<<

University of Hawai‘i at Hilo · Hawai‘i Community College HOHONU 2013 Vol. 11

entirely independent of our opinions about them; those Philosophical : Reals affect our senses according to regular laws and, . . Taking Out of . by taking advantages of the laws of , we can ascertain by how things really and truly are; and Context . . . be led to the one True conclusion.” Benjamin G. Browning, [email protected] In other words, according to Peirce, science PHIL 230, UH Hilo depends on a correspondence theory of : there is already, prior to our investigation, some existing truth, The position of pure about which our conclusions can then either be wrong holds that, in order to justify our knowledge of the world, or right. “The new conception involved here,” he writes, we must base our justifcation on something outside of “is that of .” For Peirce, it would seem that a that knowledge itself. According to the skeptic, unless which is obtained through one of the frst three methods we can provide this external justifcation, our claims to cannot be classed as knowledge, while one based on have knowledge of anything outside of our own mind science can – that we have at least some grounds for are spurious. The skeptic thus demands some foundation, connecting a scientifc conclusion to an independently in the form of epistemologically certain principles, on existing 'external world.' which all other human knowledge can be based. If these In defending his supposition of an external world foundational principles do not exist, then the ultimate against the skeptical position, Peirce suggests that there ramifcation of the skeptical position would be that we is a tacit acknowledgment of a correspondence version can never actually know anything, and that all of our of truth implicit in the skeptic's . The fact that attempts to develop knowledge through observation or this doubt produces dissatisfaction, Peirce claims, is an are futile and meaningless. indication that the doubter “that there is some This conclusion is profoundly unsettling, and one thing which a proposition should represent.” In has been attacked by many . C.S. Peirce other words, if there is not an external truth for a belief to rejects the skeptical position as impractical, and correspond to, then there is no reason to be unsatisfed advocates instead for a scientifc method that presumes with an unjustifed belief in the frst place. Thus the correspondence to an external world as a necessary skeptic's very act of doubting an external world would condition of fxing belief. Michael Williams, on the suggest that they believe that there is one. other hand, rejects both Peirce's presumption and the In the end, however, Peirce leaves the skeptics' '' of the skeptics, and instead introduces central question basically unanswered, simply asserting a '' in which our knowledge is dependent that it is not worth the effort of addressing fully: “[N]ot on the context in which it is generated or applied. This having any doubt, nor believing that anybody else whom paper draw on a mixture of the ideas of both to move I could infuence has, it would be the merest babble beyond the skeptics' objections and to defend the search for me to say more about it.” Rather than confronting for knowledge as a meaningful enterprise. the skeptics on their own terms, Peirce dismisses In his essay 'The Fixation of Belief,' Peirce begins their basic project – questioning the possibility of by noting that, as humans, we are inexorably driven to knowledge production – as useless. Since doubt causes rid ourselves of by replacing them with beliefs. dissatisfaction, and all humans wish to rid themselves of Peirce then identifes four methods which people use it, the skeptic may express reservations about the validity to develop beliefs. He is dismissive of the frst three of this endeavor, but it will nonetheless take place. For methods: tenacity, in which a person clings to beliefs by Pierce, the important question is not 'can we' or 'should ignoring to the contrary; authority, in which we' fx our beliefs, but rather 'how should we go about beliefs are imposed from above by institutions; and the doing so.' With this in mind, Peirce examines the means a priori method, in which an aesthetic sense of what which are available to us, and fxes on science – with its 'feels' right decides what is believed. It is fourth method, hypothesis of an external world included as part of the which Peirce refers to as “the method of science,” that package – as the most satisfactory and rigorous of the he ultimately champions. The goal of science, Peirce available methods. writes, is to fnd a means “by which our beliefs may be In his essay 'Epistemological Realism,' Michael determined by nothing human, but by some external Williams chooses a different route to attack the skeptical permanency – by something upon which our thinking has position. Instead of moving beyond the skeptical position no effect.” Peirce advises his readers that they “should by rejecting it as impractical, Williams examines the consider well” of the frst methods and then decide that foundations of the skeptics' questions. According to they “wish [their] opinions to coincide with fact, and Williams, what the skeptical position asks for is an that there is no reason why the results of those frst three explanation of knowledge which satisfes two conditions: methods should do so.” the totality condition and the condition. The Peirce claims that this coincidence with fact is totality condition requires that a satisfactory explanation achievable through science as a result of what he calls of knowledge must adequately justify all knowledge. its “fundamental hypothesis,” which can be paraphrased This, Williams argues, would require that some form of as follows: “There are Real things, whose characters are 66 University of Hawai‘i at Hilo · Hawai‘i Community College HOHONU 2013 Vol. 11 knowledge be 'epistemologically prior' to our experience dependent on its context, this seems incompatible with a of the world, so that we might use this prior knowledge correspondence theory of truth. How can the same belief to evaluate our supposed experiential knowledge and match an external truth in one context, but not in another, decide whether or not it passes the test. The objectivity or the same external truth match up with two conficting condition, on the other hand, requires “that the knowledge beliefs in two different situations? It would seem that we want to explain is knowledge of an objective world, a contextualism must abandon the correspondence theory world that is the way it is independently of how it appears entirely. This, however, introduces the possibility of a to us to be or what we are inclined to believe about it.” which allows almost anything to function as If we compare Williams' analysis of the skeptics' 'truth' in some contexts – a disturbing prospect for those, demands to Peirce's account of knowledge, we begin like Peirce, who would like their beliefs to “coincide to see some faws in Peirce's handling of the skeptical with fact.” position. Peirce's argument that the dissatisfaction of However, there may yet be a way to salvage Peirce's doubt is evidence of the skeptics' belief in external truth 'external permanency' in a way that is consistent with seems to handle the totality condition by indicating that Williams' rejection of epistemological foundationalism. some 'epistemologically prior' knowledge leads us to In describing this external permanency on which believe in an external world. His 'external permanency,' scientifc knowledge is to be grounded, how 'external' on the other hand, deals with the 'objectivity condition,' does Peirce require it to be? In rejecting the claims of and it is here we see an apparent incompatibility between mystics to have access to an external source of truth, Williams and Peirce. Peirce's hypothesis asserts that Peirce writes: “our external permanency would not be 'real' things “affect our senses according to regular laws, external, in our sense, if it was restricted in its infuence and. . .by taking advantage of the laws of perception, we to one individual. It must be something which affects, can ascertain by reasoning how things really and truly or might affect, every man.” This permanency, then, is are.” Williams, on the other hand, cautions us that such not necessarily the same as the 'external world' that the assumptions of “connections between experiential data skeptic demands of. Rather, it is a 'permanency' and worldly fact” will not truly rid us of the skeptical that is grounded in the of humanity. By thus position: “[I]f, in a desperate attempt to avoid skepticism, restricting the 'truth' with which our knowledge should we insist on such connections, we make the way the correspond, we can provide a specifc context within world is depend on how it appears to us, in violation of which our beliefs can function as knowledge. It is by the objectivity requirement.” checking our individual beliefs and experiences against Williams does not, however, conclude that this larger context that we can assign our beliefs the the skeptic is correct, but goes on to undermine the status of knowledge. assumptions on which it rests by exposing the conceptual This adds an element of a 'coherence' theory of baggage of the 'totality condition.' This condition, truth to Peirce's hypothesis. The 'truth' to which our Williams argues, assumes that all knowledge is somehow beliefs correspond need not completely external, but fundamentally related, and that the class or category of rather can be judged by how well it 'coheres' or fts in things we refer to as knowledge is a meaningful object with an existing framework of beliefs – one composed, of theoretical exploration in its own right. Rather than not merely of one individual's subjective experiences, accepting this assumption that all knowledge is in some but rather of the combined experiences of humanity as way homogeneous, Williams points out the diversity and whole. While this combined subjectivity may not be complexity of the different ideas and beliefs which are properly 'objective' as such, or as 'permanent' as Peirce commonly referred to as knowledge. He thus refutes the might wish, it nevertheless provides individual believers idea that certain kinds of knowledge have corresponding with something external against which to check their epistemological which can give them priority beliefs. over other kinds, regardless of situation or context. It is With this contextual framework now in place, we this very context, Williams argues, which defnes what can disregard the skeptics' question – how is it the case does and does not qualify as knowledge. that we can have knowledge – and move on to what Thus Williams does away entirely with the need Peirce found more interesting: how shall we go about to prove an external world. Our knowledge of 'things getting it. If the skeptical request for proof of an 'external outside of us' is perfectly justifed in the context in which world' refers to a world that is external not only to the it normally occurs. All that I need to know about a chair individual, but to all humanity, then it is diffcult to in order to sit down in it is contained in my knowledge see how anything so external could affect our beliefs that 'that is a chair.' Asking whether I really know that it about the human context in any case. Thus the skeptics' is a chair, under the conditions of totality and objectivity, questions can remain unanswered – for us, the answers is simply removing that item of knowledge from the become irrelevant. commonsense context in which it has meaning. This context dependency, however, may lead us to a conclusion just as unsettling as the skeptical we sought to escape in the frst place. If all knowledge is

67 University of Hawai‘i at Hilo · Hawai‘i Community College HOHONU 2013 Vol. 11

Works Cited

Peirce, Charles S. "The Fixation of Belief." Popular Science Monthly 12 (1877): 1-15. The Fixation of Belief. www.peirce.org. Web. 14 Sept. 2012. . Williams, Michael. "Epistemological Realism." 1991. : An Anthology. Malden (Mass.): Blackwell, 2008. 51-72. Print.

68