Dilemmas of Objectivity

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Dilemmas of Objectivity SOCIALEPISTEMOLOGY , 2002, VOL. 16, NO . 3, 267–281 Dilemmas of objectivity MARIANNE JANACK Objectivityis a virtuein most circles.As weevaluateour students (even those we don’t like)we tryto be objective. As wedeliberateon juries,we tryto be objective about the accused and thevictim, the prosecutor and thedefence. As wetoteup theevidence for and againsta certainposition or theory, we try to separate our personal preferences fromthe argument, or we try to separate the arguer (and ourevaluation of him/ her) fromthe case presented.Sometimes we do wellat this,sometimes we do lesswell at it,but we recognize something valuable intheeffort. Considerthe following cases inwhich objectivity or its failure is at issue: (1)A professorgives his favourite student an Ainaclass inwhichthe student has done onlymediocre work. (2)A scientistoverlooks evidence that would call intoquestion a theorythat she has goneout on alimbto defend,and has investedmuch timeand energyin pursuing. (3)A scientistskews data inorder to bolster support for a favouritepolitical cause. (4)A particularphilosophy journal, which does not use a blindreview process, only publishesarticles written by men. (5)A memberof a trialjury questions evidence presented in atrialbecause it conicts withracist stereotypes. Some ofthese invocations of objectivity imply that a separationshould exist between thesource or origin of the theory or argument and theargument itself. Some imply thatour deliberations should be answerable only to ‘ theevidence’ or ‘ thefacts’ and notsimply to our own preferences and idiosyncrasies.Some implythat our emotionsor biases (broadly understood to include emotions) should not interfere withour reasoning. Inits ontological guise, the appeal toobjectivity is a wayof appealing to the way thingsare, or to the world as itis independently of our desires about howwe want it tobe. So, while it might seem reasonable to think of objectivity as an epistemic virtue,the term also carriesmetaphysical overtones. It would seem to be an uncontroversialepistemic virtue premised on a fairlycommon-sense realism: there is awaythe world is, and theway the world is isin principle distinguishable from the way we wish it were. Author : MarianneJanack is Assistant Professorof Philosophy atHamiltonCollege in Clinton, NY,13323, USA.She teachesclasses in epistemology,philosophy of scienceand feminist philosophy .She ispresently workingon alongerproject on rationalityandfeminist theories of emotion. Social Epistemology ISSN0269-1728 print/ISSN1464-5297 online # 2002 Taylor &FrancisLtd http://www.tandf.co.uk/journals DOI:10.1080/ 0269172022000025624 268 MARIANNEJANACK Theconnection between objectivity and truthhas beenan importanttool for feministand otherlibratory projects, but failuresof objectivity are not always or onlyepistemic failures. The claim thatthere is still sexism in the world can only bedenied by someone who fails to be objective. This is a failurethat has two differentand separableaspects to it. It is an epistemicfailure, in so faras it seemsto involve a wilfulavoidance of evidence that is all tooclear (that women ofall racesstill suffer the greater burden of social ills like poverty, spousal abuse, discriminatorypay practicesand discriminatoryhiring practices, for example, and enjoyfewer of the social goods likefreedom of self-determination, respect, etc. thando men).It is also an instanceof a theoryor claim thatfails to correspond tothe facts. That is, this case involvesboth bad reasoningand falsehood.Would sound reasoning(we’ ll call thisobjectivity r)have guaranteedcorrespondence to reality (call this objectivity c)?Notnecessarily, buthad our claimant been objective r she mighthave beenmore likely tobe objective c.Yet, as we all know, objectivity c doesnot require objectivity r—peoplecan getthe facts rightaccidentally (i.e.by guessing) orthrough faulty reasoning. Objectivity c is notsecured byobjectivity r, and objectivity r is neither necessary norsuf cient forobjectivity c. Comparethis situation, however, to the situation described in (4)above. Of course,it ispossiblethat no women write articles that are as good as thosewritten by men, and so thelack ofpublishedarticles by women is dueto the inferior quality of articleswritten bywomen, but thefact that the review process is notblind leads oneto suspect that the qualityof the manuscript is notthe only factor being used in the evaluations. We think thatit seems unlikely that all themanuscripts submitted by women would be unacceptableby the journal’ s standards,unless, of course, the author’ s sexenters into theevaluation either implicitly or explicitly. Let’ s say thatthe author’ s sexis explicitlyconsidered in the evaluation process, that in fact the journal is dedicated to publishingarticles written only by men. Would thisbe a failureof objectivity? Not necessarily;it might be fairly explicit sexism, but notnecessarily a failureof objectivity,since the reviewers do notclaim tobe impartial; in this instance they simplydo notwant to publish articles by women. Were we to question their motivationfor this stance, we might eventually encounter a failureof objectivity— thatis, the justi cation for this practice might ultimately lead us back toa failureof objectivityon the part of the publishers. The beliefs upon which the practice is based mightbe subject to the same criticismsdetailed in the case ofthe sexism-denier describedabove. But thesimple fact that a journaldoes not publish articles by womendoes not lead totheconclusion that the journal is notobjective. Yet,if the reviewers claim notto be using sex as acriterionof evaluation, yet are implicitlydoing so, then I thinkwe have something more like a failureof objectivity. If,that is, the reviewers claim thatthey will publish all and onlythose articles they judgeto be well-argued, for instance, and measureup tocertain standards of scholarship(e.g. carefully researched, well-written, etc.) then the implicit operation of sexas awayof evaluating quality seems to be a signicant failure of objectivity. But isitthe same kindof failure as thatdescribed in the case ofthe sexism-denier? There seemsto be a certain‘ familyresemblance’ but noshared characteristics here. Case 4 seemsto be a case inwhich a certaintenet of informal reasoning has beenviolated: namelythat an argumentis valid independently of who offers it. While this seems to bea canonof good reasoninggenerally, it is different from the canon of good reasoningthat would have us lookat all theevidence available for a certainclaim. Objectivityin this sense is something more like impartiality with respect to the source DILEMMASOFOBJECTIVITY 269 ofan argumentor position, and itis atenetwe learn(or teach) in informal logic classes. Yet,the demand thatwe look for all theevidence for or against a givenposition is a much moregeneral and unreective epistemic practice— one in which, in fact, the reliabilityor credibility of a claimantmight enter as an importantpiece of evidence. 1 Ina similar,yet slightly different case, if one of our colleagues were to give the studentshe liked grades thatfailed to re ect the quality of their actual work,we wouldthink that his objectivity as ajudgewas compromised. Under these circumstances,we would want to say thathis personal attachments had interfered withhis professional judgment, and whilehe might not be epistemically culpable, wewould probably thinkthat he was morally culpable. Take, for instance, the case inwhich the professor in question gives in ated grades towork he knows to beinferior. This seems to be a moral failing,rather than an epistemicfailing. Doesthe analysis change if we tweak the story a bit?Consider the more likely scenarioin which the professor’ s evaluationof the student’ s workis in uenced by hispersonal attachments. Does this constitute a differentkind of failure of objectivity?It does seem to be different from the scenario in which the professor knowinglygives his favourite students better grades thanthey deserve. But inthe case inwhich the professor ltershis evaluations through his personal attachments,the areas of moral and epistemicculpability become murkier. We mightbe tempted to say thatin this case thefailure is more epistemic than moral,yet it seems that in ascribing epistemic culpability we would need to assume thatthe professor could reasonablyhave disentangled his personal preferencesfrom his belief-forming processes. And it’ s notclear that our beliefs and theprocesses by which we go about formingthem can beso easilyseparated intothe ‘ true’and the‘ subjectivelyenhanced’ . Considera variationon this scenario: instead of giving his favourite students better grades thantheir work warrants, he perversely gives them worse grades. He might do thisbecause, he reasons, he knows these students so well,he likes them so much and heknows that receiving a bad grade ona paperwill compel themto work much harderthan they would have if they’ d gottena mediocregrade. He might thinkthat they will respond to a lowergrade byre-doubling their efforts, and will vastlyimprove their papers as aresult.He might also judgetheir work more harshlybecause he knows what they are capable ofat theirbest— that is, his beliefsabout thequality of his favourite students’ work would, in this case, also be lteredthrough his personal attachments. The point I wishto make hereis thatit is not just that the evaluation is lteredthrough personal attachments that makes ita failureof objectivity, but ratherthat the consequences of such attachmentsis a certainkind of evaluation. The case inwhich
Recommended publications
  • A Rationalist Argument for Libertarian Free Will
    A rationalist argument for libertarian free will Stylianos Panagiotou PhD University of York Philosophy August 2020 Abstract In this thesis, I give an a priori argument in defense of libertarian free will. I conclude that given certain presuppositions, the ability to do otherwise is a necessary requirement for substantive rationality; the ability to think and act in light of reasons. ‘Transcendental’ arguments to the effect that determinism is inconsistent with rationality are predominantly forwarded in a Kantian manner. Their incorporation into the framework of critical philosophy renders the ontological status of their claims problematic; rather than being claims about how the world really is, they end up being claims about how the mind must conceive of it. To make their ontological status more secure, I provide a rationalist framework that turns them from claims about how the mind must view the world into claims about the ontology of rational agents. In the first chapter, I make some preliminary remarks about reason, reasons and rationality and argue that an agent’s access to alternative possibilities is a necessary condition for being under the scope of normative reasons. In the second chapter, I motivate rationalism about a priori justification. In the third chapter, I present the rationalist argument for libertarian free will and defend it against objections. Several objections rest on a compatibilist understanding of an agent’s abilities. To undercut them, I devote the fourth chapter, in which I give a new argument for incompatibilism between free will and determinism, which I call the situatedness argument for incompatibilism. If the presuppositions of the thesis are granted and the situatedness argument works, then we may be justified in thinking that to the extent that we are substantively rational, we are free in the libertarian sense.
    [Show full text]
  • Immanuel Kant's Theory of Knowledge: Exploring the Relation Between
    Immanuel Kant’s Theory of Knowledge: Exploring the Relation between Sensibility and Understanding Wendell Allan Marinay Kant’s critique of reason does not provide an ultimate justification of knowledge, is not the last word in philosophy but is an initial thesis aimed at successfully solving the challenge posed by two warring schools of thought during Kant’s time: empiricism and rationalism.1 Following the ancient-Greek’s nothing-in-the-mind-without-passing-through-the- senses (Aristotle), Immanuel Kant’s inquiry of knowledge starts with the things “seen” or “experienced.”2 Such inquiry entails the materials and a process by which there can (probably) be known. It probes into or upon the constitution of human reason – an epistemic investigation from within yet necessarily involving from without. This is so because “in the mind we have the pure forms of sensible intuition and the pure concepts of an object in general. Extraneous to the mind we have the unknown and unknowable source of the matter for these forms, the source of that out of which our contentful experience is made.”3 Kant mentions two faculties of the mind that are involved in the knowing process, namely, sensibility and understanding. “He distinguishes between the receptive faculty of sensibility, through which we have intuitions, and the active faculty of understanding, which is the source of concepts.”4 Through the former, the objects are “given” while 1 Otfried Höffe. Immanuel Kant trans. Marshall Farrier (New York: State University of New York Press, 1994), 55. 2 We should not be misled that by starting with things seen or experienced, knowledge would mean like a result of or is consequent to such experience.
    [Show full text]
  • 1 Hume's Robust Theory of Practical Reason1 Geoffrey Sayre-Mccord
    Hume’s Robust Theory of Practical Reason1 Geoffrey Sayre-McCord University of North Carolina at Chapel Hill Introduction Hume never uses the phrase “practical reason.” This is no surprise given his commitment to revealing the unfounded pretensions of those who appealed to “reason” as an all-purpose safe haven for their preferred views of theology, science, or morality. Yet Hume clearly has a great deal to say about practical reason. In light of what he says, Hume is regularly read as either an outright skeptic about practical reason or as an advocate of unadorned instrumentalism. According to the skeptical reading, Hume rejects the idea that reason could be practical at all; according to the instrumental reading, he embraces reason as practical, yet sees its role as being entirely a matter of figuring out efficient ways to satisfy one’s desires or achieve one’s ends.2 The instrumentalist interpretation has become so widespread that instrumentalism is often labelled ‘Humeanism’ (though in a nod to the plausibility of the skeptical reading people will often say that it is unclear whether Hume is a “Humean.”3 Not surprisingly, support for both interpretations is easy to find. So, for instance, when it comes to the case for the skeptical interpretation, people point to Hume’s claim that “…reason is perfectly inert, and can never either prevent or produce any action or affection” (T 3.1.1.8, SBN 457-458), which seems an unambiguous assertion of the skeptical view. Meanwhile, those interpreting Hume as an instrumentalist point to Hume’s assertion that “Where a passion is neither founded on false suppositions, nor chooses means insufficient for the end, the understanding can neither justify nor condemn it” (T 2.3.3.6, SBN 415-6), which seems almost as clearly to highlight explicitly just what an instrumentalist would identify as practical reason’s role – to ensure that our desires are informed and that we choose effective means to their satisfaction.
    [Show full text]
  • ABSTRACT Augustinian Auden: the Influence of Augustine of Hippo on W. H. Auden Stephen J. Schuler, Ph.D. Mentor: Richard Rankin
    ABSTRACT Augustinian Auden: The Influence of Augustine of Hippo on W. H. Auden Stephen J. Schuler, Ph.D. Mentor: Richard Rankin Russell, Ph.D. It is widely acknowledged that W. H. Auden became a Christian in about 1940, but relatively little critical attention has been paid to Auden‟s theology, much less to the particular theological sources of Auden‟s faith. Auden read widely in theology, and one of his earliest and most important theological influences on his poetry and prose is Saint Augustine of Hippo. This dissertation explains the Augustinian origin of several crucial but often misunderstood features of Auden‟s work. They are, briefly, the nature of evil as privation of good; the affirmation of all existence, and especially the physical world and the human body, as intrinsically good; the difficult aspiration to the fusion of eros and agape in the concept of Christian charity; and the status of poetry as subject to both aesthetic and moral criteria. Auden had already been attracted to similar ideas in Lawrence, Blake, Freud, and Marx, but those thinkers‟ common insistence on the importance of physical existence took on new significance with Auden‟s acceptance of the Incarnation as an historical reality. For both Auden and Augustine, the Incarnation was proof that the physical world is redeemable. Auden recognized that if neither the physical world nor the human body are intrinsically evil, then the physical desires of the body, such as eros, the self-interested survival instinct, cannot in themselves be intrinsically evil. The conflict between eros and agape, or altruistic love, is not a Manichean struggle of darkness against light, but a struggle for appropriate placement in a hierarchy of values, and Auden derived several ideas about Christian charity from Augustine.
    [Show full text]
  • Augustine's Confessiones: the Battle Between Two Conversions
    University of South Florida Scholar Commons Graduate Theses and Dissertations Graduate School 11-12-2018 Augustine's Confessiones: The Battle between Two Conversions Robert Hunter Craig University of South Florida, [email protected] Follow this and additional works at: https://scholarcommons.usf.edu/etd Part of the Philosophy of Science Commons, and the Religious Thought, Theology and Philosophy of Religion Commons Scholar Commons Citation Craig, Robert Hunter, "Augustine's Confessiones: The Battle between Two Conversions" (2018). Graduate Theses and Dissertations. https://scholarcommons.usf.edu/etd/8109 This Dissertation is brought to you for free and open access by the Graduate School at Scholar Commons. It has been accepted for inclusion in Graduate Theses and Dissertations by an authorized administrator of Scholar Commons. For more information, please contact [email protected]. Augustine’s Confessiones: The Battle between Two Conversions by Robert Hunter Craig A dissertation submitted in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy Department of Philosophy with a concentration in Philosophy and Religion College of Arts and Sciences University of South Florida Co-Major Professor: Thomas Williams, Ph.D. Co-Major Professor: Michael DeJonge, Ph.D. William Goodwin, Ph.D. Alexander Levine, Ph.D. Date of Approval: November 2, 2018 Keywords: Autopsychographical, Theo-Ratiocination, Conversion, Consciousness, Pedagogic-Apologetic Copyright © 2018, Robert Hunter Craig DEDICATED TO: God To my wife Terry Lee Craig To my professor and pastor James F. Strange PREFACE I can recall reading the Confessiones of Augustine in 1988 for the first time when I was a sophomore at Stetson University in my Introduction to Philosophy class.
    [Show full text]
  • Faith and Reason
    Phil 2301 Intro to Philosophy FAITH AND REASON "More consequences for thought and action follow from the affirmation or denial of God than from answering any other basic question. They follow for those who regard the question as answerable only by faith or only by reason, and even for those who insist upon suspending judgment entirely." —Great Books of the Western World, volume 2, p. 543. Introduction: Why do you believe in God? I. The Relationship Between Faith and Reason A. Introductory questions on the relationship between faith and reason • Is religious belief and Christian faith rational? • Is Christian faith an essentially irrational activity? • Is Christian faith an arational activity? • If the claims of religious belief cannot be proven, is it still reasonable to prove these claims? • How many things are there in life that we cannot prove, and yet we believe them any way? • In this sense, could belief in God, and other religious beliefs be properly basic? • Is it sometimes morally permissible purposefully to get one self to believe what the evidence alone does not warrant, and this for pragmatic or existential reasons? • Is faith a separate form of life wherein external judgments are precluded and objective reason plays a very limited role? “For till it be resolved how far we are to be guided by reason, and how far by faith, we shall in vain dispute, and endeavor to convince one another in matters of religion.” —John Locke, An Essay Concerning Human Understanding, ed. by A. C. Fraser (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1894), II, 415. B. The precise issue What role should reason play in the validation or invalidation of religious belief systems and practices? I.
    [Show full text]
  • Rationalism in Science David J
    The University of San Francisco USF Scholarship: a digital repository @ Gleeson Library | Geschke Center Philosophy College of Arts and Sciences 2005 Rationalism in Science David J. Stump University of San Francisco, [email protected] Follow this and additional works at: http://repository.usfca.edu/phil Part of the Philosophy Commons, and the Physical Sciences and Mathematics Commons Recommended Citation Stump, D. “Rationalism in Science” in A Companion to Rationalism, Alan Nelson, ed. London: Blackwell, 2005, pp. 408-424. ISBN: 9781405109093. http://dx.doi.org/10.1002/9780470996904.ch22 This Book Chapter is brought to you for free and open access by the College of Arts and Sciences at USF Scholarship: a digital repository @ Gleeson Library | Geschke Center. It has been accepted for inclusion in Philosophy by an authorized administrator of USF Scholarship: a digital repository @ Gleeson Library | Geschke Center. For more information, please contact [email protected]. A Companion to Rationalism Edited by Alan Nelson david stump Copyright © 2005 by Blackwell Publishing Ltd 22 Rationalism in Science DAVID STUMP If rationalism is to be defined, in part, as the belief that at least some of our knowledge of the world is gained by pure reason alone, prior to experience, then science, as the main example of human knowledge, should be a focus of discussion in philosophical de- bates over rationalism. Although the traditional characterization of modern philosophy as a debate between the British empiricists and the continental rationalists that was sup- erseded by Kant has been widely acknowledged to be problematic for various reasons, recovering the scientific influences on modern philosophers will be the key to discus- sion here.
    [Show full text]
  • The Metaphysical Foundations Underlying Augustine's Solution to the Problem of Evil
    Georgia State University ScholarWorks @ Georgia State University Philosophy Theses Department of Philosophy 11-30-2007 Between Being and Nothingness: The Metaphysical Foundations Underlying Augustine's Solution to the Problem of Evil Brian Keith Kooy Follow this and additional works at: https://scholarworks.gsu.edu/philosophy_theses Part of the Philosophy Commons Recommended Citation Kooy, Brian Keith, "Between Being and Nothingness: The Metaphysical Foundations Underlying Augustine's Solution to the Problem of Evil." Thesis, Georgia State University, 2007. https://scholarworks.gsu.edu/philosophy_theses/32 This Thesis is brought to you for free and open access by the Department of Philosophy at ScholarWorks @ Georgia State University. It has been accepted for inclusion in Philosophy Theses by an authorized administrator of ScholarWorks @ Georgia State University. For more information, please contact [email protected]. BETWEEN BEING AND NOTHINGNESS: THE METAPHYSICAL FOUNDATIONS UNDERLYING AUGUSTINE’S SOLUTION TO THE PROBLEM OF EVIL by BRIAN KEITH KOOY Under the Direction of Dr. Timothy M. Renick ABSTRACT Several commentators make the claim that Augustine is not a systematic thinker. The purpose of this thesis is to refute that claim in one specific area of Augustine's thought, the metaphysical foundations underlying his solutions to the problem of evil. Through an exegetical examination of various works in which Augustine writes on evil, I show that his solutions for both natural and moral evil rely on a coherent metaphysical system,
    [Show full text]
  • Ch3 Fundamentals of the Scientific Approach
    3 - 1 Chapter 3. Fundamentals of the Scientific Approach Approaches to Knowing Authority Personal Experience Rationalism Empiricism Defining Science Goals of Science Assumptions of Science The Scientific Method Distinguishing Observation From Inference Systematic Nature of Science Inductive and Deductive Research Strategies Role of Theory in Science Summary of the Scientific Method Thinking Critically About Everyday Information Comparisons of Science and Nonscience Common Sense and Science Molecular to Molar Levels of Analysis and Explanation Importance of Basic Research A Defense of Basic Research Two Important Reasons for Supporting Basic Research Science and Technology Science and Public Policy Case Analysis General Summary Detailed Summary Key Terms Review Questions/Exercises 3 - 2 Approaches to Knowing Almost every moment of our waking lives we are confronted with situations that require us to make choices. Shall we obey the strident summons of the morning alarm or turn off the infernal machine in favor of another forty winks? Should we go to the aid of a friend who is in the throes of an emotional “down” even though doing so means breaking other commitments we have made? Should we buy the latest recording of our favorite musical group even though it precipitates a temporary financial crisis? How many times a day do questions like this race through our thoughts? How often are we required to assess situations, make decisions, predict actions, and draw conclusions? Some questions lead to emotional issues. How old is the earth? When and how did humans evolve? What curriculum should be taught in public school? What is the basis for observed racial differences? Whether we are scientists or not, the ways in which we carry out these activities are of profound significance.
    [Show full text]
  • The Epistemology of Immanuel Kant
    Western Washington University Western CEDAR WWU Honors Program Senior Projects WWU Graduate and Undergraduate Scholarship Spring 1982 The Epistemology of Immanuel Kant David Carl Bratz Western Washington University Follow this and additional works at: https://cedar.wwu.edu/wwu_honors Part of the Philosophy Commons Recommended Citation Bratz, David Carl, "The Epistemology of Immanuel Kant" (1982). WWU Honors Program Senior Projects. 225. https://cedar.wwu.edu/wwu_honors/225 This Project is brought to you for free and open access by the WWU Graduate and Undergraduate Scholarship at Western CEDAR. It has been accepted for inclusion in WWU Honors Program Senior Projects by an authorized administrator of Western CEDAR. For more information, please contact [email protected]. The Epistemology of Immanuel Kant A Thesis Submitted to the Honors Program In Partial Fulfillment of the Requirements for Bachelor of Arts with Honors Department of Philosophy By David C. Bratz May 1982 The Epistemology of Immanuel Kant by David C. Bratz Accepted by The Honors Program of Western Washington University in Partial Fulfillment of the Requirements for the Degree Bachelor of Arts with Honors Honors Program Director & Thesis Advisor Table of Contents I. Introduction II. The Pure Intuitions: Space and Time III. The Pure Concepts of the Understanding IV. Connecting Concepts and Intuition: Schematism and Principles V. Conclusion Footnotes Bibliography "All men by nature desire knowledge." -- Aristotle, Metaphysics, bk. 1, ch. 1. It has been the tendency of philosophers in the Twentieth Century to examine the philosophy of Immanuel Kant in parcels, by analyzing key Kantian concepts, arguments, and distinctions without relation to the architectonic to v/hich they belong.
    [Show full text]
  • An Introduction to Medieval Christian Philosophy
    An Introduction to Medieval Christian Philosophy by Jeremiah Joven Joaquin1 Objectives After reading this chapter, the student should be able to: 1. State and explain the medieval project of faith seeking understanding; and, 2. Discuss the implications of this project to philosophy in general. Introduction The present-day belief that reason (philosophy or science) and faith (theology) are fundamentally at odds is something that would baffle most medieval Christian philosophers. These philosophers have a firm belief that reason and faith have their respective roles in our acquisition of truths. Some of them see reason as a tool by which one could arrive at certain truths of the Christian faith. For example, some medieval thinkers think that God’s existence could be demonstrated via a philosophical argument. Others see that reason could be used as a way of showing the consistency of some Christian doctrines. For example, some medieval philosophers think that there is a way of making sense of the doctrine of the Trinity. Still others see that reason could be used as a way of distinguishing between truths that we could arrived at by rational demonstration and truths that could only be acquired through faith. For example, some medieval philosophers tried to show that the truth about the virgin birth of Jesus is not something that we could arrive at by the use of our cognitive capacities alone. In this chapter, we will examine the philosophical terrain of medieval Christian philosophy and see how faith and reason took center stage in the speculations of the great philosophers of this age.
    [Show full text]
  • Summary and Conclusion Chapter Review Questions Key Terms
    250 | CHAPTER 3 • KNOWLEDGE SUMMARY AND CONCLUSION Epistemology is the study of human knowledge—what we can know, how we can know it, and what we cannot know. In this sense, epistemology and metaphysics are complementary disciplines. Epistemology becomes the method of approach to the knowledge of the way the world really is. For some philosophers, for example, Descartes, this approach places its primary trust in reason; accordingly, they are called rationalists. For other philosophers, for example, Locke, the preferred approach is to trust the senses and experience; they are called empiricists. The problem for both the rationalists and the empiricists is to get beyond the mere appearance of things to the reality behind them. The rationalist tries to do this by appealing to intuition and certain principles from which he or she can deduce the way the world really is. The empiricist, on the other hand, appeals to his or her experiences, trying to find evidence for the nature of reality. For both views, however, the danger is that their meth- ods do not always seem to achieve as much as they would like. Rationalists disagree about which principles to start with and which intuitions to trust. Empiricists find that their own method of experience makes it impossible to say anything about what lies beyond experi- ence. Thus Berkeley argues that only our ideas (including God) and the minds that have these ideas exist, and Hume concludes that we can never know anything about reality, but only about our own associations of ideas. Epistemologists are still working on more satis- factory answers to the questions of knowledge, and still trying to defeat or defend once and for all the skeptical conclusions so brilliantly argued by Hume.
    [Show full text]