Concepts As Correlates of Lexical Labels. a Cognitivist Perspective

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Concepts As Correlates of Lexical Labels. a Cognitivist Perspective This is a submitted manuscript version. The publisher should be contacted for permission to re-use or reprint the material in any form. Final published version, copyright Peter Lang: https://doi.org/10.3726/978-3-653-05287-9 Sławomir Wacewicz Concepts as Correlates of Lexical Labels. A Cognitivist Perspective. This is a submitted manuscript version. The publisher should be contacted for permission to re-use or reprint the material in any form. Final published version, copyright Peter Lang: https://doi.org/10.3726/978-3-653-05287-9 CONTENTS Introduction………………………………………………………………... 6 PART I INTERNALISTIC PERSPECTIVE ON LANGUAGE IN COGNITIVE SCIENCE Preliminary remarks………………………………………………………… 17 1. History and profile of Cognitive Science……………………………….. 18 1.1. Introduction…………………………………………………………. 18 1.2. Cognitive Science: definitions and basic assumptions ……………. 19 1.3. Basic tenets of Cognitive 22 Science…………………………………… 1.3.1. Cognition……………………………………………………... 23 1.3.2. Representationism and presentationism…………………….... 25 1.3.3. Naturalism and physical character of mind…………………... 28 1.3.4. Levels of description…………………………………………. 30 1.3.5. Internalism (Individualism) ………………………………….. 31 1.4. History……………………………………………………………... 34 1.4.1. Prehistory…………………………………………………….. 35 1.4.2. Germination…………………………………………………... 36 1.4.3. Beginnings……………………………………………………. 37 1.4.4. Early and classical Cognitive Science………………………… 40 1.4.5. Contemporary Cognitive Science……………………………... 42 1.4.6. Methodological notes on interdisciplinarity………………….. 52 1.5. Summary…………………………………………………………. 59 2. Intrasystemic and extrasystemic principles of concept individuation 60 2.1. Existential status of concepts ……………………………………… 60 2 This is a submitted manuscript version. The publisher should be contacted for permission to re-use or reprint the material in any form. Final published version, copyright Peter Lang: https://doi.org/10.3726/978-3-653-05287-9 2.1.1. I-language and E-language………………………………........ 60 2.1.2. I-concepts and E-concepts……………………………………. 63 2.1.3. Gottlob Frege: metaphysical views and their influence…….... 66 2.2. Internalist and externalist principles of content-individuation …….. 70 2.2.1. Externalism: arguments by H. Putnam……………………….. 71 2.2.2. Common misunderstandings concerning internalism and externalism about content………………………………………. 73 2.2.3. Case against externalism……………………………………... 80 2.4. Summary and conclusion………….………………………………. 87 PART II THEORETICAL FOUNDATIONS OF STUDY OF CONCEPTS Introduction and notation……...………………………………………... 90 3. Concept, category, categorisation, mental representation. Preliminary definitions and discussion. Historical background. …... 93 Introduction and caveats... …...………………………………………… 93 3.1. Concepts…………………………………………………………… 93 3.1.1. Preliminary definitions……………………………………….. 93 3.1.2. Historical note…………………………………………...…… 94 3.1.3. Discussion……………………………………………………. 95 3.2. Categories and categorisation……………………………………… 110 3.2.1. Preliminary definition………………………………………... 110 3.2.2. Categories………………………..…………………………... 111 3.2.3. Categorisation………………………………………………… 115 3.3. Mental representation……………………………………………… 121 Summary…………………………………………………………. 125 4. Concepts in Cognitive Science………………………………………….. 127 4.1. Scope of study……………………………………………………… 127 4.2. Concepts in Cognitive Science. Concepts as lexical categories…..... 130 3 This is a submitted manuscript version. The publisher should be contacted for permission to re-use or reprint the material in any form. Final published version, copyright Peter Lang: https://doi.org/10.3726/978-3-653-05287-9 4.2.1. Introductory remarks…………………………………………. 130 4.2.2. What is ‘a concept’? Conditions on theory of concepts……… 131 4.2.3. Concepts are mental representations. ………………………... 133 4.2.4. Concepts are categories. …………………………………….. 139 4.2.5. Concepts have lexical correlates. ……………………………. 144 4.2.6. Concepts are shareable/concepts subserve communication. … 157 4.3. Conclusion…………………………………………………………. 159 PART III CONTEMPORARY APPROACHES TO CATEGORISATION AND CONCEPTUAL STRUCTURE 5. Classical approach to categorisation and conceptual structure ……. 162 5.1. Theories of categorisation or theories of concepts? Review of terminological problems. ………………………………….. 162 5.2. Classical approach…………………………………………………. 164 5.2.1. Exposition……………………………………………………. 164 5.2.2. History……………………………………………………….. 169 5.2.3. Criticism……………………………………………………… 176 5.2.4. Evaluation……………………………………………………. 188 5.2.5. Specific problem: feature format…………………………….. 191 5.2.6. Natural Semantic Metalanguage……………………………... 194 5.3. Summary and conclusion………..…………………………………. 196 6. Conceptual atomism and its refutation……………………………….. 199 6.1. Introduction………………………………………………………… 199 6.2. Jerry Fodor’s theory of concepts…………………………………... 201 6.2.1. Naturalism……………………………………………………. 202 6.2.2. Folk psychology……………………………………………… 203 6.2.3. Systematic nature of human thought (compositionality) ……. 204 6.2.4. Consequences………………………………………………… 205 4 This is a submitted manuscript version. The publisher should be contacted for permission to re-use or reprint the material in any form. Final published version, copyright Peter Lang: https://doi.org/10.3726/978-3-653-05287-9 6.2.5. Fodor’s conceptual atomism and informational semantic…… 209 6.3. Criticism of Fodor’s conceptual atomism…………………………. 218 6.3.1. Radical concept nativism…………………………………….. 218 6.3.2. Problem of elimination of epistemic factors…………………. 223 6.4. Recapitulation……………………………………………………… 227 7. From prototype to exemplar models in nonlexical and lexical categorisation …………………………………………......................... 228 7.1. Preliminary remarks……...………………………………………… 228 7.2. Similarity as theoretical notion…………………………………….. 229 7.2.1. Problems with similarity……………………………………... 230 7.2.2. Ways of constraining similarity……………………………… 233 7.3. Prototype and exemplar models of categorisation…………………. 236 7.3.1. What is ‘a prototype’? ……………………………………… 237 7.3.2. Categorisation by prototype………………………………….. 238 7.3.3. What is ‘an exemplar’? ……………………………………… 239 7.3.4. Categorisation by exemplars…………………………………. 241 7.4. From prototype to exemplar models in lexical categorisation…….. 242 7.4.1. Distinguishing exemplar from prototype models....................... 243 7.4.2. Distinctiveness and advantages of exemplar models………… 245 7.5. Summary...…………………………………………………………. 247 Conclusion…………………………………………………………………... 249 Bibliography……………………………………………………………… 252 Glossary of central terms………………………………………………… 272 5 This is a submitted manuscript version. The publisher should be contacted for permission to re-use or reprint the material in any form. Final published version, copyright Peter Lang: https://doi.org/10.3726/978-3-653-05287-9 Introduction Objectives and Methods The primary objective of this work consists in providing a typology and a critical examination of the key contemporary approaches to the topic of concepts and conceptual structure in its relation to categorisation. In the course of the text, I advance and defend two specific main theses. Firstly, concepts – at least for the purposes relevant to cognitive scientific research – are most fruitfully understood as ‘lexical categories’, in the sense of mental representations with lexical correlates. Secondly, concepts, so conceived, have internal structures, contrary to the influential proposal put forward by conceptual atomists. By way of conclusion, I suggest that quantitative categorisation models from other content domains (e.g. perceptual categorisation), such as exemplar models, may be the best suited to revealing the internal structures of concepts. The other major goal, which can be considered auxiliary, consists in a comprehensive and epistemologically informed discussion of the cognitive perspective on the study of language, its utility and validity. What is worth stressing is the broad construal of ‘the cognitive perspective’, which embraces but also largely transcends cognitive linguistics. In accordance with the spirit of Cognitive Science, it extends to cover all research that is both founded on strong mentalistic and representational assumptions and relevant to understanding human language processing – thus being open to insights from experimental psycholinguistics, cognitive psychology, neurolinguistics, philosophy of language and mind, as well as a number of related fields. The character of the present book is theoretical. In view of the breadth of the thematic scope of this work, I pursue the two major goals presented above mostly by way of surveying and synthesising contemporary research in the cognitivist tradition. However, contemporary and historic research from other traditions is presented as well, not just to seek the due theoretical distance that is 6 This is a submitted manuscript version. The publisher should be contacted for permission to re-use or reprint the material in any form. Final published version, copyright Peter Lang: https://doi.org/10.3726/978-3-653-05287-9 necessary for this type of academic work, but also in order to provide a proper background. Despite the theoretical character, in the course of the text I devote substantial effort to grounding the theorising in available empirical findings, whenever such results come as relevant. This work is based (largely but not exclusively) on a review and analysis of literature in the English language that dominates contemporary international research on the topic of categorisation and concepts. Philosophically, it builds to a substantial degree on the theoretical achievements of
Recommended publications
  • All in the Mind Psychology for the Curious
    All in the Mind Psychology for the Curious Third Edition Adrian Furnham and Dimitrios Tsivrikos www.ebook3000.com This third edition first published 2017 © 2017 John Wiley & Sons, Ltd Edition history: Whurr Publishers Ltd (1e, 1996); Whurr Publishers Ltd (2e, 2001) Registered Office John Wiley & Sons, Ltd, The Atrium, Southern Gate, Chichester, West Sussex, PO19 8SQ, UK Editorial Offices 350 Main Street, Malden, MA 02148‐5020, USA 9600 Garsington Road, Oxford, OX4 2DQ, UK The Atrium, Southern Gate, Chichester, West Sussex, PO19 8SQ, UK For details of our global editorial offices, for customer services, and for information about how to apply for permission to reuse the copyright material in this book please see our website at www.wiley.com/wiley‐blackwell. The right of Adrian Furnham and Dimitrios Tsivrikos to be identified as the authors of this work has been asserted in accordance with the UK Copyright, Designs and Patents Act 1988. All rights reserved. No part of this publication may be reproduced, stored in a retrieval system, or transmitted, in any form or by any means, electronic, mechanical, photocopying, recording or otherwise, except as permitted by the UK Copyright, Designs and Patents Act 1988, without the prior permission of the publisher. Wiley also publishes its books in a variety of electronic formats. Some content that appears in print may not be available in electronic books. Designations used by companies to distinguish their products are often claimed as trademarks. All brand names and product names used in this book are trade names, service marks, trademarks or registered trademarks of their respective owners.
    [Show full text]
  • Cognitive and Neuroscience Research on Learning And
    The 11th International Conference on Education Research New Educational Paradigm for Learning and Instruction September 29 – October 1, 2010 Cognitive and Neuroscience Research on Learning and Instruction: Recent insights about the impact of non-conscious knowledge on problem solving, higher order thinking skills 12 and interactive cyber-learning environments. Richard E. Clark University of Southern California, USA Abstract There are as least three powerful insights from recent studies of the brain that support cognitive science research findings: First, our brains learn and process two very different types of knowledge; non conscious, automated knowledge and conscious, controllable, declarative knowledge. Evidence also suggests that we believe we control our own learning by conscious choice when in fact nearly all mental operations are highly automated, including learning and problem solving; Second, human beings have a very limited capacity to think during learning and problem solving and when that capacity is exceeded, thinking and learning stop without us being aware. Thus instruction and self managed learning must strive to avoid cognitive overload; and Third, nearly all of our instructional design and cyber learning theories and models fail to account for the influence of non-conscious cognitive processes and therefore are inadequate to deal with complex learning and performance. Evidence for these points will be described and their implications for instruction and the learning of problem solving and higher order thinking skills will be discussed. Models of learning and instruction that appear to help overcome some of these biological and cognitive barriers will be described. In addition, suggestions for new research questions on interactive learning environments that take account of the three insights will also be described.
    [Show full text]
  • The Science of Psychology 1
    PSY_C01.qxd 1/2/05 3:17 pm Page 2 The Science of Psychology 1 CHAPTER OUTLINE LEARNING OBJECTIVES INTRODUCTION PINNING DOWN PSYCHOLOGY PSYCHOLOGY AND COMMON SENSE: THE GRANDMOTHER CHALLENGE Putting common sense to the test Explaining human behaviour THE BEGINNINGS OF MODERN PSYCHOLOGY Philosophical influences Physiological influences PSYCHOLOGY TODAY Structuralism: mental chemistry Functionalism: mental accomplishment Behaviourism: a totally objective psychology Gestalt psychology: making connections Out of school: the independents The cognitive revolution FINAL THOUGHTS SUMMARY REVISION QUESTIONS FURTHER READING PSY_C01.qxd 1/2/05 3:17 pm Page 3 Learning Objectives By the end of this chapter you should appreciate that: n psychology is much more than ‘common sense’; n psychological knowledge can be usefully applied in many different professions and walks of life; n psychology emerged as a distinct discipline around 150 years ago, from its roots in physiology, physics and philosophy; n there are fundamental differences between different schools of thought in psychology; n psychology is the science of mental life and behaviour, and different schools of thought within psychology place differing degrees of emphasis on understanding these different elements of psychology; n most academic departments in the English-speaking world focus on the teaching of experimental psychology, in which scientific evidence about the structure and function of the mind and behaviour accumulates through the execution of empirical investigations; n in the history of psychology many different metaphors have been used for thinking about the workings of the human mind, and since the Second World War the most influential of these metaphors has been another complex information-processing device – the computer.
    [Show full text]
  • The Rise of Cognitive Science in the 20Th Century
    The Rise of Cognitive Science in the 20th Century Carrie Figdor (forthcoming in Kind, A., ed., Philosophy of Mind in the 20th and 21st Centuries: Routledge) Penultimate Draft Abstract. This chapter describes the conceptual foundations of cognitive science during its establishment as a science in the 20th century. It is organized around the core ideas of individual agency as its basic explanans and information-processing as its basic explanandum. The latter consists of a package of ideas that provide a mathematico- engineering framework for the philosophical theory of materialism. Keywords: cognitive science; psychology; linguistics; computer science; neuroscience; behaviorism; artificial intelligence; computationalism; connectionism Part I. Introduction. Cognitive science is the study of individual agency: its nature, scope, mechanisms, and patterns. It studies what agents are and how they function. This definition is modified from one provided by Bechtel, Abrahamson, and Graham (1998), where cognitive science is defined as “the multidisciplinary scientific study of cognition and its role in intelligent agency.” Several points motivate the modification. First (and least consequential), the multidisciplinarity of cognitive science is an accident of academic history, not a fact about its subject matter (a point also pressed in Gardner 1985). Second, the label “intelligent” is often used as a term of normative assessment, when cognitive science is concerned with behavior by entities (including possibly groups, as individual or collective agents) that are not considered intelligent, as well as unintelligent behavior of intelligent agents, for any intuitive definition of “intelligent”.1 Third and most importantly, the term “cognition” is omitted from the definiens to help emphasize a position of neutrality on a number of contemporary debates.
    [Show full text]
  • The Association of Strategy Use and Concrete-Operational Thinking in Primary School
    ORIGINAL RESEARCH published: 23 May 2018 doi: 10.3389/feduc.2018.00038 The Association of Strategy Use and Concrete-Operational Thinking in Primary School Moritz Börnert-Ringleb* and Jürgen Wilbert Department of Inclusive Education, University of Potsdam, Potsdam, Germany Concrete-operational thinking depicts an important aspect of cognitive development. A promising approach in promoting these skills is the instruction of strategies. The construction of such instructional programs requires insights into the mental operations involved in problem-solving. In the present paper, we address the question to which extent variations of the effect of isolated and combined mental operations (strategies) on correct solution of concrete-operational concepts can be observed. Therefore, a cross-sectional design was applied. The use of mental operations was measured by thinking-aloud reports from 80 first- and second-graders (N = 80) while solving tasks depicting concrete-operational thinking. Concrete-operational thinking was assessed Edited by: using the subscales conservation of numbers, classification and sequences of the TEKO. Michael S. Dempsey, Boston University, United States The verbal reports were transcribed and coded with regard to the mental operations Reviewed by: applied per task. Data analyses focused on tasks level, resulting in the analyses of Sharinaz Hassan, N = 240 tasks per subscale. Differences regarding the contribution of isolated and Curtin University, Australia Niels A. Taatgen, combined mental operations (strategies) to correct solution were observed. Thereby, University of Groningen, Netherlands the results indicate the necessity of selection and integration of appropriate mental *Correspondence: operations as strategies. The results offer insights in involved mental operations while Moritz Börnert-Ringleb solving concrete-operational tasks and depict a contribution to the construction of [email protected] instructional programs.
    [Show full text]
  • Coordination of Component Mental Operations in Sequences of Discrete Responses
    Coordination of Component Mental Operations in Sequences of Discrete Responses Shu-Chieh Wu ([email protected] ) Roger W. Remington ([email protected]) NASA Ames Research Center, Mail Stop 262-4 Moffett Field, CA 94035 USA Harold Pashler ([email protected]) Department of Psychology, University of California, San Diego La Jolla, CA 92093 USA Abstract distributed across different resources, interleaving upcoming operations in the slack time created by queued bottleneck In daily life we often perform sequences of actions, which processes, and allowing operations from different resources with practice are accomplished by overlapping mental to proceed concurrently. The success of this approach operations for successive actions. Is it possible to derive depends on the underlying assumption that component performance predictions for such sequences from a mental operations inferred from discrete task performance characterization of the mental operations for a single do not function differently in extended task environments. stimulus-response pair? We explore this by examining the joint timing of eye movements and manual responses in a This assumption has yet to be tested. Also, success has been typing-like task following Pashler (1994). Participants made achieved for tasks that are largely perceptual-motor, with separate choice responses to a series of five stimuli spread good fits obtaining after about 100 contiguous trials (e.g., over a wide viewing area. Replicating Pashler’s results, John et al., 2002). responses to the first stimulus (RT1) were elevated, with The goal of the present research is to investigate the inter-response intervals (IRI) for subsequent items rapid and coordination of component mental operations in extended flat across items.
    [Show full text]
  • Addressing Metacognitive Capacity for Self Reflection in the Psychotherapy for Schizophrenia
    58 The British Psychological Psychology and Psychotherapy: Theory, Research and Practice (2011), 84, 58–69 Society C 2010 The British Psychological Society www.wileyonlinelibrary.com Addressing metacognitive capacity for self reflection in the psychotherapy for schizophrenia: A conceptual model of the key tasks and processes ∗ , Paul H. Lysaker1,2 , Kelly D. Buck1 3, Antonino Carcione4, Michelle Procacci4, Giampaolo Salvatore4, Guiseppe Nicolo` 4 and Giancarlo Dimaggio4 1Roudebush VA Medical Center, Indianapolis, Indiana, USA 2Department of Psychiatry, Indiana University School of Medicine, Indianapolis, Indiana, USA 3Purdue University School of Nursing, Indianapolis, Indiana, USA 4Terzo Centro di Psicoterapia Cognitiva, Associazione di Psicologia Cognitiva, Rome, Italy Purpose. Recognition that recovery from schizophrenia may involve a deepening of the experience of being in the world has led to the possibility that psychotherapy may play a key role in treatment by enhancing metacognition, or the capacity to think about thinking. While the potential of psychotherapy to enhance metacognition in non- psychotic disorders has been discussed in depth, little has been written about how psychotherapy may systematically address metacognition in schizophrenia. Accordingly, the current paper formulates a model of how psychotherapy might address one specific element of metacognition, namely self-reflectivity. Methods. Procedures are outlined for assessing clients’ capacity for self-reflectivity within narrative contexts during psychotherapy. Results. Targeted interventions are identified which are tailored to clients’ capacities in the moment and which assist clients to think about their own thinking at the level of which they are capable. This may lead clients over time to develop a greater ability to engage in acts of increasingly complex self-reflectivity.
    [Show full text]
  • Metaphysics and Natural Kinds: Slingshots, Fundamentality, and Causal Structure
    METAPHYSICS AND NATURAL KINDS: SLINGSHOTS, FUNDAMENTALITY, AND CAUSAL STRUCTURE By ANDREW LEE MCFARLAND Submitted to the graduate degree program in the Department of Philosophy and the Graduate Faculty of the University of Kansas in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy. ________________________________ Chair: John Symons ________________________________ John Bricke ________________________________ Armin Schulz ________________________________ Clif Pye ________________________________ Philippe Huneman Date Defended: May 16, 2014 The Dissertation Committee for Andrew Lee McFarland certifies that this is the approved version of the following dissertation: METAPHYSICS AND NATURAL KINDS: SLINGSHOTS, FUNDAMENTALITY, AND CAUSAL STRUCTURE ________________________________ JOHN SYMONS Date approved: May 16, 2014 ii DISSERTATION ABSTRACT Metaphysics and Natural Kinds: Slingshots, Fundamentality, and Causal Structure Andrew Lee McFarland My dissertation addresses a question relevant to metaphysics, philosophy of language, and philosophy of science: What are natural kinds? I explore a view that holds that natural kinds are complex, structural properties that involve causal structure. Causal structure describes the idea that for the many properties associated with natural kinds, these properties are nomically linked – that is causally connected – in such a way that the properties of non-natural kinds are not. After criticizing arguments in favor of a nominalist theory of kinds – one that holds that a natural kind just is to be identified with its class of instances – and after defending the notion of a complex structural property from several prominent objections posed by David Lewis, I apply a causal account of natural kinds to a set of problematic cases, paying special attention to isomeric kinds from chemistry. iii Dedication I dedicate this doctoral thesis to my family and to the tireless support they have given me over the years.
    [Show full text]
  • Consciousness Is a Thing, Not a Process
    applied sciences Opinion Consciousness Is a Thing, Not a Process Susan Pockett School of Psychology, University of Auckland, Auckland, New Zealand; [email protected] Received: 30 October 2017; Accepted: 23 November 2017; Published: 2 December 2017 Featured Application: If the theory outlined here is correct, the construction of artificial consciousness will certainly be possible, but a fundamentally different approach from that currently used in work on artificial intelligence will be necessary. Abstract: The central dogma of cognitive psychology is ‘consciousness is a process, not a thing’. Hence, the main task of cognitive neuroscientists is generally seen as working out what kinds of neural processing are conscious and what kinds are not. I argue here that the central dogma is simply wrong. All neural processing is unconscious. The illusion that some of it is conscious results largely from a failure to separate consciousness per se from a number of unconscious processes that normally accompany it—most particularly focal attention. Conscious sensory experiences are not processes at all. They are things: specifically, spatial electromagnetic (EM) patterns, which are presently generated only by ongoing unconscious processing at certain times and places in the mammalian brain, but which in principle could be generated by hardware rather than wetware. The neurophysiological mechanisms by which putatively conscious EM patterns are generated, the features that may distinguish conscious from unconscious patterns, the general principles that distinguish the conscious patterns of different sensory modalities and the general features that distinguish the conscious patterns of different experiences within any given sensory modality are all described. Suggestions for further development of this paradigm are provided.
    [Show full text]
  • The Resemblance Structure of Natural Kinds
    The Resemblance Structure of Natural Kinds A Formal Model for Resemblance Nominalism Javier Belastegui Lazcano Supervisors: Dr. Thomas Mormann Dr. Jon P´erezLaraudogoitia A thesis presented for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy University of the Basque Country November 2020 (cc)2021 JAVIER BELASTEGUI LAZCANO(cc by-nc-sa 4.0) Declaration of Authorship I hereby declare that this dissertation, entitled \The Resemblance Structure of Natural Kinds: A Formal Model for Resemblance Nominalism" and written under the supervision of Thomas Mormann and Jon P´erezLaraudogoitia, is the result of my own original research. To the best of my knowledge and belief, it contains no material previously published or written by another person, except where it is explicitly acknowledged in the text. No part of this thesis has been submitted for a degree at any other university or institution. Javier Belastegui Lazcano 1 Para Ane, que se sabe todas mis canciones. Abstract The aim of this thesis is to better understand the ways natural kinds are re- lated to each other by species-genus relations and the ways in which the members of the kind are related to each other by resemblance relations, by making use of formal models of kinds. This is done by first analysing a Minimal Conception of Natural Kinds and then reconstructing it from the ontological assumptions of Resemblance Nominalism. The questions addressed are: 1. What is the external structure of kinds? In what ways are kinds related to each other by species-genus relations? 2. What is the internal structure of kinds? In what sense are the instances of a kind similar enough to each other? According to the Minimal Conception of Natural Kinds, kinds have two components, a set of members of the kind (the extension) and a set of natural attributes common to these objects (the intension).
    [Show full text]
  • Experimente Clasice in Psihologie
    PSIHOLOGIE - PSIHOTERAPIE Colecţie coordonată de Simona Reghintovschi DOUGLAS MOOK Experimente clasice în psihologie Traducere din engleză de Clara Ruse Prefaţă la ediţia în limba română de Mihai Aniţei A TRei Editori SILVIU DRAGOMIR VASILE DEM. ZAMFIRESCU Director editorial MAGDALENA MÂRCULESCU Coperta FABER STUDIO (S. OLTEANU, A. RĂDULESCU, D. DUMBRĂVICIAN) Redactor RALUCA HURDUC Director producţie CRISTIAN CLAUDIU COBAN Dtp MARIAN CONSTANTIN Corectori ELENA BIŢU EUGENIA URSU Descrierea CIP a Bibliotecii Naţionale a României MOOK, DOUGLAS Experimente clasice în psihologie / Douglas Mook; trad.: Clara Ruse. - Bucureşti: Editura Trei, 2009 ISBN 978-973-707-286-3 I. Ruse, Clara (trad.) 159.9 Această carte a fost tradusă după Classic Experiments in Psychology de Douglas Mook, Editura Greenwood Press, imprintal Grupului Editorial Greenwood, Westport, CT, U.S.A. (http://www.greenwood.com/greenwood_press.aspx) Copyright © 2004 by Douglas Mook Copyright © Editura Trei, 2009 pentru prezenta ediţie C.P. 27-0490, Bucureşti Tel./Fax: +4 021300 60 90 e-mail: [email protected] www.edituratrei.ro ISBN 978-973-707-286-3 în memoria lui Eliot Stellar, care ar fi -putut o scrie mai bine. Cuprins Prefaţă la ediţia română (de Prof.univ.dr. Mihai Aniţei)................................. 11 Prefaţă .............................................................................................................................. 15 Mulţumiri.........................................................................................................................17
    [Show full text]
  • Mental Causation and the Metaphysics of Action.Pdf
    1 Mental Causation and the Metaphysics of Action Andrea Suzanne White Submitted in accordance with the requirements for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy The University of Leeds School of Philosophy, Religion and History of Science February 2018 2 The candidate confirms that the work submitted is her own and that appropriate credit has been given where reference has been made to the work of others. This copy has been supplied on the understanding that it is copyright material and that no quotation from the thesis may be published without proper acknowledgement. The right of Andrea Suzanne White to be identified as Author of this work has been asserted by Andrea Suzanne White in accordance with the Copyright, Designs and Patents Act 1988. 3 Acknowledgements I owe greatest thanks to my supervisor Helen Steward. I have greatly enjoyed my PhD and this is, in no small way, down to Helen. My research has benefited enormously from her astute criticism and sage advice. I would also like to thank the University of Leeds for granting me the 110 Anniversary Scholarship and making this research possible. I am also grateful to the organisers of the 2016 Warwick MindGrad Conference for an exciting and interesting conference. I am especially grateful to Johannas Roessler for providing extremely helpful feedback the paper I presented there. I also wish to thank the organisers of the 21st Oxford Graduate Philosophy Conference for their excellent conference. I particularly want to thank Ursula Coope for the constructive comments she offered in response to my paper, and for her encouragement.
    [Show full text]