Faith As Rational

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Faith As Rational CHAPTER 3 Faith as Rational The reader may suspect th at I am about to contra di ct all that l sa id in th e pre- vious chapter, where I spoke of a radi cal di sj unction between fa ith and reason. By that I mean: Christi an faith is in no way a produ ct of human reason or of nat- ural human wi sdom, cann ot be coercive ly demonstrated by, or to, human reason, and even contra di cts natu ra l hum an reason. Mu st one then become an irratio nal human being in ord er to beli eve as a Chri sti an? Should we abandon the quest fo r a ra ti onal theologica l meth od, whi ch we have bee n pursuing since the beginning of thi s inquiry? I think not. Paradox ica ll y, we mu st continue to seek an under- standing of fa ith that is not onl y fa ith -full , acknowledgin g th e radi ca l di sjuncti on of fa ith and reason, but that is ra ti onal as we ll. Douglas John Hall , who affirm s in hi s own theologia crucis the "cogniti ve pri ority" of revelatio n as "poi nt of departure" fo r Chri sti an theo logy, ca n set the tone fo r our discussion: Nothin g at all can be ga ined by an auth oritarian, revelati on-based reli- gion whi ch gloats over every humiliati on of the human mind . The point of th e cross is not that th e fai th ful should win arguments, but th at the world mi ght kn ow peace. Partl y, thi s peace depend s upon the ex pos iti on of a theo logy of reve lati on whi ch does not humiliate but ca n fulfill and exa lt th e qu est of the in te ll ect. 1 I shall argue, then, th at fa ith ca n be credibl e to the intelli gent mind, and that fa ith must account fo r itself in a reasonabl e manner. Reve lati on does not merely negate hum an reason, but in fo rm s and illuminates it. What ls Rationality? The word "rati onality" deri ves fro m th e Latin ratio, "reason"; rationality, broadl y spea king, is reasonabl eness. The term denotes ri ght thinking or th e ri ght fun cti oning of the human mind . However, what constitutes ra ti onality, reason- 80 Faith as Rational 81 abl eness, or ri ght thinking and how it is to be identi fied or measured are hi ghly conte nti ous questi ons that philosophers have debated endl ess ly. I shall not pro- pose a uni versa l measurin g stick of ra ti onali ty ; all the best minds in th e hi story of philosophy have fa il ed to reach ag reement on thi s, and th ere is now a wide- spread opini on that none such ex ists. 2 I will offer here onl y a te ntati ve wo rkin g defi niti on and go on later to characte ri ze rationali ty more full y. My defi ni tion no doub t refl ects va ri ous contin gencies of my personal loca ti on and faith ori enta- tion, but I do not apo logize fo r thi s, sin ce no abso lute defini tion is ava il abl e. 1 propose to use th e term "rationality" to mea n a genuine effort of th e human min d to relate to rea li ty in all its depth and compl ex ity. Ra ti onality occurs above all in everyday prac ti ca l li fe ; it is a matter of prax is, in whi ch prac ti ca l ac ti on and theoreti cal thought co me together. It is also an as pect of every di scipline of thought. 3 Rati onal th ought implies, first of all , an appro pri ate attent io n to the obj ect of inquiry or whatever it is th at one seeks to kn ow. Tt ca n be described, th en, as recepti vity and res ponse to whatever it is th at one encoun te rs. It is also ac ti ve, in th e se nse that it calcul ates how best to ac hi eve prac ti ca l goals. Rati o- nality, for li be rt io ni st/prax is-ori ented th ought, seeks a reasoned correlati on of th eo ry and practice. It is capable of co ntempl atin g and refl ectin g on what those goa ls of prac ti cal ac ti on should be. Wh en I say "rea li ty in all its de pth and co m- pl ex ity," 1 impl y th at ra ti onal thought is as broad and deep in scope as the wh ole vast ra nge of matters about whi ch hum an bein gs inquire and whi ch th ey wish to accomplish in th e world . A ra ti onal person is chara cteri zed by an openness not onl y to that whi ch he or she seeks to kn ow but also to th e rationali ty of oth ers, and therefore to di s- cussion and persuas ion. The rati onal perso n possesses an attitude of mind that is willing to be chall enged by relevant ev idence and is open to others' vi ewpoints or arguments, whether th ey be logica l, ex peri ential, or practi ca l. Obviously th e bas ic laws of logic, such as th e laws of noncontradiction and of logical sequence, are essenti al to rationali ty. Wi thout reason in th is sense it is imposs ibl e to kn ow or to argue anything, even th e limitati ons of reason' An extremely irra ti onal per- son, on th e other hand , is eas il y recogni zed by others as insane or mentall y unbal- anced, paranoid , or delud ed. A more moderately irrati onal person is usuall y seen by others as cl osed-minded, rigidl y dogmati c, unwilling to co nsider evid ence, or simpl y very subjecti vist or emotivist in an arbitrary mann er. Rationali ty ma y be hindered not onl y by dogma or emot ion but also by ideo logy or selfis h interests. Rati onal persons, however, are not necessarily di spassionate or detached in the process of knowing, or of acting. In some as pects of ex istence- fo r exampl e, sexual love, th e appreciati on of mu sic, th e love of nature, reli gious devotion , or politi cal commi tment- passion and attachment are appropriate and rati onal in the broad sense; ind eed, to relate to th ese dimensions of life di spassionately would be irrati onal. Reason and passion, th en, are not incompatible. On the con- tra ry, reason is appro pri ately pass ionate about ce rtain things. Th e new fa th er, perceiving how beautiful and precious hi s new child is, kn ows rationall y what he 82 1?.eflections on Revelation, Faith, and Rationality never knew before. The lover, besotted with erotic passion, knows his beloved more truly than he has ever known anyone. The social activist, impassioned with outrage about a brutal war, sees injustice and cruelty with incisive accuracy. Of course, one must recognize the conventional truth as well: passion, whether sex- ual , aesthetic, or political, can obscure rational processes, blinding us to the com- plexities of the world around us. Rational persons, however, may disagree with each other, may be believers or unbelievers; Christians, Muslims, Buddhists, or atheists; and conservatives, liberals, or radicals. This implies that rationality and truth have to be distin- guished. When I say a person is rational (say, a thoughtful Muslim, Hindu, or atheist) I do not imply that I agree with that person's ideas or beliefs. Out of the givenness of their own experience and resources, they may be functioning very rationally in coming to quite different conclusions from those I reach out of my experience and resources. On the other hand, l may consider a person to be irra- tional whose basic faith and viewpoints I share (e.g., some Christians or social- ists l can think of) if they refuse to be accountable in any way for their beliefs. "To claim that a belief is rational is not the same as to claim that a belief is true."4 Rationality and truth are by no means identical, yet rational persons are not at all indifferent to truth, for truth is the goal of the rational person. The rational per- son seeks "truth," that is, needs to be in touch with reality in order to live and to act well in the real world. It is also the case that I may consider someone essen- tially a rational person and at the same time judge some of his/her views or atti- tudes to be irrational. Human rationality is fallible, so that, as limited finite creatures, we are rational only to a certain degree. l reluctantly admit that some rational persons would find me to be irrational in some respects. J. Wentzel Van Huysteen proposes a helpful, broad concept of rationality that coheres with what l am suggesting here.
Recommended publications
  • Questioning Divination: the Young Augustine and Friends Divination Is Not an Art One Ordinarily Associates with Augustine Of
    Questioning divination: the young Augustine and friends Divination is not an art one ordinarily associates with Augustine of Hippo. His preaching, like that of any other late antique bishop, decisively rejected all forms of magic, and he offered detailed critiques of astrology across many works (e.g., City of God 5). However, Augustine is also an author who gives exceptional—if incomplete—insight into times in his life where he thought differently (see esp. O’Loughlin 1992). In his Confessions and the early dialogue Against the Academics, Augustine paints a series of portraits, of himself but also of lofty and learned associates, who questioned the practical limits of divinatory power. The aim of this paper is to trace out the social context of Augustine’s early and growing skepticism towards divination. The first of the learned men, and the most studied, is the learned Vindicianus, proconsul and sometime court-physician for Valentinian I (Fiorucci 2008). Augustine, who had rejected the help of a haruspex in a poetry contest, did take up astrology. After crowning him the victor, Vindicianus tried to dissuade him, pointing to his own experiences as a young man who had once prepared to become a professional astrologer (Confessions 4.2.3-3.5). Of his reasoning, we hear comparatively little, though Augustine elsewhere lauds him for his medical expertise, whose methods he was able rationally to explain to those who had assumed them sorcerous (Ep. 138.3). The next example is more richly documented. In Contra Academicos 1.6.17-8.23, Augustine’s student Licentius describes a series of divinatory feats performed by Albicerius, a hariolus from Carthage.
    [Show full text]
  • Augustine on Knowledge
    Augustine on Knowledge Divine Illumination as an Argument Against Scepticism ANITA VAN DER BOS RMA: RELIGION & CULTURE Rijksuniversiteit Groningen Research Master Thesis s2217473, April 2017 FIRST SUPERVISOR: dr. M. Van Dijk SECOND SUPERVISOR: dr. dr. F.L. Roig Lanzillotta 1 2 Content Augustine on Knowledge ........................................................................................................................ 1 Acknowledgements ................................................................................................................................ 4 Preface .................................................................................................................................................... 5 Abstract ................................................................................................................................................... 6 Introduction ............................................................................................................................................ 7 The life of Saint Augustine ................................................................................................................... 9 The influence of the Contra Academicos .......................................................................................... 13 Note on the quotations ........................................................................................................................ 14 1. Scepticism ........................................................................................................................................
    [Show full text]
  • Skepticism and Pluralism Ways of Living a Life Of
    SKEPTICISM AND PLURALISM WAYS OF LIVING A LIFE OF AWARENESS AS RECOMMENDED BY THE ZHUANGZI #±r A DISSERTATION SUBMITTED TO THE GRADUATE DIVISION OF THE UNIVERSITY OF HAWAI'I IN PARTIAL FULFILLMENT OF THE REQUIREMENTS FOR THE DEGREE OF DOCTOR OF PHILOSOPHY IN PHILOSOPHY AUGUST 2004 By John Trowbridge Dissertation Committee: Roger T. Ames, Chairperson Tamara Albertini Chung-ying Cheng James E. Tiles David R. McCraw © Copyright 2004 by John Trowbridge iii Dedicated to my wife, Jill iv ACKNOWLEDGEMENTS In completing this research, I would like to express my appreciation first and foremost to my wife, Jill, and our three children, James, Holly, and Henry for their support during this process. I would also like to express my gratitude to my entire dissertation committee for their insight and understanding ofthe topics at hand. Studying under Roger Ames has been a transformative experience. In particular, his commitment to taking the Chinese tradition on its own terms and avoiding the tendency among Western interpreters to overwrite traditional Chinese thought with the preoccupations ofWestern philosophy has enabled me to broaden my conception ofphilosophy itself. Roger's seminars on Confucianism and Daoism, and especially a seminar on writing a philosophical translation ofthe Zhongyong r:pJm (Achieving Equilibrium in the Everyday), have greatly influenced my own initial attempts to translate and interpret the seminal philosophical texts ofancient China. Tamara Albertini's expertise in ancient Greek philosophy was indispensable to this project, and a seminar I audited with her, comparing early Greek and ancient Chinese philosophy, was part ofthe inspiration for my choice ofresearch topic. I particularly valued the opportunity to study Daoism and the Yijing ~*~ with Chung-ying Cheng g\Gr:p~ and benefited greatly from his theory ofonto-cosmology as a means of understanding classical Chinese philosophy.
    [Show full text]
  • Kant's Theory of Knowledge and Hegel's Criticism
    U.Ü. FEN-EDEBİYAT FAKÜLTESİ SOSYAL BİLİMLER DERGİSİ Yıl: 2, Sayı: 2, 2000-2001 KANT’S THEORY OF KNOWLEDGE AND HEGEL’S CRITICISM A. Kadir ÇÜÇEN* ABSTRACT Kant inquires into the possibility, sources, conditions and limits of knowledge in the tradition of modern philosophy. Before knowing God, being and reality, Kant, who aims to question what knowledge is, explains the content of pure reason. He formalates a theory of knowledge but his theory is neither a rationalist nor an empiricist theory of knowledge. He investigates the structure of knowledge, the possible conditions of experience and a priori concepts and categories of pure reason; so he makes a revolution like that of Copernicus . Hegel, who is one of proponents of the German idealism, criticizes the Kantian theory of knowledge for “wanting to know before one knows”. For Hegel, Kant’s a priori concepts and categories are meaningless and empty. He claims that the unity of subject and object has been explained in that of the “Absolute”. Therefore, the theory of knowledge goes beyond the dogmatism of the “thing-in- itself” and the foundations of mathematics and natural sciences; and reaches the domain of absolute knowledge. Hegel’s criticism of Kantian theory of knowledge opens new possibilities for the theory of knowledge in our age. ÖZET Kant’ın Bilgi Kuramı ve Hegel’in Eleştirisi Modern felsefe geleneği çerçevesinde Kant, bilginin imkânını, kaynağını, kapsamını ve ölçütlerini ele alarak, doğru bilginin sınırlarını irdelemiştir. Tanrı’yı, varlığı ve gerçekliği bilmeden önce, bilginin neliğini sorgulamayı kendine amaç edinen Kant, saf aklın içeriğini incelemiştir. Saf aklın a priori kavram ve kategorilerini, deneyin görüsünü ve bilgi yapısını veren, fakat ne usçu ne de deneyci * Uludag University, Faculty of Sciences and Letters, Dept.
    [Show full text]
  • Dilemmas of Objectivity
    SOCIALEPISTEMOLOGY , 2002, VOL. 16, NO . 3, 267–281 Dilemmas of objectivity MARIANNE JANACK Objectivityis a virtuein most circles.As weevaluateour students (even those we don’t like)we tryto be objective. As wedeliberateon juries,we tryto be objective about the accused and thevictim, the prosecutor and thedefence. As wetoteup theevidence for and againsta certainposition or theory, we try to separate our personal preferences fromthe argument, or we try to separate the arguer (and ourevaluation of him/ her) fromthe case presented.Sometimes we do wellat this,sometimes we do lesswell at it,but we recognize something valuable intheeffort. Considerthe following cases inwhich objectivity or its failure is at issue: (1)A professorgives his favourite student an Ainaclass inwhichthe student has done onlymediocre work. (2)A scientistoverlooks evidence that would call intoquestion a theorythat she has goneout on alimbto defend,and has investedmuch timeand energyin pursuing. (3)A scientistskews data inorder to bolster support for a favouritepolitical cause. (4)A particularphilosophy journal, which does not use a blindreview process, only publishesarticles written by men. (5)A memberof a trialjury questions evidence presented in atrialbecause it conicts withracist stereotypes. Some ofthese invocations of objectivity imply that a separationshould exist between thesource or origin of the theory or argument and theargument itself. Some imply thatour deliberations should be answerable only to ‘ theevidence’ or ‘ thefacts’ and notsimply to our own preferences and idiosyncrasies.Some implythat our emotionsor biases (broadly understood to include emotions) should not interfere withour reasoning. Inits ontological guise, the appeal toobjectivity is a wayof appealing to the way thingsare, or to the world as itis independently of our desires about howwe want it tobe.
    [Show full text]
  • David Hume, "The Dialogues Concerning Natural Religion," and Religious Tolerance
    University of Tennessee, Knoxville TRACE: Tennessee Research and Creative Exchange Supervised Undergraduate Student Research Chancellor’s Honors Program Projects and Creative Work 5-2020 David Hume, "The Dialogues Concerning Natural Religion," and Religious Tolerance Jarrett Delozier [email protected] Follow this and additional works at: https://trace.tennessee.edu/utk_chanhonoproj Part of the History of Philosophy Commons, History of Religion Commons, Intellectual History Commons, and the Religious Thought, Theology and Philosophy of Religion Commons Recommended Citation Delozier, Jarrett, "David Hume, "The Dialogues Concerning Natural Religion," and Religious Tolerance" (2020). Chancellor’s Honors Program Projects. https://trace.tennessee.edu/utk_chanhonoproj/2382 This Dissertation/Thesis is brought to you for free and open access by the Supervised Undergraduate Student Research and Creative Work at TRACE: Tennessee Research and Creative Exchange. It has been accepted for inclusion in Chancellor’s Honors Program Projects by an authorized administrator of TRACE: Tennessee Research and Creative Exchange. For more information, please contact [email protected]. DeLozier 1 Introduction In the history of philosophy of religion and natural theology, David Hume is an immensely influential contributor. One of his most important works in the field is his Dialogues Concerning Natural Religion, which contains his greatest treatment of natural theology, specifically the design argument. However, there’s a big problem which the Dialogues present to understanding Hume. Eleven of the twelve parts of the Dialogues contain Hume’s sharp criticisms and attacks on the Design argument. But in the final part, in what is often called “Philo’s Reversal,” he seems to completely reverse course by renouncing his skepticism and endorsing the Design argument.
    [Show full text]
  • Ingolf U. Dalferth Varieties of Philosophical Theology Before and After Kant
    Ingolf U. Dalferth Varieties of Philosophical Theology Before and After Kant 1. Prehistory, History, and Posthistory of Philosophical Theology Philosophical theology (PT),1 which replaced natural and rational theology after Kant, began its modern career as a distinct philosophical project, based not on faith and religion but on reason and reflection and/or nature, experience, and science. However, it has never been a monolithic endeavour, and its impact on Christian thinking has been constructive as well as critical or even destructive. Its prehistory that is sometimes mistakenly taken to be part of it includes such diverse factors as Platonist dualism, the Aristotelian pattern of causality, Stoic immanentism, Philonean personalism, Neoplatonist negative theology and Sozinian antitrinitarian- ism. From its most ancient roots the theology of the philosophers in the Western tradition was intimately bound up with the rise of reason and science in ancient Greece. When the gods ceased to be part of the furniture of the world, God (the divine) became an explanatory principle based not on the traditional mythological tales but on cosmo- logical science, astronomical speculation, and metaphysical reflection. Its idea of God involved the ideas of divine singularity (there is only one God), of divine transcendence (God is neither part nor the whole of the world) and of divine immanence (God’s active presence can be discerned in the order, regularity, and beauty of the cosmos). And even though it took a long time to grasp those differences clearly, the monotheistic difference between gods and God, the cosmological difference between God and the world, and the metaphysical difference between the transcendence and immanence of God have remained central to the intellectual enterprise of theological reflection in philosophy.
    [Show full text]
  • Is It Rational to Have Faith? Looking for New Evidence, Good’S Theorem, and Risk Aversion
    Lara Buchak, November 2009 DRAFT DO NOT CITE Is it rational to have faith? Looking for new evidence, Good’s Theorem, and Risk Aversion 0. Introduction Although statements involving ascriptions of faith are quite common, faith and rationality are often thought to conflict; at best, they are thought to have nothing to say to each other. In this paper, I analyze the concept of faith: in particular, I give an account that unifies statements of faith in mundane matters and statements of religious faith. My account focuses on spelling out the sense in which faith requires going beyond the evidence, and I argue that faith requires stopping ones search for further evidence. I then turn to the question of whether it is rational to have faith, taking into account both epistemic rationality and practical rationality. I argue that faith need not conflict with epistemic rationality at all; however, whether faith can be practically rational hinges on which attitudes towards risk it is rationally permissible to adopt when making decisions: more specifically, it hinges on how one should respond to the risk of misleading evidence. I have argued elsewhere that practical rationality permits a wider range of attitudes towards risk than is commonly supposed, and if this is right, then it is also rationally permissible to have faith; indeed, depending on the attitude towards risk that one decides to adopt, it is sometimes rationally required.1 1. Faith Statements I begin by sketching some characteristics that faith statements have in common. By faith statements, I simply mean statements involving the term faith.
    [Show full text]
  • Kant, Hegel, Schelling, Nietzsche, and Heidegger
    German Philosophers: Kant, Hegel, Schelling, Nietzsche, and Heidegger Daniel Ferrer at Matrin Heidegger’s Todtnauberg haunt (Die Hütte, Rütte, Todtnauberg, Black Forest, Schwarzwald, Germany) By Daniel Fidel Ferrer 1 2011 Daniel Fidel Ferrer. All rights reserved. No part of this book may be used or reproduced in any manner whatsoever without written permission. No part of this book may be stored in a retrieval system or transmitted in any form or by any means including electronic, electrostatic, magnetic tape, mechanical, photocopying, recording, digital, optical or by any information storage and retrieval system now known or hereafter invented; or otherwise without the prior permission in writing and signed by the author, Daniel Fidel Ferrer. Photo of Daniel Fidel Ferrer at Heidegger’s Todtnauberg haunt copyright ©Daniel Fidel Ferrer. Photo taken by Dr. Harald van Veghel with my 35 MM camera. Location: front page, title page. Die Hütte, Rütte, Todtnauberg, Black Forest, Schwarzwald, Germany, Deutschland. Some brief cataloging. Ferrer, Daniel Fidel (1952- ) German Philosophers: Kant, Hegel, Schelling, Nietzsche, and Heidegger Includes bibliographical references. Index. 1. Ontology. 2. Metaphysics. 3. Philosophy, German. 4.Thought and thinking. 5. Kant, Immanuel, 1724-1804. 6. Schelling, Friedrich Wilhelm Joseph von, 1775-1854. 7. Hegel, Georg Wilhelm Friedrich, 1770-1831. 8. Philosphy, Asian. 9. Philosophy, Indic. 10. Philosophy, Modern -- 20th century. 11. Philosophy, Modern -- 19th century. 12. Practice (Philosophy). 13. Philosophy and civilization. 14. Postmodernism. 15. Nietzsche, Friedrich Wilhelm, 1844-1900. 16. Heidegger, Martin, 1889-1976. -- 17. g r una nd cent. I. Ferrer, Daniel Fidel, 1952-. Dedication and Acknowledgements Family members. Families: Ferrer, Reavis, Kuhn, Lindstrom, Schmidt, and Yeager.
    [Show full text]
  • Skill in Epistemology I: Skill and Knowledge
    Skill in Epistemology I: Skill and Knowledge Carlotta Pavese Abstract Knowledge and skill are intimately connected. In this essay, I discuss the question of their relationship and of which (if any) is prior to which in the order of explanation. I review some of the answers that have been given thus far in the literature, with a particular focus on the many foundational issues in epistemology that intersect with the philosophy of skill. 1 Introduction Knowledge and skill are intimately connected. Scientists cannot get new knowledge without developing their skills for devising experiments. And skilled artists, scientists, and mathematicians must know a lot about their area of expertise in order to perform skillfully and routinely manifest that knowledge through their skillful performances. Despite this obvious interrelationship, knowledge and skill have received different treatment in analytic epistemology. While philosophers in this tradition have long been in the business of understanding and defining knowledge, the topic of skill has been marginalized. It is only quite recently that skills have made a powerful entrance in two epistemological debates: the debate on virtue epistemology and the debate on the nature of know how. In this essay, I discuss the question of the relationship between skill and knowledge (Section §2) and of which (if any) is prior to which in the order of explanation (Section §3), with an eye to highlighting the many foundational issues in epistemology that intersect with the philosophy of skill. In section §3, I will start discussing the relationship between skill and know how, which will be the main topic of the sequel to this essay.
    [Show full text]
  • Preliminary Conclusions in the Search of Philosophical Grounds for Contemporary Unitarian Identity
    Preliminary Conclusions in the Search of Philosophical Grounds for Contemporary Unitarian Identity By Neville Buch The Unitarian denomination itself always remained small, of course, but the Harvard moralists had resigned themselves to this very early. “Our object is not to convert men to our party, but to our principles,” they declared. “Unitarians have done more…by promoting a real though gradual change for the better in the opinions of other sects, than by building up their own denomination”. [Daniel Walker Howe. The Unitarian Consciencei] Whether it be Utilitarianism or Unitarianism, [William] James argued in 1868, the philosopher’s role includes not only crystallizing the doctrine but also presenting it in the most persuasive light to the populace. [Gerald E. Myers. William James: His Life and Thought ii]. William James remark on the philosopher’s role in a letter to Oliver Wendell Holmes in 1868 is a direct challenge to a disempowering attitude that has unfortunately prevailed in Unitarianism since the remark of James Walker in 1830 as quoted by Daniel Howe above. The disempowering attitude is unfortunate because it can be shown that its own advocacy is eroded by an apparent meaninglessness when clear preciseness is demanded. To deconstruct Walker’s statement -- what has been overlooked is that ‘our party’ and ‘our principles’ are related in an inseparable Unitarian identity. “Our party” is the Unitarian body. “Our principles” are Unitarian principles, that is, principles belonging to the Unitarian body. They are principles marked out as Unitarian because Unitarians have claimed them as their own. The philosophical reasons for this claim are not yet apparent.
    [Show full text]
  • The Etienne Gilson Series 21
    The Etienne Gilson Series 21 Remapping Scholasticism by MARCIA L. COLISH 3 March 2000 Pontifical Institute of Mediaeval Studies This lecture and its publication was made possible through the generous bequest of the late Charles J. Sullivan (1914-1999) Note: the author may be contacted at: Department of History Oberlin College Oberlin OH USA 44074 ISSN 0-708-319X ISBN 0-88844-721-3 © 2000 by Pontifical Institute of Mediaeval Studies 59 Queen’s Park Crescent East Toronto, Ontario, Canada M5S 2C4 Printed in Canada nce upon a time there were two competing story-lines for medieval intellectual history, each writing a major role for scholasticism into its script. Although these story-lines were O created independently and reflected different concerns, they sometimes overlapped and gave each other aid and comfort. Both exerted considerable influence on the way historians of medieval speculative thought conceptualized their subject in the first half of the twentieth cen- tury. Both versions of the map drawn by these two sets of cartographers illustrated what Wallace K. Ferguson later described as “the revolt of the medievalists.”1 One was confined largely to the academy and appealed to a wide variety of medievalists, while the other had a somewhat narrower draw and reflected political and confessional, as well as academic, concerns. The first was the anti-Burckhardtian effort to push Renaissance humanism, understood as combining a knowledge and love of the classics with “the discovery of the world and of man,” back into the Middle Ages. The second was inspired by the neo-Thomist revival launched by Pope Leo XIII, and was inhabited almost exclusively by Roman Catholic scholars.
    [Show full text]