Symbolic Logic

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Symbolic Logic Symbolic Logic J. Dmitri Gallow Draft of January 5, 2016 Contents 1 Basic Concepts of Logic 1 2 Sentence Logic 5 2.1 Syntax for SL ................................ 6 2.1.1 Vocabulary ............................. 6 2.1.2 Grammar ............................. 6 2.1.3 Main Operators and Subformulae ................ 7 2.2 Semantics for SL .............................. 10 2.2.1 The Meaning of the Statement Letters .............. 10 2.2.2 The Meaning of ‘∼’ ........................ 10 2.2.3 The Meaning of ‘&’ ........................ 11 2.2.4 The Meaning of ‘_’ ........................ 11 2.2.5 The Meaning of ‘⊃’ ........................ 12 2.2.6 The Meaning of ‘≡’ ........................ 12 2.2.7 Determining the Truth-value of a wff of SL ........... 12 2.3 Translation from SL to English ...................... 15 2.4 Translation from English to SL ...................... 18 2.4.1 Negation .............................. 18 2.4.2 Conjunction ............................ 19 2.4.3 Disjunction ............................ 20 2.4.4 The Material Conditional and Biconditional ........... 21 2.5 What a Truth-Table Represents ...................... 21 2.6 SL Tautologies, Contradictions, and Contingencies ............ 22 2.7 SL Equivalence ............................... 23 2.8 Disjunctive Normal Form and Expressive Completeness ......... 24 2.8.1 Disjunctive Normal Form ..................... 24 2.8.2 Expressive Completeness ..................... 28 2.9 SL-Validity and SL-Invalidity ....................... 30 2.10 SL-Validity and SL-Tautologies ...................... 35 2.11 SL-Consistency & SL-Inconsistency .................... 36 2.12 SL-Consistency and the Other Logical Properties of SL ......... 38 i Contents ii 3 Sentence Logic Trees 42 3.1 Truth Trees: The Basics .......................... 42 3.2 Rules for Truth Trees ............................ 45 3.3 Summary of Rules ............................. 53 3.4 Strategies for Applying Rules ....................... 54 3.5 ST-Consistency ............................... 55 3.6 Reading Truth-Value Assignments off of Open Branches ........ 57 3.7 ST-Validity ................................. 61 3.8 ST-Tautologies, ST-Contradictions, and ST-Contingencies ....... 64 3.8.1 ST-Tautologies ........................... 64 3.8.2 ST-Contradictions ......................... 65 3.8.3 ST-Contingencies ......................... 67 3.9 ST-Equivalence ............................... 68 4 Predicate Logic 70 4.1 The Language PL .............................. 70 4.1.1 The Syntax of PL ......................... 71 4.1.2 Semantics for PL ......................... 79 4.1.3 More on PL-Interpretations of Predicates ............ 81 4.1.4 Truth on an Interpretation .................... 83 4.1.5 Notation .............................. 86 4.2 PL-Validity ................................. 87 4.3 Proving PL-validity and the method of Semantic Proof ......... 90 4.4 Translations from PL into English ..................... 92 4.4.1 Translating Atomic wffs of PL .................. 92 4.4.2 Translating Simple Quantified wffs of PL ............ 93 4.4.3 Translating More Complicated Quantified wffs of PL ...... 94 4.5 Translations from English into PL ..................... 97 4.6 Overlapping Quantifiers and Relational Predicates ............ 99 4.6.1 Changing the Order of the Quantifiers .............. 100 4.6.2 Changing the Order of the Bound Variables ........... 104 4.6.3 Translating ‘(8x)(9y)Rxy’ and ‘(8x)(9y)Ryx’ .......... 106 4.6.4 Changing the Order of the Quantifiers and the Order of the Bound Variables .......................... 107 5 Predicate Logic Trees 109 5.1 Notation and Terminology ......................... 109 5.2 Predicate Logic Trees ............................ 110 5.2.1 Rule for Universally Quantified Wffs ............... 111 5.2.2 Rule for Existentially Quantified Wffs .............. 115 5.2.3 Rules for Negations of Quantified Wffs .............. 117 5.3 Strategies for Applying Rules ....................... 119 5.4 Sample Predicate Logic Trees ....................... 120 5.5 Logical Properties of PL .......................... 121 5.6 PT-Consistency .............................. 122 5.7 Reading Partial PL Interpretations off of Open Branches ........ 124 Contents iii 5.8 PT Validity ................................. 125 5.9 PT Tautologies, PT Contradictions, and PT Contingencies ....... 128 5.10 PT-Equivalence .............................. 131 5.11 Infinite Trees ................................ 133 6 Predicate Logic with Identity and Functions 140 6.1 The Language PLI ............................. 140 6.1.1 Preliminary Orientation ...................... 140 6.1.2 Syntax for PLI ........................... 141 6.1.3 Semantics for PLI ......................... 145 6.1.4 More on PLI-Interpretations of Function Symbols ....... 147 6.1.5 Truth on a PLI Interpretation ................... 150 6.2 Logical Notions of PLI ........................... 152 6.3 Trees for PLI ................................ 152 6.3.1 The Rule (=) ........................... 153 6.3.2 The Rule (, ×) .......................... 155 6.3.3 Completing Trees ......................... 156 6.4 PT I Consistency .............................. 160 6.5 PT I Validity ................................ 161 6.6 PT I Tautologies, Contingencies, and Contradictions ........... 163 6.6.1 Properties of Identity ....................... 164 6.7 PT I Equivalence .............................. 166 6.8 Infinite PLI Trees ............................. 167 6.9 Number Claims ............................... 168 6.10 The Only .................................. 176 6.11 Definite Descriptions ............................ 177 7 Metatheory for Sentence Logic 179 7.1 Use & Mention ............................... 179 7.2 Object Language & Metalanguage .................... 180 7.3 Metavariables ................................ 181 7.3.1 Use and Mention with Metavariables ............... 182 7.4 Syntax and Semantics ........................... 183 7.5 Syntactic Validity and Semantic Validity ................. 186 7.6 Soundness and Completeness of the Tree Method ............ 187 7.7 Mathematical Induction .......................... 190 7.7.1 Terminology ............................ 191 7.7.2 Examples of Mathematical Induction ............... 193 7.8 Varieties of Mathematical Induction ................... 195 7.9 Choosing the Right Inductive Property .................. 197 7.10 More Examples of Mathematical Induction ................ 199 7.10.1 Number of Parentheses ...................... 201 7.10.2 Substitution of SL-equivalents .................. 204 7.10.3 Duals ................................ 208 Contents iv 8 Soundness of the Tree Method for Sentence Logic 211 8.1 Preliminaries ................................ 211 8.2 The Proof in Broad Outline ........................ 213 8.3 Proof that the Tree Method for SL is Sound ................ 215 9 Completeness of the Tree Method for Sentence Logic 225 9.1 The Proof in Broad Outline ........................ 226 9.2 Proof that the Tree Method for SL is Complete .............. 227 Chapter 1 Basic Concepts of Logic 1. Logic is the study of arguments. (a) An argument is (for our purposes), just a collection of statements (or declarative sentences), one of which is designated as the conclusion, the remainder of which are designated as premises. (b) A statement (declarative sentence) is a sentence of which it makes sense to say that it is true or false. i. It’s true/false that it is Monday. X −! ‘It is Monday’ is a state- ment. ii. It’s true/false that close the door! × −! ‘Close the door!’ is not a statement. 2. There are many good-making features that an argument can have. (a) The premises can give good (though not conclusive) reason to accept the conclusion. (b) The premises can be true. (c) The premises can be probable. 3. In this course, we’ll just be focusing on one good-making feature that an argument can have: the property of deductive validity. Deductive Validity An argument is deductively valid if and only if (‘iff’) there is no possible scenario in which the premises are all true while the conclusion is false. 1 2 An argument is deductively invalid iff it is not deductively valid. Deductive Invalidity An argument is deductively invalid iff there is a possible scenario in which the premises are all true while the conclusion is false. 4. We may also characterize deductive validity in terms of the notion of a counterex- ample. Counterexample A counterexample to the deductive validity of an argu- ment is a specification of a possibility in which the premises of the argument are all true yet the conclusion is simultaneously false. Then, Deductive Validity (2) An argument is deductively valid iff it has no coun- terexample. Deductive Invalidity (2) An argument is deductively invalid iff it has a counterexample. 5. What we want is a theory that tells us, of any given argument, whether it is de- ductively valid (or just ‘valid’) or deductively invalid. 6. Other important logical notions: (a) Logical properties of statements: Statements can be logical tautologies, logi- cal contradictions, or logical contingencies. p q Logical Tautology A statement A is a logical tautology iff there is no p q p q possibility in which A is false (i.e., iff A is true in every possibility). p q Logical Contradiction A statement A is a logical contradic- p q p q tion iff there is no possibility in which A is true (i.e., iff A is false in every possibility). p q Logical Contingency A statement A is a logical contingency iff p q there is some possibility
Recommended publications
  • Gibbardian Collapse and Trivalent Conditionals
    Gibbardian Collapse and Trivalent Conditionals Paul Égré* Lorenzo Rossi† Jan Sprenger‡ Abstract This paper discusses the scope and significance of the so-called triviality result stated by Allan Gibbard for indicative conditionals, showing that if a conditional operator satisfies the Law of Import-Export, is supraclassical, and is stronger than the material conditional, then it must collapse to the material conditional. Gib- bard’s result is taken to pose a dilemma for a truth-functional account of indicative conditionals: give up Import-Export, or embrace the two-valued analysis. We show that this dilemma can be averted in trivalent logics of the conditional based on Reichenbach and de Finetti’s idea that a conditional with a false antecedent is undefined. Import-Export and truth-functionality hold without triviality in such logics. We unravel some implicit assumptions in Gibbard’s proof, and discuss a recent generalization of Gibbard’s result due to Branden Fitelson. Keywords: indicative conditional; material conditional; logics of conditionals; triva- lent logic; Gibbardian collapse; Import-Export 1 Introduction The Law of Import-Export denotes the principle that a right-nested conditional of the form A → (B → C) is logically equivalent to the simple conditional (A ∧ B) → C where both antecedentsare united by conjunction. The Law holds in classical logic for material implication, and if there is a logic for the indicative conditional of ordinary language, it appears Import-Export ought to be a part of it. For instance, to use an example from (Cooper 1968, 300), the sentences “If Smith attends and Jones attends then a quorum *Institut Jean-Nicod (CNRS/ENS/EHESS), Département de philosophie & Département d’études cog- arXiv:2006.08746v1 [math.LO] 15 Jun 2020 nitives, Ecole normale supérieure, PSL University, 29 rue d’Ulm, 75005, Paris, France.
    [Show full text]
  • Glossary for Logic: the Language of Truth
    Glossary for Logic: The Language of Truth This glossary contains explanations of key terms used in the course. (These terms appear in bold in the main text at the point at which they are first used.) To make this glossary more easily searchable, the entry headings has ‘::’ (two colons) before it. So, for example, if you want to find the entry for ‘truth-value’ you should search for ‘:: truth-value’. :: Ambiguous, Ambiguity : An expression or sentence is ambiguous if and only if it can express two or more different meanings. In logic, we are interested in ambiguity relating to truth-conditions. Some sentences in natural languages express more than one claim. Read one way, they express a claim which has one set of truth-conditions. Read another way, they express a different claim with different truth-conditions. :: Antecedent : The first clause in a conditional is its antecedent. In ‘(P ➝ Q)’, ‘P’ is the antecedent. In ‘If it is raining, then we’ll get wet’, ‘It is raining’ is the antecedent. (See ‘Conditional’ and ‘Consequent’.) :: Argument : An argument is a set of claims (equivalently, statements or propositions) made up from premises and conclusion. An argument can have any number of premises (from 0 to indefinitely many) but has only one conclusion. (Note: This is a somewhat artificially restrictive definition of ‘argument’, but it will help to keep our discussions sharp and clear.) We can consider any set of claims (with one claim picked out as conclusion) as an argument: arguments will include sets of claims that no-one has actually advanced or put forward.
    [Show full text]
  • Expressive Completeness
    Truth-Functional Completeness 1. A set of truth-functional operators is said to be truth-functionally complete (or expressively adequate) just in case one can take any truth-function whatsoever, and construct a formula using only operators from that set, which represents that truth-function. In what follows, we will discuss how to establish the truth-functional completeness of various sets of truth-functional operators. 2. Let us suppose that we have an arbitrary n-place truth-function. Its truth table representation will have 2n rows, some true and some false. Here, for example, is the truth table representation of some 3- place truth function, which we shall call $: Φ ψ χ $ T T T T T T F T T F T F T F F T F T T F F T F T F F T F F F F T This truth-function $ is true on 5 rows (the first, second, fourth, sixth, and eighth), and false on the remaining 3 (the third, fifth, and seventh). 3. Now consider the following procedure: For every row on which this function is true, construct the conjunctive representation of that row – the extended conjunction consisting of all the atomic sentences that are true on that row and the negations of all the atomic sentences that are false on that row. In the example above, the conjunctive representations of the true rows are as follows (ignoring some extraneous parentheses): Row 1: (P&Q&R) Row 2: (P&Q&~R) Row 4: (P&~Q&~R) Row 6: (~P&Q&~R) Row 8: (~P&~Q&~R) And now think about the formula that is disjunction of all these extended conjunctions, a formula that basically is a disjunction of all the rows that are true, which in this case would be [(Row 1) v (Row 2) v (Row 4) v (Row6) v (Row 8)] Or, [(P&Q&R) v (P&Q&~R) v (P&~Q&~R) v (P&~Q&~R) v (~P&Q&~R) v (~P&~Q&~R)] 4.
    [Show full text]
  • Three Ways of Being Non-Material
    Three Ways of Being Non-Material Vincenzo Crupi, Andrea Iacona May 2019 This paper presents a novel unified account of three distinct non-material inter- pretations of `if then': the suppositional interpretation, the evidential interpre- tation, and the strict interpretation. We will spell out and compare these three interpretations within a single formal framework which rests on fairly uncontro- versial assumptions, in that it requires nothing but propositional logic and the probability calculus. As we will show, each of the three intrerpretations exhibits specific logical features that deserve separate consideration. In particular, the evidential interpretation as we understand it | a precise and well defined ver- sion of it which has never been explored before | significantly differs both from the suppositional interpretation and from the strict interpretation. 1 Preliminaries Although it is widely taken for granted that indicative conditionals as they are used in ordinary language do not behave as material conditionals, there is little agreement on the nature and the extent of such deviation. Different theories tend to privilege different intuitions about conditionals, and there is no obvious answer to the question of which of them is the correct theory. In this paper, we will compare three interpretations of `if then': the suppositional interpretation, the evidential interpretation, and the strict interpretation. These interpretations may be regarded either as three distinct meanings that ordinary speakers attach to `if then', or as three ways of explicating a single indeterminate meaning by replacing it with a precise and well defined counterpart. Here is a rough and informal characterization of the three interpretations. According to the suppositional interpretation, a conditional is acceptable when its consequent is credible enough given its antecedent.
    [Show full text]
  • False Dilemma Wikipedia Contents
    False dilemma Wikipedia Contents 1 False dilemma 1 1.1 Examples ............................................... 1 1.1.1 Morton's fork ......................................... 1 1.1.2 False choice .......................................... 2 1.1.3 Black-and-white thinking ................................... 2 1.2 See also ................................................ 2 1.3 References ............................................... 3 1.4 External links ............................................. 3 2 Affirmative action 4 2.1 Origins ................................................. 4 2.2 Women ................................................ 4 2.3 Quotas ................................................. 5 2.4 National approaches .......................................... 5 2.4.1 Africa ............................................ 5 2.4.2 Asia .............................................. 7 2.4.3 Europe ............................................ 8 2.4.4 North America ........................................ 10 2.4.5 Oceania ............................................ 11 2.4.6 South America ........................................ 11 2.5 International organizations ...................................... 11 2.5.1 United Nations ........................................ 12 2.6 Support ................................................ 12 2.6.1 Polls .............................................. 12 2.7 Criticism ............................................... 12 2.7.1 Mismatching ......................................... 13 2.8 See also
    [Show full text]
  • Material Conditional Cnt:Int:Mat: in Its Simplest Form in English, a Conditional Is a Sentence of the Form “If Sec
    int.1 The Material Conditional cnt:int:mat: In its simplest form in English, a conditional is a sentence of the form \If sec . then . ," where the . are themselves sentences, such as \If the butler did it, then the gardener is innocent." In introductory logic courses, we earn to symbolize conditionals using the ! connective: symbolize the parts indicated by . , e.g., by formulas ' and , and the entire conditional is symbolized by ' ! . The connective ! is truth-functional, i.e., the truth value|T or F|of '! is determined by the truth values of ' and : ' ! is true iff ' is false or is true, and false otherwise. Relative to a truth value assignment v, we define v ⊨ ' ! iff v 2 ' or v ⊨ . The connective ! with this semantics is called the material conditional. This definition results in a number of elementary logical facts. First ofall, the deduction theorem holds for the material conditional: If Γ; ' ⊨ then Γ ⊨ ' ! (1) It is truth-functional: ' ! and :' _ are equivalent: ' ! ⊨ :' _ (2) :' _ ⊨ ' ! (3) A material conditional is entailed by its consequent and by the negation of its antecedent: ⊨ ' ! (4) :' ⊨ ' ! (5) A false material conditional is equivalent to the conjunction of its antecedent and the negation of its consequent: if ' ! is false, ' ^ : is true, and vice versa: :(' ! ) ⊨ ' ^ : (6) ' ^ : ⊨ :(' ! ) (7) The material conditional supports modus ponens: '; ' ! ⊨ (8) The material conditional agglomerates: ' ! ; ' ! χ ⊨ ' ! ( ^ χ) (9) We can always strengthen the antecedent, i.e., the conditional is monotonic: ' ! ⊨ (' ^ χ) ! (10) material-conditional rev: c8c9782 (2021-09-28) by OLP/ CC{BY 1 The material conditional is transitive, i.e., the chain rule is valid: ' ! ; ! χ ⊨ ' ! χ (11) The material conditional is equivalent to its contrapositive: ' ! ⊨ : !:' (12) : !:' ⊨ ' ! (13) These are all useful and unproblematic inferences in mathematical rea- soning.
    [Show full text]
  • Exclusive Or from Wikipedia, the Free Encyclopedia
    New features Log in / create account Article Discussion Read Edit View history Exclusive or From Wikipedia, the free encyclopedia "XOR" redirects here. For other uses, see XOR (disambiguation), XOR gate. Navigation "Either or" redirects here. For Kierkegaard's philosophical work, see Either/Or. Main page The logical operation exclusive disjunction, also called exclusive or (symbolized XOR, EOR, Contents EXOR, ⊻ or ⊕, pronounced either / ks / or /z /), is a type of logical disjunction on two Featured content operands that results in a value of true if exactly one of the operands has a value of true.[1] A Current events simple way to state this is "one or the other but not both." Random article Donate Put differently, exclusive disjunction is a logical operation on two logical values, typically the values of two propositions, that produces a value of true only in cases where the truth value of the operands differ. Interaction Contents About Wikipedia Venn diagram of Community portal 1 Truth table Recent changes 2 Equivalencies, elimination, and introduction but not is Contact Wikipedia 3 Relation to modern algebra Help 4 Exclusive “or” in natural language 5 Alternative symbols Toolbox 6 Properties 6.1 Associativity and commutativity What links here 6.2 Other properties Related changes 7 Computer science Upload file 7.1 Bitwise operation Special pages 8 See also Permanent link 9 Notes Cite this page 10 External links 4, 2010 November Print/export Truth table on [edit] archived The truth table of (also written as or ) is as follows: Venn diagram of Create a book 08-17094 Download as PDF No.
    [Show full text]
  • An Introduction to Formal Logic
    forall x: Calgary An Introduction to Formal Logic By P. D. Magnus Tim Button with additions by J. Robert Loftis Robert Trueman remixed and revised by Aaron Thomas-Bolduc Richard Zach Fall 2021 This book is based on forallx: Cambridge, by Tim Button (University College Lon- don), used under a CC BY 4.0 license, which is based in turn on forallx, by P.D. Magnus (University at Albany, State University of New York), used under a CC BY 4.0 li- cense, and was remixed, revised, & expanded by Aaron Thomas-Bolduc & Richard Zach (University of Calgary). It includes additional material from forallx by P.D. Magnus and Metatheory by Tim Button, used under a CC BY 4.0 license, from forallx: Lorain County Remix, by Cathal Woods and J. Robert Loftis, and from A Modal Logic Primer by Robert Trueman, used with permission. This work is licensed under a Creative Commons Attribution 4.0 license. You are free to copy and redistribute the material in any medium or format, and remix, transform, and build upon the material for any purpose, even commercially, under the following terms: ⊲ You must give appropriate credit, provide a link to the license, and indicate if changes were made. You may do so in any reasonable manner, but not in any way that suggests the licensor endorses you or your use. ⊲ You may not apply legal terms or technological measures that legally restrict others from doing anything the license permits. The LATEX source for this book is available on GitHub and PDFs at forallx.openlogicproject.org.
    [Show full text]
  • Conditional Heresies *
    CONDITIONAL HERESIES * Fabrizio Cariani and Simon Goldstein Abstract The principles of Conditional Excluded Middle (CEM) and Simplification of Disjunctive Antecedents (SDA) have received substantial attention in isolation. Both principles are plausible generalizations about natural lan- guage conditionals. There is however little discussion of their interaction. This paper aims to remedy this gap and explore the significance of hav- ing both principles constrain the logic of the conditional. Our negative finding is that, together with elementary logical assumptions, CEM and SDA yield a variety of implausible consequences. Despite these incom- patibility results, we open up a narrow space to satisfy both. We show that, by simultaneously appealing to the alternative-introducing analysis of disjunction and to the theory of homogeneity presuppositions, we can satisfy both. Furthermore, the theory that validates both principles re- sembles a recent semantics that is defended by Santorio on independent grounds. The cost of this approach is that it must give up the transitivity of entailment: we suggest that this is a feature, not a bug, and connect it with recent developments of intransitive notions of entailment. 1 Introduction David Lewis’s logic for the counterfactual conditional (Lewis 1973) famously invalidates two plausible-sounding principles: simplification of disjunctive antecedents (SDA),1 and conditional excluded middle (CEM).2 Simplification states that conditionals with disjunctive antecedents entail conditionals whose antecedents are the disjuncts taken in isolation. For instance, given SDA, (1) en- tails (2). *Special thanks to Shawn Standefer for extensive written comments on a previous version of this paper and to anonymous reviewers for Philosophy and Phenomenological Research and the Amsterdam Colloquium.
    [Show full text]
  • TMM023- DISCRETE MATHEMATICS (March 2021)
    TMM023- DISCRETE MATHEMATICS (March 2021) Typical Range: 3-4 Semester Hours A course in Discrete Mathematics specializes in the application of mathematics for students interested in information technology, computer science, and related fields. This college-level mathematics course introduces students to the logic and mathematical structures required in these fields of interest. TMM023 Discrete Mathematics introduces mathematical reasoning and several topics from discrete mathematics that underlie, inform, or elucidate the development, study, and practice of related fields. Topics include logic, proof techniques, set theory, functions and relations, counting and probability, elementary number theory, graphs and tree theory, base-n arithmetic, and Boolean algebra. To qualify for TMM023 (Discrete Mathematics), a course must achieve all the following essential learning outcomes listed in this document (marked with an asterisk). In order to provide flexibility, institutions should also include the non-essential outcomes that are most appropriate for their course. It is up to individual institutions to determine if further adaptation of additional course learning outcomes beyond the ones in this document are necessary to support their students’ needs. In addition, individual institutions will determine their own level of student engagement and manner of implementation. These guidelines simply seek to foster thinking in this direction. 1. Formal Logic – Successful discrete mathematics students are able to construct and analyze arguments with logical precision. These students are able to apply rules from logical reasoning both symbolically and in the context of everyday language and are able to translate between them. The successful Discrete Mathematics student can: 1.1. Propositional Logic: 1.1a. Translate English sentences into propositional logic notation and vice-versa.
    [Show full text]
  • Forall X: an Introduction to Formal Logic 1.30
    University at Albany, State University of New York Scholars Archive Philosophy Faculty Books Philosophy 12-27-2014 Forall x: An introduction to formal logic 1.30 P.D. Magnus University at Albany, State University of New York, [email protected] Follow this and additional works at: https://scholarsarchive.library.albany.edu/ cas_philosophy_scholar_books Part of the Logic and Foundations of Mathematics Commons Recommended Citation Magnus, P.D., "Forall x: An introduction to formal logic 1.30" (2014). Philosophy Faculty Books. 3. https://scholarsarchive.library.albany.edu/cas_philosophy_scholar_books/3 This Book is brought to you for free and open access by the Philosophy at Scholars Archive. It has been accepted for inclusion in Philosophy Faculty Books by an authorized administrator of Scholars Archive. For more information, please contact [email protected]. forallx An Introduction to Formal Logic P.D. Magnus University at Albany, State University of New York fecundity.com/logic, version 1.30 [141227] This book is offered under a Creative Commons license. (Attribution-ShareAlike 3.0) The author would like to thank the people who made this project possible. Notable among these are Cristyn Magnus, who read many early drafts; Aaron Schiller, who was an early adopter and provided considerable, helpful feedback; and Bin Kang, Craig Erb, Nathan Carter, Wes McMichael, Selva Samuel, Dave Krueger, Brandon Lee, Toan Tran, and the students of Introduction to Logic, who detected various errors in previous versions of the book. c 2005{2014 by P.D. Magnus. Some rights reserved. You are free to copy this book, to distribute it, to display it, and to make derivative works, under the following conditions: (a) Attribution.
    [Show full text]
  • Form and Content: an Introduction to Formal Logic
    Connecticut College Digital Commons @ Connecticut College Open Educational Resources 2020 Form and Content: An Introduction to Formal Logic Derek D. Turner Connecticut College, [email protected] Follow this and additional works at: https://digitalcommons.conncoll.edu/oer Recommended Citation Turner, Derek D., "Form and Content: An Introduction to Formal Logic" (2020). Open Educational Resources. 1. https://digitalcommons.conncoll.edu/oer/1 This Book is brought to you for free and open access by Digital Commons @ Connecticut College. It has been accepted for inclusion in Open Educational Resources by an authorized administrator of Digital Commons @ Connecticut College. For more information, please contact [email protected]. The views expressed in this paper are solely those of the author. Form & Content Form and Content An Introduction to Formal Logic Derek Turner Connecticut College 2020 Susanne K. Langer. This bust is in Shain Library at Connecticut College, New London, CT. Photo by the author. 1 Form & Content ©2020 Derek D. Turner This work is published in 2020 under a Creative Commons Attribution- NonCommercial-NoDerivatives 4.0 International License. You may share this text in any format or medium. You may not use it for commercial purposes. If you share it, you must give appropriate credit. If you remix, transform, add to, or modify the text in any way, you may not then redistribute the modified text. 2 Form & Content A Note to Students For many years, I had relied on one of the standard popular logic textbooks for my introductory formal logic course at Connecticut College. It is a perfectly good book, used in countless logic classes across the country.
    [Show full text]