Page ACKNOWLEDGMENTS • . ii VITA • • • • • • • • • • • · • • • iii Chapter I. INTRODUCTION . 1 Discovery as a Direction for Philosophy of Science • • • • • • • . • . • . 1 The Justification Approach to Philosophy of Science . 2 The Discovery Alternative . • . • . • . • • 6 II. THE IMPLICATIONS OF THEORY-LADENNESS FOR THE HISTORY AND RATIONALITY OF SCIENCE. • • • • 10 Normal Science. • • . • . • . • . • • • • . • • 12 Revolutionary Science • • • • • • • . • • • 16 Kuhn's Historical Method. • . • . • . • . • . 20 The Success of Kuhn's Replacement • . • • . 22 III. THE IMPLICATIONS OF THEORY-LADENNESS FOR THE STABILITY OF EVIDENCE IN SCIENCE. • . • . • • • 29 Relative Stability of Observation Terms . • • . 32 The "Useh Criterion for the Theory-Observation Distinction • • • • . • . • . • . • . • • . 37 The Problem of Circularity. • . 43 IV.
    [Show full text]
  • A Centennial Volume for Rudolf Carnap and Hans Reichenbach
    W. Spohn (Ed.) Erkenntnis Orientated: A Centennial Volume for Rudolf Carnap and Hans Reichenbach Rudolf Carnap was born on May 18, 1891, and Hans Reichenbach on September 26 in the same year. They are two of the greatest philosophers of this century, and they are eminent representatives of what is perhaps the most powerful contemporary philosophical movement. Moreover, they founded the journal Erkenntnis. This is ample reason for presenting, on behalf of Erkenntnis, a collection of essays in honor of them and their philosophical work. I am less sure, however, whether it is a good time for resuming their philosophical impact; their work still is rather part than historical basis of the present philosophical melting-pot. Their basic philosophical theses have currently, it may seem, not so high a standing, but their impact can be seen in numerous detailed issues; they have opened or pushed forward lively fields of research which are still very actively pursued not only within philosophy, but also in many neighboring disciplines. Whatever the present balance of opinions about their philosophical ideas, there is something even more basic in their philosophy than their tenets which is as fresh, as stimulating, as exemplary as ever. I have in mind their way of philosophizing, their conception of how to Reprinted from `ERKENNTNIS', 35: 1-3, do philosophy. It is always a good time for reinforcing that conception; and if this volume 1991, IV, 471 p. would manage to do so, it would fully serve its purpose. Printed book Hardcover ▶ 194,99 € | £175.50 | $269.00 ▶ *208,64 € (D) | 214,49 € (A) | CHF 260.25 eBook Available from your bookstore or ▶ springer.com/shop MyCopy Printed eBook for just ▶ € | $ 24.99 ▶ springer.com/mycopy Order online at springer.com ▶ or for the Americas call (toll free) 1-800-SPRINGER ▶ or email us at: [email protected].
    [Show full text]
  • Rudolf Carnap Papers, 1920-1968
    http://oac.cdlib.org/findaid/ark:/13030/tf7q2nb520 No online items Finding Aid for the Rudolf Carnap papers, 1920-1968 Processed by UCLA Library Special Collections staff; machine-readable finding aid created by Caroline Cubé UCLA Library Special Collections UCLA Library Special Collections staff Room A1713, Charles E. Young Research Library Box 951575 Los Angeles, CA 90095-1575 Email: [email protected] URL: http://www.library.ucla.edu/libraries/special/scweb/ © 1998 The Regents of the University of California. All rights reserved. Note Arts and Humanities --PhilosophyHistory --History, University of California --History, UC Los AngelesGeographical (By Place) --University of California --University of California Los Angeles Finding Aid for the Rudolf Carnap 1029 1 papers, 1920-1968 Finding Aid for the Rudolf Carnap papers, 1920-1968 Collection number: 1029 UCLA Library Special Collections UCLA Library Special Collections staff Los Angeles, CA Contact Information UCLA Library Special Collections staff UCLA Library Special Collections Room A1713, Charles E. Young Research Library Box 951575 Los Angeles, CA 90095-1575 Telephone: 310/825-4988 (10:00 a.m. - 4:45 p.m., Pacific Time) Email: [email protected] URL: http://www.library.ucla.edu/libraries/special/scweb/ Processed by: UCLA Library Special Collections staff, 1998 Encoded by: Caroline Cubé Online finding aid edited by: Josh Fiala, June 2002 © 1998 The Regents of the University of California. All rights reserved. Descriptive Summary Title: Rudolf Carnap papers, Date (inclusive): 1920-1968 Collection number: 1029 Creator: Carnap, Rudolf, 1891-1970 Extent: 56 boxes (28 linear ft.) Repository: University of California, Los Angeles. Library Special Collections.
    [Show full text]
  • On the Origins of Carnap's Aufbau from Reductive Empiricism to The
    The publication of this book was supported by the Student Union of ELTE University and the Student Union of the Faculty of Humanities at ELTE University. Published by the Philosophy Workshop of Eötvös József Collegium Budapest, 2016 Director of publication: Dr. László Horváth Edited by Megyer Gyöngyösi, Zsolt Kapelner, Zsófia Ádám, István Faragó-Szabó Cover design by Hunor Gyöngyösi Designed by Zsófia Machó isbn © 2016 Philosophy Workshop of Eötvös József Collegium © The authors On the Origins of Carnap’s Aufbau From reductive empiricism 13 to the Geisteswissenschaften Ádám Tamás Tuboly Rudolf Carnap’s Der logische Aufbau der Welt is considered to be the magnum opus of (early) analytic philosophy. Contrary to this analytic tradition stands, as the saying goes, everything else – the so called continental philosophies. It has been highlighted recently, however, that the contexts of the Aufbaudiffer radically from the usual received view. In order to obtain a better picture of (the influences of) the Aufbau, I will present in Sect. 1 the received view which characterizes the book as a reductive empiricist, foundationalist and phenomenalist work. In Sect. 2 I will show step-by-step that this view is mistaken and the influences on the Aufbau could be located around Neo-Kantianism, the philosophy of Husserl and the human sciences [Geisteswissenschaften]. The contribution of this paper is connected to these approaches and argues for a different and currently unanalyzed and mainly ignored aspect of Carnap’s work, namely his theory of geistige Gegenstände. After all, I will claim that the motivations and continental roots of the Aufbau are just much deeper than it is usually thought.
    [Show full text]
  • Joseph Fletcher the Father of Biomedical Ethics by Richard Taylor
    L J Spring 1984 Vol. 4, No. 2 Joseph Fletcher The Father of Biomedical Ethics by Richard Taylor Special Features The Foundations of Religious liberty Carl Henry, Father Ernest Fortin, Paul Kurtz, and Lee Nisbet God and the New Physics Mario Bunge, Mendel Sachs, and Paul Davies Plus: Floyd Matson, Matthew Ies Spetter, Richard Kostelanetz, and Nicholas Capaldi SPRING 1984 ISSN 0272-0701 VOL. 4, NO. 2 Contents 3 LETTERS TO THE EDITOR SAVE OUR CHILDREN 4 Christian Science, Faith Healing,, and the Law Rita Swan 10 Ultrafundamentalist Sects and Child Abuse Lowell D. Streiker 17 Joseph Fletcher: The Father of Biomedical Ethics Richard Taylor THE FOUNDATIONS OF RELIGIOUS LIBERTY AND DEMOCRACY 20 Religious Liberty: Cornerstone of Human Rights Carl F. H. Henry 27 Democracy Without Theology Paul Kurtz 32 Is Liberal Democracy Really Christian? Ernest Fortin 35 Father Fortins Protestant Politics Lee Nisbet 38 Biblical Views of Sex: Blessing or Handicap? Jeffrey J. W. Baker 41 A Naturalistic Basis for Morality John Kekes BIBLICAL CRITICISM 44 On Miracles Randel Helms HUMANIST SELF-PORTRAITS 46 A Humanist Credo Matthew les Specter 47 The Distinctions of Humanism Richard Kosielanetz 48 Humane-ism Floyd Matson VIEWPOINTS 49 Moral Absolutes and Foreign Policy Nicholas Capaldi 50 The Vatican Ambassador Edd Doerr BOOKS 52 God and the Physicists Mario Bunge, Mendel Sachs, and Paul Davies 51 POETRY 60 ON THE BARRICADES 62 CLASSIFIED Cover art courtesy of the Buffalo and Erie County Public Library and AP/Wide World Edirur: Paul Kurtz -I ssueiare Editors: Gordon Stein, Lee Nisbet l s.sistartt Editors: Doris Doyle, Andrea Szalanski Ir, Director: Gregory Lyde Vigrass Contributing Editors: Lionel Abel, author, critic, SUNY at Buffalo; Paul Beattie, president, Fellowship of Religious Humanists; Jo-Ann Boydston, director, Dewey Center; Laurence Briskman, lecturer.
    [Show full text]
  • 1 a Tale of Two Interpretations
    Notes 1 A Tale of Two Interpretations 1. As Georges Dicker puts it, “Hume’s influence on contemporary epistemology and metaphysics is second to none ... ” (1998, ix). Note, too, that Hume’s impact extends beyond philosophy. For consider the following passage from Einstein’s letter to Moritz Schlick: Your representations that the theory of rel. [relativity] suggests itself in positivism, yet without requiring it, are also very right. In this also you saw correctly that this line of thought had a great influence on my efforts, and more specifically, E. Mach, and even more so Hume, whose Treatise of Human Nature I had studied avidly and with admiration shortly before discovering the theory of relativity. It is very possible that without these philosophical studies I would not have arrived at the solution (Einstein 1998, 161). 2. For a brief overview of Hume’s connection to naturalized epistemology, see Morris (2008, 472–3). 3. For the sake of convenience, I sometimes refer to the “traditional reading of Hume as a sceptic” as, e.g., “the sceptical reading of Hume” or simply “the sceptical reading”. Moreover, I often refer to those who read Hume as a sceptic as, e.g., “the sceptical interpreters of Hume” or “the sceptical inter- preters”. By the same token, I sometimes refer to those who read Hume as a naturalist as, e.g., “the naturalist interpreters of Hume” or simply “the natu- ralist interpreters”. And the reading that the naturalist interpreters support I refer to as, e.g., “the naturalist reading” or “the naturalist interpretation”. 4. This is not to say, though, that dissenting voices were entirely absent.
    [Show full text]
  • Medium-Term Strategic Plan of the Institute of Philosophy (2020–2023) 1A) Analysis of the External Environment the Situation
    Medium-term Strategic Plan of the Institute of Philosophy (2020–2023) 1a) Analysis of the external environment The situation of the Institute has been determined by the fundamental science policy reform in the course of which the Research Centre for the Humanities changed its operational form. Instead of being a budgetary entity of the Public Body of the Hungarian Academy of Sciences (HAS), as of 1 September 2019, it continues to operate as a central budgetary entity directed by the Eötvös Loránd Research Network (ELRN). 1b) Review of the internal capacities The previous period (2016–2018) saw the creation of the first excellence research team within the Institute, which has had an important budget from funds, and which has studied the values underlying scientific research. We have published monographs about the philosophy of Kant, Hume, and Saint Augustine of Hippo, about quantum theory, logical empiricism, historical philosophy and other topics. In addition to the publication of Latin- and Hungarian-language sources, the Hungarian Philosophical Archives has also been launched, which contains documents and biographical data. The Institute is a founding member of the Artificial Intelligence Coalition. The Institute has increased its presence in international professional forums, as has been reflected – in addition to our publication activities – by the higher number of international conferences attended and organized in the recent period. In accordance with the broad interpretation of philosophy’s mission of usefulness for the community, the fellows of the Institute have been involved in public life extensively as well as in popular science and interdisciplinary activities, both through their lectures delivered in Hungary and abroad, and their media appearances and writings.
    [Show full text]
  • 26 Huttemann Love Reduction
    View metadata, citation and similar papers at core.ac.uk brought to you by CORE provided by PhilPapers Reduction Andreas Hüttemann Alan C. Love Abstract Reduction and reductionism have been central philosophical topics in analytic philosophy of science for more than six decades. Together they encompass a diversity of issues from metaphysics and epistemology. This article provides an introduction to the topic that illuminates how contemporary epistemological discussions took their shape historically and limns the contours of concrete cases of reduction in specific natural sciences. The unity of science and the impulse to accomplish compositional reduction in accord with a layer-cake vision of the sciences, the seminal contributions of Ernest Nagel on theory reduction and how they strongly conditioned subsequent philosophical discussions, and the detailed issues pertaining to different accounts of reduction that arise in both physical and biological science (e.g., limit-case and part-whole reduction in physics, the difference-making principle in genetics, and mechanisms in molecular biology) are explored. The conclusion argues that the epistemological heterogeneity and patchwork organization of the natural sciences encourages a pluralist stance about reduction. Keywords composition, limit-case reduction, Ernest Nagel, mechanisms, part-whole reduction, theory reduction Reduction and reductionism have been central philosophical topics in analytic philosophy of science for more than six decades. Together they encompass a diversity of issues from metaphysics (e.g., physicalism and emergence) and epistemology (e.g., theory structure, 1 causal explanation, and methodology). “Reduction” usually refers to an asymmetrical relationship between two items (e.g., theories, explanations, properties, etc.) where one item is reduced to another.
    [Show full text]
  • July, and October
    ISSN 0739-4934 NEWSLETTER I {!STORY OF SCIENCE _iu_'i_i_u~-~-~-o~_9_N_u_M_B_E_R_3__________ S00ETY AAASREPORT HSSEXECUTIVE A Larger Role for History of Science COMMITTEE PRESIDENT in Undergraduate Education STEPHEN G. BRUSH, University of Maryland NORRISS S. HETHERINGTON VICE-PRESIDENT Office for the History of Science and Technology, SALLY GREGORY KOHLSTEDT, University of California, Berkeley University of Minnesota EXECU11VESECRETARY HISTORIANS OF SCIENCE have often been called to contribute to under­ MICHAEL M. SOKAL, Worcester graduate education. As HSS President Stephen G. Brush notes jNewsletter, Polytechnic Institute January 1990, pp. 1, 8-10), historically oriented science courses could be­ TREASURER come a valuable part of the core curriculum at many institutions, and fac­ MARY LOUISE GLEASON, New York City ulty at many colleges-especially science professors-have expressed strong EDITDR interest in using materials and perspectives from history of science. RONALD L. NUMBERS, University of We are now called again, this time by the American Association for the Wisconsin-Madison Advancement of Science. The Liberal Art of Science: Agenda for Action, published by the AAAS in May 1990, argues that science is one of the liberal The Newsletter of the History of Science arts and that it should be taught as such, as integrated into the totality of Society is published in January, April, July, and October. Regular issues are sent to individual human experience. This argument and advice may seem obvious to histori­ members of the Society who reside in North ans of science, but it is a revolutionary departure from tradition for many America. Airmail copies are sent to those scientists, and one that could transform both undergraduate education and members overseas who pay $5 yearly to cover postal costs: The Newsletter is available to the role of our discipline.
    [Show full text]
  • Hans Reichenbach
    Coming to America: Carnap, Reichenbach and the Great Intellectual Migration Part II: Hans Reichenbach Sander Verhaegh Tilburg University Ich habe das Gefühl, dass gerade Amerika mit seinem Sinn für das konkrete und technische mehr Verständnis haben müsste für meine naturwissenschaftliche Philosophie als Europa, wo noch immer die mystisch-metaphysischen Spekulationen als die wahre Philosophie angesehen werden. ⎯ Reichenbach to Sidney Hook, January 31, 1935 II.1. Introduction In the late-1930s, Rudolf Carnap and Hans Reichenbach, arguably the two most prominent scientific philosophers of their time, emigrated to the United States, escaping the increasingly perilous situation on the continent. Once in the U.S., the two significantly changed the American philosophical landscape. In this two-part paper, I reconstruct Carnap’s and Reichenbach’s surprisingly numerous interactions with American scholars throughout the 1920s and 1930s in order to better explain the transformation of analytic philosophy in the years before and after the Second World War. In the first part of this paper, I reconstructed Carnap’s contacts with American philosophers throughout the 1920s and 1930s. In this second part, I focus on Reichenbach’s interactions with the American philosophical community before he moved to the United States. I argue that some of Reichenbach’s work from the mid-1930s⎯ in particular Experience and Prediction (1938)⎯ can be better understood if we take into account the context in which it was written. This paper is structured as follows. After an overview of Reichenbach’s ignorance about Anglophone philosophy in the first stages of his academic career (§II.2), I reconstruct his ‘American turn’ in the early 1930s, focusing especially on the reception of his philosophy by a group of New York philosophers (§II.3).
    [Show full text]