THE SOURCEBOOK

THE DEMOCRACY SOURCEBOOK

edited by Robert Dahl, Ian Shapiro, and Jose´ Antonio Cheibub

The MIT Press Cambridge, Massachusetts London, England 6 2003 Massachusetts Institute of Technology

All rights reserved. No part of this book may be reproduced in any form by any electronic or mechanical means (including photocopying, recording, or information storage and retrieval) without permission in writing from the publisher.

Excerpt from The Liberal Tradition in America: An Interpretation of American Political Thought since the Revolu- tion, copyright 6 1955 and renewed 1983 by Louis Hartz, reprinted by permission of Harcourt, Inc.

Every e¤ort has been made to contact those who hold rights for each of the selections. Any rights holders not credited should contact the editors so a correction can be made in the next printing.

This book was set in Times New Roman on 3B2 by Asco Typesetters, , and was printed and bound in the of America.

Library of Congress Cataloging-in-Publication Data

The democracy sourcebook / Robert Dahl, Ian Shapiro, and Jose´ Antonio Cheibub, editors. p. cm. Includes bibliographical references and index. ISBN 0-262-04217-7 (hc : alk. paper) — ISBN 0-262-54147-5 (pbk : alk. paper) 1. Democracy. I. Dahl, Robert Alan, 1915– . II. Shapiro, Ian. III. Cheibub, Jose´ Antonio. JC423.D4312 2003 321.8—dc21 2002045209

10987654321 Contents

Introduction ix Democracy and the Market: Political and Economic Reforms in 1 DEFINING DEMOCRACY 1 Eastern Europe and Latin America 76 The Social Contract 2 Democracy’s Third Wave 93 Jean-Jacques Rousseau Samuel P. Huntington Capitalism, , and South Africa’s Negotiated Democracy 5 Transition: Democracy, Opposition, Joseph Schumpeter and the New Constitutional Order 99 Minimalist Conception of Courtney Jung and Ian Shapiro Democracy: A Defense 12 Economic Development and Adam Przeworski Political Regimes 108 Democracy and Disagreement 18 Adam Przeworski, Michael E. Amy Gutmann and Dennis Alvarez, Jose´ Antonio Cheibub, Thompson and Fernando Limongi The Voice of the People 25 3 DEMOCRACY, CULTURE, James S. Fishkin AND SOCIETY 117 Defining and Developing Democracy 29 Larry Diamond The Federalist No. 10 118 James Madison Participation and Democratic Theory 40 The Federalist No. 14 123 James Madison Polyarchal Democracy 48 The Concept of a Liberal Society 126 Robert Dahl Louis Hartz Pluralism and Social Choice 133 2 SOURCES OF DEMOCRACY 55 Nicholas R. Miller Political Man: The Social Bases of Consociational Democracy 142 56 The Contest of Ideas 147 Social Revolutions in the Modern Donald Horowitz World 65 The State of Democratic Theory 153 Ian Shapiro The Impact of Economic Democracy 157 Development on Democracy 71 Robert D. Putnam Evelyne Huber, Dietrich Rueschemeyer, and John D. Modernization, Cultural Change, Stephens and the Persistence of Traditional Values 168 and Wayne E. Baker Contents vi

Culture and Democracy 181 5 PRESIDENTIALISM VERSUS Adam Przeworski, Jose´ Antonio PARLIAMENTARISM 257 Cheibub, and Fernando Limongi The Perils of Presidentialism 258 4 DEMOCRACY AND Juan Linz CONSTITUTIONALISM 191 Presidentialism, Multipartism, and Democracy: The Di‰cult The Federalist No. 23 192 Combination 266 Alexander Hamilton Scott Mainwaring The Federalist No. 47 193 Presidents and Assemblies 272 James Madison Matthew Soberg Shugart and John The Federalist No. 48 195 Carey James Madison Minority Governments, Deadlock The Federalist No. 62 197 Situations, and the Survival of James Madison Presidential 277 Jose´ Antonio Cheibub The Federalist No. 70 199 Alexander Hamilton Minority Governments in Parliamentary Democracies: The The Federalist No. 78 201 Rationality of Nonwinning Cabinet Alexander Hamilton Solutions 284 Madisonian Democracy 207 Kaare Strom Robert Dahl Institutional Design, Party Systems, A Bill of Rights for Britain 217 and Governability: Di¤erentiating Ronald Dworkin the Presidential Regimes of Latin America 296 A Rights-Based Critique of Joe Foweraker Constitutional Rights 221 Jeremy Waldron Presidential Power, Legislative Organization, and Party Behavior in The Political Origins of Judicial Brazil 304 Empowerment through Argelina Cheibub Figueiredo and Constitutionalization: Lessons from Fernando Limongi Four Constitutional Revolutions 232 Ran Hirschl 6 REPRESENTATION 311 Decision Making in a Democracy: The Supreme Court as a National Representative Government 312 Policymaker 246 Robert Dahl On Elections 315 Democratic Justice 252 Marquis de Condorcet Ian Shapiro Liberalism against Populism 317 William H. Riker Contents vii

Saving Democracy from Political Inside Campaign Finance: Myths Science 321 and Realities 408 Gerry Mackie Frank J. Sorauf Unlikelihood of Condorcet’s 8 DEMOCRACY’S EFFECTS 419 Paradox in a Large Society 326 A. S. Tangian The Economics and Politics of Congruence between Citizens and Growth 420 Policymakers in Two Visions of Karl de Schweinitz, Jr. Liberal Democracy 330 Rent Seeking and Redistribution John D. Huber and G. Bingham under Democracy versus Powell, Jr. Dictatorship 427 The Political Consequences of Ronald Wintrobe Electoral Laws 343 Dictatorship, Democracy, and Douglas W. Rae Development 436 South Africa’s Negotiated Mancur Olson Transition: Democracy, Opposition, Freedom Favors Development 444 and the New Constitutional Order 350 Courtney Jung and Ian Shapiro Political Regimes and Economic The Representation of Women 354 Growth 447 Anne Phillips Adam Przeworski, Michael E. Alvarez, Jose´ Antonio Cheibub, 7 INTEREST GROUPS 363 and Fernando Limongi The Governmental Process: Political Democracy in America 455 Interests and Public Opinion 364 Alexis de Tocqueville David B. Truman Does Democracy Engender Justice? 459 The Logic of Collective Action: John E. Roemer Public Goods and the Theory of Facing up to the American Dream: Groups 372 Race, Class, and the Soul of the Mancur Olson Nation 463 Neo-Pluralism: A Class Analysis of Jennifer L. Hochschild Pluralism I and Pluralism II 381 Beyond Tocqueville, Myrdal, and John F. Manley Hartz: The Multiple Traditions in The Theory of Economic Regulation 393 America 480 George J. Stigler Rogers M. Smith Interest Intermediation and Regime 9 DEMOCRACY AND THE Governability in Contemporary GLOBAL ORDER 489 Western Europe and North America 398 Philippe C. Schmitter Perpetual Peace 490 Immanuel Kant Contents viii

How Democracy, Interdependence, and International Organizations Create a System for Peace 492 Bruce Russett Dirty Pool 497 Donald P. Green, Soo Yeon Kim, and David H. Yoon Democracy and Collective Bads 504 Russell Hardin Representation and the Democratic Deficit 510 The Transformation of Political Community: Rethinking Democracy in the Context of Globalization 516 David Held

Appendix 527 Index 535 Introduction

This sourcebook is designed for undergraduate ture in social choice theory. Excerpts from Amy courses on democracy, though it will be useful Gutmann and Dennis Thompson, and James for introductory graduate courses as well. It is Fishkin, exemplify the deliberative alternative not a textbook, but it could be a companion to to proceduralism. We also include Larry Dia- many textbooks, and it could be used in courses mond’s reformulation of the substantive view on democracy that are taught without textbooks. and Carole Pateman’s theory of participatory The materials range over conceptual, norma- democracy. We end with Robert Dahl’s influen- tive, and empirical issues, giving students access, tial account of polyarchy, which synthesizes ele- in one moderately priced volume, to classic ments of these di¤erent views. arguments as well as the state of the art in con- Chapter 2, ‘‘Sources of Democracy,’’ guides temporary scholarship. The materials draw on students through debates about democracy and literature in American politics, comparative and modernization, various macrohistorical argu- international politics, and . ments about the causes of democracy, and the In this, they reflect an increasingly intercon- literature on democratic transitions. The objec- nected world and the increasingly interdisci- tive here is to illustrate the di¤erent arguments plinary character of . The about why we observe democracies in some sourcebook is methodologically diverse and countries and not in others. We begin with the avoids unnecessarily technical or jargon-laden seminal defense of modernization theory by material. It also contains information providing Seymour Martin Lipset. Observing a correlation vital statistics about the world’s democracies. between levels of economic development and The sourcebook is divided into nine self- democracy, he argues that development leads contained chapters. In each, we combine edited people to embrace values and attitudes that are selections from classic philosophical statements friendly to democracy’s emergence and viability. with more recent theoretical arguments and em- We then include various emendations of mod- pirical applications. ernization theory, including Barrington Moore’s Chapter 1, ‘‘Defining Democracy,’’ is orga- argument about the importance of a bourgeoisie nized around the debates among proponents of as summarized by Theda Skocpol, and an argu- procedural, deliberative, and substantive democ- ment from Evelyne Huber, Dietrich Ruesch- racy. Procedural democrats emphasize practices meyer, and John Stephens that emphasizes the and institutions that characterize democratic presence of a working class. Then we turn to regimes, without specifying any outcome these the literature on democratic transitions, where regimes are supposed to bring about and without we include Przeworski’s account of the relations paying much attention to how preferences are between political and economic transitions, a formed. Deliberative democrats problematize discussion by Samuel Huntington of the three preferences, arguing that appropriately delibera- waves of democratic transitions, and a case study tive procedures transform them in felicitous ways of the South African transition by Courtney for democracy. Advocates of substantive de- Jung and Ian Shapiro. We conclude with a re- mocracy see procedures as necessary but insuf- cent empirical evaluation of the modernization ficient to bring about democratic results. We literature, which shows that although there is begin with Joseph Schumpeter’s influential as- no relationship between modernization and the sault on Jean-Jacques Rousseau and defense of emergence of democracy, there is one between his alternative ‘‘minimalist’’ conception of de- the level of economic development and the sus- mocracy. Then we turn to Adam Przeworski’s tainability of democracy. recent elaboration and defense of a procedural Chapter 3, ‘‘Democracy, Culture, and Soci- view in light of the last several decades of litera- ety,’’ explores debates about cultural and socio- Introduction x

logical preconditions for viable democracy with Waldron’s critique are followed by a recent excerpts from The Federalist Papers, Louis comparative empirical assessment of the e¤ects Hartz, and the literature on pluralism and social of bills of rights on the actual protection of hu- cleavages. We then turn to the debate on con- man rights by Ran Hirschl, an analysis of the sociationalism, beginning with Arend Lijphart’s e¤ect of constitutional courts on safeguarding contention that divisions are so intense in some rights by Dahl, and a discussion of types of ju- societies that majoritarian politics would be dicial review that complement democracy rather explosively dysfunctional. In such circumstances, than undermine it by Shapiro. he argues, minorities must be overrepresented, or ‘‘Presidentialism versus Parliamentarism,’’ even given veto rights over matters of intense chapter 5, deals with the relations between forms importance to them. (In fact, this argument goes of democratic government and political stability. back to The Federalist Papers and accounts for Presidential systems are hailed for their strong such consociational elements in the U.S. Consti- executives with popular mandates and com- tution as requiring concurrent majorities and paratively inclusive legislatures. Parliamentary supermajorities for constitutional reform, as well systems are touted as providing decisive govern- as overrepresentation of small states in the Sen- ments and strong oppositions, where there is ate.) This is followed by a critique of Lijphart alternation in power between clearly defined po- by Donald Horowitz and a discussion by Sha- litical forces. We begin with an excerpt from piro about how to think about democratic insti- Juan Linz’s classic discussion of the relative tutional design in a world in which it is unclear advantages of parliamentary democracies. This how important culture and society are to demo- is followed by Scott Mainwaring’s modifica- cracy’s viability. We then proceed to discus- tion of Linz’s thesis, in which he argues that sions of democracy and social capital prompted what matters for the functioning of democratic by Robert Putnam’s Bowling Alone. This leads regimes is not presidentialism per se, but the to consideration of debates about the role of combination of an independently elected presi- ‘‘strong’’ civil society in sustaining democratic dent with a multiparty system. We then move to institutions that includes an article by Ronald more recent scholarship that, in one way or an- Inglehart and Wayne Baker about the role of other, modifies or refutes the thesis put forward modernization in bringing about cultural change by Linz. We include a discussion by Matthew and an empirical assessment of arguments about Soberg Shugart and John Carey on the powers social and cultural preconditions for democracy of the presidency and their impact on the insta- by Przeworski, Jose´ Antonio Cheibub, and Fer- bility of presidential regimes. They show that nando Limongi. presidents di¤er significantly in the legislative Chapter 4, ‘‘Democracy and Constitution- and nonlegislative powers granted them by the alism,’’ centers on the role of independent courts constitution. They also suggest, still very much in the operation of democracies. It has long been within the framework set up by Linz, that insta- an article of faith among legal theorists and lib- bility in presidential regimes is mostly due to the eral constitutionalists that bills of rights enforced combination of a strong president (that is, one through powers of judicial review are important with a wide range of legislative and nonlegis- guarantors of human freedom. We start with the lative powers) and a strong congress. We also relevant passages from The Federalist Papers, include an analysis by Cheibub in which he shows and then turn to Dahl’s skeptical critique in A that minority presidents and deadlock situations Preface to Democratic Theory. Then we turn to are not as pervasive under presidentialism as contemporary debates: Ronald Dworkin’s de- many, since Linz, have believed, and that they fense of a bill of rights for Britain and Jeremy do not a¤ect the survival of democratic regimes. Introduction xi

This is followed by a piece by Kaare Strom in clude an excerpt from John Huber and G. Bing- which he shows that minority governments ham Powell, Jr.’s discussion of proportionality as under parliamentarism are not infrequent and, producing policies closer to those preferred by most significantly, that they are the product of the median voter, Jung and Shapiro’s account of political parties’ calculus about the costs and the price paid for proportionality in terms of lost benefits of participating in government, given ‘‘loyal’’ opposition, and Douglas Rae’s argu- that they are concerned not only with achieving ment that although proportional representation o‰ce but also with the policies that are to be may be more representative at the electoral implemented by the government. Next, we in- stage, this is not necessarily the case at the gov- clude a discussion by Joe Foweraker in which he ernment-formation stage. We conclude with a calls attention to the fact that coalition forma- discussion by Anne Phillips about the represen- tion is an instrument available and frequently tation of women in democracy. used by presidents to govern, and that this may Chapter 7, ‘‘Interest Groups,’’ is organized mitigate the problems faced by presidents whose around the debate over whether such groups parties do not control a majority of seats in the are good or bad for democracy. We start by legislature. Finally, we include an analysis of the characterizing the pluralist view, according to Brazilian presidential system by Argelina Figuei- which the influence of interest groups is positive. redo and Fernando Limongi. They show that We use passages from to high- the president’s legislative and agenda powers light the concepts of ‘‘latent groups’’ and ‘‘over- granted by Brazil’s 1988 constitution, as well as lapping membership,’’ central to the pluralist the centralized organization of congress, work to perspective on interest groups. We then turn neutralize the centripetal tendencies of the polit- to attacks on these arguments. We use Mancur ical system that are generated by the presidential Olson’s criticism of how groups form, John form of government and the country’s extremely Manley’s defense of class analysis in view of permissive electoral and party legislation. pluralism’s inability to account for existing po- Chapter 6, ‘‘Representation,’’ is concerned litical and economic inequality, George Stigler’s with debates over the fairest system of demo- demonstration of how interest group demands cratic accountability. We organize the selections influence the regulatory process, and a text by around two debates: over whether democratic Philippe Schmitter about the e¤ect of corpora- systems represent voters at all and over propor- tism on governability. Finally, we include a se- tional versus majoritarian representation. We lection by Frank Sorauf about the relationship start with John Stuart Mill’s argument that rep- between money and politics as an illustration resentative government is the best polity. Then of the contemporary concerns about the role of we proceed to the locus classicus of the first interest groups on the democratic process. debate: Condorcet’s observation about cycling In chapter 8, ‘‘Democracy’s E¤ects,’’ we turn generalized by Kenneth Arrow in 1951. We will to the e¤ects of democracy on the economy and include a nontechnical summary of Arrow’s social life. The extracts on the economy are theorem by William Riker, followed by excerpts organized around the controversy over whether from recent empirical work by Gerry Mackie democracy is good or bad for economic growth. and A. S. Tangian suggesting that the empirical We include two types of negative arguments. likelihood of voting cycles is actually low. This One that is mostly made with respect to de- suggests that the theoretical energy that has been veloping countries, represented by Karl de directed at resolving the Arrow problem may not Schweinitz, Jr., emphasizes the negative impact be warranted by its empirical importance. On of democracy on investment. The other, repre- majoritarianism versus proportionality, we in- sented here by Ronald Wintrobe, emphasizes the Introduction xii

propensity of politicians either to overregulate concluding selection. He makes the case that the economy or to extract rents by threatening to just as the centralization of national political do so. We also include two arguments on the authority was a precondition for the creation of other side: Olson’s contention that a good national democracy, so the creation of e¤ective economy requires secure property rights that are systems of transnational authority must precede better guaranteed by democracies than dictator- meaningful transnational democracy. On this ships, and Amartya Sen’s argument that famines view, those who bemoan the democratic deficit do not occur in democracies because democratic should see it as transitionally necessary—a posi- governments are forced by popular pressure to tive development for the medium-term project of respond to crises. This is followed by an empiri- promoting European democracy. cal selection from Przeworski et al., suggesting In the appendix we include a discussion of the that democracy does not a¤ect aggregate eco- di¤erent measures of democracy that are com- nomic activity: it is neither a requirement nor a monly used in empirical research and informa- hindrance for a well-working economy. Turning tion summarizing the distribution of democracies to democracy’s e¤ects on social life, we start with in the world across regions and over time. Alexis de Tocqueville’s claims about democracy as a cause of social leveling. This is followed by critiques of it with respect to the reduction of class inequality by and , and of race and gender inequality by . Our final chapter, ‘‘Democracy and the Global Order,’’ contains materials on the e¤ects of democracy on international relations, as well as on the changing international system on democracies. With respect to the first, we start with Immanuel Kant’s observation in Perpetual Peace that democracies tend not to fight one another. Next we have an excerpt from Bruce Russett, which updates Kant’s observation and attempts to account for it empirically. This is followed by an empirically based critique by Donald Green et al., suggesting that democracy does not have a significant e¤ect on the propen- sity to go to war (whether with democracies or nondemocracies). Turning to the e¤ects of the global order on democracy, the focus is on the erosion of national sovereignty by transnational forces, illustrated by Russell Hardin’s discussion of the loss of control over environmental policy. As Pippa Norris argues in our next selection, democratic theorists are more generally con- cerned with the creation of ‘‘democratic deficits’’ in transnational entities such as the European Union. David Held challenges this view in our 1 DEFINING DEMOCRACY

The Social Contract Jean-Jacques Rousseau

Capitalism, Socialism, and Democracy Joseph Schumpeter

Minimalist Conception of Democracy: A Defense Adam Przeworski

Democracy and Disagreement Amy Gutmann and Dennis Thompson

The Voice of the People James S. Fishkin

Defining and Developing Democracy Larry Diamond

Participation and Democratic Theory Carole Pateman

Polyarchal Democracy Robert Dahl The Social Contract

Jean-Jacques Rousseau

if ever the social pact is violated, every man The Social Pact regains his original rights and, recovering his natural freedom, loses that civil freedom for I assume that men reach a point where the which he exchanged it. obstacles to their preservation in a state of These articles of association, rightly under- nature prove greater than the strength that each stood, are reducible to a single one, namely the man has to preserve himself in that state. Beyond total alienation by each associate of himself and this point, the primitive condition cannot endure, all his rights to the whole community. . . . for then the human race will perish if it does not If, then, we eliminate from the social pact change its mode of existence. everything that is not essential to it, we find it Since men cannot create new forces, but comes down to this: ‘‘Each one of us puts into merely combine and control those which already the community his person and all his powers exist, the only way in which they can preserve under the supreme direction of the general will; themselves is by uniting their separate powers in and as a body, we incorporate every member as a combination strong enough to overcome any an indivisible part of the whole.’’ resistance, uniting them so that their powers are Immediately, in place of the individual person directed by a single motive and act in concert. of each contracting party, this act of association Such a sum of forces can be produced only by creates an artificial and corporate body com- the union of separate men, but as each man’s posed of as many members as there are voters in own strength and liberty are the chief instru- the assembly, and by this same act that body ments of his preservation, how can he merge his acquires its unity, its common ego, its life and its with others’ without putting himself in peril and will. The public person thus formed by the union neglecting the care he owes to himself ? This dif- of all other persons was once called the city, and ficulty, in terms of my present subject, may be is now known as the republic or the body politic. expressed in these words: In its passive role it is called the state, when it ‘‘How to find a form of association which will plays an active role it is the sovereign; and when defend the person and goods of each member it is compared to others of its own kind, it is a with the collective force of all, and under which power. Those who are associated in it take col- each individual, while uniting himself with the lectively the name of a people, and call them- others, obeys no one but himself, and remains as selves individually citizens, in that they share free as before.’’ This is the fundamental problem in the sovereign power, and subjects, in that to which the social contract holds the solution. they put themselves under the laws of the state. The articles of this contract are so precisely However, these words are often confused, each determined by the nature of the act, that the being mistaken for another; but the essential slightest modification must render them null and thing is to know how to recognize them when void; they are such that, though perhaps never they are used in their precise sense. formally stated, they are everywhere the same, everywhere tacitly admitted and recognized; and The Sovereign Excerpted from: Jean-Jacques Rousseau, The Social Contract. Translated by Maurice Cranston. London: This formula shows that the act of association Penguin Books, 1968. Reprinted by permission of the consists of a reciprocal commitment between Estate of Maurice Cranston. Defining Democracy 3

society and the individual, so that each person, design and the working of the political machine, in making a contract, as it were, with himself, and which alone bestows justice on civil contracts finds himself doubly committed, first, as a mem- —without it, such contracts would be absurd, ber of the sovereign body in relation to individ- tyrannical and liable to the grossest abuse. . . . uals, and secondly as a member of the state in relation to the sovereign. . . . Now, as the sovereign is formed entirely of the Whether the General Will Can Err individuals who compose it, it has not, nor could it have, any interest contrary to theirs; and so the It follows from what I have argued that the gen- sovereign has no need to give guarantees to the eral will is always rightful and always tends to subjects, because it is impossible for a body to the public good; but it does not follow that the wish to hurt all of its members, and, as we shall deliberations of the people are always equally see, it cannot hurt any particular member. The right. We always want what is advantageous to sovereign by the mere fact that it is, is always all us but we do not always discern it. The people is that it ought to be. never corrupted, but it is often misled; and only But this is not true of the relation of subject to then does it seem to will what is bad. sovereign. Despite their common interest, sub- There is often a great di¤erence between jects will not be bound by their commitment un- the will of all [what all individuals want] and less means are found to guarantee their fidelity. the general will; the general will studies only the For every individual as a man may have a common interest while the will of all studies pri- private will contrary to, or di¤erent from, the vate interest, and is indeed no more than the sum general will that he has as a citizen. His private of individual desires. But if we take away from interest may speak with a very di¤erent voice these same wills, the pluses and minuses which from that of the public interest; his absolute and cancel each other out, the balance which remains naturally independent existence may make him is the general will. regard what he owes to the common cause as a From the deliberations of a people properly gratuitous contribution, the loss of which would informed, and provided its members do not have be less painful for others than the payment is any communication among themselves, the great onerous for him; and fancying that the artificial number of small di¤erences will always produce person which constitutes the state is a mere ficti- a general will and the decision will always be tious entity (since it is not a man), he might seek good. But if groups, sectional associations are to enjoy the rights of a citizen without doing the formed at the expense of the larger associa- duties of a subject. The growth of this kind of tion, the will of each of these groups will become injustice would bring about the ruin of the body general in relation to its own members and pri- politic. vate in relation to the state; we might then say Hence, in order that the social pact shall not that there are no longer as many votes as there be an empty formula, it is tacitly implied in that are men but only as many votes as there are commitment—which alone can give force to all groups. The di¤erences become less numerous others—that whoever refuses to obey the general and yield a result less general. Finally, when one will shall be constrained to do so by the whole of these groups becomes so large that it can out- body, which means nothing other than that he weigh the rest, the result is no longer the sum of shall be forced to be free; for this is the necessary many small di¤erences, but one great divisive condition which, by giving each citizen to the di¤erence; then there ceases to be a general will, nation, secures him against all personal depen- and the opinion which prevails is no more than a dence, it is the condition which shapes both the private opinion. Chapter 1 4

Thus if the general will is to be clearly expressed, it is imperative that there should be no sectional associations in the state, and that every citizen should make up his own mind for himself—such was the unique and sublime in- vention of the great Lycurgus. But if there are sectional associations, it is wise to multiply their number and to prevent inequality among them, as Solon, Numa and Servius did. These are the only precautions which can ensure that the gen- eral will is always enlightened and the people protected from error. . . . Capitalism, Socialism, and Democracy

Joseph Schumpeter

good and what is bad, takes part, actively and The Classical Doctrine of Democracy responsibly, in furthering the former and fighting the latter and all the members taken together I. The Common Good and the Will of the control their public a¤airs. People It is true that the management of some of these a¤airs requires special aptitudes and tech- The eighteenth-century philosophy of democracy niques and will therefore have to be entrusted to may be couched in the following definition: the specialists who have them. This does not a¤ect democratic method is that institutional arrange- the principle, however, because these specialists ment for arriving at political decisions which simply act in order to carry out the will of the realizes the common good by making the people people exactly as a doctor acts in order to carry itself decide issues through the election of indi- out the will of the patient to get well. It is also viduals who are to assemble in order to carry out true that in a community of any size, especially if its will. Let us develop the implications of this. it displays the phenomenon of division of labor, It is held, then, that there exists a Common it would be highly inconvenient for every indi- Good, the obvious beacon light of policy, which vidual citizen to have to get into contact with all is always simple to define and which every nor- the other citizens on every issue in order to do his mal person can be made to see by means of part in ruling or governing. It will be more con- rational argument. There is hence no excuse for venient to reserve only the most important deci- not seeing it and in fact no explanation for sions for the individual citizens to pronounce the presence of people who do not see it except upon—say by referendum—and to deal with the ignorance—which can be removed—stupidity rest through a committee appointed by them— and anti-social interest. Moreover, this common an assembly or parliament whose members will good implies definite answers to all questions so be elected by popular vote. This committee or that every social fact and every measure taken body of delegates, as we have seen, will not rep- or to be taken can unequivocally be classed as resent the people in a legal sense but it will do ‘‘good’’ or ‘‘bad.’’ All people having therefore to so in a less technical one—it will voice, reflect agree, in principle at least, there is also a Com- or represent the will of the electorate. Again as mon Will of the people (¼ will of all reasonable a matter of convenience, this committee, being individuals) that is exactly coterminous with large, may resolve itself into smaller ones for the the common good or interest or welfare or hap- various departments of public a¤airs. Finally, piness. The only thing, barring stupidity and among these smaller committees there will be a sinister interests, that can possibly bring in dis- general-purpose committee, mainly for dealing agreement and account for the presence of an with current administration, called cabinet or opposition is a di¤erence of opinion as to the government, possibly with a general secretary speed with which the goal, itself common to or scapegoat at its head, a so-called prime nearly all, is to be approached. Thus every minister.1 member of the community, conscious of that goal, knowing his or her mind, discerning what is 1. The o‰cial theory of the functions of a cabinet minister holds in fact that he is appointed in order to Excerpted from: Joseph Schumpeter, Capitalism, So- see to it that in his department the will of the people cialism, and Democracy. New York: Allen & Unwin, prevails. 1976. Chapter 1 6

As soon as we accept all the assumptions that definite answers to individual issues. Opinions on are being made by this theory of the polity— these might di¤er to an extent important enough or implied by it—democracy indeed acquires a to produce most of the e¤ects of ‘‘fundamental’’ perfectly unambiguous meaning and there is dissension about ends themselves. The problems no problem in connection with it except how to centering in the evaluation of present versus bring it about. Moreover we need only forget a future satisfactions, even the case of socialism few logical qualms in order to be able to add that versus capitalism, would be left still open, for in this case the democratic arrangement would instance, after the conversion of every individ- not only be the best of all conceivable ones, but ual citizen to utilitarianism. ‘‘Health’’ might be that few people would care to consider any desired by all, yet people would still disagree on other. It is no less obvious however that these vaccination and vasectomy. And so on. assumptions are so many statements of fact The utilitarian fathers of democratic doctrine every one of which would have to be proved if failed to see the full importance of this simply we are to arrive at that conclusion. And it is because none of them seriously considered any much easier to disprove them. substantial change in the economic framework There is, first, no such thing as a uniquely and the habits of bourgeois society. They saw determined common good that all people could little beyond the world of an eighteenth-century agree on or be made to agree on by the force of ironmonger. rational argument. This is due not primarily to But, third, as a consequence of both preceding the fact that some people may want things other propositions, the particular concept of the will of than the common good but to the much more the people or the volonte´ ge´ne´rale that the utili- fundamental fact that to di¤erent individuals tarians made their own vanishes into thin air. and groups the common good is bound to mean For that concept presupposes the existence of di¤erent things. This fact, hidden from the utili- a uniquely determined common good discern- tarian by the narrowness of his outlook on the ible to all. Unlike the romanticists the utili- world of human valuations, will introduce rifts tarians had no notion of that semi-mystic entity on questions of principle which cannot be rec- endowed with a will of its own—that ‘‘soul of onciled by rational argument because ultimate the people’’ which the historical school of juris- values—our conceptions of what life and what prudence made so much of. They frankly derived society should be—are beyond the range of mere their will of the people from the wills of individ- logic. They may be bridged by compromise in uals. And unless there is a center, the common some cases but not in others. Americans who good, toward which, in the long run at least, all say, ‘‘We want this country to arm to its teeth individual wills gravitate, we shall not get that and then to fight for what we conceive to be right particular type of ‘‘natural’’ volonte´ ge´ne´rale. all over the globe’’ and Americans who say, ‘‘We The utilitarian center of gravity, on the one want this country to work out its own problems hand, unifies individual wills, tends to weld them which is the only way it can serve humanity’’ are facing irreducible di¤erences of ultimate 2. The very meaning of ‘‘greatest happiness’’ is open to values which compromise could only maim and serious doubt. But even if this doubt could be removed degrade. and definite meaning could be attached to the sum to- Secondly, even if a su‰ciently definite com- tal of economic satisfaction of a group of people, that mon good—such as for instance the utilitarian’s maximum would still be relative to given situations maximum of economic satisfaction2—proved and valuations which it may be impossible to alter, or acceptable to all, this would not imply equally compromise on, in a democratic way. Defining Democracy 7

by means of rational discussion into the will of actions and reactions of the ‘‘democratic pro- the people and, on the other hand, confers upon cess,’’ the result lacks not only rational unity the latter the exclusive ethical dignity claimed but also rational sanction. The former means by the classic democratic creed. This creed does that, though from the standpoint of analysis, not consist simply in worshiping the will of the the democratic process is not simply chaotic— people as such but rests on certain assumptions for the analyst nothing is chaotic that can be about the ‘‘natural’’ object of that will which brought within the reach of explanatory prin- object is sanctioned by utilitarian reason. Both ciples—yet the results would not, except by the existence and the dignity of this kind of chance, be meaningful in themselves—as for volonte´ ge´ne´rale are gone as soon as the idea of instance the realization of any definite end or the common good fails us. And both the pillars ideal would be. The latter means, since that will of the classical doctrine inevitably crumble into is no longer congruent with any ‘‘good,’’ that in dust. order to claim ethical dignity for the result it will now be necessary to fall back upon an unquali- II. The Will of the People and Individual fied confidence in democratic forms of govern- Volition ment as such—a belief that in principle would have to be independent of the desirability of Of course, however conclusively those arguments results. As we have seen, it is not easy to place may tell against this particular conception of oneself on that standpoint. But even if we do so, the will of the people, they do not debar us from the dropping of the utilitarian common good trying to build up another and more realistic still leaves us with plenty of di‰culties on our one. I do not intend to question either the reality hands. or the importance of the socio-psychological facts In particular, we still remain under the practi- we think of when speaking of the will of a na- cal necessity of attributing to the will of the in- tion. Their analysis is certainly the prerequisite dividual an independence and a rational quality for making headway with the problems of de- that are altogether unrealistic. If we are to argue mocracy. It would however be better not to re- that the will of the citizens per se is a political tain the term because this tends to obscure the factor entitled to respect, it must first exist. That fact that as soon as we have severed the will of is to say, it must be something more than an the people from its utilitarian connotation we indeterminate bundle of vague impulses loosely are building not merely a di¤erent theory of the playing about given slogans and mistaken im- same thing, but a theory of a completely di¤er- pressions. Everyone would have to know defi- ent thing. We have every reason to be on our nitely what he wants to stand for. This definite guard against the pitfalls that lie on the path of will would have to be implemented by the ability those defenders of democracy who while accept- to observe and interpret correctly the facts that ing, under pressure of accumulating evidence, are directly accessible to everyone and to sift more and more of the facts of the democratic critically the information about the facts that process, yet try to anoint the results that process are not. Finally, from that definite will and turns out with oil taken from eighteenth-century from these ascertained facts a clear and prompt jars. conclusion as to particular issues would have But though a common will or public opinion to be derived according to the rules of logical of some sort may still be said to emerge from inference—with so high a degree of general e‰- the infinitely complex jumble of individual ciency moreover that one man’s opinion could and group-wise situations, volitions, influences, be held, without glaring absurdity, to be roughly Chapter 1 8

as good as every other man’s.3 And all this the cess. The question whether these conditions are model citizen would have to perform for himself fulfilled to the extent required in order to make and independently of pressure groups and pro- democracy work should not be answered by paganda,4 for volitions and inferences that are reckless assertion or equally reckless denial. It imposed upon the electorate obviously do not can be answered only by a laborious appraisal of qualify for ultimate data of the democratic pro- a maze of conflicting evidence. Before embarking upon this, however, I want 3. This accounts for the strongly equalitarian character to make quite sure that the reader fully appre- both of the classical doctrine of democracy and of ciates another point that has been made already. popular democratic beliefs. It will be pointed out later I will therefore repeat that even if the opinions on how Equality may acquire the status of an ethical and desires of individual citizens were perfectly postulate. As a factual statement about human nature definite and independent data for the democratic it cannot be true in any conceivable sense. In recogni- process to work with, and if everyone acted on tion of this the postulate itself has often been reformu- them with ideal rationality and promptitude, it lated so as to mean ‘‘equality of opportunity.’’ But, would not necessarily follow that the political disregarding even the di‰culties inherent in the word opportunity, this reformulation does not help us much decisions produced by that process from the because it is actual and not potential equality of per- raw material of those individual volitions would formance in matters of political behavior that is represent anything that could in any convincing required if each man’s vote is to carry the same weight sense be called the will of the people. It is not in the decision of issues. only conceivable but, whenever individual wills It should be noted in passing that democratic phra- are much divided, very likely that the political seology has been instrumental in fostering the associa- decisions produced will not conform to ‘‘what tion of inequality of any kind with ‘‘injustice’’ which is people really want.’’ Nor can it be replied that, if so important an element in the psychic pattern of the not exactly what they want, they will get a ‘‘fair unsuccessful and in the arsenal of the politician who compromise.’’ This may be so. The chances for uses him. One of the most curious symptoms of this was the Athenian institution of ostracism or rather the this to happen are greatest with those issues use to which it was sometimes put. Ostracism consisted which are quantitative in nature or admit of in banishing an individual by popular vote, not neces- gradation, such as the question how much is to be sarily for any particular reason: it sometimes served as spent on unemployment relief provided every- a method of eliminating an uncomfortably prominent body favors some expenditure for that purpose. citizen who was felt to ‘‘count for more than one.’’ But with qualitative issues, such as the question 4. This term is here being used in its original sense and whether to persecute heretics or to enter upon a not in the sense which it is rapidly acquiring at present war, the result attained may well, though for and which suggests the definition: propaganda is any di¤erent reasons, be equally distasteful to all the statement emanating from a source that we do not like. people whereas the decision imposed by a non- I suppose that the term derives from the name of the democratic agency might prove much more ac- committee of cardinals which deals with matters con- ceptable to them. . . . cerning the spreading of the Catholic faith, the con- gregatio de propaganda fide. In itself therefore it does . . . If results that prove in the long run satis- not carry any derogatory meaning and in particular it factory to the people at large are made the test of does not imply distortion of facts. One can make pro- government for the people, then government by paganda, for instance, for a scientific method. It simply the people, as conceived by the classical doctrine means the presentation of facts and arguments with a of democracy, would often fail to meet it. view to influencing people’s actions or opinions in a definite direction. Defining Democracy 9

assumptions and tenability of propositions, it Another Theory of Democracy greatly improves the theory of the democratic process. I. Competition for Political Leadership First of all, we are provided with a reasonably e‰cient criterion by which to distinguish demo- I think that most students of politics have by cratic governments from others. We have seen now come to accept the criticisms leveled at the that the classical theory meets with di‰culties classical doctrine of democracy in the preceding on that score because both the will and the good chapter. I also think that most of them agree, of the people may be, and in many historical or will agree before long, in accepting another instances have been, served just as well or better theory which is much truer to life and at the by governments that cannot be described as same time salvages much of what sponsors of the democratic according to any accepted usage of democratic method really mean by this term. the term. Now we are in a somewhat better po- Like the classical theory, it may be put into the sition partly because we are resolved to stress a nutshell of a definition. modus procedendi the presence or absence of It will be remembered that our chief troubles which it is in most cases easy to verify.2 about the classical theory centered in the propo- For instance, a parliamentary monarchy like sition that ‘‘the people’’ hold a definite and ra- the English one fulfills the requirements of the tional opinion about every individual question democratic method because the monarch is and that they give e¤ect to this opinion—in a practically constrained to appoint to cabinet democracy—by choosing ‘‘representatives’’ who o‰ce the same people as parliament would elect. will see to it that that opinion is carried out. A ‘‘constitutional’’ monarchy does not qualify Thus the selection of the representatives is made to be called democratic because electorates and secondary to the primary purpose of the demo- parliaments, while having all the other rights cratic arrangement which is to vest the power of that electorates and parliaments have in parlia- deciding political issues in the electorate. Sup- mentary monarchies, lack the power to impose pose we reverse the roles of these two elements their choice as to the governing committee: the and make the deciding of issues by the electorate cabinet ministers are in this case servants of the secondary to the election of the men who are to monarch, in substance as well as in name, and do the deciding. To put it di¤erently, we now can in principle be dismissed as well as appointed take the view that the role of the people is to by him. Such an arrangement may satisfy the produce a government, or else an intermediate people. The electorate may rea‰rm this fact by body which in turn will produce a national voting against any proposal for change. The executive1 or government. And we define: the monarch may be so popular as to be able to democratic method is that institutional arrange- defeat any competition for the supreme o‰ce. ment for arriving at political decisions in which But since no machinery is provided for making individuals acquire the power to decide by means this competition e¤ective the case does not come of a competitive struggle for the people’s vote. within our definition. Defense and explanation of this idea will Second, the theory embodied in this definition speedily show that, as to both plausibility of leaves all the room we may wish to have for a proper recognition of the vital fact of leader- 1. The insincere word ‘‘executive’’ really points in the ship. The classical theory did not do this but, wrong direction. It ceases however to do so if we use as we have seen, attributed to the electorate an it in the sense in which we speak of the ‘‘executives’’ of a business corporation who also do a great deal more than ‘‘execute’’ the will of stockholders. 2. See however the fourth point below. Chapter 1 10

altogether unrealistic degree of initiative which we have restricted the kind of competition for practically amounted to ignoring leadership. But leadership which is to define democracy, to free collectives act almost exclusively by accepting competition for a free vote. The justification for leadership—this is the dominant mechanism of this is that democracy seems to imply a recog- practically any collective action which is more nized method by which to conduct the competi- than a reflex. Propositions about the working tive struggle, and that the electoral method is and the results of the democratic method that practically the only one available for commu- take account of this are bound to be infinitely nities of any size. But though this excludes many more realistic than propositions which do not. ways of securing leadership which should be They will not stop at the execution of a volonte´ excluded,4 such as competition by military in- ge´ne´rale but will go some way toward showing surrection, it does not exclude the cases that are how it emerges or how it is substituted or faked. strikingly analogous to the economic phenomena What we have termed Manufactured Will is no we label ‘‘unfair’’ or ‘‘fraudulent’’ competition longer outside the theory, an aberration for the or restraint of competition. And we cannot ex- absence of which we piously pray; it enters on clude them because if we did we should be left the ground floor as it should. with a completely unrealistic ideal.5 Between this Third, however, so far as there are genuine ideal case which does not exist and the cases in group-wise volitions at all—for instance the will which all competition with the established leader of the unemployed to receive unemployment is prevented by force, there is a continuous range benefit or the will of other groups to help—our of variation within which the democratic method theory does not neglect them. On the contrary of government shades o¤ into the autocratic one we are now able to insert them in exactly the by imperceptible steps. But if we wish to under- role they actually play. Such volitions do not as a stand and not to philosophize, this is as it should rule assert themselves directly. Even if strong be. The value of our criterion is not seriously and definite they remain latent, often for de- impaired thereby. cades, until they are called to life by some polit- Fifth, our theory seems to clarify the relation ical leader who turns them into political factors. that subsists between democracy and individual This he does, or else his agents do it for him, by freedom. If by the latter we mean the existence organizing these volitions, by working them up of a sphere of individual self-government the and by including eventually appropriate items in boundaries of which are historically variable— his competitive o¤ering. The interaction between no society tolerates absolute freedom even of sectional interests and public opinion and the way in which they produce the pattern we call 4. It also excludes methods which should not be the political situation appear from this angle in a excluded, for instance, the acquisition of political lead- new and much clearer light. ership by the people’s tacit acceptance of it or by elec- Fourth, our theory is of course no more defi- tion quasi per inspirationem. The latter di¤ers from nite than is the concept of competition for lead- election by voting only by a technicality. But the for- ership. This concept presents similar di‰culties mer is not quite without importance even in modern as the concept of competition in the economic politics; the sway held by a party boss within his party is often based on nothing but tacit acceptance of his sphere, with which it may be usefully compared. leadership. Comparatively speaking however these are In economic life competition is never completely details which may, I think, be neglected in a sketch like lacking, but hardly ever is it perfect. Similarly, this. in political life there is always some competi- 5. As in the economic field, some restrictions are tion, though perhaps only a potential one, for implicit in the legal and moral principles of the the allegiance of the people. To simplify matters community. Defining Democracy 11

conscience and of speech, no society reduces that Seventh, our theory sheds much-needed light sphere to zero—the question clearly becomes a on an old controversy. Whoever accepts the matter of degree. We have seen that the demo- classical doctrine of democracy and in conse- cratic method does not necessarily guarantee a quence believes that the democratic method is greater amount of individual freedom than an- to guarantee that issues be decided and policies other political method would permit in similar framed according to the will of the people must circumstances. It may well be the other way be struck by the fact that, even if that will were round. But there is still a relation between the undeniably real and definite, decision by simple two. If, on principle at least, everyone is free to majorities would in many cases distort it rather compete for political leadership6 by presenting than give e¤ect to it. Evidently the will of the himself to the electorate, this will in most cases majority is the will of the majority and not the though not in all mean a considerable amount of will of ‘‘the people.’’ The latter is a mosaic that freedom of discussion for all. In particular it will the former completely fails to ‘‘represent.’’ To normally mean a considerable amount of free- equate both by definition is not to solve the dom of the press. This relation between democ- problem. Attempts at real solutions have how- racy and freedom is not absolutely stringent and ever been made by the authors of the various can be tampered with. But, from the standpoint plans for Proportional Representation. of the intellectual, it is nevertheless very impor- These plans have met with adverse criticism on tant. At the same time, it is all there is to that practical grounds. It is in fact obvious not only relation. that proportional representation will o¤er oppor- Sixth, it should be observed that in making it tunities for all sorts of idiosyncrasies to assert the primary function of the electorate to produce themselves but also that it may prevent democ- a government (directly or through an interme- racy from producing e‰cient governments and diate body) I intended to include in this phrase thus prove a danger in times of stress.7 But before also the function of evicting it. The one means concluding that democracy becomes unworkable simply the acceptance of a leader or a group of if its principle is carried out consistently, it is leaders, the other means simply the withdrawal just as well to ask ourselves whether this prin- of this acceptance. This takes care of an element ciple really implies proportional representation. the reader may have missed. He may have As a matter of fact it does not. If acceptance of thought that the electorate controls as well as leadership is the true function of the electorate’s installs. But since electorates normally do not vote, the case for proportional representation col- control their political leaders in any way except lapses because its premises are no longer binding. by refusing to reelect them or the parliamentary The principle of democracy then merely means majorities that support them, it seems well to re- that the reins of government should be handed to duce our ideas about this control in the way those who command more support than do any indicated by our definition. Occasionally, spon- of the competing individuals or teams. And this taneous revulsions occur which upset a govern- in turn seems to assure the standing of the ma- ment or an individual minister directly or else jority system within the logic of the democratic enforce a certain course of action. But they are method, although we might still condemn it on not only exceptional, they are, as we shall see, grounds that lie outside of that logic. . . . contrary to the spirit of the democratic method. 7. The argument against proportional representation 6. Free, that is, in the same sense in which everyone is has been ably stated by Professor F. A. Hermens in free to start another textile mill. ‘‘The Trojan Horse of Democracy,’’ Social Research, November 1938. Minimalist Conception of Democracy: A Defense

Adam Przeworski

nal deliberation, and to be represented as the Introduction view of the informed majority, the fact that rulers are elected is of no particular significance. I want to defend a ‘‘minimalist,’’ Schumpeterian, Voting is just a time-saving expedient (Buchanan conception of democracy, by minimalist, Pop- and Tullock 1962) and majority rule is just a perian, standards. In Schumpeter’s (1942) con- technically convenient way of identifying what ception, democracy is just a system in which everyone would or should have agreed to. Yet if rulers are selected by competitive elections. Pop- the point of departure is that in any society there per (1962: 124) defends it as the only system in are conflicts, of values and of interests, electing which citizens can get rid of governments with- rulers appears nothing short of miraculous. out bloodshed. . . . Let us put the consensualist view of democ- Since neither the position I wish to defend nor racy where it belongs—in the Museum of the claim in its favor are new, what do I defend Eighteenth-century Thought—and observe that them from? Perusing innumerable definitions, all societies are ridden with economic, cultural, one discovers that democracy has become an al- or moral conflicts. True, as the modernization tar on which everyone hangs his or her favorite theory (notably Coser 1959) emphasized, these ex voto. Almost all normatively desirable aspects conflicts can be ‘‘cross-cutting’’: they need not of political, and sometimes even of social and pit class against class or religion against religion. economic, life are credited as intrinsic to de- They can be attenuated by an ‘‘overlapping con- mocracy: representation, accountability, equal- sensus’’: consensus about practicalities compati- ity, participation, justice, dignity, rationality, ble with di¤erences of values (Rawls 1993). They security, freedom, . . . , the list goes on. We are may be also moderated by public discussion of repeatedly told that ‘‘unless democracy is x or both normative and technical reasons, although, generates x, . . .’’ The ellipsis is rarely spelled out, as I have argued above, deliberation is a two- but it insinuates either that a system in which edged sword, for it may lead just to solidifying governments are elected is not worthy of being conflicting views. Yet in the end, when all the called ‘‘democracy’’ unless x is fulfilled or that coalitions have been formed, the practical con- democracy in the minimal sense will not endure sensus has been elaborated, and all arguments unless x is satisfied.2 The first claim is normative, have been exhausted, conflicts remain. even if it often hides as a definition. The second My defense of the minimalist conception pro- is empirical. . . . ceeds in two steps. I take it as obvious that Yet suppose this is all there is to democracy: that rulers are elected. Is it little? It depends on the point of departure.24 If one begins with a vi- 2. Widely cited statements in this vein are We¤ort sion of a basic harmony of interests, a common 1992 and Schmitter and Karl 1991, but the phrase is ubiquitous. Here is Shapiro (1996: 108): ‘‘If democracy good to be discovered and agreed to by a ratio- does not function to improve the circumstances of those who appeal to it, its legitimacy as a political sys- Excerpted from: Adam Przeworski, ‘‘Minimalist Con- tem will atrophy.’’ Even Kelsen (1988 [1929]: 38) poses ception of Democracy: A Defense.’’ In Democracy’s the threat that ‘‘Modern democracy will not live unless Value, edited by Ian Shapiro and Casiano Hacker- the Parliament will show itself an instrument appro- Cordo´n. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, priate for the solution of the social questions of the 1999. 6 Cambridge University Press, 1999. Reprinted hour.’’ with the permission of Cambridge University Press. 24. Shapiro (1996: 82) also takes this position. Defining Democracy 13

we want to avoid bloodshed, resolving conflicts Yet the very prospect that governments would through violence.25 Starting with this assump- alternate may induce the conflicting political tion, I first argue that the mere possibility of forces to comply with the rules rather than en- being able to change governments can avoid gage in violence, for the following reason. Al- violence. Secondly, I argue that being able to though the losers would be better o¤ in the short do it by voting has consequences of its own. run rebelling rather than accepting the outcome Popper’s defense of democracy is that it allows of the current round, if they have a su‰cient us to get rid of governments peacefully. But why chance to win and a su‰ciently large payo¤ in should we care about changing governments?26 the future rounds, they are better o¤ continuing My answer is that the very prospect that gov- to comply with the verdict of the coin toss rather ernments may change can result in a peaceful than fighting for power. Similarly, while the regulation of conflicts. To see this argument in winners would be better o¤ in the short run not its starkest form, assume that governments are tossing the coin again, they may be better o¤ in selected by a toss of a, not necessarily fair, coin: the long run peacefully leaving o‰ce rather than ‘‘heads’’ mean that the incumbents should provoking violent resistance to their usurpation remain in o‰ce, ‘‘tails’’ that they should leave. of power. Regulating conflicts by a coin toss Thus, a reading of the toss designates ‘‘winners’’ is then a self-enforcing equilibrium (Przeworski and ‘‘losers.’’ This designation is an instruction 1991: chap. 1). Bloodshed is avoided by the mere what the winners and the losers should and fact that, a` la Aristotle, the political forces expect should not do: the winners should move into a to take turns. White or Pink House or perhaps even a palacio; Suppose first that the winners of the coin while there they can take everything up to the toss get some predetermined part of the pie, constitutional constraint for themselves and their 1=2 < x < 1, while losers get the rest.27 Winners supporters, and they should toss the same coin decide at each time whether to hold elections at again when their term is up. The losers should the next time and losers whether to accept defeat not move into the House and should accept get- or to rebel. If democracy is repeated indefinitely ting not more than whatever is left. from t ¼ 0 on, the winner at t ¼ 0 expects to get Note that when the authorization to rule is DW ¼ x þ VW(e; x) and the loser at t ¼ 0 expects determined by a lottery, citizens have no elec- to get DL ¼ (1 x) þ VL(1 e; x), where V toral sanction, prospective or retrospective, and stands for the present value of continuing under the incumbents have no electoral incentives to democracy beyond the current round, e is the behave well while in o‰ce. Since electing gov- probability the current incumbent will win the ernments by a lottery makes their chances of next toss. Let ‘‘democratic equilibrium’’ stand survival independent of their conduct, there are for a pair of strategies in which the current win- no reasons to expect that governments act in a ners always hold tosses if they expect losers to representative fashion because they want to earn comply and the current losers always comply re-election: any link between elections and rep- if they expect the winners to hold tosses. Then resentation is severed. such an equilibrium exists if everyone is better o¤ under democracy than under rebellion: if 25. I am not arguing against Locke that violence is DW > RW and DL > RL, where R stands for the never justified, just that a system that systematically expected values of violent conflict for each of the avoids it is preferable to one that does not. two parties. 26. I want to thank Ignacio Sanchez-Cuenca for pos- ing this question. 27. This analysis is based on joint work with James Fearon, still in progress. Chapter 1 14

Moreover, the prospect of alternation may mine the strength of the adversaries in an open induce moderation while in o‰ce. Suppose that conflict. Hence, to avoid violence, the conflicting the current incumbent can either manipulate the political forces adopt the following device: agree probability, e, of being re-elected or can decide over those issues that can be specified and allow what share of the pie, x A [0; 1], to take, or both. the residual control to alternate according to There are some initial values {e(0); x(0)}; at t ¼ 1 specified probabilities. In this sense, the consti- the coin is tossed and it designates winners tution specifies x, the limits on incumbents, and losers. Whoever is the winner now chooses and e, their chances in electoral competition, but {e(1); x(1)}: the rules for this round, etc. Hence, a random device decides who holds residual rules are not given ex ante: the incumbent control. manipulates them at will. Yet there are con- Yet we do not use random devices; we vote. ditions under which a democratic equilibrium What di¤erence does that make? exists in which the incumbents do not grab Voting is an imposition of a will over a will. everything. If the cost of rebellion is su‰ciently When a decision is reached by voting, some high for both, each incumbent will prefer to people must submit to an opinion di¤erent from moderate its behavior while in o‰ce under de- theirs or to a decision contrary to their inter- mocracy rather than provoke a rebellion by the est.28 Voting authorizes compulsion. It em- current loser. powers governments, our rulers, to keep people As Hardin (1989: 113) puts it, ‘‘for the consti- in jail,29 sometimes even to take their life, to tutional case, the ultimate source [of stability] seize money from some and give it to others, to is the internal costs of collective action for re- regulate private behavior of consenting adults. coordination or, in Caesar’s word, mutiny.’’ Yet Voting generates winners and losers, and it if the threat of mutiny were the only incentive to authorizes the winners to impose their will, even moderation, why would we ever adopt proce- if within constraints, on the losers. This is what dures that subject control over the exercise of ‘‘ruling’’ is. Bobbio’s (1984: 93) parenthetical rule to a lottery? If the relevant political actors addition bares a crucial implication of the knew what would happen as the result of an Schumpeterian definition: ‘‘by ‘democratic sys- open conflict, they could just agree to a distri- tem’,’’ Bobbio says, ‘‘I mean one in which su- bution that would have resulted from an open preme power (supreme in so far as it alone is confrontation. Instead of a coin toss deciding authorized to use force as a last resort) is exerted who gets what, the distribution would be fixed to in the name of and on behalf of the people by reflect the strength the conflicting political forces virtue of the procedure of elections.’’ could muster in an open confrontation, x for It is voting that authorizes coercion, not rea- one, (1 x) for the other. So why do we have sons behind it. Pace Cohen (1997: 5), who claims democracy: an agreement to toss a coin with that the participants ‘‘are prepared to cooperate probabilities e and (1 e)? in accordance with the results of such discussion, The reason, in my view, is that it would be impossible to write a dictatorial contract that 28. This sentence is a paraphrase of Condorcet (1986 would specify every contingent state of nature. [1785]: 22): ‘‘il s’agit, dans une loi qui n’a pas e´te´ vote´e In turn, leaving the residual control—control unanimement, de soumettre des hommes a` une opinion over issues not explicitly regulated by contract— qui n’est pas la leur, ou a` une de´cision qu’ils croient to the dictator would generate increasing returns contraire a` leur inte´reˆt.’’ to power and undermine the contract. Endowed 29. Indeed, the oldest democracy in the world is also with residual control, the dictator could not one that keeps more people in jail than any other commit itself not to use the advantage to under- country in the world. Defining Democracy 15

treating those results as authoritative,’’ it is the which the will of the majority of qualified citi- result of voting, not of discussion, that autho- zens rules, taking qualified citizens to constitute rizes governments to govern, to compel. Delib- the great bulk of the inhabitants, say, roughly eration may lead to a decision that is reasoned: three-fourths, so that physical force of the citizens it may illuminate the reasons a decision is or coincides (broadly speaking) with their voting should not be taken. Further, these reasons may power’’ (italics supplied). Condorcet claims that guide the implementation of the decision, the this was the reason for adopting majority rule: actions of the government. But if all the reasons for the good of peace and general welfare, it have been exhausted and yet there is no un- was necessary to place authority where lies the animity, some people must act against their force.30 Clearly, once physical force diverges reasons. They are coerced to do so, and the from sheer numbers, when the ability to wage authorization to coerce them is derived from war becomes professionalized and technical, counting heads, the sheer force of numbers, not voting no longer provides a reading of chances in from the validity of reasons. a violent conflict. But voting does reveal infor- What di¤erence, then, does it make that we mation about passions, values, and interests. If vote? One answer to this question is that the elections are a peaceful substitute for rebellion right to vote imposes an obligation to respect the (Hampton 1994), it is because they inform results of voting. In this view, democracy persists everyone who would mutiny and against what. because people see it as their duty to obey out- They inform the losers—‘‘Here is the distribu- comes resulting from a decision process in which tion of force: if you disobey the instructions they voluntarily participated. Democracy is conveyed by the results of the election, I will be legitimate in the sense that people are ready to more likely to beat you than you will be able to accept decisions of as yet undetermined content, beat me in a violent confrontation’’—and the as long as they can participate in the making of winners—‘‘If you do not hold elections again these decisions. I do not find this view persua- or if you grab too much, I will be able to put up sive, however, either normatively or positively. a forbidding resistance.’’ Dictatorships do not Clearly, this is not the place to enter into a dis- generate this information; they need secret police cussion of a central topic of political theory to find out. In democracies, even if voting does (Dunn 1996a: chap. 4) but I stand with Kelsen not reveal a unique collective will, it does indi- (1998 [1929]: 21) when he observes that ‘‘The cate limits to rule. Why else would we interpret purely negative assumption that no individual participation as an indication of legitimacy, why counts more than any other does not permit to would we be concerned about support for ex- deduce the positive principle that the will of the tremist parties? majority should prevail,’’ and I know no evi- In the end, the miracle of democracy is that dence to the e¤ect that participation induces conflicting political forces obey the results of compliance. Yet I think that voting does induce com- 30. ‘‘Lorsque l’usage de soumettre tous les individus pliance, through a di¤erent mechanism. Vot- a` la volonte´ du plus grand nombre, s’introduisit dans ing constitutes ‘‘flexing muscles’’: a reading of les socie´tes, et que les hommes convinrent de regarder chances in the eventual war. If all men are la de´cision de la pluralite´ comme la volonte´ de tous, equally strong (or armed) then the distribution of ils n’adopte´rent pas cette me´thode comme un moyen vote is a proxy for the outcome of war. Referring d’e´viter l’erreur et de se conduire d’apre´s des de´cisions to Herodotus, Bryce (1921: 25–6) announces fonde´es sur la ve´rite´: mais ils trouve`rent que, pour le bien de la paix et l’utilite´ ge´ne´rale, il falloit placer l’au- that he uses the concept of democracy ‘‘in its old torite´ ou` etoit la force’’ (Condorcet 1986 [1785]: 11; and strict sense, as denoting a government in italics supplied). Chapter 1 16

voting. People who have guns obey those with- more durable than pure presidential ones. The out them. Incumbents risk their control of gov- expected life of democracy under presidentialism ernmental o‰ces by holding elections. Losers is twenty-one years, while under parliamentarism wait for their chance to win o‰ce. Conflicts are it is seventy-two years. Presidential systems are regulated, processed according to rules, and thus less stable under any distribution of seats; in- limited. This is not consensus, yet not mayhem deed, they are less stable whatever variable is either. Just limited conflict; conflict without kill- controlled for. The most likely reason presiden- ing. Ballots are ‘‘paper stones,’’ as Engels once tial democracies are more fragile than parlia- observed. mentary ones is that presidents rarely change Yet this miracle does not work under all con- because they are defeated in elections. Most of ditions.31 The expected life of democracy in a them leave o‰ce because they are obligated to country with per capita income under $1,000 is do so by constitutionally imposed term limits. about eight years.32 Between $1,001 and $2,000, In turn, whenever incumbent presidents can an average democracy can expect to endure run and do, two out of three win reelection eighteen years. But above $6,000, democracies (Cheibub and Przeworski 1996). Presidentialism last forever. Indeed, no democracy ever fell, re- thus appears to give an excessive advantage to gardless of everything else, in a country with a incumbents when they are legally permitted to per capita income higher than that of Argentina run for re-election and, in turn, to prevent the in 1976: $6,055. Thus Lipset (1959: 46) was incumbents from exploiting this advantage, it undoubtedly correct when he argued that ‘‘The obligates them to leave o‰ce whether or not more well-to-do a country, the greater the voters want them to stay. chance that it will sustain democracy.’’ Here then are three facts: (1) democra`cies are Several other factors a¤ect the survival of more likely to survive in wealthy countries; (2) democracies but they all pale in comparison to they are more likely to last when no single polit- per capita income. Two are particularly relevant. ical force dominates; and (3) they are more likely First, it turns out that democracies are more to endure when voters can choose rulers through likely to fall when one party controls a large elections. And these facts add up: democracy share (more than two-thirds) of seats in the leg- lasts when it o¤ers an opportunity to the con- islature. Secondly, democracies are most stable flicting forces to advance their interests within when the heads of governments change not too the institutional framework. infrequently, more often than once every five In the end then, the Popperian posture is years (although not as often as less than every not su‰cient, because democracy endures only two years). Thus, democracy is more likely to under some conditions. Elections alone are not survive when no single force dominates politics su‰cient for conflicts to be resolved through completely and permanently. elections. And while some of these conditions are Finally, the stability of democracies does economic, others are political and institutional. depend on their particular institutional arrange- Thus, a minimalist conception of democracy ments: parliamentary democracies are much does not alleviate the need for thinking about institutional design. In the end, the ‘‘quality of 31. The forthcoming paragraphs are based on Prze- democracy,’’ to use the currently fashionable worski, Alvarez, Cheibub, and Limongi 1996, and phrase, does matter for its very survival. But my Przeworski and Limongi 1997b. point is not that democracy can be, needs to be, 32. Expected life is the inverse of the probability of improved, but that it would be worth defending dying. The income numbers are in purchasing power even if it could not be. parity international dollars of 1985. Defining Democracy 17

———. 1991. Democracy and the Market. New York: References Cambridge University Press. Przeworski, Adam, Mike Alvarez, Jose Antonio Chei- Bobbio, Norberto. 1984. The Future of Democracy. bub, and Fernando Limongi. 1996. ‘‘What makes Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press. democracies endure?’’ Journal of Democracy 7: 39–55. Bryce, James. 1921. Modern Democracies. New York: Przeworski, Adam and Fernando Limongi. 1997a. Macmillan. ‘‘Modernization: theories and facts.’’ World Politics Buchanan, James and Gordon Tullock. 1962. The 49: 155–183. Calculus of Consent: Logical Foundations of Constitu- ———. 1997b. ‘‘Development and democracy.’’ In tional Democracy. Ann Arbor: University of Michigan Alex Hadenius (ed.), Democracy’s Victory and Crisis. Press. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Cheibub, Jose Antonio and Adam Przeworski. 1996. Rawls, John. 1993. ‘‘The domain of the political and ‘‘Democracy, elections, and accountability for eco- overlapping consensus.’’ In David Copp, Jean Hamp- nomic outcomes.’’ Revised paper presented at the ton, and John H. Roemer (eds.), The Idea of Democ- Conference on Democracy and Accountability, New racy. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. York University, 27–9 April. Schmitter, Philippe and Terry Lynn Karl. 1991. ‘‘What Cohen, Joshua. 1997. ‘‘Procedure and substance in de- democracy is . . . and what it is not’’. Journal of De- liberative democracy.’’ In (ed.), Democratic mocracy 2: 75–88. Deliberation. New York: Cambridge University Press. Schumpeter, Joseph A. 1942. Capitalism, Socialism, Condorcet. 1986 (1785). ‘‘Essai sur l’application de and Democracy. New York: Harper & Brothers. l’analyse a la probabilite´ des de´cisions rendues a la Shapiro, Ian. 1996. Democracy’s Place. Ithaca: Cornell pluralite´ des voix.’’ In Sur les e´lections et autres textes. University Press. Textes choisis et revus par Olivier de Bernon. Paris: Fayard. We¤ort, Francisco. 1992. Qual Democracia? Sao Paulo: Companhia das Letras. Coser, Lewis. 1959. The Functions of Social Conflict. Glencoe: Free Press. Dunn, John. 1996a. The History of Political Theory and other Essays. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Hampton, Jean. 1994. ‘‘Democracy and the rule of law.’’ In Ian Shapiro (ed.), NOMOS XXXVI: The Rule of Law, pp. 13–45. Hardin, Russell. 1989. ‘‘Why a constitution?’’ In Ber- nard Grofman and Donald Wittman (eds.), The Fed- eralist Papers and the New Institutionalism, pp. 100–20. New York: Agathon Press. Kelsen, Hans. 1988 (1929). La De´mocratie. Sa Nature—Sa Valeur. Paris: Economica. Lipset, Seymour Martin. 1959. ‘‘Some social requisites of democracy: economic development and political legitimacy.’’ American Political Science Review 53: 69–105. Popper, Karl. 1962. The Open Society and Its Enemies. London: Routledge and Kegan Paul. Przeworski, Adam. 1986. Capitalism and Social De- mocracy. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Democracy and Disagreement

Amy Gutmann and Dennis Thompson

The aim of the moral reasoning that our Introduction deliberative democracy prescribes falls between impartiality, which requires something like al- Of the challenges that American democracy truism, and prudence, which demands no more faces today, none is more formidable than the than enlightened self-interest. Its first principle problem of moral disagreement. Neither the is reciprocity. . . . When citizens reason recipro- theory nor the practice of democratic politics has cally, they seek fair terms of social cooperation so far found an adequate way to cope with con- for their own sake; they try to find mutually ac- flicts about fundamental values. We address the ceptable ways of resolving moral disagreements. challenge of moral disagreement here by devel- The precise content of reciprocity is di‰cult oping a conception of democracy that secures a to determine in theory, but its general counte- central place for moral discussion in political life. nance is familiar enough in practice. It can be Along with a growing number of other politi- seen in the di¤erence between acting in one’s cal theorists, we call this conception deliberative self-interest (say, taking advantage of a legal democracy. The core idea is simple: when citi- loophole or a lucky break) and acting fairly zens or their representatives disagree morally, (following rules in the spirit that one expects they should continue to reason together to reach others to adopt). In many of the controversies . . . mutually acceptable decisions. But the meaning the possibility of any morally acceptable resolu- and implications of the idea are complex. . . . tion depends on citizens’ reasoning beyond their Deliberative democracy involves reasoning narrow self-interest and considering what can be about politics, and nothing has been more con- justified to people who reasonably disagree with troversial in political philosophy than the nature them. Even though the quality of deliberation of reason in politics. We do not believe that and the conditions under which it is conducted these controversies have to be settled before are far from ideal in the controversies we con- deliberative principles can guide the practice of sider, the fact that in each case some citizens and democracy. Since on occasion citizens and their some o‰cials make arguments consistent with representatives already engage in the kind of reciprocity suggests that a deliberative perspec- reasoning that those principles recommend, de- tive is not utopian. liberative democracy simply asks that they do so . . . Citizens who reason reciprocally can rec- more consistently and comprehensively. The best ognize that a position is worthy of moral respect way to prove the value of this kind of reasoning even when they think it morally wrong. They is to show its role in arguments about specific can believe that a moderate pro-life position on principles and policies, and its contribution to abortion, for example, is morally respectable actual political debates. That is also ultimately even though they think it morally mistaken. . . . the best justification for our conception of delib- The presence of deliberative disagreement has erative democracy itself. . . . important implications for how citizens treat one another and for what policies they should adopt. Reprinted by permission of the publisher from Democ- When a disagreement is not deliberative (for racy and Disagreement: Why Moral Conflict Cannot Be example, about a policy to legalize discrimina- Avoided in Politics, and What Should Be Done about It tion against blacks and women), citizens do not by Amy Gutmann and Dennis Thompson, pp. 1–5, 12–18, Cambridge, Mass.: The Belknap Press of Har- have any obligations of mutual respect toward vard University Press, Copyright 6 1996 by the Presi- their opponents. In deliberative disagreement dent and Fellows of Harvard College. (for example, about legalizing abortion), citizens Defining Democracy 19

should try to accommodate the moral convic- a deliberative deficit not only in our democratic tions of their opponents to the greatest extent politics but also in our democratic theory. We possible, without compromising their own moral are unlikely to lower the deficit in our politics if convictions. We call this kind of accommodation we do not also reduce it in our theory. an economy of moral disagreement, and believe The conception of deliberative democracy that that, though neglected in theory and practice, it is we defend here seeks to diminish that deficit in essential to a morally robust democratic life. . . . theory and in politics.4 The conception consists Some readers may still wonder why delibera- of three principles—reciprocity, publicity, and tion should have such a prominent place in de- accountability—that regulate the process of pol- mocracy. Surely, they may say, citizens should itics, and three others—basic liberty, basic op- care more about the justice of public policies portunity, and fair opportunity—that govern the than the process by which they are adopted, at content of policies. It would promote extensive least so long as the process is basically fair and moral argument about the merits of public poli- at least minimally democratic. One of our main cies in public forums, with the aim of reaching aims in this book is to cast doubt on the dichot- provisional moral agreement and maintaining omy between policies and process that this con- cern assumes. Having good reason as individuals 4. For other discussions of the basis of deliberative to believe that a policy is just does not mean that democracy, see Seyla Benhabib, ‘‘Deliberative Ratio- collectively as citizens we have su‰cient justifi- nality and Models of Democratic Legitimacy,’’ Con- cation to legislate on the basis of those reasons. stellations, 1 (April 1994): 26–52; Joseph Bessette, The The moral authority of collective judgments Mild Voice of Reason: Deliberative Democracy and about policy depends in part on the moral qual- American National Government (Chicago: University ity of the process by which citizens collectively of Chicago Press, 1994), pp. 1–66; Joshua Cohen, ‘‘Deliberation and Democratic Legitimacy,’’ in The reach those judgments. Deliberation is the most Good Polity: Normative Analysis of the State, ed. Alan appropriate way for citizens collectively to re- Hamlin and (Oxford: Basil Blackwell, solve their moral disagreements not only about 1989), pp. 17–34; John S. Dryzek, Discursive Democ- policies but also about the process by which racy (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1990); policies should be adopted. Deliberation is not David M. Estlund, ‘‘Who’s Afraid of Deliberative De- only a means to an end, but also a means for mocracy? On the Strategic/Deliberative Dichotomy in deciding what means are morally required to Recent Constitutional Jurisprudence,’’ Texas Law Re- pursue our common ends. . . . view, 71 (June 1993): 1437–77; James Fishkin, Democ- The sound of moral argument in American racy and Deliberation (New Haven: Yale University democracy may be familiar, but the very famil- Press, 1971); Charles Larmore, Patterns of Moral Complexity (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, iarity has bred neglect, if not contempt. In the 1987), esp. pp. 59–66; Bernard Manin, ‘‘On Legiti- practice of our democratic politics, communi- macy and Political Deliberation,’’ Political Theory,15 cating by sound bite, competing by character (August 1987): 338–368; , ‘‘Motivat- assassination, and resolving political conflicts ing Deliberation in Congress,’’ in Constitutionalism through self-seeking bargaining too often substi- in America, ed. Sarah Baumgartner Thurow, 3 vols. tute for deliberation on the merits of controver- (Lanham, Md.: University Press of America, 1988), 2: sial issues. In the standard theories of democracy 59–86; Jane Mansbridge, ‘‘A Deliberative Theory of —proceduralism and constitutionalism—delib- Interest Representation,’’ in The Politics of Interests: eration likewise receives little attention. These Interest Groups Transformed, ed. Mark P. Petracca theories are surprisingly silent about the need (Boulder, Colo.: Westview Press, 1992), pp. 32–57; and Cass Sunstein, The Partial Constitution (Cambridge, for ongoing discussion of moral disagreement in Mass.: Harvard University Press, 1993), pp. 133–145. everyday political life. As a result, we su¤er from Chapter 1 20

mutual respect among citizens. In its most gen- present in our political life, criticizing and eral form, the demand for deliberation has been extending them in light of other principles also a familiar theme in the American constitutional present in our political culture.7 The character- tradition. It is integral to the ideal of republi- istics of moral arguments we find in actual can government as the Founders understood it. political debate provide the basis for developing James Madison judged the design of political the normative principles with which we assess institutions in part by how well they furthered the ongoing debates. These features of moral deliberation.5 disagreement themselves point toward a deliber- Deliberation should not be confined to consti- ative way of dealing with the disagreement. tutional conventions, Supreme Court opinions, What counts as a moral argument in de- or their theoretical analogues. It should extend liberative democracy? The most rudimentary throughout the political process—to what we criterion—sometimes called generality—is one call the land of middle democracy. The forums that deliberative democracy shares with most of deliberation in middle democracy embrace moral and political theories. The criterion of virtually any setting in which citizens come generality is so widely accepted that it is often together on a regular basis to reach collective identified with the moral point of view.8 Moral decisions about public issues—governmental arguments apply to everyone who is similarly as well as nongovernmental institutions. They include not only legislative sessions, court pro- 7. Our view of deliberation should be distinguished ceedings, and administrative hearings at all levels from that presented by Bessette, who also looks at of government but also meetings of grass roots actual arguments in political debate, in particular those organizations, professional associations, share- in the U.S. Congress. Although he also sees delibera- holders meetings, and citizens’ committees in tive democracy as ‘‘reasoning on the merits of public hospitals and other similar institutions.6 policy’’ (Mild Voice of Reason, p. 46), one of his main In defending this conception of deliberative arguments is that there is already more deliberation in Congress than most political scientists assume. democracy, we look at moral arguments already Whether or not he is correct, we do not presume that the present state of deliberation in Congress and 5. Madison favored political discussion, in which American politics generally is adequate, and in any ‘‘minds [are] changing,’’ in which ‘‘much [is] gained by case we do not focus, as he does, only on the need for a yielding and accommodating spirit,’’ and in which no deliberation among political elites and their role in citizen is ‘‘obliged to retain his opinions any longer preventing spontaneous or passionate judgments by the than he [is] satisfied of their propriety and truth.’’ See masses. Perhaps because he is content with deliberation ‘‘Jared Sparks: Journal,’’ summarizing James Madi- among political elites, Bessette is skeptical about pub- son’s views on the secret discussion in the Constitu- licity and argues in favor of secrecy (pp. 208–209). In tional Convention and Congress, in Records of the another respect, Bessette demands more of deliberation Federal Convention of 1787, rev. ed., ed. Max Farrand, than we do. For him the ‘‘singular mark’’ of a deliber- 4 vols. (New Haven: Yale University Press, 1966), 3: ative process is that it must have ‘‘a real persuasive 479. The passage is quoted in a somewhat di¤erent e¤ect’’ and involve ‘‘some kind of change or develop- form in Sunstein, The Partial Constitution, p. 164. ment in the policymaker’s understanding’’ (pp. 52–53). 6. In the same spirit, Ju¨rgen Habermas identifies de- We do not insist that deliberation must change people’s liberative democracy with the idea of a ‘‘decentered minds to be valuable. society’’ in ‘‘Three Normative Models of Democracy,’’ 8. See Kurt Baier, The Moral Point of View (Ithaca, Constellations, 1 (April 1994): 1–10. For discussions N.Y.: Cornell University Press, 1958), pp. 187–213; of neglected deliberative forums, see David Mathews, and , A Theory of Justice (Cambridge, Politics for People (Urbana: University of Illinois Mass.: Harvard University Press, 1971), pp. 130–136. Press, 1994); and Fishkin, Democracy and Deliberation. Defining Democracy 21

situated in the morally relevant respects. The our fellow citizens. . . . It enables us, for exam- poor woman who seeks an abortion, the white ple, mutually to respect one another as moral male employee who fails to receive his pro- agents who share the goal of reaching delibera- motion, the mother who needs prenatal care do tive agreement even when we disagree with one not assert merely that they, or even only their another’s conclusions. friends, family, and associates, should receive the Reciprocity also applies to the empirical benefit; they maintain that all citizens similarly claims that often accompany moral arguments. situated should receive it. Their claims, if fully Moral arguments take place in context, and they developed, would impute rights and wrongs, or therefore depend at least implicitly on matters ascribe virtue and vice, to anyone who is similar of fact, estimates of risk, suppositions about fea- in the respects that the argument assumes to be sibility, and beliefs about human nature and so- morally significant. cial processes. Sometimes these assumptions are As these examples suggest, generality is not a plausible but controversial: hiring and promot- purely formal standard. It always raises a sub- ing simply on the basis of qualification will not stantive question: What are the morally relevant end racial discrimination soon enough. Some- respects in which people are similarly situated? times they are widely accepted but questionable: Does the same argument against preferential Arizona cannot a¤ord both prenatal care and treatment for white males, for example, apply organ transplants because voters will not ap- equally to preferential treatment of black Amer- prove higher taxes. Sometimes the assumptions icans and white women? Generality forces us are obviously true: only women bear children. to take up substantive arguments . . . which con- If technological advances and cultural changes sider whether the di¤erences between whites and were somehow to eliminate all the social and blacks, and men and women, in this country are psychological e¤ects of this biological fact, our morally relevant in a way that would support a moral attitudes and public policies might be dif- policy of preferential hiring. ferent. But that possibility, even if realized in In politics, however, substantive moral argu- some other place or some other time, should not ment calls for more than merely satisfying the a¤ect the moral argument for us now. . . . criterion of generality. Political decisions are Reciprocity asks that our empirical claims collectively binding, and they should therefore be in political argument be consistent with reliable justifiable, as far as possible, to everyone bound methods of inquiry, as these methods are avail- by them. Three characteristics of moral argu- able to us here and now, not for all times and ments are especially important in politics. The all places. Neither relativity nor uncertainty is first corresponds to our principle of reciprocity, a grounds for abandoning the most reliable meth- form of mutuality in the face of disagreement. . . . ods of inquiry at our collective disposal. By using Citizens try to o¤er reasons that other similarly the most reliable methods of inquiry, we dem- motivated citizens can accept even though they onstrate our mutual commitment to reach delib- recognize that they share only some of one erative agreement in the empirical realms that another’s values. When our deliberations about are relevant to moral argument. moral disagreements in politics are guided by Once the fragments of moral argument with reciprocity, citizens recognize and respect one which this chapter began are put into context, another as moral agents, not merely as abstract they reveal two other characteristics of moral objects of others’ moral reasoning. disagreement in politics. They take us beyond Reciprocity asks us to appeal to reasons the nature of reasoning to the forums and the that are shared or could come to be shared by agents of the disagreement. Moral conflicts Chapter 1 22

in politics typically take place in public forums Even when citizens find some provisionally or are intended for dissemination in public justifiable principles, their disagreement over forums. . . . The principle of publicity . . . captures public policy may persist. In politics, disagree- this feature of moral disagreement in politics. ments often run deep. If they did not, there The third feature of this disagreement con- would be no need for argument. But if they ran cerns the agents by whom and to whom the too deep, there would be no point in argument. moral reasons are publicly o¤ered. The agents Deliberative disagreements lie in the depths be- are typically citizens and public o‰cials who are tween simple misunderstanding and immutable accountable to one another for their political irreconcilability. . . . actions. One common way in which public o‰- Some theorists would abstract from these cials o¤er an account of their actions is by moral disagreements and imagine a nearly ideal responding to challenges from reporters such as society in which some could be more readily Judy Woodru¤, who put President Carter on resolved and many would not arise at all. In the spot about subsidizing abortions for poor some familiar theories of justice, moral claims women. Accountability is ultimately to citizens, are constructed as hypothetical agreements who not only vote for or against the president among individuals who are not accountable to but also speak their minds between elections, anyone and who are assumed to be living in a often through organized groups and intermedi- just society.11 In such a society no one would ary institutions. Accountability through moral need to argue for or against preferential hiring as disagreement in public forums extends not only a means of overcoming racial or gender discrim- to prominent elected o‰cials such as the presi- ination because no such discrimination would dent but also to far less conspicuous o‰cials, exist in that society. Deliberative democracy, in professionals, corporate executives, union lead- contrast, admits reasons and principles that are ers, employers and employees, and ordinary suitable for actual societies, which all still su¤er citizens when they act in a public capacity. from discrimination and other kinds of injustice. The principle of accountability . . . captures this Actual deliberation has an important advantage characteristic of moral disagreement in politics. over hypothetical agreement: it encourages citi- These three features of moral disagreement, zens to face up to their actual problems by lis- then, point to the need and at the same time tening to one another’s moral claims rather than provide the support for the three principles that concluding (on the basis of only a thought ex- refer to the process of deliberative democracy. periment) that their fellow citizens would agree Taken together the principles constitute a pro- with them on all matters of justice if they were cess that seeks deliberative agreement—on poli- all living in an ideal society. cies that can be provisionally justified to the Deliberative democracy does not assume that citizens who are bound by them. Accountable the results of all actual deliberations are just. agents reach out publicly to find reasons that In fact, most of the time democracies fall far others who are motivated to find deliberative short of meeting the conditions that delibera- agreement can also accept. When citizens and tive democracy prescribes. But we can say that accountable o‰cials disagree, and also recognize the more nearly the conditions are satisfied, the that they are seeking deliberative agreement, they remain willing to argue with one another 11. The most prominent contemporary example is with the aim of achieving provisionally justifi- Rawls, A Theory of Justice. See also Bruce Ackerman, able policies that they all can mutually recognize Social Justice in the Liberal State (New Haven: Yale as such. University Press, 1980). Defining Democracy 23

more nearly justifiable are the results likely to solely on satisfying the conditions of delibera- be.12 Even if, as one critic suggests, ‘‘all of the tion. Principles such as basic liberty and op- inequalities of society in general’’ were ‘‘repli- portunity therefore are valued only for their cated in the content of deliberation,’’13 it would contribution to deliberation, not as constraints not discredit deliberation. The process of de- on what counts as a morally legitimate resolu- liberation as we understand it here is self- tion of disagreement. If leaving ‘‘all concrete constraining; its own defining principles provide moral and ethical judgments to participants a basis for criticizing the unjust inequalities that themselves’’15 means that principles such as a¤ect the process. Deliberative democracy cer- liberty and opportunity should never constrain tainly does not accept as equally valid what- these judgments, then discourse theory does not ever reasons and principles citizens and public adequately protect basic rights.16 o‰cials put forward in defense of their own Habermas and other discourse theorists try interests. to avoid this implication by, in e¤ect, building Neither should we make deliberation the guarantees of basic liberty and opportunity into sovereign guide to resolving moral disagreements in politics, as some ‘‘discourse theorists’’ seem to 14. Ju¨rgen Habermas, ‘‘Discourse Ethics,’’ in Moral suggest. Ju¨rgen Habermas writes that ‘‘all con- Consciousness and Communicative Action, trans. Chris- tents, no matter how fundamental the action tian Lenhardt and Shierry Weber Nicholsen (Cam- norm involved may be, must be made to depend bridge, Mass.: MIT Press, 1993), p. 94. on real discourses (or advocatory discourses 15. Thomas McCarthy, ‘‘Introduction’’ to Habermas, conducted as substitutes for them).’’14 Habermas Moral Consciousness and Communicative Action, p. xi. seems to imply that a provisionally justifiable McCarthy writes that this is why Habermas is critical resolution of moral conflicts in politics depends of Rawls’s two principles of justice. But one may criti- cize the two principles for going beyond what moral reasonableness demands while still recognizing the 12. In this respect the hypothetical approach may need for some principles of liberty and opportunity have a role in assessing deliberation, but only in com- that give content to a common perspective and are not bination with an empirical approach that examines the solely conditions of deliberation. actual conditions under which deliberation takes place. 16. Another important deliberative democrat, Seyla shows how these approaches, when com- Benhabib, argues that deliberation can ensure the le- bined to evaluate a theory of justice, ‘‘provide a check gitimacy but not the rationality of outcomes: ‘‘We ac- on one another,’’ in Justice as Impartiality (Oxford: cept the will of the majority at the end of an electoral Oxford University Press, 1995), pp. 195–199. process that has been fairly and correctly carried out, 13. This critic, Frederick Schauer, concludes that de- but even when we accept the legitimacy of the process liberation is no ‘‘more likely to ameliorate than to we may have grave doubts about the rationality of the exacerbate the existing inequalities in a society.’’ The outcome.’’ If deliberation aims only at legitimacy, and only alternative suggested by Schauer is a ‘‘more legitimacy is defined as whatever ‘‘result[s] from the controlled communicative environment.’’ Would the free and unconstrained public deliberation of all about people who controlled communication do so without matters of common concern,’’ then deliberation may obtaining deliberative assent from citizens or their ac- succeed (by definition) at ensuring legitimacy. Benha- countable representatives? If so, why should we think bib, ‘‘Deliberative Rationality,’’ p. 26. But this concept that they would be more egalitarian in their policies of legitimacy has too little moral content to provide a than people who are willing to subject their exercise of robust defense of deliberative democracy. Why should political power to the deliberative assent of citizens? we defend deliberation, so understood, over a concep- See Frederick Schauer, ‘‘Discourse and Its Discon- tion of deliberative democracy that is dedicated both tents,’’ Working Paper no. 94–2, Joan Shorenstein to respecting basic liberty and opportunity and to sub- Barone Center on the Press, Politics, and Public Policy, jecting these principles to ongoing deliberation? Cambridge, Mass., September 1994, p. 9. Chapter 1 24

the ideal conditions of deliberation. They do so ‘‘reflexively’’ subject to deliberative understand- by qualifying what counts as a moral ideal of ing, as discourse theorists correctly insist.20 But deliberation. The participants in practical delib- so should deliberation itself. erations must regard one another as ‘‘competent We do not assume that deliberative democracy subjects’’17 and ‘‘moral and political equals.’’18 can guarantee social justice either in theory or Their deliberations not only must be free but in practice. Our argument is rather that in the also must be reasoned.19 Deliberative outcomes, absence of robust deliberation in democracy, then, would have to respect basic liberty and citizens cannot even provisionally justify many opportunity as an ongoing condition of their controversial procedures and constitutional own legitimacy. rights to one another. Insofar as deliberation is This understanding still does not capture the missing in political life, citizens also lack a mu- value of basic rights. Citizens value basic liberty tually justifiable way of living with their ongoing and opportunity, and their mutual recognition moral disagreements. When citizens deliberate by fellow citizens, for reasons other than the role in democratic politics, they express and respect of these values in democratic deliberation. As their status as political equals even as they con- we shall suggest, even in deliberative democracy, tinue to disagree about important matters of deliberation does not have priority over liberty public policy. and opportunity. The condition of honoring Before exploring how deliberative democracy basic liberty and opportunity should still be deals with disagreement, we need first to examine the sources of that disagreement. Then we can 17. Habermas, ‘‘Discourse Ethics,’’ p. 100. See also better see why procedural and constitutional de- Ju¨rgen Habermas, ‘‘Reconciliation through the Use mocracy can be only partial solutions to the of Public Reason: Remarks on John Rawls’s Political problem of moral conflict, and how deliberative Liberalism,’’ Journal of Philosophy, 92 (March 1995): democracy provides a more nearly complete 109–131. solution. . . . 18. Benhabib, ‘‘Deliberative Rationality,’’ p. 27. Hab- ermas writes that participants in deliberation must 20. Habermas, ‘‘Discourse Ethics,’’ p. 67. be ‘‘free and equal’’ and the discourse ‘‘inclusive and noncoercive’’ (‘‘Reconciliation,’’ pp. 109¤.). This de- scription calls into question his earlier characterization of discourse ethics as o¤ering ‘‘a rule of argumenta- tion only’’ which ‘‘does not prejudge substantive regu- lations’’ (‘‘Discourse Ethics,’’ p. 94). Discourse ethics is ‘‘not compatible with all substantive legal and moral principles,’’ as Habermas recognizes, partly because it is committed to a substantive view of what counts as ideal deliberation. The deliberative ideal lends itself to a stronger defense when it acknowledges the (partly) independent values of basic liberty and opportunity. 19. Benhabib, ‘‘Deliberative Rationality,’’ pp. 30–35. Once content is given to reasoned discourse, a common perspective becomes far less purely procedural than Benhabib suggests: ‘‘Agreements in societies living with value-pluralism are to be sought for not at the level of substantive beliefs but at the level of procedures, pro- cesses, and practices for attaining and revising beliefs’’ (p. 34). The Voice of the People

James S. Fishkin

. . . The deliberative poll is unlike any poll or voice to the people under conditions where the survey ever conducted. Ordinary polls model people can think. . . . what the public is thinking, even though the . . . The deliberative poll has not developed in a public may not be thinking very much or paying vacuum. It builds on important work in encour- much attention. A deliberative poll attempts to aging citizen deliberation. It also builds on the model what the public would think, had it a bet- movement toward public journalism. . . . ter opportunity to consider the questions at issue. . . . We gathered the national random sam- The idea is simple. Take a national random ple for the first deliberative poll, April 15–17, sample of the electorate and transport those 1994, at the Granada Television Studio in Man- people from all over the country to a single chester, England. We attracted participants by place. Immerse the sample in the issues, with paying their expenses, o¤ering them a small carefully balanced briefing materials, with inten- honorarium, telling them they would be on sive discussions in small groups, and with the national television, and advising them that they chance to question competing experts and politi- would be part of an important experiment in cians. At the end of several days of working democracy. . . . through the issues face to face, poll the partic- What did the event accomplish? It demon- ipants in detail. The resulting survey o¤ers a strated the viability of a di¤erent form of opin- representation of the considered judgments of ion polling and, in a sense, a di¤erent form of the public—the views the entire country would democracy. As we have seen, Americans have come to if it had the same experience of behav- long struggled with how to adapt democracy to ing more like ideal citizens immersed in the the large nation-state. Face-to-face democracy issues for an extended period. cannot be applied to large states. Even in Rhode A deliberative poll is not meant to describe or Island, the anti-Federalists could not gather predict public opinion. Rather it prescribes. It everyone together to hear all the arguments on has a recommending force: these are the con- either side. It was for this reason that the Fed- clusions people would come to, were they better eralists boycotted the referendum on the U.S. informed on the issues and had the opportunity Constitution and said that the only appropriate and motivation to examine those issues seriously. method for making a decision was the elected It allows a microcosm of the country to make state convention. A representation of the people, recommendations to us all after it has had the in the form of those elected to go to the conven- chance to think through the issues. If such a poll tion, would be able to hear all the competing were broadcast before an election or a referen- arguments and make an informed decision. dum, it could dramatically a¤ect the outcome. But recall the persistent anti-Federalist worry A deliberative poll takes the two technologies, that no elected representation would be repre- polling and television, that have given us a su- sentative. Ordinary people like them—farmers, perficial form of mass democracy, and harnesses laborers, people without a great deal of educa- them to a new and constructive purpose—giving tion—would tend to get left out. The lawyers and judges and wealthy elite of the day would Excerpted from: James S. Fishkin, The Voice of the make the decisions. The elected microcosm, in People. New Haven, Conn.: Yale University Press, other words, would not be a genuine microcosm 1995. 6 Yale University Press, 1995. Reprinted by —and might not consider or understand their permission of Yale University Press. interests. Chapter 1 26

Democracy, even in the elitist sense of the attracted by, because it will be framed in terms Founders, was only revived by the notion of that speak to their concerns in ordinary life. . . . elected representation. But another form of rep- Most ambitiously, the Deliberative Poll can be resentation lay hidden in the dust of history. It thought of as an actual sample for a hypothetical was employed by the legislative commissions, society—the deliberative and engaged society citizens’ juries and the Council in ancient Athens we do not have. Ideally, we should get everyone (the crucial body that set the agenda for meet- thinking and discussing the issues. But as we ings of the citizen Assembly). This other method have seen the forces of rational ignorance are was selection by lot or random sampling. In one powerful. Yet although we cannot get everyone sense the use of random sampling in politics actively engaged under most conditions, through was revived by opinion polling. After all, what the deliberative poll we can do the experiment is a random sample, at bottom, but a lottery? and get the microcosm engaged—and then But in the ancient Greek form, and in the form broadcast the results to everyone else. Citizens in employed in the deliberative poll, opinions are the microcosm are not subject to rational igno- taken not from isolated citizens but from citi- rance. Instead of one insignificant vote in mil- zens meeting together, deliberating on common lions each of them has an important role to play problems. These polls represent the considered in a nationally televised event. With true en- judgments of the polity, not the top-of-the-head gagement and attention from the microcosm this reactions of isolated citizens. Institutions that representation of the public’s judgment becomes speak for the people need to be both represen- a voice worth listening to. tative and deliberative. The ancient Greek inno- One of the key decisions we made in planning vation was a random sample of citizens who the British Deliberative Poll sheds light on the deliberated together and in that way realized experiment’s aspirations, both in Britain and in both values. And this is the form I propose to the United States. The problem was the seem- adapt to the television age. ingly simple issue of where in the schedule to If this new—and very old—form of democ- place the small-group discussions. We struggled racy were employed in a general election, at the with two di¤erent models of how these dis- beginning of the primary season, or before a cussions serve the deliberative process. One is referendum, then the recommending force of the by absorption, the other is by activation. In one public’s considered judgments, broadcast on na- model the respondents absorb information from tional television, might well make a di¤erence to competing experts, mull that information over the outcome. Recall Samuel Popkin’s argument in small groups, and form their conclusions. On that voters are inclined to follow cues as arbi- this model the participants would spend a great trary as President Ford’s choking on a tamale in deal of time listening to competing presenta- San Antonio. Surely, the cues formed from an tions of relevant factual materials and then they elaborate deliberative process should be worth would process those materials in small group paying attention to. When broadcast on national discussions. television and disseminated in the press, the de- In the second model, we attempt to do some- liberative poll can a¤ect the public’s conclusions, thing far more ambitious. There, the small group but it can also a¤ect the way that public frames discussions come first, before participants have and understands issues. If televised deliberative any contact with experts or politicians. On this polls succeed in communicating the delibera- strategy, we facilitate the citizens’ melding into tive process, they can help transform the public groups first, identifying their key concerns first, agenda to the agenda of an engaged public— establishing rapport among themselves first, set- to an agenda citizens will care about, and be ting the agenda of the questions and concerns Defining Democracy 27

they wish to raise first—and only then put them ative poll, however, o¤ers a representation of a together with the competing experts and com- democracy that meets all four conditions. With peting politicians. The second model, instead of a deliberative atmosphere of mutual respect, absorbing its agenda from the experts, energizes tyranny of the majority is unlikely. When all a public voice coming from the citizens so that the citizens are e¤ectively motivated to think it can speak to the elites. This strategy was fol- through the issues, when each citizen’s views lowed in the Manchester experiment, and it set count equally, and when every member of the an example for how we hope to conduct future microcosm participates, the other three values deliberative polls. . . . are realized as well. Fully realizing those values The logic is very simple. If we take a micro- throughout the entire society may be hypothet- cosm of the entire country and subject it to a ical. But we can see, in microcosm, what de- certain experience, and if the microcosm (behav- liberation, political equality, participation and ing in the way we would like ideal citizens to non-tyranny would look like. behave in seriously deliberating about the issues) Suppose, hypothetically, that the new institu- then comes to di¤erent conclusions about those tion of Deliberative Polling somehow became issues, our inference is simply that if, somehow, as accepted a part of our public life as, say, con- the entire country were subjected to the same ventional polling is today. Deliberative Polling experience as the microcosm, then hypothetically at the state and local level need not be unusual the entire country would also come to similar or expensive. Transportation is a key component conclusions. of the expense on the national level, and local Of course, it is unlikely the entire country ever deliberative polls would not face such a hurdle. would approximate the experiences of a deliber- The experience of serious citizen delibera- ative poll. Even when there is an intense debate, tion seems to have a galvanizing e¤ect on the it may well be dominated by attack ads and participant’s interest in public a¤airs. So far the misleading sound bites. But the point is that if, evidence for this proposition has been largely somehow, the public were enabled to behave anecdotal, but we hope to study this phenome- more like ideal citizens, then the deliberative poll non systematically in follow-ups with partic- o¤ers a representation of what the conclusions ipants in the British project. Suppose, for the might look like. That representation should have sake of argument, that there is a continuing ef- a prescriptive value. It is an opportunity for the fect. In the same way that the citizen mentioned country, in microcosm, to make recommenda- earlier was galvanized to read ‘‘every newspaper tions to itself through television under conditions every day,’’ we might imagine that he continues where it can arrive at considered judgments. to be a far more engaged citizen—discussing Earlier I emphasized four democratic values— public issues with others, being more aware of deliberation, nontyranny, political equality, and the media, and becoming more likely to partici- participation. I noted that e¤orts to fully realize pate in public or civic a¤airs. If Deliberative all four have usually been unsuccessful. In par- Polls ever became a staple of public life, we ticular, the move toward mass democracy—a would end up with a society of more seriously move realized by increasing participation and engaged citizens—one which was not just a rep- political equality—has had a cost in delibera- resentation of how all four democratic values tion. By transferring the e¤ective locus of many could be achieved but rather an embodiment of decisions to the mass public, the system is far less their achievement. Just as the apparatus of selec- deliberative than it would have been had those tion by lot in ancient Athens involved so many decisions been left in the hands of elites—elected citizens, so often, that it seems to have galva- representatives and party leaders. The deliber- nized an active citizenry, it is not inconceivable Chapter 1 28

that selection by lot for Deliberative Polls could, someday, have the same e¤ect on our country. It is not inconceivable, but it is, admittedly, unlikely. Such a flourishing of a new institution is clearly utopian, even as a matter of aspiration. But the image helps clarify an ideal—a picture of the reconstructed role of citizen, not just on television but in actual life. At a minimum, the deliberative poll can articulate the considered judgments of an informed citizenry and broad- cast those conclusions to the nation. It provides a di¤erent, and more thoughtful, public voice. Other innovations and other institutions would have to be relied on if we are to create a seriously engaged mass citizenry as a routine part of our national life. . . . To make a democracy that works, we need citizens who are engaged, communities that function, and media that speak for us as well as about us. If we pay attention to the conditions under which citizens become reconnected to political life, we can create a public worthy of public opinion—and public judgment. It would indeed be ‘‘magic town’’ if we brought such a spirit to the entire country. Defining and Developing Democracy

Larry Diamond

The basis of a democratic state is liberty. Thus, as Locke, Montesquieu, and the Ameri- —Aristotle, The Politics can Federalists asserted, only a constitutional government, restraining and dividing the tempo- Since April of 1974, when the Portuguese mili- rary power of the majority, can protect indi- tary overthrew the Salazar/Caetano dictatorship, vidual freedom. This fundamental insight (and the number of democracies in the world has value) gave birth to a tradition of political multiplied dramatically. Before the start of this thought—liberalism—and to a concept—liberal global trend, there were about forty democracies. democracy—that are central to this book. As The number increased moderately through the elaborated below, I use the term liberal to mean late 1970s and early 1980s as several states a political system in which individual and group experienced transitions from authoritarian rule liberties are well protected and in which there (predominantly military) to democratic rule. exist autonomous spheres of civil society and In the mid-1980s, the pace of global democratic private life, insulated from state control. . . . expansion accelerated markedly. By the end of Even if we think of democracy as simply the 1995, there were as many as 117 democracies or rule of the people, as a system for choosing gov- as few as 76, depending on how one counts. . . . ernment through free and fair electoral competi- tion at regular intervals, governments chosen The Best Form of Government in this manner are generally better than those that are not. They o¤er the best prospect for . . . The normative perspective underlying this accountable, responsive, peaceful, predictable, book is that is generally a good good governance. And, as Robert Dahl cogently thing and that democracy is the best form of observes, they promote ‘‘freedom as no feasible 6 government. However, democracy is not an un- alternative can.’’ ... mitigated blessing. Dating back to Aristotle (and Up to a point consistent with the principles of to Plato, who had even less sympathy for de- constitutionalism and representative democracy, mocracy), the key shapers of democratic political government is better when it is more democratic. thought have held that the best realizable form This is not to argue that even electoral democracy 7 of government is mixed, or constitutional, gov- is easily attainable in any country at any time. ernment, in which freedom is constrained by the rule of law and popular sovereignty is tempered 3. Gabriel A. Almond, ‘‘Political Science: The History by state institutions that produce order and sta- of the Discipline,’’ in A New Handbook of Political bility.3 Aristotle saw that, in a state of pure de- Science, edited by Robert E. Goodin and Hans-Dieter Klingemann (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1996), mocracy, ‘‘where the multitude have the supreme 53–61. See also David Held, Models of Democracy power, and supersede the law by their decrees . . . (Stanford: Stanford University Press, 1987), chaps. 1, 2. demagogues spring up,’’ and democracy degen- 4 4. Aristotle, The Politics, edited by Stephen Everson erates into a form of despotism. (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1988), 1292. 6. Robert A. Dahl, Democracy and Its Critics (New Excerpted from: Larry Diamond, Developing Democ- Haven: Yale University Press, 1989), chap. 8; quota- racy: Toward Consolidation, pp. 1–19. Baltimore: tions at 88 and 89. 6 Johns Hopkins University Press, 1999. 1999 The 7. There are certain economic, social, and cultural Johns Hopkins University Press. Reprinted with per- conditions for democracy to be viable, but they are mission of The Johns Hopkins University Press. often overstated, and we should be cautious about Chapter 1 30

However, more democracy makes government the world that could possibly qualify as liberal.12 more responsive to a wider range of citizens. . . . And there will not be any significant ones in Normatively, I assume here that account- the future, for liberalism insists upon the sover- ability of rulers to the ruled and government eignty of the people to decide their form of responsiveness to the diverse interests and pref- government—and these days, according to Marc erences of the governed are basic goods. So also Plattner, ‘‘popular sovereignty can hardly fail are the minimization of violence in political life to lead to popular government.’’13 In an age of and of arbitrary action by government. And so, widespread communication and political con- above all, is liberty. Increasingly in the twentieth sciousness, people expect political participation century, the freedoms of the individual to think, and accountability much more than they did in believe, worship, speak, publish, inquire, associ- the eighteenth, nineteenth, and early twentieth ate, and become informed, and the freedoms centuries. The only way the demand for mean- from torture, arbitrary arrest, and unlawful ingful political participation and choice can be detention—not to mention enslavement and suppressed is to constrain liberty. Thus, as noted genocide—are recognized as universal and in- above, there is a powerful association between alienable human rights. . . . democracy and liberty: ‘‘countries that hold free Liberal democracy provides, by definition, elections are overwhelmingly more liberal than comparatively good protection for human rights. those that do not.’’14 Indeed, the more closely However, there is no reason that electoral de- countries meet the standards of electoral democ- mocracy and liberty must go together. Histori- racy (free and fair, multiparty elections by secret cally, liberty—secured through constitutional, and universal ballot), the higher their human limited government and a rule of law—came rights rating.15 ... about before democracy both in England and, in varying degrees, in other European states. And 12. And even these governments are not very liberal, today . . . there are many illiberal democracies, for the same reason that liberal autocracy is generally with human rights abuses and civil strife. These not possible: when Antiguans and Tongans demand two facts have rekindled intellectual interest real democracy, they are harassed by the state or the in liberal autocracy as a better, safer, more stable ruling party. Freedom House, : form of government for many transitional The Annual Survey of Political Rights and Civil Lib- societies.11 erties, 1996–1997 (New York: Freedom House, 1997), 125, 488. As I explain in greater detail below, each year In times of very limited education and politi- Freedom House rates countries on a scale from 1 to 7 cal consciousness, when the franchise could be on two measures, political rights and civil liberties (1 confined to a narrow elite, liberal autocracy was being most liberal). It also classifies all the countries in possible. In today’s world, it is an illusion, a his- the world as to whether or not they are electoral torical anachronism. Save for two island states democracies. Of the countries that are not electoral with populations of 100,000 each (Tonga; Anti- democracies, only the above two have scores of 3 on gua and Barbuda), there are no autocracies in civil liberties (and none has better than 3). 13. Marc F. Plattner, ‘‘Liberalism and Democracy,’’ positing them as ‘‘prerequisites.’’ See Larry Diamond, Foreign A¤airs 77, no. 2 (1998): 171–180; quotation on ‘‘Economic Development and Democracy Reconsid- 175. ered,’’ in Reexamining Democracy: Essays in Honor 14. Ibid., 173. of Seymour Martin Lipset, edited by Gary Marks and 15. Russell Bova, ‘‘Democracy and Liberty: The Cul- Larry Diamond (Newbury Park, Calif.: Sage, 1992), tural Connection,’’ Journal of Democracy 8, no. 1 93–139. (1997): 115, table 1. The di¤erence in average rating on 11. Fareed Zakaria, ‘‘The Rise of Illiberal Democ- the Humana human rights scale between countries that racy,’’ Foreign A¤airs 76, no. 6 (1997): 22–43. clearly have electoral democracy and those that clearly Defining Democracy 31

The above positive benefits of democracy de- Where conceptions of democracy diverge to- rive, as Russett notes with respect to interstate day is on the range and extent of political prop- peace, from both the norms and the political erties encompassed by democracy. Minimalist institutions that characterize democracies. But definitions of what I call electoral democracy which democracies? For peace and develop- descend from Joseph Schumpeter, who defined ment and for the just treatment of minorities, democracy as a system ‘‘for arriving at political is it enough that governments come to power decisions in which individuals acquire the power through free, fair, and competitive elections? to decide by means of a competitive struggle for Or do these objectives require other features of the people’s vote.’’32 Huntington, among others, democracy—a rule of law, free information, civil explicitly embraces Schumpeter’s emphasis on liberties, and a distribution of power that pro- competitive elections for e¤ective power as the duces a horizontal accountability of rulers to one essence of democracy.33 However, Schumpeter’s another? What do we mean by democracy? corporation of socioeconomic criteria into the defini- tion of democracy, see Terry Lynn Karl, ‘‘Dilemmas of Conceptualizing Democracy Democratization in Latin America,’’ Comparative Pol- itics 23, no. 1 (1990): 2. Just as political scientists and observers do not 32. Joseph Schumpeter, Capitalism, Socialism, and agree on how many democracies there are in Democracy, 2d ed. (New York: Harper, 1947), 269. the world, so they di¤er on how to classify spe- For Schumpeter, Held explains, ‘‘the democratic cit- cific regimes, the conditions for making and izen’s lot was, quite straightforwardly, the right peri- consolidating democracy, and the consequences odically to choose and authorize governments to act on of democracy for peace and development. A key their behalf’’ (Models of Democracy, 165). Schumpeter element in all these debates is lack of consensus was clearly uneasy with direct political action by citi- zens, warning that ‘‘the electoral mass is incapable of on the meaning of democracy.... action other than a stampede’’ (283). Thus, his ‘‘case . . . By and large, most scholarly and policy for democracy can support, at best, only minimum uses of the term democracy today refer to a political involvement: that involvement which could be purely political conception of the term, and this considered su‰cient to legitimate the right of compet- intellectual shift back to an earlier convention ing elites to rule’’ (ibid., 168). This is, indeed, as spare a has greatly facilitated progress in studying the notion of democracy as one could posit without drain- dynamics of democracy, including the relation- ing the term of meaning. ship between political democracy and various 33. Huntington, The Third Wave, 5–13, esp. 6; Samuel social and economic conditions.31 P. Huntington, ‘‘The Modest Meaning of Democracy,’’ in Democracy in the Americas: Stopping the Pendulum, edited by Robert A. Pastor (New York: Holmes and do not is enormous: 85 to 35. For a description of this Meier, 1989), 15. For similar conceptions of democ- 100-point scale (with 100 being the top score), see racy based on competitive elections, see Seymour Charles Humana, World Human Rights Guide, 3d ed. Martin Lipset, Political Man: The Social Bases of Pol- (New York: Oxford University Press, 1992). itics (Baltimore: Johns Hopkins University Press, 31. Severe, persistent socioeconomic inequality may 1981), 27; Lipset, ‘‘The Social Requisites of Democ- well be (as some scholars find) a major threat to polit- racy Revisited,’’ American Sociological Review 59, no. ical democracy. But to establish this, we must first have 1 (1994): 1; Juan J. Linz, The Breakdown of Democratic a measure of democracy that is limited to features Regimes: Crisis, Breakdown, and Reequilibration (Bal- of the political system. For an e¤ort exhibiting this timore: Johns Hopkins University Press, 1978), 5–6; J. approach (and finding), see Zehra F. Arat, Democracy Roland Pennock, Democratic Political Theory (Prince- and Human Rights in Developing Countries (Boulder, ton: Princeton University Press, 1979), 7–15; G. Bing- Colo.: Lynne Rienner, 1991). For a critique of the in- ham Powell, Contemporary Democracies: Participation, Chapter 1 32

concise expression has required periodic elabo- and assembly) in order for competition and par- ration (or what Collier and Levitsky call ‘‘pre- ticipation to be meaningful. But, typically, they cising’’) to avoid inclusion of cases that do not fit do not devote much attention to them, nor do the implicit meaning. they incorporate them into actual measures of The seminal elaboration is Dahl’s conception democracy. Thus (consistent with most other of polyarchy, which has two overt dimensions: e¤orts to classify or measure regimes), Przewor- opposition (organized contestation through regu- ski and his colleagues define democracy simply lar, free, and fair elections) and participation (the as ‘‘a regime in which governmental o‰ces are right of virtually all adults to vote and contest for filled as a consequence of contested elections’’ o‰ce). Yet embedded in these two dimensions is a (with the proviso that real contestation requires third, without which the first two cannot be truly an opposition with some nontrivial chance of meaningful: civil liberty. Polyarchy encompasses winning o‰ce and that the chief executive o‰ce not only freedom to vote and contest for o‰ce and legislative seats are filled by contested elec- but also freedom to speak and publish dissenting tions).36 Such Schumpeterian conceptions (com- views, freedom to form and join organizations, and alternative sources of information.34 Both 36. Adam Przeworski, Michael Alvarez, Jose´ Antonio Dahl’s original formulation and a later, more Cheibub, and Fernando Limongi, ‘‘What Makes comprehensive e¤ort to measure polyarchy take Democracies Endure?’’ Journal of Democracy 7, no. 1 seriously the nonelectoral dimensions.35 (1996): 50–51. Their methodology is more compre- hensively explained in Michael Alvarez, Jose´ Antonio Electoral Democracy Cheibub, Fernando Limongi, and Adam Przeworski, ‘‘Classifying Political Regimes for the ACLP Data Set,’’ Working Paper 4, Chicago Center on Democ- Minimalist conceptions of electoral democracy racy, . Many other approaches usually also acknowledge the need for minimum to conceiving and measuring democracy in quantita- levels of freedom (of speech, press, organization, tive, cross-national analyses have also tended to rely on indicators of competition and participation (whether Stability, and Violence (Cambridge: Harvard Univer- dichotomous, categorical, or continuous), but some of sity Press, 1982), 3; Tatu Vanhanen, The Process of these were gravely flawed by their incorporation of Democratization: A Comparative Study of 147 States, substantively inappropriate indicators, such as voter 1980–88 (New York: Crane Russak, 1990), 17–18; turnout or political stability. (On this and other con- Giuseppe Di Palma, To Craft Democracies: An Essay ceptual and methodological problems, see Kenneth A. on Democratic Transitions (Berkeley: University of Bollen, ‘‘Political Democracy: Conceptual and Mea- California Press, 1991), 16; Adam Przeworski, Democ- surement Traps,’’ in Inkeles, Measuring Democracy, racy and the Market: Political and Economic Reforms 3–20.) in Eastern Europe and Latin America (Cambridge: As an alternative approach that explicitly includes Cambridge University Press, 1991), 10–11. the behavioral, noninstitutional dimensions of democ- 34. Dahl, Polyarchy, 2–3. Dahl uses the term poly- racy, the combined Freedom House scales of political archy to distinguish these systems from a more ideal rights and civil liberties, described below, are increas- form of democracy, ‘‘one of the characteristics of ingly being used in quantitative analysis. For examples, which is the quality of being completely or almost see Henry S. Rowen, ‘‘The Tide Underneath the ‘Third completely responsive to all its citizens’’ (2). Wave,’’’ Journal of Democracy 6, no. 1 (1995): 52–64; Surjit S. Bhalla, ‘‘Freedom and Economic Growth: 35. Ibid., app. A; Michael Coppedge and Wolfgang A Virtuous Cycle?’’ in Hadenius, Democracy’s Victory H. Reinecke, ‘‘Measuring Polyarchy,’’ in On Measur- and Crisis, 195–241. While the Freedom House data is ing Democracy: Its Consequences and Concomitants, available annually, it goes back in time only to 1972, edited by Alex Inkeles (New Brunswick, N.J.: Trans- and the criteria for scoring have become stricter over action, 1991), 47–68. time (particularly in the 1990s), creating problems for Defining Democracy 33

mon among Western foreign policy makers as of a democratic transition, proliferate in a bewil- well) risk committing what Terry Karl calls the dering variety.’’38 ‘‘fallacy of electoralism.’’ This flawed concep- In recent years, electoral conceptions of de- tion of democracy privileges elections over other mocracy have expanded to rule out the latter dimensions of democracy and ignores the de- element of ambiguity or misclassification; many gree to which multiparty elections (even if they now exclude regimes that su¤er substantial re- are competitive and uncertain in outcome) may served domains of military (or bureaucratic, or exclude significant portions of the population oligarchical) power that are not accountable to from contesting for power or advancing and elected o‰cials.39 But still, such formulations defending their interests, or may leave signifi- may still fail to give due weight to political re- cant arenas of decision making beyond the con- pression and marginalization, which exclude sig- trol of elected o‰cials.37 Philippe Schmitter and nificant segments of the population—typically Terry Karl remind us that, ‘‘however central to the poor or ethnic and regional minorities— democracy, elections occur intermittently and from exercising their democratic rights. One of only allow citizens to choose between the highly the most rigorous and widely used measures of aggregated alternatives o¤ered by political democracy in cross-national, quantitative re- parties, which can, especially in the early stages search—in the ‘‘polity’’ data sets—acknowl- edges civil liberties as a major component of interpreting changes in scores over time. The appeal of democracy but, because of the paucity of data, a simple dichotomous measure such as that used by does not incorporate them.40 Przeworski and his colleagues is precisely the relative simplification of data collection and regime classifi- 38. Philippe C. Schmitter and Terry Lynn Karl, cation and the ability to conduct a straightforward ‘‘What Democracy Is . . . and Is Not,’’ Journal of De- ‘‘event history’’ analysis that analyzes changes toward mocracy 2, no. 3 (1991): 78. and away from democratic regime forms. Encourag- 39. Collier and Levitsky, ‘‘Democracy with Adjec- ingly, the Freedom House ratings and other measures tives.’’ A seminal discussion of reserved domains of democracy are generally highly correlated with one appears in J. Samuel Valenzuela, ‘‘Democratic Con- another (Alex Inkeles, introduction to Measuring De- solidation in Post-Transitional Settings: Notion, mocracy). In fact, Przeworski et al. report that the Process, and Facilitating Conditions,’’ in Issues in Freedom House combined ratings for 1972 to 1990 Democratic Consolidation: The New South American predict 93 percent of their regime classifications during Democracies in Comparative Perspective, edited by this period (‘‘What Makes Democracies Endure?’’ 52). Scott Mainwaring, Guillermo O’Donnell, and J. However, as we see in chapter 2, since 1990 the formal Samuel Valenzuela (Notre Dame: University of Notre properties and the liberal substance of democracy have Dame Press, 1992), 64–66. See also Huntington, The increasingly diverged. Thus, the substantive validity of Third Wave, 10; Schmitter and Karl, ‘‘What Democ- measures that focus mainly on formal competition may racy Is,’’ 81; Guillermo O’Donnell, ‘‘Illusions about be particularly suspect after 1990. Consolidation,’’ Journal of Democracy 7, no. 2 (1996): 37. Terry Lynn Karl, ‘‘Imposing Consent? Elec- 34–51; Juan J. Linz and Alfred Stepan, Problems toralism versus Democratization in El Salvador,’’ in of Democratic Transition and Consolidation: Southern Elections and Democratization in Latin America, 1980– Europe, South America, and Post-Communist Europe 1985, edited by Paul Drake and Eduardo Silva (San (Baltimore: Johns Hopkins University Press, 1996), Diego: Center for Iberian and Latin American Studies, 3–5. Center for US/Mexican Studies, University of Califor- 40. On the Polity III data set, see Keith Jaggers and nia at San Diego, 1986), 9–36; Karl, ‘‘Dilemmas of Ted Robert Gurr, ‘‘Tracking Democracy’s Third Wave Democratization in Latin America,’’ 14–15; Karl, with the Polity III Data,’’ Journal of Peace Research ‘‘The Hybrid Regimes of Central America,’’ Journal of 32, no. 4 (1995): 469–482. On the Polity II data (which Democracy 6, no. 3 (1995): 72–86. Chapter 1 34

Freedom exists over a continuum of variation. to one another and which occupy intermediate Rights of expression, organization, and assem- locations in the continuum between electoral and bly vary considerably across countries that do liberal democracy.41 have regular, competitive, multiparty elections in How does liberal democracy extend beyond which votes are (more or less) honestly counted these formal and intermediate conceptions? In and in which the winning candidates exercise addition to the elements of electoral democracy, (most of the) e¤ective power in the country. How it requires, first, the absence of reserved domains overtly repressed must a minority be for the po- of power for the military or other actors not ac- litical system to be disqualified as a polyarchy (a countable to the electorate, directly or indirectly. liberal democracy)? . . . Second, in addition to the vertical accountability By the minimalist definition, Turkey, , of rulers to the ruled (secured mainly through Sri Lanka, Colombia, and Russia qualify as elections), it requires the horizontal account- democracies. But by the stricter conception of ability of o‰ceholders to one another; this con- liberal democracy, all (except perhaps India as a strains executive power and so helps protect whole) fall short. In fact, the gap between elec- constitutionalism, legality, and the deliberative toral and liberal democracy has grown markedly process.42 Third, it encompasses extensive pro- during the latter part of the third wave, forming one of its most significant but little-noticed fea- 41. Among the expanded procedural definitions that tures. As a result, human rights violations have appear to bear a strong a‰nity to the conception of become widespread in countries that are for- liberal democracy articulated here, but that are some- mally democratic. what cryptic or ambiguous about the weight given to civil liberties, are Karl, ‘‘Dilemmas of Democratization Liberal Democracy in Latin America,’’ 2; Dietrich Rueschemeyer, Evelyne Huber Stephens, and John D. Stephens, Capitalist Development and Democracy (Chicago: University of Electoral democracy is a civilian, constitutional Chicago Press, 1992), 43–44, 46. system in which the legislative and chief execu- 42. Obviously, the independent power of the legisla- tive o‰ces are filled through regular, competi- ture to ‘‘check and balance’’ executive power will dif- tive, multiparty elections with universal su¤rage. fer markedly between presidential and parliamentary While this minimalist conception remains popu- regimes. However, even in parliamentary regimes, lar in scholarship and policy, it has been ampli- democratic vigor requires striking a balance between fied, or precised, to various degrees by several disciplined parliamentary support for the governing scholars and theorists. This exercise has been party and independent capacity to scrutinize and ques- constructive, but it has left behind a plethora of tion the actions of cabinet ministers and executive what Collier and Levitsky term ‘‘expanded pro- agencies. For the political quality of democracy, the cedural’’ conceptions, which do not clearly relate most important additional mechanism of horizontal accountability is an autonomous judiciary, but crucial as well are institutionalized means (often in a separate, Polity III corrects and updates to 1994), see Ted Rob- autonomous agency) to monitor, investigate, and pun- ert Gurr, Keith Jaggers, and Will H. Moore, ‘‘The ish government corruption at all levels. On the concept Transformation of the Western State: The Growth of of lateral, or ‘‘constitutional,’’ accountability and its Democracy, Autocracy, and State Power since 1800,’’ importance, see Richard L. Sklar, ‘‘Developmental in Inkeles, Measuring Democracy, 69–104. Although Democracy,’’ Comparative Studies in Society and His- it does not measure civil liberties, the democracy mea- tory 29, no. 4 (1987): 686–714; Sklar, ‘‘Towards a sure of the polity data sets goes beyond electoral com- Theory of Developmental Democracy,’’ in Democ- petitiveness to measure institutional constraints on the racy and Development: Theory and Practice, edited exercise of executive power (the phenomenon of ‘‘hori- by Adrian Leftwich (Cambridge: Polity Press, 1996), zontal accountability’’). 25–44. For the concept and theory of ‘‘horizontal Defining Democracy 35

visions for political and civic pluralism as well sumption of party alternation in government, as for individual and group freedoms, so that but no group that adheres to constitutional contending interests and values may be expressed principles is denied the right to form a party and and compete through ongoing processes of ar- contest elections (even if electoral thresholds and ticulation and representation, beyond periodic other rules exclude small parties from winning elections. representation in parliament). Freedom and pluralism, in turn, can be . Cultural, ethnic, religious, and other minor- secured only through a ‘‘rule of law,’’ in which ity groups (as well as historically disadvantaged legal rules are applied fairly, consistently, and majorities) are not prohibited (legally or in predictably across equivalent cases, irrespective practice) from expressing their interests in the of the class, status, or power of those subject to political process or from speaking their language the rules. Under a true rule of law, all citizens or practicing their culture. have political and legal equality, and the state . Beyond parties and elections, citizens have and its agents are themselves subject to the multiple, ongoing channels for expression and law.43 representation of their interests and values, Specifically, liberal democracy has the follow- including diverse, independent associations and ing components: movements, which they have the freedom to . Control of the state and its key decisions and form and join.44 allocations lies, in fact as well as in constitutional . There are alternative sources of information theory, with elected o‰cials (and not democrati- (including independent media) to which citizens cally unaccountable actors or foreign powers); have (politically) unfettered access. in particular, the military is subordinate to the . Individuals also have substantial freedom of authority of elected civilian o‰cials. belief, opinion, discussion, speech, publication, . Executive power is constrained, constitution- assembly, demonstration, and petition. ally and in fact, by the autonomous power of . Citizens are politically equal under the law other government institutions (such as an inde- (even though they are invariably unequal in their pendent judiciary, parliament, and other mecha- political resources). nisms of horizontal accountability). . Individual and group liberties are e¤ectively . Not only are electoral outcomes uncertain, protected by an independent, nondiscriminatory with a significant opposition vote and the pre- judiciary, whose decisions are enforced and respected by other centers of power. accountability,’’ see Guillermo O’Donnell, ‘‘Delegative . Democracy,’’ Journal of Democracy 5, no. 1 (1994): The rule of law protects citizens from unjusti- 60–62, and ‘‘Horizontal Accountability and New Poly- fied detention, exile, terror, torture, and undue archies,’’ in Andreas Schedler, Larry Diamond, and interference in their personal lives not only by Marc F. Plattner, eds., The Self-Restraining State: Power and Accountability in New Democracies (Boul- 44. This is a particular emphasis of Schmitter and der, Colo.: Lynne Rienner, forthcoming). Karl, ‘‘What Democracy Is,’’ 78–80, but it has long 43. For an important explication of the rule of law and figured prominently in the work and thought of demo- its related concepts, see Guillermo O’Donnell, ‘‘The cratic pluralists such as Robert A. Dahl. In addition to (Un)Rule of Law in Latin America,’’ in The Rule of his Polyarchy, see Dahl, Who Governs? (New Haven: Law and the Underprivileged in Latin America, edited Yale University Press, 1961); Dahl, Dilemmas of Plu- by Juan Me´ndez, Guillermo O’Donnell, and Paulo ralist Democracy: Autonomy versus Control (New Se´rgio Pinheiro (Notre Dame: University of Notre Haven: Yale University Press, 1982). Dame Press, forthcoming). Chapter 1 36

the state but also by organized nonstate or anti- process as well, and to use O’Donnell’s language, state forces. individuals must be able to exercise their rights of citizenship not only in elections but also in These ten conditions imply an eleventh: if obtaining ‘‘fair access to public agencies and political authority is to be constrained and bal- courts,’’ which is often denied in ‘‘informally anced, individual and minority rights protected, institutionalized’’ polyarchies. and a rule of law assured, democracy requires a The distinction between political and civil constitution that is supreme. Liberal democracies freedom, on the one hand, and cultural freedom in particular ‘‘are and have to be constitutional (or license), on the other, is often confused in democracies. The lack of a constitutional spirit, the debate over whether democracy is inappro- of an understanding of the centrality of consti- priate for Asia (or East Asia, or Confucian Asia, tutional stability, is one of the weaknesses’’ of or simply Singapore) because of incompatible many illiberal third-wave democracies in the values. Liberal democracy does not require postcommunist world, as well as in the Third the comprehensively exalted status of individual 45 World. ... rights that obtains in Western Europe and espe- cially the United States. Thus, one may accept Midrange Conceptions many of the cultural objections of advocates of the ‘‘Asian values’’ perspective (that Western Conceptual approaches are no longer easily democracies have shifted the balance too much dichotomized into electoral and liberal ap- in favor of individual rights and social entitle- proaches. Some conceptions of democracy fall ments over the rights of the community and the somewhere in between, explicitly incorporating social obligations of the individual to the com- basic freedoms of expression and association munity) and still embrace the political and civic yet still allowing for constrictions in citizenship fundamentals of liberal democracy as articulated rights and a porous, insecure rule of law. The above.55 crucial distinction turns on whether freedoms are relevant mainly to the extent that they ensure Pseudodemocracies and Nondemocracies meaningful electoral competition and partici- pation or whether they are, instead, viewed as An appreciation of the dynamics of regime necessary for a wider range of democratic change and the evolution of democracy must functions. . . . allow for a third class of regimes, which are less The question of how extensive liberty must be than minimally democratic but still distinct from before a political system can be termed a liberal purely authoritarian regimes. This requires a democracy is a normative and philosophical one. second cutting point, between electoral democ- The key distinction is whether the political pro- racies and electoral regimes that have multiple cess centers on elections or whether it encom- passes a much broader and more continuous 55. For a perspective that does just this, see Joseph play of interest articulation, representation, and Chan, ‘‘Hong Kong, Singapore, and Asian Values: contestation. If we view the latter as an essential An Alternative View,’’ Journal of Democracy 8, no. 2 component of democracy, then there must be (1997): 35–48. One can have a political system that adequate freedoms surrounding that broader meets the ten criteria of liberal democracy I outline but that is culturally conservative or restrictive in some 45. Juan J. Linz, ‘‘Democracy Today: An Agenda for policies. The key test is whether those who disagree Students of Democracy,’’ Scandinavian Political Stud- with these policies have full civic and political freedom ies 20, no. 2 (1997): 120–121. to mobilize to change them. Defining Democracy 37

parties and many other constitutional features of This framework leaves a fourth, residual electoral democracy but that lack at least one category, of authoritarian regimes. They vary key requirement: an arena of contestation su‰- in their level of freedom . . . , and they may ciently fair that the ruling party can be turned even hold somewhat competitive elections (as in out of power. Juan Linz, Seymour Martin Lip- Uganda and other previously one-party African set, and I term these regimes pseudodemocracies, regimes). They may a¤ord civil society and the ‘‘because the existence of formally democratic judiciary some modest autonomy. Or they may political institutions, such as multiparty electoral be extremely closed and repressive, even totali- competition, masks (often in part to legitimate) tarian. But they all lack a crucial building block the reality of authoritarian domination.’’56 of democracy: legal, independent opposition There is wide variation among pseudode- parties. All the most repressive regimes in the mocracies. They include semidemocracies, which world fall into this category. more nearly approach electoral democracies in This four-fold typology neatly classifies na- their pluralism and competitiveness, as well as tional political regimes, but political reality is what Giovanni Sartori terms ‘‘hegemonic party always messier. Level of democracy may vary systems,’’ in which a relatively institutionalized significantly across sectors and institutional are- ruling party makes extensive use of coercion, nas (as would be expected if democracy emerges patronage, media control, and other features to in parts). It may also vary considerably across deny formally legal opposition parties a fair and territories within the national state. . . . authentic chance to compete for power.57 ... With large countries, in particular, it is What distinguishes pseudodemocracies from necessary to disaggregate to form a more other nondemocracies is that they tolerate sensitive picture of the quality and extent of legal alternative parties, which constitute at least democracy. . . . somewhat real and independent opposition to the ruling party. Typically, this toleration is ished subtypes’’ of democracy. Those subtypes that are accompanied by more space for organizational missing the attribute of free elections or relatively fair pluralism and dissident activity in civil society multiparty contestation are pseudodemocracies. Those than is the case in the most repressive authori- that have real and fair multiparty competition but with tarian regimes. Invariably, pseudodemocracies limited su¤rage constitute exclusionary, or oligarchic, are illiberal, but they vary in their repressiveness democracy, which is not relevant to the contemporary and in their proximity to the threshold of elec- era of universal su¤rage. Those regimes without ade- quate civil liberties or civilian control of the military toral democracy (which Mexico could well cross may nevertheless be electoral democracies. Care is in its next presidential election, in the year 2000). needed to empirically apply concepts, however. For Thus, pseudodemocracies tend to have some- example, Donald K. Emmerson’s category of ‘‘illiberal what higher levels of freedom than other au- democracy’’ would seem to be coincident with ‘‘elec- thoritarian regimes.58 ... toral democracy’’ in my framework. However, as Emmerson applies the concept to what he calls ‘‘one- 56. Diamond et al., ‘‘What Makes for Democracy?’’ 8. party democracy’’ in Singapore and Malaysia, the coincidence breaks down. Civil and political freedoms 57. Giovanni Sartori, Parties and Party Systems: A are so constrained in these two countries that the min- Framework for Analysis (Cambridge: Cambridge Uni- imum criterion of electoral democracy (a su‰ciently versity Press, 1976), 230–238. level electoral playing field to give opposition parties a 58. . . . Taking seriously Collier and Levitsky’s appeal chance at victory) is not met. See Emmerson, ‘‘Region to reduce the conceptual clutter in comparative demo- and Recalcitrance: Rethinking Democracy through cratic studies, we relate our categories here to similar Southeast Asia,’’ Pacific Review 8, no. 2 (1995): 223– concepts in other studies, particularly the ‘‘dimin- 248. Chapter 1 38

But by permitting widespread liberty and the real Democracy in Developmental Perspective possibility of selecting alternative governments and policies, and by permitting disadvantaged Even liberal democracies fall short of demo- groups to organize and mobilize politically, cratic ideals. At the less liberal end of the group, democracies (particularly liberal democracies) they may have serious flaws in their guaran- provide the best long-run prospects for reducing tees of personal and associational freedom. And social injustices and correcting mistaken policies certainly ongoing practices in Italy, Japan, Bel- and corrupt practices. gium, , the United States, and most other It is important, then, not to take the existence industrialized democracies underscore that even of democracy, even liberal democracy, as cause long-established and well-institutionalized democ- for self-congratulation. Democracy should be racies with the most liberal average freedom viewed as a developmental phenomenon. Even scores of 1 or 1.5 are a¿icted with corruption, when a country is above the threshold of elec- favoritism, and unequal access to political power, toral (or even liberal) democracy, democratic not to mention voter apathy, cynicism, and dis- institutions can be improved and deepened or engagement. may need to be consolidated; political competi- There is not now and has never been in the tion can be made fairer and more open; partici- modern world of nation-states a perfect democ- pation can become more inclusive and vigorous; racy, one in which all citizens have roughly equal citizens’ knowledge, resources, and competence political resources and in which government is can grow; elected (and appointed) o‰cials can completely or almost completely responsive to be made more responsive and accountable; civil all citizens. This is why Robert Dahl uses the liberties can be better protected; and the rule term polyarchy to characterize the more limited of law can become more e‰cient and secure.66 form of democracy that has been attained to Viewed in this way, continued democratic de- date. Important currents in democracy’s third velopment is a challenge for all countries, wave are the increased valorization of such including the United States; all democracies, limited political democracy as an end in itself new and established, can become more demo- and the growing tendency of intellectuals (even cratic. many who had once been on the Marxist left) Obviously, the improvement and invigoration to recognize the need for realism in what can of democracy will not solve all social and eco- be expected of democracy. Certainly, democ- nomic problems that societies face. But widening racy does not produce all good things. As Linz the scope of public deliberation, empowering observes, ‘‘political democracy does not neces- historically marginalized and alienated groups, sarily assure even a reasonable approximation of and increasing citizen competence and govern- what we would call a democratic society, a soci- ment responsiveness—reforms that deepen and ety with considerable equality of opportunity extend democracy—may increase the sophisti- in all spheres.’’64 As Schmitter and Karl argue, cation of mass publics and the legitimacy (and democracies are not necessarily more economi- hence the governing capacity) of elected o‰- cally or administratively e‰cient, or more or- derly and governable, than autocratic regimes.65 66. On civic competence and the challenges to improving it in contemporary, large-scale, complex, 64. Linz, The Breakdown of Democratic Regimes, 97. media-intensive, and information-saturated societies, Emphasis is mine. see Robert A. Dahl, ‘‘The Problem of Civic Compe- 65. Schmitter and Karl, ‘‘What Democracy Is,’’ tence,’’ Journal of Democracy 3, no. 4 (1992): 45–59. 85–87. Defining Democracy 39

cials.67 Beyond this, increasing citizen compe- eral, abusive, corrupt, exclusive, narrow, un- tence and participation in the political process responsive, and unaccountable. And liberal will spill over into other arenas of social life. democracies, too, can either improve or decline Civic engagement, such as participation in vol- in their levels of political accountability, ac- untary associations and community networks, cessibility, competitiveness, and responsiveness. generates trust, reciprocity, and cooperation, There is no guarantee that democratic develop- which reduce cynicism, encourage political par- ment moves in only one direction, and there ticipation, and facilitate economic development, is much to suggest that all political systems democratic stability, and the resolution of social (including democracies, liberal or otherwise) problems. Increasingly, social scientists view become rigid, corrupt, and unresponsive in the such social capital as a critical resource for deal- absence of periodic reform and renewal.70 ing with the seemingly intractable problems of Democracy not only may lose its quality, it poverty, alienation, and crime in the United may even e¤ectively disappear, not merely States and other industrialized democracies. through the breakdown of formal institutions Otherwise, ‘‘mutual distrust and defection, verti- but also through the more insidious processes of cal dependence and exploitation, isolation and decay. . . . disorder, criminality and backwardness [rein- force] one another in . . . interminable vicious 70. Such a developmental perspective may help to in- circles.’’68 oculate democratic theory against the tendency toward Viewed from a developmental perspective, teleological thinking that Guillermo O’Donnell dis- the fate of democracy is open-ended. The ele- cerns in the literature on democratic consolidation: ments of liberal democracy emerge in various that is, the underlying assumption that there is a sequences and degrees, at varying paces in the particular natural path and end state of democratic di¤erent countries.69 Democratic change can development. also move in di¤ering directions. Just as electoral democracies can become more democratic— more liberal, constitutional, competitive, ac- countable, inclusive, and participatory—so they can also become less democratic—more illib-

67. In their comparative study of the restructuring of property relations in postsocialist Eastern Europe, Postsocialist Pathways (Cambridge: Cambridge Uni- versity Press, 1997), Laszlo Bruszt and David Stark argue that policy coherence, e¤ectiveness, and sustain- ability are fostered when executives are constrained and reform policies are negotiated between govern- ments and ‘‘deliberative associations.’’ 68. Robert D. Putnam with Robert Leonardi and Ra¤aella Y. Nanetti, Making Democracy Work: Civic Traditions in Modern Italy (Princeton: Princeton Uni- versity Press, 1993), 181; see also Putnam, ‘‘Bowling Alone: America’s Declining Social Capital,’’ Journal of Democracy 6, no. 1 (1995): 65–78. See also chapter 6, this volume. 69. Sklar, ‘‘Developmental Democracy.’’ Participation and Democratic Theory

Carole Pateman

. . . At the beginning of the century the size that the outstanding characteristic of most citi- and complexity of industrialized societies and the zens, more especially those in the lower socio- emergence of bureaucratic forms of organisation economic status (SES) groups, is a general lack seemed to many empirically minded writers on of interest in politics and political activity and politics to cast grave doubts on the possibility of further, that widespread non-democratic or the attainment of democracy as that concept was authoritarian attitudes exist, again particularly usually understood. . . . among lower socio-economic status groups. The But by the middle of the century even the ideal conclusion drawn (often by political sociologists itself seemed to many to have been called in wearing political theorists’ hats) is that the question; at least, ‘‘democracy’’ was still the ‘‘classical’’ picture of democratic man is hope- ideal, but it was the emphasis on participation lessly unrealistic, and moreover, that in view of that had become suspect and with it the ‘‘clas- the facts about political attitudes, an increase sical’’ formulation of democratic theory. The in political participation by present non- collapse of the Weimar Republic, with its high participants could upset the stability of the dem- rates of mass participation, into fascism, and the ocratic system. post-war establishment of totalitarian regimes There was a further factor that helped along based on mass participation, albeit participation the process of the rejection of earlier democratic backed by intimidation and coercion, underlay theories, and that was the now familiar argument the tendency for ‘‘participation’’ to become that those theories were normative and ‘‘value- linked to the concept of totalitarianism rather laden,’’ whereas modern political theory should than that of democracy. The spectre of totali- be scientific and empirical, grounded firmly in tarianism also helps explain the concern with the the facts of political life. But even so, it may be necessary conditions for stability in a democratic doubted whether the revision of democratic polity, and a further factor here was the insta- theory would have been undertaken with such bility of so many states in the post-war world, enthusiasm by so many writers if it had not been especially ex-colonial states that rarely main- that this very question of the apparent contrast tained a democratic political system on Western between the facts of political life and attitudes lines. and their characterisation in earlier theories If this background had led to great doubts and had not already been taken up, and answered, reservations about earlier theories of democracy, by Joseph Schumpeter. His extraordinarily in- then the facts revealed by the post-war expansion fluential book Capitalism, Socialism and Democ- of political sociology appear to have convinced racy (1943) was in fact written before the vast most recent writers that these doubts were amounts of empirical information that we now fully justified. Data from large-scale empirical have on politics became available, but neverthe- investigations into political attitudes and behav- less Schumpeter considered that the facts showed iour, undertaken in most Western countries over that ‘‘classical’’ democratic theory was in need the past twenty or thirty years, have revealed of revision, and he provided just such a revised theory. More than that, however, and even Excerpted from: Carole Pateman, Participation and more importantly for the theories that followed, Democratic Theory. 6 Cambridge University Press, he put forward a new, realistic definition of 1970. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1970. democracy. . . . Reprinted with the permission of Cambridge Univer- The very great di¤erence between [participa- sity Press. tory] theories of democracy . . . and the theories Defining Democracy 41

of . . . theorists of representative government including both the psychological aspect and the makes it di‰cult to understand how the myth gaining of practice in democratic skills and pro- of one ‘‘classical’’ theory of democracy has sur- cedures. Thus there is no special problem about vived so long and is so vigorously propagated. the stability of a participatory system; it is self- The theories of participatory democracy . . . were sustaining through the educative impact of the not just essays in prescription as is often claimed, participatory process. Participation develops and rather they o¤er just those ‘‘plans of action and fosters the very qualities necessary for it; the specific prescriptions’’ for movement towards a more individuals participate the better able they (truly) democratic polity that it has been sug- become to do so. Subsidiary hypotheses about gested are lacking. But perhaps the strangest participation are that it has an integrative e¤ect criticism is that these earlier theorists were not, and that it aids the acceptance of collective as Berelson puts it, concerned with the ‘‘general decisions. features necessary if the (political) institutions Therefore, for a democratic polity to exist it is are to work as required,’’ and that they ignored necessary for a participatory society to exist, i.e. the political system as a whole in their work. It is a society where all political systems have been quite clear that this is precisely what they were democratised and socialisation through partici- concerned with. Although the variable identified pation can take place in all areas. The most im- as crucial in those theories for the successful portant area is industry; most individuals spend establishment and maintenance of a democratic a great deal of their lifetime at work and the political system, the authority structures of non- business of the workplace provides an education Governmental spheres of society, is exactly the in the management of collective a¤airs that it is same one that Eckstein indicates in his theory of di‰cult to parallel elsewhere. The second aspect stable democracy, the conclusions drawn from of the theory of participatory democracy is that this by the earlier and later theorists of democ- spheres such as industry should be seen as polit- racy are entirely di¤erent. In order that an eval- ical systems in their own right, o¤ering areas of uation of these two theories of democracy can participation additional to the national level. If be undertaken I shall now briefly set out (in a individuals are to exercise the maximum amount similar fashion to the contemporary theory of of control over their own lives and environment democracy above), a participatory theory of then authority structures in these areas must be democracy. . . . so organised that they can participate in decision The theory of participatory democracy is built making. A further reason for the central place of round the central assertion that individuals and industry in the theory relates to the substan- their institutions cannot be considered in isola- tive measure of economic equality required to tion from one another. The existence of repre- give the individual the independence and secu- sentative institutions at national level is not rity necessary for (equal) participation; the dem- su‰cient for democracy; for maximum partici- ocratising of industrial authority structures, pation by all the people at that level social- abolishing the permanent distinction between isation, or ‘‘social training,’’ for democracy must ‘‘managers’’ and ‘‘men’’ would mean a large step take place in other spheres in order that the toward meeting this condition. necessary individual attitudes and psychological The contemporary and participatory theories qualities can be developed. This development of democracy can be contrasted on every point of takes place through the process of participation substance, including the characterisation of ‘‘de- itself. The major function of participation in the mocracy’’ itself and the definition of ‘‘political,’’ theory of participatory democracy is therefore an which in the participatory theory is not confined educative one, educative in the very widest sense, to the usual national or local government sphere. Chapter 1 42

Again, in the participatory theory ‘‘participa- earlier theorists with these concerns in mind. tion’’ refers to (equal) participation in the mak- Any explanation of this would, no doubt, in- ing of decisions, and ‘‘political equality’’ refers to clude a mention of the widely held belief that equality of power in determining the outcome of (although these earlier theories are often said to decisions, a very di¤erent definition from that in be descriptive) ‘‘traditional’’ political theorists, the contemporary theory. Finally, the justifica- especially theorists of democracy, were engaged tion for a democratic system in the participatory in a largely prescriptive and ‘‘value-laden’’ en- theory of democracy rests primarily on the hu- terprise and their work is thus held to have little man results that accrue from the participatory direct interest for the modern, scientific, political process. One might characterise the participatory theorist. . . . model as one where maximum input (participa- tion) is required and where output includes not just policies (decisions) but also the development Conclusions of the social and political capacities of each in- dividual, so that there is ‘‘feedback’’ from output Recent discussions of the theory of democracy to input. have been obscured by the myth of the ‘‘classical Many of the criticisms of the so-called ‘‘clas- doctrine of democracy’’ propagated so success- sical’’ theory of democracy imply that the latter fully by Schumpeter. The failure to re-examine theory has only to be stated for it to become the notion of a ‘‘classical’’ theory has prevented obvious that it is unrealistic and outmoded. With a proper understanding of the arguments of the participatory theory of democracy this is far (some of ) the earlier theorists of democracy from the case; indeed, it has many features that about the central role of participation in the reflect some of the major themes and orienta- theory of democracy; prevented it even on the tions in recent political theory and political soci- part of writers who wished to defend a partici- ology. For example, the fact that it is a model of patory theory of democracy. This has meant that a self-sustaining system might make it attractive the prevailing academic orthodoxy on the sub- to the many writers on politics who, explicitly ject, the contemporary theory of democracy, has or implicitly, make use of such models. Again, not been subjected to substantive, rigorous criti- similarities between the participatory theory of cism, nor has a really convincing case been pre- democracy and recent theories of social plural- sented for the retention of a participatory theory ism are obvious enough, although these usually in the face of the facts of modern, large-scale argue only that ‘‘secondary’’ associations should political life. exist to mediate between the individual and the The major contribution to democratic theory national polity and say nothing about the au- of those ‘‘classical’’ theorists whom we have thority structures of those associations. The wide called the theorists of participatory democracy is definition of the ‘‘political’’ in the participatory to focus our attention on the interrelationship theory is also in keeping with the practice in between individuals and the authority structures modern political theory and political science. of institutions within which they interact. This is One of the advocates of the contemporary theory not to say that modern writers are completely of democracy discussed above, Dahl (1963, p. 6), unaware of this dimension; clearly this is not so, has defined a political system as ‘‘any persistent as much political sociology, especially that deal- pattern of human relationships that involves to ing with political socialisation, confirms, but the a significant extent power, rule or authority.’’ implications of the findings on socialisation for All this makes it very odd that no recent writer the contemporary theory of democracy have not on democratic theory appears to have reread the been appreciated. The link between these find- Defining Democracy 43

ings, particularly those on the development of anti-democratic arguments of the last century. the sense of political e‰cacy in adults and chil- No longer is democratic theory centred on the dren, and the notion of a ‘‘democratic character’’ participation of ‘‘the people,’’ on the participa- has been overlooked. Although many of the tion of the ordinary man, or the prime virtue of advocates of the contemporary theory of de- a democratic political system seen as the devel- mocracy argue that a certain type of character, opment of politically relevant and necessary or a set of psychological qualities or attitudes, qualities in the ordinary individual; in the con- is necessary for (stable) democracy—at least temporary theory of democracy it is the partici- among a proportion of the population—they are pation of the minority e´lite that is crucial and the far less clear on how this character could be non-participation of the apathetic, ordinary man developed or what the nature of its connection lacking in the feeling of political e‰cacy, that is with the working of the ‘‘democratic method’’ regarded as the main bulwark against instability. itself really is. While most do not support Apparently it has not occurred to recent theorists Schumpeter’s declaration that the democratic to wonder why there should be a positive corre- method and the democratic character are lation between apathy and low feelings of politi- unconnected, nor do they take much trouble to cal e‰cacy and low socio-economic status. It examine the nature of the postulated relation- would be more plausible to argue that the earlier ship. Even Almond and Verba, after clearly democratic theorists were unrealistic in their no- showing the connection between a participatory tion of the ‘‘democratic character’’ and in their environment and the development of a sense of claim that it was, given a certain institutional political e‰cacy, show no realisation of the sig- setting, open to every individual to develop in nificance of this in their final, theoretical chapter. this direction, if the persons today who do not However, this failure is only part of a more measure up to this standard were to be found in general, and striking, feature of much recent roughly equal proportions in all sections of the writing on democratic theory. Despite the stress community. The fact that they are not should most modern political theorists lay on the em- surely cause empirical political theorists to pause pirical and scientific nature of their discipline and ask why. they display, at least so far as democratic theory Once it is asked whether there might not be is concerned, a curious reluctance to look at the institutional factors that could provide an expla- facts in a questioning spirit. That is, they seem nation for the facts about apathy as suggested in reluctant to see whether or not a theoretical ex- the participatory theory of democracy, then the planation can be o¤ered of why the political argument from stability looks far less securely facts are as they are; instead they have taken it based. Most recent theorists have been content for granted that one theory which could possibly to accept Sartori’s assurance that the inactivity have yielded an explanation had already been of the ordinary man is ‘‘nobody’s fault’’ and to shown to be outmoded, and so concentrated on take the facts as given for the purpose of theory uncritically building a ‘‘realistic’’ theory to fit the building. Yet we have seen that the evidence facts as revealed by political sociology. supports the arguments of Rousseau, Mill and The result of this one-sided procedure has Cole that we do learn to participate by partic- been not only a democratic theory that has ipating and that feelings of political e‰cacy are unrecognised normative implications, implica- more likely to be developed in a participatory tions that set the existing Anglo-American polit- environment. Furthermore, the evidence indi- ical system as our democratic ideal, but it has cates that experience of a participatory authority also resulted in a ‘‘democratic’’ theory that in structure might also be e¤ective in diminishing many respects bears a strange resemblance to the tendencies toward non-democratic attitudes in Chapter 1 44

the individual. If those who come newly into the ment is compatible with either theory, the two political arena have been previously ‘‘educated’’ theories of democracy remain in conflict over for it then their participation will pose no dan- their most important aspect, over their respective gers to the stability of the system. Oddly enough, definitions of a democratic polity. Is it solely the this evidence against the argument from stability presence of competing leaders at national level should be welcomed by some writers defending for whom the electorate can periodically vote, or the contemporary theory, for they occasionally does it also require that a participatory society remark that they deplore the low levels of politi- exist, a society so organised that every individual cal participation and interest that now obtain. has the opportunity directly to participate in all The argument from stability has only seemed political spheres? We have not, of course, set out as convincing as it has because the evidence to prove that it is one or the other; what we have relating to the psychological e¤ects of participa- been considering is whether the idea of a partic- tion has never been considered in relation to the ipatory society is as completely unrealistic as issues of political, more specifically, democratic those writers contend who press for a revision of theory. Both sides in the current discussion of the the participatory theory of democracy. role of participation in modern theory of de- The notion of a participatory society requires mocracy have grasped half of the theory of par- that the scope of the term ‘‘political’’ is extended ticipatory democracy; the defenders of the earlier to cover spheres outside national government. theorists have emphasised that their goal was the It has already been pointed out that many polit- production of an educated, active citizenry and ical theorists do argue for just such an extension. the theorists of contemporary democracy have Unfortunately this wider definition, and more pointed to the importance of the structure of importantly its implications for political theory, authority in non-governmental spheres for polit- are usually forgotten when these same theorists ical socialisation. But neither side has realised turn their attention to democratic theory. Rec- that the two aspects are connected or realised the ognition of industry as a political system in its significance of the empirical evidence for their own right at once removes many of the confused arguments. ideas that exist about democracy (and its rela- However, the socialisation aspect of the par- tion to participation) in the industrial context. Its ticipatory theory of democracy is also capable rules out the use of ‘‘democratic’’ to describe a of being absorbed into the general framework of friendly approach by supervisors that ignores the the contemporary theory, providing the founda- authority structure within which this approach tion for a more soundly based theory of stable occurs, and it also rules out the argument that democracy than those o¤ered at present. The insists that industrial democracy already exists analysis of participation in the industrial con- on the basis of a spurious comparison with na- text has made it clear that only a relatively tional politics. There is very little in the empirical minor modification of existing authority struc- evidence on which to base the assertion that in- tures there may be necessary for the development dustrial democracy, full higher level participa- of the sense of political e‰cacy. It is quite con- tion, is impossible. On the other hand there is a ceivable, given recent theories of management, great deal to suggest that there are many di‰- that partial participation at the lower level may culties and complexities involved. . . . become widespread in well-run enterprises in the The major di‰culty in a discussion of the em- future because of the multiplicity of advantages pirical possibilities of democratising industrial it appears to bring for e‰ciency and the capacity authority structures is that we do not have su‰- of the enterprise to adapt to changing circum- cient information on a participatory system that stances. Nevertheless, if the socialisation argu- contains opportunities for participation at both Defining Democracy 45

the higher and lower levels to test some of the young worker the opportunity to participate in arguments of the participatory theory of democ- the workplace are convincing then there is a racy satisfactorily. . . . good case for giving his contemporary, the stu- Today, the question of economic e‰ciency is dent, similar opportunities; both are the mature bound to loom very large in any discussion of citizens of the future. One person whom the the issues involved in democratising industrial opportunities for participation in industry would authority structures; in particular how far the pass by is the full-time housewife. She might find economic equality implied in a system of indus- opportunities to participate at the local gov- trial democracy would be compatible with e‰- ernment level, especially if these opportunities ciency. Economic equality is often dismissed as included the field of housing, particularly public of little relevance to democracy yet once industry housing. The problems of running large housing is recognised as a political system in its own right developments would seem to give wide scope to then it is clear that a substantive measure of residents for participation in decision making economic equality is necessary. If inequalities in and the psychological e¤ects of such partici- decision-making power are abolished the case for pation might prove extremely valuable in this other forms of economic inequality becomes context. There is little point in drawing up a correspondingly weaker. . . . catalogue of possible areas of participation but We have considered the possibility of estab- these examples do give an indication of how a lishing a participatory society with respect to one move might be made toward a participatory area only, that of industry, but because industry society. occupies a vitally important place in the theory A defender of the contemporary theory of de- of participatory democracy, that is su‰cient to mocracy might object at this point that although establish the validity, or otherwise of the notion the idea of a participatory society might not be of a participatory society. The analysis of the completely unrealistic, this does not a¤ect his concept of participation presented here can be definition of democracy. Even though authority applied to other spheres, although the empirical structures in industry, and perhaps other areas, questions raised by the extension of participation were democratised this would have little e¤ect to areas other than industry cannot be consid- on the role of the individual; this would still be ered. Nevertheless, it might be useful to indicate confined, our objector might argue, to a choice briefly some of the possibilities in this direction. between competing leaders or representatives. To begin, as it were, at the beginning, with the The paradigm of direct participation would have family. Modern theories of child-rearing . . . have no application even in a participatory society. . . . helped to influence family life, especially among [W]ithin the industrial context, this objection middle-class families, in a more democratic di- is misplaced. Where a participatory industrial rection than before. But if the general trend is system allowed both higher and lower level par- toward participation the educative e¤ects arising ticipation then there would be scope for the in- from this may be nullified if the later experiences dividual directly to participate in a wide range of of the individual do not work in the same direc- decisions while at the same time being part of a tion. The most urgent demands for more par- representative system; the one does not preclude ticipation in recent years have come from the the other. students and clearly these demands are very rel- If this is the case where the alternative areas of evant to our general argument. With regard to participation are concerned, there is an obvious the introduction of a participatory system in sense in which the objection is valid at the level of institutions of higher education, it is su‰cient to the national political system. In an electorate of, note here that if the arguments for giving the say, thirty-five million the role of the individual Chapter 1 46

must consist almost entirely of choosing rep- participatory society the significance of his vote resentatives; even where he could cast a vote in to the individual would have changed; as well as a referendum his influence over the outcome being a private individual he would have multi- would be infinitesimally small. Unless the size of ple opportunities to become an educated, public national political units were drastically reduced citizen. then that piece of reality is not open to change. It is this ideal, an ideal with a long history In another sense, however, this objection misses in political thought, that has become lost from the point because it rests on a lack of apprecia- view in the contemporary theory of democracy. tion of the importance of the participatory Not surprisingly perhaps when for some recent theory of democracy for modern, large scale, writers such a wide-ranging democratic ideal is industrialised societies. In the first place it is only regarded as ‘‘dangerous,’’ and they recommend if the individual has the opportunity directly to that we pitch our standards of what might be participate in decision making and choose rep- achieved in democratic political life only mar- resentatives in the alternative areas that, under ginally above what already exists. The claim that modern conditions, he can hope to have any real the Anglo-American political system tackles dif- control over the course of his life or the devel- ficult questions with distinction looks rather less opment of the environment in which he lives. Of plausible since, for example, the events in the course, it is true that exactly the same decisions American cities of the late 1960s or the discovery are not made, for example, in the workplace as in Britain that in the midst of a¿uence many in the House of Commons or the Cabinet, but citizens are not only poor but also homeless, one may agree with Schumpeter and his fol- than it may have done in the late 1950s and early lowers in this respect at least: that it is doubtful if 1960s, but such a statement could have only the average citizen will ever be as interested in all seemed a ‘‘realistic’’ description then because the decisions made at national level as he would questions were never asked about certain fea- in those made nearer home. But having said that, tures of the system or certain aspects of the data the important point is, secondly, that the oppor- collected, despite the much emphasised empirical tunity to participate in the alternative areas basis of the new theory. In sum, the contempo- would mean that one piece of reality would have rary theory of democracy represents a consider- changed, namely the context within which all able failure of the political and sociological political activity was carried on. The argument imagination on the part of recent theorists of of the participatory theory of democracy is democracy. that participation in the alternative areas would When the problem of participation and its role enable the individual better to appreciate the in democratic theory is placed in a wider context connection between the public and the private than that provided by the contemporary theory spheres. The ordinary man might still be more of democracy, and the relevant empirical mate- interested in things nearer home, but the exis- rial is related to the theoretical issues, it becomes tence of a participatory society would mean clear that neither the demands for more partici- that he was better able to assess the performance pation, nor the theory of participatory democ- of representatives at the national level, better racy itself, are based, as is so frequently claimed, equipped to take decisions of national scope on dangerous illusions or on an outmoded when the opportunity arose to do so, and better and unrealistic theoretical foundation. We can able to weigh up the impact of decisions taken still have a modern, viable theory of democracy by national representatives on his own life and which retains the notion of participation at its immediate surroundings. In the context of a heart. Defining Democracy 47

Bibliography

Blumberg, P. (1968), Industrial Democracy: The Soci- ology of Participation, Constable, London. Dahl, R. A. (1963), Modern Political Analysis, Prentice-Hall, New Jersey. Schumpeter, J. A. (1943), Capitalism, Socialism and Democracy, Geo. Allen & Unwin, London. Polyarchal Democracy

Robert Dahl

one necessary procedural rule for the perfect or I ideal attainment of political equality and popu- lar sovereignty; but because the theory is no Examination of Madisonian and populistic more than an exercise in axiomatics, it tells us theory suggests at least two possible methods one nothing about the real world. However, let us might employ to construct a theory of democ- now pose the key question in slightly di¤erent racy. One way, the method of maximization, is to form: What are the necessary and su‰cient con- specify a set of goals to be maximized; democ- ditions for maximizing democracy in the real racy can then be defined in terms of the specific world? I shall show that the words ‘‘in the real governmental processes necessary to maximize world’’ fundamentally alter the problem. these goals or some among them. . . . Madisonian Let us begin, however, with a meticulous con- theory postulates a non-tyrannical republic as cern for precision of meaning. First, what do we the goal to be maximized; populistic theory pos- mean by ‘‘maximizing democracy’’? Evidently tulates popular sovereignty and political equal- here, . . . we must proceed by regarding democ- ity. A second way—this one might be called the racy as a state of a¤airs constituting a limit, and descriptive method—is to consider as a single all actions approaching the limit will be max- class of phenomena all those nation states and imizing actions. But how shall we describe the social organizations that are commonly called state of a¤airs constituting the limit? democratic by political scientists, and by exam- The model of populistic democracy suggests ining the members of this class to discover, first, three possible characteristics that might be made the distinguishing characteristics they have in operationally meaningful: (1) Whenever policy common, and, second, the necessary and su‰- choices are perceived to exist, the alternative cient conditions for social organizations possess- selected and enforced as governmental policy is ing these characteristics. the alternative most preferred by the members. These are not, however, mutually exclusive (2) Whenever policy choices are perceived to ex- methods. And we shall see that if we begin by ist, in the process of choosing the alternative to employing the first method it will soon become be enforced as government policy, the preference necessary to employ something rather like the of each member is assigned an equal value. (3) second as well. The Rule: In choosing among alternatives, the alternative preferred by the greater number is II selected. To make the first of these operational we must . . . [T]he goals of populistic democracy and the either ignore the problem of di¤erent intensities simple Rule deduced from these goals do not of preference among individuals or find ourselves provide us with anything like a complete theory. in so deep a morass of obstacles to observation One basic defect of the theory is that it does no and comparison that it would be very nearly im- more than to provide a formal redefinition of possible to say whether or not the characteristic in fact exists. I shall return to this problem in the next chapter. But if we ignore intensities, then in Excerpted from: Robert Dahl, A Preface to Democratic e¤ect we adopt the second characteristic as our Theory. Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1956. 6 1956. The University of Chicago. Reprinted by criterion: that the preference of each member is permission. assigned an equal value. It would appear at first Defining Democracy 49

glance that the question whether the preference extreme, through deep and careful probing we of each member of an organization is assigned could search for psychological evidence. If the an equal value is more or less susceptible of ob- first is often naı¨ve, the second is impossible on servation. Likewise the third characteristic, the a su‰cient scale. In practice most of us adopt Rule, should be observable. But since the Rule a middle course and take our clues from the is deducible from the first two characteristics, prevailing environment in which the particular would it not be enough simply to examine a so- preference is expressed. In one environment we cial organization in order to discover the extent accept the overt act of voting as an adequate to which the Rule is or is not followed? That is, if imperfect index; in another we reject it do we have in the Rule an adequate definition of entirely. . . . the limit of democracy? Suppose we observe that a majority prefers x to y, and x happens to be selected as government policy. Yet it may be III that among the majority is a dictator; if he were in the minority, then y would be selected. The The e¤ect of the argument so far is to divide our condition of political equality evidently requires key question into two: (1) What acts shall we ‘‘interchangeability,’’ i.e., the interchange of consider su‰cient to constitute an expression an equal number of individuals from one side to of individual preferences at a given stage in the another would not a¤ect the outcome of the decision process? (2) Taking these acts as an decision. But how can we observe whether inter- expression of preferences, what events must we changeability is present? Evidently no single de- observe in order to determine the extent to which cision provides us with enough information, for the Rule is employed in the organization we at best a single decision can only reveal that the are examining? We are still looking, let us re- Rule is not being followed and that political member, for a set of limiting conditions to be equality therefore does not exist during that de- approached. cision. We can infer interchangeability only by At a minimum, two stages need to be dis- examining a large number of cases. . . . tinguished: the election stage3 and the interelec- . . . If we take any specific action, such as tion stage. The election stage in turn consists of the outcome of balloting, as a satisfactory index at least three periods which it is useful to distin- of preference, then no operational tests exist for guish: the voting period, the prevoting period, determining political equality, other than those and the postvoting period. . . . necessary for determining whether the Rule is or During the voting period we would need to is not being followed. That is, given the expres- observe the extent to which at least three con- sion of preferences as adequate, the only opera- ditions exist: tional test for political equality is the extent 1. Every member of the organization performs to which the Rule is followed in a number of the acts we assume to constitute an expression cases. . . . What events must we observe in the real world in order to determine the extent to which the Rule is employed in an organization? 1. More accurately, in using votes and opinion polls we generally rely on some overt statements of individ- Unfortunately, the phrase ‘‘given the expres- uals who compile the returns. sion of preferences’’ harbors some serious di‰- 3. Election is used here in a broad sense. To apply the culties. What kinds of activity shall we take as analysis to the internal operation of an organization indices of preference? At one extreme we could that is itself constituted through elections, such as a rely on some overt act of choosing, such as cast- legislative body, one would consider votes on measures ing a ballot or making a statement.1 At the other as ‘‘the election stage.’’ Chapter 1 50

of preference among the scheduled alternatives, At first glance it might be thought that these e.g., voting. five conditions are su‰cient to guarantee the 2. In tabulating these expressions (votes), the operation of the Rule; but, at least in principle, it weight assigned to the choice of each individual would be possible for a regime to permit these is identical. conditions to operate through the prevoting and voting periods and then simply to ignore the 3. The alternative with the greatest number of results. Consequently, we must postulate at least votes is declared the winning choice. two more conditions for the postvoting period . . . [I]t is self-evident that we have thus far both of which are su‰ciently obvious to need no begged the first of our questions. A totalitarian discussion: plebiscite might meet—and indeed in practice 6. Alternatives (leaders or policies) with the evidently often has met—these three conditions greatest number of votes displace any alterna- better than a national election or legislative de- tives (leaders or policies) with fewer votes. cision in countries that most Western political scientists would call democratic. The crux of the 7. The orders of elected o‰cials are executed. problem is in our first question, what we take to These, then, constitute our set of more or less constitute an expression of individual preference. observable limiting conditions which when pres- Can it not be truthfully said that the peasant ent during the election stage will be taken as ev- who casts his ballot for the dictatorship is idence for the maximal operation of the Rule, expressing his preferences among the scheduled which in turn is taken as evidence for the maxi- alternatives as he sees them? For, perhaps, the mal attainment of political equality and popular alternatives he sees are either to vote for the dic- sovereignty. What of the interelection stage? If tatorship or to take a journey to Siberia. . . . our argument so far is correct, then maximiza- What we balk at in accepting the vote of the tion of political equality and popular sovereignty Soviet citizen as an expression of preference is in the interelection stage would require: that he is not permitted to choose among all the alternatives that we, as outside observers, regard 8.1. Either that all interelection decisions are as in some sense potentially available to him. . . . subordinate or executory to those arrived at What we have done, then, is to formulate a during the election stage, i.e., elections are in a fourth limiting condition, one that must exist in sense controlling the prevoting period governing the scheduling of 8.2. Or that new decisions during the interelec- alternatives for the voting period. tion period are governed by the preceding seven 4. Any member who perceives a set of alterna- conditions, operating, however, under rather tives, at least one of which he regards as pref- di¤erent institutional circumstances erable to any of the alternatives presently 8.3. Or both. scheduled, can insert his preferred alternative(s) among those scheduled for voting. IV . . . [W]e must lay down a fifth condition operating in the prevoting period. I think it may be laid down dogmatically that no human organization—certainly none with more 5. All individuals possess identical information than a handful of people—has ever met or is about the alternatives. ever likely to meet these eight conditions. It is ... true that the second, third, and sixth conditions Defining Democracy 51

are quite precisely met in some organizations, tively studied by political scientists, and these although in the United States corrupt practices have been the most di‰cult of all, the govern- sometimes nullify even these; the others are, at ments of national states, and in a few instances best, only crudely approximated. . . . the smaller governmental units. . . . Because human organizations rarely and per- . . . What are the necessary and su‰cient con- haps never reach the limit set by these eight ditions in the real world for the existence of these conditions, it is necessary to interpret each of eight conditions, to at least the minimum degree the conditions as one end of a continuum or we have agreed to call polyarchy? . . . scale along which any given organization might be measured. Unfortunately there is at present no known way of assigning meaningful weights V to the eight conditions. However, even without weights, if the eight scales could each be metri- . . . [W]e can set down some hypotheses for cized, it would be possible and perhaps useful which considerable evidence exists. to establish some arbitrary but not meaningless . . . It would seem truistic that if all the mem- classes of which the upper chunk might be called bers of an organization rejected the norms pre- ‘‘polyarchies.’’ scribing the eight conditions, then the conditions It is perfectly evident, however, that what would not exist; or alternatively, the extent to has just been described is no more than a pro- which polyarchy exists must be related to the gram, for nothing like it has, I think, ever been extent to which the norms are accepted as desir- attempted. I shall simply set down here, there- able. If we are willing to assume that the extent fore, the following observations. Organizations of agreement (consensus) on the eight basic do in fact di¤er markedly in the extent to which norms is measurable, then we can formulate the they approach the limits set by these eight con- following hypotheses, which have been com- ditions. Furthermore, ‘‘polyarchies’’ include a monplace in the literature of political science: variety of organizations which Western politi- 1. Each of the conditions of polyarchy increases cal scientists would ordinarily call democratic, with the extent of agreement (or consensus) on including certain aspects of the governments of the relevant norm. nation states such as the United States, Great Britain, the Dominions (South Africa possibly 2. Polyarchy is a function of consensus on the 11 excepted), the Scandinavian countries, Mexico, eight norms, other things remaining the same. Italy, and France; states and provinces, such as Unfortunately for the simplicity of the hypoth- the states of this country and the provinces of eses, consensus possesses at least three dimen- Canada; numerous cities and towns; some trade- sions: the number of individuals who agree, the unions; numerous associations such as Parent- intensity or depth of their belief, and the extent Teachers’ Associations, chapters of the League to which overt activity conforms with belief. . . . of Women Voters, and some religious groups; The extent of agreement, in turn, must be and some primitive societies. Thus it follows that functionally dependent upon the extent to which the number of polyarchies is large. (The number the various processes for social training are of egalitarian polyarchies is probably relatively employed on behalf of the norms by the family, small or perhaps none exist at all.) The number of polyarchies must run well over a hundred and 11. Appendix E to this chapter raises some questions probably well over a thousand. Of this number, about treating polyarchy as positive and increasing however, only a tiny handful has been exhaus- with both consensus and political activity. Chapter 1 52

schools, churches, clubs, literature, newspapers, exists on the norms. The more disagreement and the like. Again, if it were possible to measure there is about the norms, the more likely it is that the extent to which these processes are used, our some of the means of social training—the family hypotheses could be stated as: and the school in particular—will train some individuals in conflicting norms. The relationship 3. The extent of agreement (consensus) on each between social training and consensus is thus a of the eight norms increases with the extent of perfect instance of the hen-and-egg problem. social training in the norm. Hence: 4. Consensus is therefore a function of the total social training in all the norms. 8. The extent of social training in one of the eight norms also increases with the extent of It also follows from the preceding hypotheses agreement on it. that: ... 5. Polyarchy is a function of the total social Now the extent of agreement cannot be con- training in all the norms.12 sidered entirely independently of the extent of political activity in an organization. The extent . . . It is reasonable to suppose that the less the to which some of the conditions for polyarchy— agreement on policy choices, the more di‰cult 1, 4, and 5—are met is also a measure of the it will be in any organization to train members political activity of members, that is, the extent in the eight norms. For then, although the oper- to which they vote in elections and primaries, ation of the rules may confer benefits on some participate in campaigns, and seek and dissem- members, it will impose severe restraints on inate information and propaganda. Thus by others. If the results are severe for relatively large definition: numbers, then it is reasonable to suppose that those who su¤er from the operation of the rules 9. Polyarchy is a function of the political activity will oppose them and hence resist training in of the members.18 them. Thus: A good deal is now known about the variables 6. Social training in the eight norms increases with which political activity is associated. . . . At with the extent of consensus or agreement on present we know that political activity, at least in choices among policy alternatives. the United States, is positively associated to a significant extent with such variables as income, From 5 and 6 it follows that: socio-economic status, and education, and that 7. One or more of the conditions of polyarchy it is also related in complex ways with belief increases with consensus on policy alternatives. systems, expectations, and personality structures. We now know that members of the ignorant and Hypothesis 6 suggests, moreover, that the re- unpropertied masses which Madison and his verse of Hypothesis 4 is also valid. We would colleagues so much feared are considerably less expect that the extent to which social training active politically than the educated and well-to- in the norms is indulged in is itself dependent do. By their propensity for political passivity the upon the amount of agreement that already 18. For an important complexity in this hypothetical 12. For a ‘‘Summary of the hypothetical functions function, see Appendix E to this chapter, ‘‘A note on relating polyarchy to its preconditions’’ see Appendix the relation between agreement and political activity.’’ C to this chapter. Defining Democracy 53

poor and uneducated disfranchise themselves.19 Since they also have less access than the wealthy to the organizational, financial, and propaganda resources that weigh so heavily in campaigns, elections, legislative, and executive decisions, anything like equal control over government policy is triply barred to the members of Madi- son’s unpropertied masses. They are barred by their relatively greater inactivity, by their rela- tively limited access to resources, and by Madi- son’s nicely contrived system of constitutional checks.

VI

. . . Because we are taught to believe in the necessity of constitutional checks and balances, we place little faith in social checks and balances. We admire the e‰cacy of constitutional separa- tion of powers in curbing majorities and minor- ities, but we often ignore the importance of the restraints imposed by social . Yet if the theory of polyarchy is roughly sound, it follows that in the absence of certain social prerequisites, no constitutional arrangements can produce a nontyrannical republic. The history of numerous Latin-American states is, I think, su‰cient evidence. Conversely, an increase in the extent to which one of the social prerequisites is present may be far more important in strength- ening democracy than any particular constitu- tional design. Whether we are concerned with tyranny by a minority or tyranny by a majority, the theory of polyarchy suggests that the first and crucial variables to which political scientists must direct their attention are social and not constitutional. . . .

19. Cf. especially B. R. Berelson, P. F. Lazarsfeld, and W. N. McPhee, [Voting (Chicago: Chicago University Press, 1954)]; S. M. Lipset et al., ‘‘The Psychology of Voting: An Analysis of Political Behavior,’’ Handbook of Social Psychology (Cambridge: Addison-Wesley, 1954).

2 SOURCES OF DEMOCRACY

Political Man: The Social Bases of Politics Seymour Martin Lipset

Social Revolutions in the Modern World Theda Skocpol

The Impact of Economic Development on Democracy Evelyne Huber, Dietrich Rueschemeyer, and John D. Stephens

Democracy and the Market: Political and Economic Reforms in Eastern Europe and Latin America Adam Przeworski

Democracy’s Third Wave Samuel P. Huntington

South Africa’s Negotiated Transition: Democracy, Opposition, and the New Constitutional Order Courtney Jung and Ian Shapiro

Economic Development and Political Regimes Adam Przeworski, Michael E. Alvarez, Jose´ Antonio Cheibub, and Fernando Limongi Political Man: The Social Bases of Politics

Seymour Martin Lipset

motor vehicle compared to 143 for the less dem- Economic Development and Democracy ocratic. In the less dictatorial Latin-American countries there are 99 persons per motor vehicle Democracy in a complex society may be defined versus 274 for the more dictatorial.10 Income as a political system which supplies regular con- di¤erences for the groups are also sharp, drop- stitutional opportunities for changing the gov- ping from an average per capita income of $695 erning o‰cials, and a social mechanism which permits the largest possible part of the popula- tion to influence major decisions by choosing 9. Lyle W. Shannon has correlated indices of eco- among contenders for political o‰ce. . . . nomic development with whether a country is self- governing or not, and his conclusions are substantially Perhaps the most common generalization the same. Since Shannon does not give details on the linking political systems to other aspects of soci- countries categorized as self-governing and nonself- ety has been that democracy is related to the governing, there is no direct measure of the relation state of economic development. The more well- between ‘‘democratic’’ and ‘‘self-governing’’ countries. to-do a nation, the greater the chances that it will All the countries examined in this chapter, however, sustain democracy. . . . were chosen on the assumption that a characterization To test this hypothesis concretely, I have used as ‘‘democratic’’ is meaningless for a nonself-governing various indices of economic development— country, and therefore, presumably, all of them, wealth, industrialization, urbanization, and edu- whether democratic or dictatorial, would fall within cation—and computed averages (means) for the Shannon’s ‘‘self-governing’’ category. Shannon shows that underdevelopment is related to lack of self- countries which have been classified as more or government; my data indicate that once self- less democratic in the Anglo-Saxon world and government is attained, development is still related to Europe, and in Latin America. the character of the political system. See the book In each case, the average wealth, degree of edited by Shannon, Underdeveloped Areas (New industrialization and urbanization, and level of York: Harper & Bros., 1957), and also his article, ‘‘Is education is much higher for the more demo- Level of Development Related to Capacity for Self- cratic countries. . . . If I had combined Latin Government?’’ American Journal of Economics and America and Europe . . . the di¤erences would Sociology, 17 (1958), pp. 367–382. In the latter paper have been even greater.9 Shannon constructs a composite index of development, The main indices of wealth used are per capita using some of the same indices, such as inhabitants per physician, and derived from the same United Nations income, number of persons per motor vehicle sources, as appear in the tables to follow. Shannon’s and thousands of persons per physician, and the work did not come to my attention until after this number of radios, telephones, and newspapers chapter was first prepared, so that the two analyses per thousand persons. The di¤erences are strik- can be considered as separate tests of comparable ing on every score. . . . In the more democratic hypotheses. European countries, there are 17 persons per 10. It must be remembered that these figures are means, compiled from census figures for the various Excerpted from: Seymour Martin Lipset, Political countries. The data vary widely in accuracy, and there Man: The Social Bases of Politics, pp. 33–53. Balti- is no way of measuring the validity of compound cal- more: The Johns Hopkins University Press, 1981. 6 culated figures such as those presented here. The con- 1959, 1960, 1981 by Seymour Martin Lipset. Reprinted sistent direction of all these di¤erences, and their large by permission of The Johns Hopkins University Press. magnitude, is the main indication of validity. Sources of Democracy 57

for the more democratic countries of Europe to metropolitan areas. On all three of these indices $308 for the less democratic; the corresponding the more democratic countries score higher than di¤erence for Latin America is from $171 to the less democratic for both of the areas under $119. The ranges are equally consistent, with the investigation. lowest per capita income in each group falling in Many people have suggested that the higher the ‘‘less democratic’’ category, and the highest the education level of a nation’s population, in the ‘‘more democratic.’’ the better the chances for democracy, and the Industrialization, to which indices of wealth comparative data available support this propo- are of course clearly related, is measured by the sition. The ‘‘more democratic’’ countries of percentage of employed males in agriculture and Europe are almost entirely literate: the lowest the per capita commercially produced ‘‘energy’’ has a rate of 96 percent; while the ‘‘less demo- being used in the country (measured in terms of cratic’’ nations have an average rate of 85 per- tons of coal per person per year). Both of these cent. In Latin America the di¤erence is between show equally consistent results. The average an average rate of 74 percent for the ‘‘less dicta- percentage of employed males working in agri- torial’’ countries and 46 percent for the ‘‘more culture and related occupations was 21 in the dictatorial.’’12 The educational enrollment per ‘‘more democratic’’ European countries and 41 thousand total population at three di¤erent in the ‘‘less democratic’’; 52 in the ‘‘less dicta- levels—primary, post-primary, and higher edu- torial’’ Latin-American countries and 67 in the cational—is equally consistently related to the ‘‘more dictatorial.’’ The di¤erences in per capita degree of democracy. The tremendous disparity energy employed are equally large. is shown by the extreme cases of Haiti and the The degree of urbanization is also related to United States. Haiti has fewer children (11 per the existence of democracy.11 Three di¤erent thousand) attending school in the primary grades indices of urbanization are available from data than the United States has attending colleges compiled by International Urban Research (almost 18 per thousand). (Berkeley, California): the percentage of the The relationship between education and de- population in communities of 20,000 and over, mocracy is worth more extensive treatment since the percentage in communities of 100,000 and an entire philosophy of government has seen over, and the percentage residing in standard increased education as the basic requirement of democracy.13 As James Bryce wrote, with special 11. Urbanization has often been linked to democracy by political theorists. Harold J. Laski asserted that 12. The pattern indicated by a comparison of the ‘‘organized democracy is the product of urban life,’’ averages for each group of countries is sustained by the and that it was natural therefore that it should have ranges (the high and low extremes) for each index. ‘‘made its first e¤ective appearance’’ in the Greek city Most of the ranges overlap; that is, some countries states, limited as was their definition of ‘‘citizen.’’ See which are in the ‘‘less democratic’’ category are higher his article ‘‘Democracy’’ in the Encyclopedia of the on any given index than some which are ‘‘more demo- Social Sciences (New York: Macmillan, 1937), Vol. V, cratic.’’ It is noteworthy that in both Europe and Latin pp. 76–85. Max Weber held that the city, as a certain America, the nations which are lowest on any of the type of political community, is a peculiarly Western indices presented in the table are also in the ‘‘less phenomenon, and traced the emergence of the notion democratic’’ category. Conversely, almost all countries of ‘‘citizenship’’ from social developments closely which rank at the top of any of the indices are in the related to urbanization. For a partial statement of ‘‘more democratic’’ class. his point of view, see the chapter on ‘‘Citizenship’’ in 13. See John Dewey, Democracy and Education (New General Economic History (Glencoe: The Free Press, York: Macmillan, 1916). 1950), pp. 315–338. Chapter 2 58

reference to South America, ‘‘education, if it vant studies indicate that education is more sig- does not make men good citizens, makes it at nificant than either income or occupation. least easier for them to become so.’’14 Education These findings should lead us to anticipate a presumably broadens man’s outlook, enables far higher correlation between national levels of him to understand the need for norms of toler- education and political practice than we in fact ance, restrains him from adhering to extremist find. and France have been among doctrines, and increases his capacity to make the best educated nations of Europe, but this by rational electoral choices. itself did not stabilize their democracies.16 It The evidence on the contribution of education may be, however, that their educational level has to democracy is even more direct and strong on served to inhibit other antidemocratic forces. the level of individual behavior within countries If we cannot say that a ‘‘high’’ level of educa- than it is in cross-national correlations. Data tion is a su‰cient condition for democracy, the gathered by public opinion research agencies available evidence suggests that it comes close to which have questioned people in di¤erent coun- being a necessary one. In Latin America, where tries about their beliefs on tolerance for the op- widespread illiteracy still exists, only one of all position, their attitudes toward ethnic or racial the nations in which more than half the popula- minorities, and their feelings for multi-party as tion is illiterate—Brazil—can be included in the against one-party systems have showed that the ‘‘more democratic’’ group. . . . most important single factor di¤erentiating those Although the evidence has been presented giving democratic responses from the others has separately, all the various aspects of econom- been education. The higher one’s education, the ic development—industrialization, urbanization, more likely one is to believe in democratic values and support democratic practices.15 All the rele- 15. See G. H. Smith, ‘‘Liberalism and Level of Infor- mation,’’ Journal of Educational Psychology, 39 (1948), 14. James Bryce, South America: Observations and pp. 65–82; Martin A. Trow, Right Wing Radicalism Impressions (New York: Macmillan, 1912), p. 546. and Political Intolerance (Ph.D. thesis, Department of Bryce considered several classes of conditions in South Sociology, Columbia University, 1957), p. 17; Samuel America which a¤ected the chances for democracy, A. Stou¤er, Communism, Conformity, and Civil Lib- some of which are substantially the same as those pre- erties (New York: Doubleday & Co., Inc., 1955); sented here. The physical conditions of a country de- Kotaro Kido and Masataka Sugi, ‘‘A Report of Re- termined the ease of communications between areas, search on Social Stratification and Mobility in Tokyo’’ and thus the ease of formation of a ‘‘common public (III), Japanese Sociological Review, 4 (1954), pp. 74– opinion.’’ By ‘‘racial’’ conditions Bryce really meant 100. This point is also discussed in Chap. 4. whether there was ethnic homogeneity or not, with the 16. Dewey has suggested that the character of the existence of di¤erent ethnic or language groups pre- educational system will influence its e¤ect on democ- venting that ‘‘homogeneity and solidarity of the com- racy, and this may shed some light on the sources of munity which are almost indispensable conditions instability in Germany. The purpose of German edu- to the success of democratic government.’’ Economic cation, according to Dewey, writing in 1916, was one and social conditions included economic development, of ‘‘disciplinary training rather than of personal devel- widespread political participation, and literacy. Bryce opment.’’ The main aim was to produce ‘‘absorption also detailed the specific historical factors which, over of the aims and meaning of existing institutions,’’ and and above these ‘‘general’’ factors, operated in each ‘‘thoroughgoing subordination’’ to them. This point South American country. See James Bryce, op. cit., pp. raises issues which cannot be entered into here, but 527–533 and 580 ¤. See also Karl Mannheim, Free- indicates the complex character of the relationship be- dom, Power and Democratic Planning (New York: Ox- tween democracy and closely related factors, such as ford University Press, 1950). education. See John Dewey, op. cit., pp. 108–110. Sources of Democracy 59

wealth, and education—are so closely inter- capita income mark in 1949—France, Iceland, related as to form one major factor which has Czechoslovakia, Finland, West Germany, Hun- the political correlate of democracy.18 ... gary, Italy, and Austria—and which have had Economic development, producing increased at least one postwar democratic election in income, greater economic security, and wide- which both communist and noncommunist spread higher education, largely determines the parties could compete, the Communist party has form of the ‘‘class struggle,’’ by permitting those had more than 16 percent of the vote in six, and in the lower strata to develop longer time per- an over-all average of more than 20 percent in spectives and more complex and gradualist views the eight countries as a group. The two low- of politics. A belief in secular reformist gradual- income countries in which the Communists are ism can be the ideology of only a relatively well- weak—Germany and Austria—have both had to-do lower class. Striking evidence for this thesis direct experience with Soviet occupation.24 may be found in the relationship between the Leftist extremism has also dominated patterns of working-class political action in dif- working-class politics in two other European ferent countries and the national income, a cor- nations which belong to the under $500 per cap- relation that is almost startling in view of the ita income group— and Greece. In Spain many other cultural, historical, and juridical before Franco, anarchism and left socialism were factors which a¤ect the political life of nations. much stronger than moderate socialism; while In the two wealthiest countries, the United in Greece, whose per capita income in 1949 was States and Canada, not only are communist only $128, the Communists have always been parties almost nonexistent but socialist parties much stronger than the socialists, and fellow- have never been able to establish themselves as traveling parties have secured a large vote in re- major forces. Among the eight next wealthiest cent years.25 countries—New Zealand, , Sweden, United Kingdom, Denmark, Australia, Norway, 24. It should be noted that before 1933–34, Germany Belgium, Luxembourg and Netherlands—all of had one of the largest Communist parties in Europe; whom had a per capita income of over $500 a while the Socialist party of Austria was the most left- year in 1949 (the last year for which standardized wing and Marxist European party in the Socialist United Nations statistics exist), moderate social- International. ism predominates as the form of leftist politics. 25. Greece, economically the poorest political democ- In none of these countries did the Communists racy in Europe, ‘‘is now the only country in Europe secure more than 7 percent of the vote, and the where there is no socialist party. The Socialist party actual Communist party average among them (ELD), established in 1945 by individuals who colla- borated with the Communists during the Occupation, has been about 4 percent. In the eight Euro- dissolved itself in August 1953, a victim of its fickle and pean countries which were below the $500 per pro-Communist policy. The whole field was then sur- rendered to the Communists with the justification that 18. This statement is a ‘‘statistical’’ statement, which conditions were not mature enough for the develop- necessarily means that there will be many exceptions to ment of a socialist movement!’’ Manolis Korakas, the correlation. Thus we know that poorer people are ‘‘Grecian Apathy,’’ Socialist Commentary, May 1957, more likely to vote for the Democratic or Labor parties p. 21; in the elections of May 11, 1958, the ‘‘Commu- in the U.S. and England. The fact that a large minority nist directed’’ Union of the Democratic Left won 78 of the lower strata vote for the more conservative party out of 300 parliamentary seats and is now the second in these countries does not challenge the proposition largest party in the country. See New York Times, May that stratification position is a main determinant of 16, 1958, p. 3, col. 4. party choice. Chapter 2 60

The inverse relationship between national This does not mean that economic hardship or economic development as reflected by per capita poverty per se is the main cause of radicalism. income and the strength of Communists and There is much evidence to sustain the argu- other extremist groups among Western nations ment that stable poverty in a situation in which is seemingly stronger than the correlations be- individuals are not exposed to the possibilities tween other national variables like ethnic or of change breeds, if anything, conservatism.28 religious factors.26 Two of the poorer nations Individuals whose experience limits their signifi- with large Communist movements—Iceland cant communications and interaction to others and Finland—are Scandinavian and Lutheran. on the same level as themselves will, other con- Among the Catholic nations of Europe, all ditions being equal, be more conservative than the poor ones except Austria have large people who may be better o¤ but who have been Communist or anarchist movements. The two exposed to the possibilities of securing a better wealthiest Catholic democracies—Belgium and way of life.29 The dynamic in the situation Luxembourg—have few Communists. Though would seem to be exposure to the possibility of a the French and Italian cantons of Switzerland better way of life rather than poverty as such. As are strongly a¤ected by the cultural life of put it in a perceptive passage: ‘‘A France and Italy, there are almost no Commu- house may be large or small; as long as the sur- nists among the workers in these cantons, living rounding houses are equally small it satisfies all in the wealthiest country in Europe. social demands for a dwelling. But if a palace The relation between low per capita wealth arises beside the little house, the little house and the precipitation of su‰cient discontent to shrinks into a hut.’’30 provide the social basis for political extremism is With the growth of modern means of com- supported by a recent comparative polling sur- munication and transportation both within and vey of the attitudes of citizens of nine countries. among countries, it seems increasingly likely that Among these countries, feelings of personal the groups in the population that are poverty- security correlated with per capita income (.45) stricken but are isolated from knowledge of bet- and with per capita food supply (.55). If satis- ter ways of life or unaware of the possibilities for faction with one’s country, as measured by responses to the question, ‘‘Which country in the 27. William Buchanan and Hadley Cantril, How Na- world gives you the best chance of living the kind tions See Each Other (Urbana: University of Illinois of life you would like to live?’’ is used as an index Press, 1953), p. 35. of the amount of discontent in a nation, then the 28. See Emile Durkheim, Suicide: A Study in Sociol- relationship with economic wealth is even higher. ogy (Glencoe: The Free Press, 1951), pp. 253–254; see The study reports a rank order correlation of .74 also Daniel Bell, ‘‘The Theory of Mass Society,’’ between per capita income and the degree of Commentary, 22 (1956), p. 80. satisfaction with one’s own country.27 29. There is also a considerable body of evidence which indicates that those occupations which are eco- nomically vulnerable and those workers who have ex- 26. The relationship expressed above can be pre- perienced unemployment are prone to be more leftist in sented in another way. The seven European countries their outlook. See Chap. 7, pp. 242–249. in which Communist or fellow-traveling parties have secured large votes in free elections had an average per 30. Karl Marx, ‘‘Wage-Labor and Capital,’’ in Se- capita income in 1949 of $330. The ten European lected Works, Vol. I (New York: International Pub- countries in which the Communists have been a failure lishers, 1933), pp. 268–269. ‘‘Social tensions are an electorally had an average per capita income of $585. expression of unfulfilled expectations,’’ Daniel Bell, op. cit., p. 80. Sources of Democracy 61

improvement in their condition are becoming gap between the income of professional and rarer and rarer, particularly in the urban areas semiprofessional personnel on the one hand and of the Western world. One may expect to find ordinary workers on the other is much wider such stable poverty only in tradition-dominated in the poorer than in the wealthier countries. societies. Among manual workers, ‘‘there seems to be a Since position in a stratification system is al- greater wage discrepancy between skilled and ways relative and gratification or deprivation is unskilled workers in the less developed countries. experienced in terms of being better or worse o¤ In contrast the leveling process, in several of the than other people, it is not surprising that the developed countries at least, has been facilitated lower classes in all countries, regardless of the by the over-all increase of national income . . . wealth of the country, show various signs of not so much by reduction of the income of the resentment against the existing distribution of relatively rich as by the faster growth of the rewards by supporting political parties and other incomes of the relatively poor.’’33 organizations which advocate some form of The distribution of consumption goods also redistribution.31 The fact that the form which tends to become more equitable as the size these political parties take in poorer countries is of national income increases. The wealthier a more extremist and radical than it is in wealthier country, the larger the proportion of its popu- ones is probably more related to the greater de- lation which owns automobiles, telephones, gree of inequality in such countries than to the bathtubs, refrigerating equipment, and so forth. fact that their poor are actually poorer in abso- Where there is a dearth of goods, the sharing of lute terms. A comparative study of wealth dis- such goods must inevitably be less equitable than tribution by the United Nations ‘‘suggest[s] that in a country in which there is relative abundance. the richest fraction of the population (the richest For example, the number of people who can 10th, 5th, etc.) generally receive[s] a greater pro- portion of the total income in the less developed 33. United Nations Preliminary Report . . . , ibid. (See than in the more developed countries.’’32 The also Table II.) A recently completed comparison of in- come distribution in the United States and a number of 31. A summary of the findings of election studies in western European countries concludes that ‘‘there has many countries shows that, with few exceptions, there not been any great di¤erence’’ in patterns of income is a strong relationship between lower social position distribution among these countries. These findings and support of ‘‘leftist’’ politics. There are, of course, of Robert Solow appear to contradict those reported many other characteristics which are also related to above from the U.N. Statistics O‰ce, although the left voting, some of which are found among relatively latter are dealing primarily with di¤erences between well paid but socially isolated groups. Among the industrialized and underdeveloped nations. In any population as a whole, men are much more likely to case, it should be noted that Solow agrees that the rel- vote for the left than women, while members of mi- ative position of the lower strata in a poor as compared nority religious and ethnic groups also display a leftist with a wealthy country is quite di¤erent. As he states, tendency. . . . ‘‘in comparing Europe and America, one may ask whether it makes sense to talk about relative income 32. United Nations Preliminary Report on the World inequality independently of the absolute level of in- Social Situation (New York: 1952), pp. 132–133. come. An income four times another income has dif- Gunnar Myrdal, the Swedish economist, has recently ferent content according as the lower income means pointed out: ‘‘It is, indeed, a regular occurrence malnutrition on the one hand or provides some surplus endowed almost with the dignity of an economic law on the other.’’ Robert M. Solow, A Survey of Income that the poorer the country, the greater the di¤erence Inequality Since the War (Stanford: Center for between poor and rich.’’ An International Economy Advanced Study in the Behavioral Sciences, 1958, (New York: Harper & Bros., 1956), p. 133. mimeographed), pp. 41–44, 78. Chapter 2 62

a¤ord automobiles, washing machines, decent mid, with a large lower-class base, to a diamond housing, telephones, good clothes, or have their with a growing middle class. A large middle class children complete high school or go to college tempers conflict by rewarding moderate and still represents only a small minority of the pop- democratic parties and penalizing extremist ulation in many European countries. The great groups. national wealth of the United States or Canada, The political values and style of the upper or even to a lesser extent the Australasian class, too, are related to national income. The Dominions or Sweden, means that there is rela- poorer a country and the lower the absolute tively little di¤erence between the standards of standard of living of the lower classes, the living of adjacent social classes, and that even greater the pressure on the upper strata to treat classes which are far apart in the social structure the lower as vulgar, innately inferior, a lower will enjoy more nearly similar consumption pat- caste beyond the pale of human society. The terns than will comparable classes in Southern sharp di¤erence in the style of living between Europe. To a Southern European, and to an those at the top and those at the bottom makes even greater extent to the inhabitant of one of this psychologically necessary. Consequently, the the ‘‘underdeveloped’’ countries, social stratifi- upper strata in such a situation tend to regard cation is characterized by a much greater dis- political rights for the lower strata, particularly tinction in ways of life, with little overlap in the the right to share power, as essentially absurd goods the various strata own or can a¤ord to and immoral. The upper strata not only resist purchase. It may be suggested, therefore, that the democracy themselves; their often arrogant wealthier a country, the less is status inferiority political behavior serves to intensify extremist experienced as a major source of deprivation. reactions on the part of the lower classes. Increased wealth and education also serve The general income level of a nation also democracy by increasing the lower classes’ ex- a¤ects its receptivity to democratic norms. If posure to cross-pressures which reduce their there is enough wealth in the country so that it commitment to given ideologies and make them does not make too much di¤erence whether less receptive to extremist ones. The operation of some redistribution takes place, it is easier to this process will be discussed in more detail in accept the idea that it does not matter greatly the next chapter, but it means involving those which side is in power. But if loss of o‰ce means strata in an integrated national culture as distinct serious losses for major power groups, they will from an isolated lower-class one. seek to retain or secure o‰ce by any means Marx believed that the proletariat was a revo- available. A certain amount of national wealth lutionary force because it had nothing to lose but is likewise necessary to ensure a competent civil its chains and could win the whole world. But service. The poorer the country, the greater Tocqueville, analyzing the reasons why the lower the emphasis on nepotism—support of kin and strata in America supported the system, para- friends. And this in turn reduces the opportunity phrased and transposed Marx before Marx ever to develop the e‰cient bureaucracy which a made his analysis by pointing out that ‘‘only modern democratic state requires.35 those who have nothing to lose ever revolt.’’34 Increased wealth also a¤ects the political role 35. For a discussion of this problem in a new state, see of the middle class by changing the shape of the David Apter, The Gold Coast in Transition (Princeton: stratification structure from an elongated pyra- Princeton University Press, 1955), esp. Chaps. 9 and 13. Apter shows the importance of e‰cient bureau- cracy, and the acceptance of bureaucratic values and 34. Alexis de Tocqueville, Democracy in America, Vol. I (New York: Alfred A. Knopf, Vintage ed., 1945), behavior patterns for the existence of a democratic p. 258. political order. Sources of Democracy 63

Intermediary organizations which act as It is obvious that the conditions related to sources of countervailing power seem to be sim- stable democracy discussed here are most readily ilarly associated with national wealth. Tocque- found in the countries of northwest Europe and ville and other exponents of what has come to be their English-speaking o¤spring in America and known as the theory of the ‘‘mass society’’36 Australasia; and it has been suggested, by Weber have argued that a country without a multitude of organizations relatively independent of the 37. See Edward Banfield, The Moral Basis of a Back- central state power has a high dictatorial as well ward Society (Glencoe: The Free Press, 1958), for as revolutionary potential. Such organizations an excellent description of the way in which abysmal serve a number of functions: they inhibit the poverty serves to reduce community organization in state or any single source of private power from southern Italy. The data which do exist from polling dominating all political resources; they are a surveys conducted in the United States, Germany, source of new opinions; they can be the means France, Great Britain, and Sweden show that some- of communicating ideas, particularly opposition where between 40 and 50 per cent of the adults in these countries belong to voluntary associations, without ideas, to a large section of the citizenry; they lower rates of membership for the less stable democ- train men in political skills and so help to in- racies, France and Germany, than among the more crease the level of interest and participation stable ones, the United States, Great Britain, and in politics. Although there are no reliable data Sweden. These results seemingly challenge the general on the relationship between national patterns of proposition, although no definite conclusion can be voluntary organization and national political made, since most of the studies employed non- systems, evidence from studies of individual comparable categories. This point bears further re- behavior demonstrates that, regardless of other search in many countries. For the data on these factors, men who belong to associations are countries see the following studies. more likely than others to give the democratic For France, see Arnold Rose, Theory and Method in the Social Sciences (Minneapolis, University of Min- answer to questions concerning tolerance and nesota Press, 1954), p. 74 and O. R. Gallagher, ‘‘Vol- party systems, to vote, or to participate actively untary Associations in France,’’ Social Forces,36 in politics. Since the more well-to-do and better (1957), pp. 154–156; for Germany see Erich Rei- educated a man is, the more likely he is to belong grotzki, Soziale Verflechtungen in der Bundesrepublik to voluntary organizations, the propensity to (Tu¨bingen: J. D. B. Mohr, 1956), p. 164; for the U.S. form such groups seems to be a function of level see Charles L. Wright and Herbert H. Hyman, ‘‘Vol- of income and opportunities for leisure within untary Association Memberships of American Adults: given nations.37 Evidence from National Sample Surveys,’’ American ... Sociological Review, 23 (1958), p. 287, J. C. Scott, Jr., ‘‘Membership and Participation in Voluntary Associa- tions,’’ American Sociological Review, 22 (1957), pp. 36. See Emil Lederer, The State of the Masses (New 315–326 and Herbert Maccoby, ‘‘The Di¤erential Po- York: Norton, 1940); Hannah Arendt, Origins of litical Activity of Participants in a Voluntary Associa- Totalitarianism (New York: Harcourt, Brace & Co., tion,’’ American Sociological Review, 23 (1958), pp. 1951); Max Horkheimer, Eclipse of Reason (New 524–533; for Great Britain see Mass Observation, York: Oxford University Press, 1947); Karl Mann- Puzzled People (London: Victor Gollancz, 1947), p. heim, Man and Society in an Age of Reconstruction 119 and Thomas Bottomore, ‘‘Social Stratification in (New York: Harcourt, Brace & Co., 1940); Philip Voluntary Organizations,’’ in David Glass, ed., Social Selznick, The Organizational Weapon (New York: Mobility in Britain (Glencoe: The Free Press, 1954), p. McGraw-Hill Book Co., 1952); Jose´ Ortega y Gasset, 354; for Sweden see Gunnar Heckscher, ‘‘Pluralist De- The Revolt of the Masses (New York: Norton, 1932); mocracy: The Swedish Experience,’’ Social Research, William Kornhauser, The Politics of Mass Society 15 (1948), pp. 417–461. (Glencoe: The Free Press, 1959). Chapter 2 64

among others, that a historically unique concat- enation of elements produced both democracy and capitalism in this area. Capitalist economic development, the basic argument runs, had its greatest opportunity in a Protestant society and created the burgher class whose existence was both a catalyst and a necessary condition for democracy. Protestantism’s emphasis on indi- vidual responsibility furthered the emergence of democratic values in these countries and resulted in an alignment between the burghers and the throne which preserved the monarchy and extended the acceptance of democracy among the conservative strata. Men may question whether any aspect of this interrelated cluster of economic development, Protestantism, monar- chy, gradual political change, legitimacy, and democracy is primary, but the fact remains that the cluster does hang together.44 ...

44. In introducing historical events as part of the analysis of factors external to the political system, which are part of the causal nexus in which democracy is involved, I am following in good sociological and even functionalist tradition. As Radcli¤e-Brown has well put it: ‘‘. . . one ‘explanation’ of a social system will be its history, where we know it—the detailed ac- count of how it came to be what it is and where it is. Another ‘explanation’ of the same system is obtained by showing . . . that it is a special exemplification of laws of social psychology or social functioning. The two kinds of explanation do not conflict but supple- ment one another.’’ A. R. Radcli¤e-Brown, ‘‘On the Concept of Function in Social Science,’’ American An- thropologist, New Series, 37 (1935), p. 401; see also Max Weber, The Methodology of the Social Sciences (Glencoe: The Free Press, 1949), pp. 164–188, for a detailed discussion of the role of historical analysis in sociological research. Social Revolutions in the Modern World

Theda Skocpol

5 skepticism about the victors’ claims provide essential I. Social Origins: An Analytic Summary safeguards against being taken in by the dominant mythology. A scholar who tries to be objective needs A. The Moral of the Story these feelings as part of his ordinary working equipment.7 [Barrington Moore’s] Social Origins of Dictator- ship and Democracy is not organized or written What is the particular truthful message with in the style of a scientist trying to elaborate a critical ring that Social Origins attempts to clearly and minutely justify a falsifiable theory of convey? I believe it is the conclusion that ‘‘the comparative modernization. It is, rather, like a evidence from the comparative history of mod- giant mural painted in words, in which a man ernization’’ tells us that ‘‘the costs of moderation who has contemplated the modern histories of have been at least as atrocious as those of revo- 8 eight major nations seeks to convey in broad lution, perhaps a great deal more.’’ This con- strokes the moral and factual discoveries that he clusion is argued by Moore in several ways. personally has made, about the various routes to First, in assessing the evidence of British history, the ‘‘world of modern industry’’ traveled by his he emphasizes the legal violent su¤ering inflicted ‘‘subject’’ countries, about the roles of landed on peasants by the enclosure movements; upper classes and peasantries in the politics of second, in discussing the Indian case, Moore that transformation, and about the consequences emphasizes the costs in popular su¤ering of of each route for human freedom and societal ‘‘democratic stagnation,’’ or modernization for- rationality. For Professor Moore’s purpose in gone. Finally, and I believe most important, writing Social Origins is as much moral as Moore organizes Social Origins around three theoretical—and it is important that he sees no main ‘‘Routes to the modern world,’’ and de- contradiction between these purposes. . . . votes considerable e¤ort to demonstrating that . . . Professor Moore argues in Social Origins each has contained a roughly equivalent measure that because in of popular su¤ering and large-scale collective violence. ‘‘A pox on all their houses’’ is the mes- any society the dominant groups are the ones with the sage about modes of modernization, and the most to hide about the way the society works. . . . organizing framework of Social Origins func- [V]ery often . . . truthful analyses are bound to have tions more to facilitate the exposition of this a critical ring, to seem like exposures rather than ob- moral conclusion than to clarify or test the (ba- jective statements, as the term is conventionally used sically Marxist) conceptions of social change and [to denote ‘‘mild-mannered statements in favor of the political process which informed Moore’s inter- status quo . . .’’]. . . . For all students of human society, sympathy with the victims of historical processes and pretation of ‘‘the facts,’’ which to him dictated that moral conclusion.

Excerpted from: Theda Skocpol, Social Revolutions in the Modern World. Cambridge: Cambridge University 7. Pp. 522–523. All page number references for quotes Press, 1994. 6 Cambridge University Press, 1994. are to Barrington Moore, Jr., Social Origins of Dicta- Reprinted with the permission of Cambridge Univer- torship and Democracy (Boston: Beacon Press, 1966). sity Press. A paperback edition was published by Beacon Press in 1967; pagination is the same as in the hardback edition. 5. Reading the following analytic summary is no sub- stitute for reading Social Origins itself. The summary 8. Ibid., p. 505. presupposes acquaintance with the book. Chapter 2 66

B. The Theoretical Argument (Germany, Japan); and ‘‘peasant revolution’’ in the case of the societies (Russia, China) that be- Social Origins, in the words of its author, came Communist dictatorships. Two of Moore’s Routes—the Communist and the ‘‘Capitalist endeavors to explain the varied political roles played Reactionary (or Fascist)’’—represent genuine by the landed upper classes and the peasantry in the theoretical constructs in that they identify pat- transformation from agrarian societies . . . to modern industrial ones. . . . [I]t is an attempt to discover the terns of (a) initial class structure, (b) revolution- range of historical conditions under which either or ary political conflict, and (c) ultimate systemic both of these rural groups have become important political outcome that Moore argues apply to forces behind the emergence of Western parliamentary both of the two societies classified in each Route. versions of democracy, and dictatorships of the right The ‘‘Bourgeois Route,’’ on the other hand, is and the left, that is, fascist and communist regimes.9 actually a residual category defined only by the twentieth-century political system (‘‘Western The book is organized around the discussion of democracy’’) common to its ‘‘members.’’ Britain, three distinct Routes to the modern world, each France, and the United States, as Moore culminating in one of the three societal political emphasizes, started the modernizing process outcomes that interest Moore: Western democ- with very di¤erent social structures; and the po- racy, fascism, and communist dictatorship.10 litical upheavals these societies underwent dur- The class structures of ‘‘agrarian states’’ under- ing modernization—the English Civil War, the going the initial stages of economic moderniza- French Revolution, and the American Civil tion are linked to alternate political outcomes via War—were characterized by very di¤erent con- critical political events analyzed as class strug- crete patterns of class struggle. Moore labels gles: ‘‘bourgeois revolution’’ in the case of the each of these conflicts ‘‘bourgeois revolution,’’ three societies that ended up as Western par- but admits that he does so in each case primarily liamentary democracies (Britain, France, the because the conflict in question contributed cru- U.S.A.); ‘‘revolution from above’’ in the case of cially to the eventual establishment of ‘‘bour- societies that ended up as fascist dictatorships geois democracy,’’ not because any one of them constituted simply or mainly a political o¤ensive 9. Ibid., p. xi. of a ‘‘rising bourgeoisie.’’ Insofar as any theo- 10. India does not fit well into the theoretical analysis retically significant common causal pattern is that Moore presents for the three main Routes; hence, identified as characteristic of the three ‘‘bour- I shall have little to say about that case account in geois revolutions,’’ it is ‘‘the development of a this essay. Both India’s inclusion in the book, and its group in society with an independent economic classification as a ‘‘democracy’’ seem dubious to me. And Moore’s conclusions about India are entirely base, which attacks obstacles to a democratic equivocal. version of capitalism that have been inherited Since the United States was never an agrarian bu- from the past.’’11 In this respect, Moore empha- reaucracy or a feudal society, it does not fit well into sizes the role of commercial agrarians—gentry the overall explanatory scheme of Social Origins either. in the English Civil War, rich peasants in the I believe that Moore badly twisted the facts of Ameri- French Revolution, and commercial farmers in can history in order to present the Civil War as a the American Civil War. ‘‘bourgeois revolution.’’ Lee Benson has made a basi- Moore (rather nonsystematically) elaborates cally sound (though overly rancorous) argument to this and interrelates three key variables in order to e¤ect in his Toward the Scientific Study of History explain (a) di¤erences among the sequences (Philadelphia: J. B. Lippincott, 1972), chap. 8, and I will not repeat what would be a similar argument in this essay. 11. Social Origins, p. xv. Sources of Democracy 67

characteristic of the major Routes, and (b) dif- explanation of patterns and outcomes of class- ferences among the ‘‘Bourgeois Revolution’’ conflict political struggles (e.g., strong bourgeois cases. His overall ‘‘explanation sketch’’ seems so impulse ! politically aggressive bourgeoisie ! nonsystematic not only because he fails to define bourgeois revolution). But, for Moore, agrarian variables and spell out their roles in explaining strata are the strategic actors in the political sequences of structures and events, but also be- revolutions from above or below which create cause so much of Social Origins is taken up by the conditions for the development of various case accounts for individual countries. This fact forms of political institutions in industrial soci- has even led one reviewer to assert that Moore’s eties. Therefore, he must identify variables method is ‘‘idiographic’’! However, appearances which can explain agrarian strata’s (a) political can be very deceptive: what Moore really does propensities (pro- or anti-liberal/democratic) in the case analyses is to interpret available sec- and (b) opportunities for extra-agrarian class ondary materials in a way that makes his ex- alliances. planatory and moral concepts seem plausible. It The one general pattern of cross-class alliance is those concepts that I am attempting to make that Moore discusses is alliance between agrar- explicit in this review. ian and urban upper classes: The first key variable is the strength of a bourgeois or commercial impulse. Some degree The coalitions and countercoalitions that have arisen . . . across these two groups have constituted and in of commercialization—which for Moore seems some parts of the world still constitute the basic to mean growth of urban-based commodity framework and environment of political action, markets—is asserted to be operating to under- forming the series of opportunities, temptations, and mine and destabilize each agrarian state that impossibilities within which political leaders have had Moore discusses. Just as a ‘‘rising bourgeoisie’’ is to act.12 the prime mover, itself not moved, in virtually every Marxist account of European moderniza- Here the critical thing seems to be the ‘‘strength’’ tion, so in Social Origins, commercialization is of the bourgeoisie: if it is ‘‘strong,’’ it will set the an unexplained given. But degrees of strength cultural and political ‘‘tone’’ of any coalition of the commercial or bourgeois impulse are with a landed upper class (i.e., as in England, di¤erentiated and function as the one variable according to Moore) no matter who actually which both cuts across and di¤erentiates all three holds political o‰ce; if it is only of ‘‘medium’’ Routes. According to Moore, ‘‘Bourgeois Revo- strength, the landed upper class will set the tone. lution’’ countries (seventeenth-century England, As for the political propensities and capacities eighteenth-century France, nineteenth-century of agrarian strata, Moore’s elaboration and ap- U.S.) are characterized by the presence of a plication to case analyses of two remaining key ‘‘strong’’ bourgeois impulse at an early stage of variables—(1) the form of commercial agricul- modernization (though the ‘‘strong’’ bourgeois ture: ‘‘labor-repressive’’ versus ‘‘market,’’ and (2) impulse is weakest in France); the bourgeois ‘‘peasant revolutionary potential’’—constitute impulse is of ‘‘medium’’ strength in early mod- the core of Social Origins’ analyses of the politics ernizing (late eighteenth–mid-nineteenth cen- of modernization. tury) Germany and Japan; and is ‘‘weak’’ in For any Marxist: late nineteenth-century China and Russia (and It is always the direct relationship of the owners of the twentieth-century India). conditions of production to the direct producers . . . An old-fashioned Marxist might proceed di- [t]he specific form in which unpaid surplus labor is rectly from assertions about the strength of the bourgeoisie in relation to other classes to the 12. Ibid., p. 423. Chapter 2 68

pumped out of the direct producers . . . which reveals United States. In contrast, ‘‘labor-repressive the innermost secret, the hidden basis of the entire agrarian systems provide[d] an unfavorable soil social structure, and with it the political form of the for the growth of democracy and [if peasant relation of sovereignty and dependence, in short, the revolution failed and a moderately strong bour- 13 corresponding specific form of the state. geoisie existed] an important part of the insti- Yet Marx himself concentrated on analyzing tutional complex leading to fascism.’’16 Why? the capitalist-proletarian relationship, and most Moore gives us two main reasons: First: Marxist writers since have been content to con- While a system of labor-repressive agriculture may be trast the exploitative relationship under capital- started in opposition to the central authority, it is likely ism (capitalist-worker) with a generic ‘‘feudal’’ to fuse with the monarchy at a later point in search lord-peasant exploitative relationship, without of political support. This situation can also lead to the attempting to come to grips with the various preservation of a military ethic among the nobility in producer-surplus-controller relationships found a manner unfavorable to the growth of democratic in commercial agricultures. It is this task that institutions.17 Moore tackles by drawing a distinction between Second: ‘‘labor-repressive’’ and ‘‘market’’ forms of com- mercial agriculture: At a later stage in the course of modernization, a new and crucial factor is likely to appear in the form of a The form of commercial agriculture . . . [is] just as im- rough working coalition between influential sectors of 14 portant as commercialization itself. . . . the landed upper classes and the emerging commercial There are certain forms of capitalist transformation and manufacturing interests.18 in the countryside that may succeed economically, Industrial development may proceed rapidly under in the sense of yielding good profits, but which are such auspices. But the outcome, after a brief and un- for fairly obvious reasons unfavorable to the growth stable period of democracy has been fascism.19 of free institutions of the nineteenth-century Western variety. . . . Finally, let me introduce the third key vari- The distinction I am trying to suggest is one between able, ‘‘peasant revolutionary potential.’’ ‘‘Re- the use of political mechanisms (using the term ‘‘politi- actionary Capitalist’’ modernization is possible, cal’’ broadly . . . [to include ‘‘traditional relationships and attitudes’’ used by landlords]) on the one hand and reliance on the labor market, on the other hand, to en- 15. Ibid., pp. 433–434, italics added. Moore explic- sure an adequate labor force for working the soil and itly excludes from the category ‘‘labor-repressive’’ the creation of an agricultural surplus for consumption agriculture: (1) family farming; (2) ‘‘a system of hired by other classes.15 agricultural laborers where the workers . . . [have] con- siderable real freedom to refuse jobs and move about The ‘‘labor-repressive’’- versus ‘‘market’’- . . .’’; and (3) ‘‘precommercial and pre-industrial agrar- commercial agriculture distinction stands at the ian systems . . . if there is a rough balance between the heart of the explanation of di¤erent patterns and overlord’s contribution to justice and security and the outcomes of modernization o¤ered in Social cultivators’ contribution in the form of crops’’ (pp. Origins. ‘‘Market’’ commercialization created 434–435). Strictly speaking, it seems to me, (3) should not even be relevant, since the ‘‘labor-repressive’’ ver- crucial agrarian political allies for ‘‘strong’’ sus ‘‘market’’ distinction refers only to commercial bourgeoisies in England and the (Northern) agricultures. 16. Ibid., p. 435. 13. Karl Marx, Capital, Vol. 3 (New York: Interna- 17. Ibid. tional Publishers, 1967; originally published, 1894), 18. Ibid., p. 436. p. 791. 19. Ibid., p. xvi. 14. Social Origins, p. 420. Sources of Democracy 69

Table 2.1 Categories and explanatory variable clusters in Barrington Moore’s Social Origins of Dictatorship and Democracy Route one Route two Route three ‘‘Bourgeois revolution’’ ‘‘Reactionary capitalism’’ ‘‘Communism’’ Common starting Agrarian bureaucracy Agrarian bureaucracy Agrarian bureaucracy point* (except U.S.A.) Key variable clusters Bourgeois impulse Strong Strong Medium-strength Weak Mode of commercial agriculture Market Labor-repressive Labor-repressive Labor-repressive Peasant revolutionary potential Low High Low High Critical political event Bourgeois revolution Revolution from above Peasant revolution Major systemic political outcome Democratic capitalism Fascism Communist dictatorship Cases Britain France Germany Russia U.S.A. Japan China *[P]owerful central governments that we can loosely call royal absolutisms or agrarian bureaucracies established themselves in the sixteenth and seventeenth centuries in all the major countries examined in connection with this study (except of course the United States). . . . [T]he fact forms a convenient if partly arbitrary peg upon which to hang the beginnings of modernization’’ (Social Origins, p. 417). according to Moore’s analysis, only if both which is not making (or promoting) a successful ‘‘bourgeois’’ and peasant revolution from below transition to modern industrialism; and a ‘‘radi- fail to occur. Peasants provide much of the in- cal’’ form of peasant community solidarity surrectionary force in both types of revolution. (where ‘‘institutional arrangements are such as This leads Moore to ask: ‘‘what kinds of social to spread grievances through the peasant com- structure and historical situations produce peas- munity . . .’’).23 Factors tending to produce weak ant revolutions and which ones inhibit or prevent revolutionary potential are: strong ties to the them[?]’’20 A very basic condition for any social revolution, he concludes, is that ‘‘commercial- 22. On pp. 470–473 of Social Origins, Moore develops ization’’ in an agrarian state must be of such a what I consider to be a naive functionalist definition (moderate or low) strength and form as to leave of ‘‘exploitation’’ in landlord-peasant relationships. He peasant society basically intact, but ‘‘impaired.’’ holds that one can objectively measure whether lords Beyond that, the interaction of several factors (in precommercial agrarian systems) are performing determines whether the peasantry will have a valuable services for ‘‘the community’’ in return for the ‘‘strong or weak revolutionary potential.’’ Fac- surpluses they claim. But Moore overlooks the fact that any upper class quite unmanipulatively creates tors conducive21 to strong potential are: weak 22 through its own existence and activities many of the and ‘‘exploitative’’ ties to a landed upper class problems that it simultaneously overcomes in ‘‘service’’ to ‘‘the community.’’ Thus, if feudal lords had not 20. Ibid., p. 453. been wont to fight among themselves, ‘‘their’’ peasants 21. All ‘‘conducive factors’’ need not be present in would not have needed the protection for which they any particular case of peasant revolution, according to supposedly ‘‘gave’’ their surpluses in ‘‘fair exchange’’! Moore’s argument. 23. Ibid., p. 475. Chapter 2 70

landed upper class, and weak peasant commu- The essence of . . . [Moore’s] argument [ ] . . . is that nity solidarity, or else a ‘‘conservative’’ form of certain combinations of factors make certain subse- solidarity (which ties ‘‘those with actual and quent events more likely. . . . One wants to know: what potential grievances into the prevailing social are the antecedents or consequences of structure X? Weber has referred to the notion that once certain structure’’).24 Finally, Moore points out that structures appear, the ‘‘die is cast,’’ making it more potentially revolutionary peasants must have likely that certain events will occur on the next roll of non-peasant allies to succeed, but he is not able the dice.27 to provide a general formula for ascertaining who they might be. Still, what made the French Significantly, Moore does not attain complete Revolution ‘‘bourgeois,’’ according to Moore’s explanation (or anything approaching it): he analysis, was the fact that a peasantry with a tends to assume commercialization-flowing-into- significant rich peasant element was able to find industrialization, and focuses on determinants Third Estate allies; combined rich peasant and of political institutional outcomes. This really Third Estate interest in promoting private prop- means that he does not explain the process of erty precluded a collectivist outcome.25 economic development per se, but instead iden- Now that an analytic summary has been pro- tifies what seem to him probable sequences vided of the Routes and the key variables that of three types of states or events—agrarian Moore uses to explain di¤erences among and bureaucratic social structures, revolutions (from within them, it may be helpful to the reader to above or below), and ‘‘modern’’ political provide at this point a schematic summary of arrangements—with economic development what has been presented (table 2.1): assumed as the continuous process connecting A word should be said about the kind of and activating the sequence of structures and explanation that Moore appears to be attempt- events. . . . ing in Social Origins. Robert Somers aptly labels it ‘‘sequence analysis . . . the systematic study 26. Robert Somers, ‘‘Applications of an Expanded of particular kinds of sequences of events that Survey Research Model to Comparative Institutional are assumed to have some kind of causal Studies,’’ in Ivan Vallier, ed., Comparative Methods connection.’’26 in Sociology (Berkeley and Los Angeles: University of California Press, 1971), p. 392. 24. Ibid., p. 476. 27. Ibid., p. 389. 25. I am not going to have much to say about Moore’s discussion of ‘‘peasant revolutionary potential’’ in the critical remarks which follow. For three reasons: first, I think Moore is basically on the right track in refusing to focus on peasants alone, or as an aggregate mass; instead, he considers both peasant community social structures and peasant ties to upper strata. Second, what di¤erences I have with Moore on the peasant question stem from my alternative approach to social revolutions, viewed holistically, and those di¤erences are spelled out in a paper delivered at the August 1973 meetings of the American Sociological Association in New York City. Finally, for the theoretical purposes of this paper, it is more important to criticize the way Moore handles upper-class relations to political processes. The Impact of Economic Development on Democracy

Evelyne Huber, Dietrich Rueschemeyer, and John D. Stephens

class and strengthens subordinate classes. The Methods, Theory, and Major Results working and the middle classes—unlike other subordinate classes in history—gain an un- Any account of the social and economic con- precedented capacity for self-organization due to ditions of democracy must come to terms with such developments as urbanization, factory pro- the central finding of the cross-national statisti- duction, and new forms of communication and cal research: a sturdy (though not perfect) asso- transportation. ciation between economic development and This thesis negates other explanations. The democracy. But these correlations do not vali- primary link between capitalist development and date the theoretical accounts that have often democracy is not found in an expansion of been associated with them, in particular mod- the middle classes. Nor can the relationship be ernization theory. Nor do cross-sectional corre- explained by the argument that more complex lations allow us to make adequate inferences societies require a di¤erentiated and flexible about causal sequence. Similar outcomes might form of government, as modernization theory be produced by a variety of factors and causal suggested. And finally democracy is not the cre- sequences. ation of the bourgeoisie, the new dominant class To tackle these questions of causation, we of capital owners, as was claimed by both liberal adopted a strategy of analytic induction based and Marxist political theory. The bourgeoisie on comparative historical research. This strategy made important contributions to the move to- is a case-based method of study, which builds on wards democracy by insisting on its share in a theoretical framework that takes past research political power in the form of parliamentary into account, and then proceeds by analyzing control of the state, but the bourgeoisie was successive individual histories. In this way, this also hostile to further democratization when method gains information on historical sequence its interests seemed threatened. In fact, one of and can do justice to the particular historical the more important findings of our comparative context of each factor analyzed. Each case research, which we did not fully anticipate, is may modify both the specific hypotheses used that—especially in Latin America—the eco- in earlier analyses and the broader theoretical nomically dominant classes accepted democracy framework. The result is a range of cases inter- only where their political interests were e¤ec- preted by a single set of theoretical propositions tively protected by large parties of a conservative and a progressively modified theory that is con- or non-ideological character. It is also important sistent with the cases studied. . . . to note that the bourgeoisie often comes around Our central thesis, and indeed our most basic to support democracy once it turns out that its finding, can now be stated in stark fashion: interests can be protected within the system. . . . Capitalist development is related to democracy The fact that class interests are historically because it shifts the balance of class power, constructed has crucial consequences for the because it weakens the power of the landlord analysis. It raises interclass relations to critical importance. One class may exercise hegemonic Excerpted from: Evelyne Huber, Dietrich Ruesche- influence over another, and this will a¤ect the meyer, and John D. Stephens, ‘‘The Impact of Economic alliance options among classes. The interests Development on Democracy.’’ Journal of Economic actually pursued by peasants and even by urban Perspectives 7, no. 3 (1993): 71–86. Reprinted by per- mission. middle classes are often profoundly shaped by Chapter 2 72

landlords, the bourgeoisie, and the state as well 32 percent, while trade union organizations grew as state-a‰liated churches. The alliance devel- spectacularly, increasing two and a half times. opments at the top—among landlords, bour- The organized working class was also the most geoisie, and the state—can be decisive for the consistently pro-democratic force in the period alliance options of other classes. This is of criti- under consideration: at the onset of World War cal importance for the chances of democracy I, European labor movements had converged because the working class, even the European on an ideology which placed the achievement working class, was too weak on its own to suc- of universal su¤rage and parliamentary govern- ceed in the final push toward democracy with ment at the center of their program (Zolberg, universal su¤rage. 1986). . . . Does Latin America show similar develop- ments? Patterns for large land-holding and the Democratic Transition and Breakdown in Europe existence of a powerful class of landlords with a and South America need for a large cheap labor force also posed significant problems for democracy in South In 1870, only one European country, Switzer- America. Breakthroughs to full democracy land, was a democracy. Many countries fre- before the 1970s, even if temporary, were only quently thought to be democratic at this time possible where the large landowners were pri- such as Britain, Netherlands, and Belgium, marily engaged in ranching and thus had lower had parliamentary government and competitive labor needs (Argentina and Uruguay), or where party systems, but the electorate was limited by their economic power was undermined or coun- income or property qualifications. By contrast, terbalanced by the presence of a strong mining by 1920, almost all Western European countries export sector (Venezuela and Bolivia). were fully democratic. This period of transition Like its counterpart in Europe, the bourgeoisie to democracy in Europe was also marked by was not a promoter of full democracy in South the arrival of the organized working class. The America. As in Europe, the forces pushing for change in the underlying class structure as indi- democracy were the organized segments of the cated by labor force figures is significant enough: subordinate classes, but the leadership roles were between 1870 and 1910, the non-agricultural reversed. In South America the middle classes workforce grew by one-third to one-half, even- were the driving force, but they mainly promoted tually reaching an average of 61 percent of the their own inclusion and thus often accepted total workforce in the 13 European countries restricted forms of democracy. For full democ- we studied. The change at the level of class for- racy to be installed, the middle classes had to be mation and class organization was even more dependent on working class support in their push significant: in 1870, in no country were the for democracy, and they had to receive support socialists a significant mass-based party, and the from a working class which had some measure of trade unions organized a minuscule proportion strength. . . . of the labor force. By the eve of World War I, The political history of 20th century Latin the major socialist and labor parties garnered America is characterized by numerous break- an average of 26 percent of the vote (despite throughs to restricted or full democracies, then su¤rage restrictions in a number of countries) followed by breakdowns of democracy. Essen- and the trade unions organized an average of tially, the economically dominant classes tol- 11 percent of the non-agricultural labor force. erated democracy only as long as what they In the immediate postwar elections, the social- perceived to be their vital interests were pro- ists’ electoral share increased to an average of tected. Where the capacity of the state or politi- Sources of Democracy 73

cal parties to channel and contain militant action Not surprisingly, then, all but two of the of subordinate classes declined, economic elites Spanish-speaking countries in the Caribbean turned to the military in search of allies to re- basin were ruled by authoritarian regimes in place the democratic with authoritarian regimes. the 1960s and 1970s, and during the 1970s, eco- . . . The position of South American countries nomic elites and the military establishment in the world economy as late and dependent resorted to increasingly violent repression of developers, with imported technology, resulted both revolutionary movements and democratic in small industrial working classes compared to reformist forces. The exceptions were Costa Rica Europe at similar levels of economic develop- and, from 1978 on, the Dominican Republic. ment, and thus in class structures inimical to In contrast, all but two of the English-speaking democratization. Economic dependence further Caribbean countries had democratic regimes meant high vulnerability to fluctuations in world from the time of their independence in the 1960s markets, and the resulting economic instability throughout the 1970s.3 How do we explain these made stabilization and legitimization of regimes contrasting political developments? di‰cult, whether those regimes were authoritar- The antecedents of the contrasts in the 1960s ian or democratic. . . . and 1970s lie in the developments of the 1930s. The Depression brought great disruptions to the extremely export-dependent societies in the re- Central America and the West Indies gion. In response to decreasing real wages and increasing unemployment, attempts at labor The West Indies and the Central American organization and labor protests emerged in vir- countries share a number of socioeconomic tually all countries throughout this region. The characteristics that have been shown to be inim- reactions of the economic elites to these protests ical to democracy.2 Their economies were tradi- and organizing attempts were universally nega- tionally plantation economies, with some mining tive, but the reaction of the state varied widely. and industrialization—and tourism in the West British colonialism was important here, because Indies—superimposed in the post–World War II it was an alternative to the Central American period. The corresponding societies were tradi- pattern of landlord or military control of the tionally very hierarchical and their economies state, and thus an alternative to the use of the highly dependent on foreign trade and foreign coercive forces of the state to repress both investment. Low economic development, ex- the protests and the emerging labor unions and tremely high dependence, high inequality, a allied political parties. Consequently, the ’30s small working class, and rapid social change marked the beginning of organized political life, all have been found to be unfavorable for the and opened the way for the subsequent consoli- installation and consolidation of democratic dation of civil society in the West Indies, whereas regimes, and they all characterized Caribbean in Central America they solidified the pattern Basin countries in the post–World War II of the primacy of the coercive apparatus of the period. state and of state control over the repression of civil society, exercised either by landowner- 2. The term ‘‘West Indies’’ refers to the English- speaking Caribbean countries (the larger ones are 3. Racially polarized Guyana and tiny Grenada were Jamaica, Barbados, Trinidad, and Guyana); the the exceptions, but analysis of these two countries term ‘‘Caribbean’’ includes them along with Spanish, would take us too far afield here; the interested reader French, and Dutch-speaking countries; the term should see Rueschemeyer, Stephens and Stephens ‘‘Caribbean Basin’’ refers to Caribbean and Central (1992, pp. 251–258). American countries. Chapter 2 74

military coalitions or the military alone. Costa ence and could be turned to coercive purposes on Rica, the deviant case in Central America, a national scale. Such a state had been created resembled the West Indies insofar as the large across the European continent in the course of landowners were not in firm control of the state the centuries-long consolidation of the European apparatus (though for di¤erent reasons, as we states, largely as a result of warfare between the shall see in a moment) and consequently unions states. As Tilly (1975, pp. 40–44) points out, the and political parties were allowed to consolidate coalition of large landlords with the central state their organizations. was a militarily strong one and was frequently In sum, the growth of democracy cannot be victorious in these centuries of war. Moreover, read o¤ from the economic development and its the state-building process in these countries gen- e¤ect on the development of the class structure erally resulted in the landed upper classes having alone. Both Central American and Caribbean a strong foothold in the military, which made countries started from roughly similar levels of recourse to authoritarian politics more attractive development, similar economic structures, and since landlords and their allies could rely on the similar world market niches. What emerges as military to exercise the coercion necessary to critical in this comparison of the emergence of maintain or install authoritarian rule. democracy in the West Indies and its absence in Central America is the nature of state-class relations, especially the critical contribution of Questions, Method, and Applications British colonialism. Similarly, the development of a strong military Our program of comparative historical research state or its absence cannot be explained by confirmed the conclusion of the cross-national internal factors alone. The third power cluster, statistical analyses of the correlates of political transnational structures of power, must be democracy: The level of economic development brought in to complete the explanation. The is causally related to the development of political United States’ economic and geopolitical inter- democracy. However, the underlying reason ests, along with political alignments within the for the connection, in our view, is that capitalist United States, led it to support the build-up of development transforms the class structure, the coercive apparatus of the Central American enlarging the working and middle classes and states. In Britain, by contrast, the colonies facilitating their self-organization, thus making it were increasingly viewed as an expense which a more di‰cult for elites to exclude them politi- declining power could ill a¤ord and which the cally. Simultaneously, development weakens the social democratic forces, which were far stronger landed upper class, democracy’s most consistent in Britain, no longer desired. opponent. The development of the class struc- This analysis of the West Indies and Central ture hardly accounts for all national di¤erences America leads to a reinterpretation of our evi- in democratic development, as the contrasting dence on Europe, as one would expect in this political development in the Spanish-speaking strategy of analytic induction. In the discussion Central American countries and the English- of Europe, we attributed the authoritarian tra- speaking Caribbean islands demonstrates, but it jectory of four of the countries—Germany, Italy, is of central importance. Austria-Hungary, and Spain—to the strength of Some readers may be familiar with the argu- the landed upper classes in those countries. The ment that the bourgeoisie played an important West Indian cases indicate that this strength had role as the agents of democratic reform, and thus to be complemented with a structure of state may be surprised at how little weight we give this power which was open to strong landlord influ- factor. Surely, leading businessmen in contem- Sources of Democracy 75

porary advanced capitalist countries are rightly economic problems in the Third World, eco- regarded as supporters of democracy. However, nomic stagnation and the crushing debt, are also most of their predecessors in 19th century Eu- a problem for democracy. There is no doubt that rope and 20th century Latin America were not, rapid economic growth, or a growing economic because they feared that extending su¤rage to pie, facilitates compromise between capital and workers would represent a threat to their mate- labor and that, conversely, slow growth makes it rial interests. As democracy was established almost impossible to satisfy both parties. Under during the 20th century and these fears proved to such conditions, demands for mere economic be exaggerated, the bourgeoisies of advanced betterment on the part of workers become a capitalist societies gradually came to accept and threat to business. then strongly to support democratic institutions. The analysis leads us to expect some countries A similar process occurred in the West Indies in within the Third World to have better prospects the post–World War II period, and one can hope for democratization than others. Most obvi- that contemporary South America is experienc- ously, the prospects are brighter for those coun- ing the same phenomenon. . . . tries at higher levels of economic development. We conclude with a few observations about However, as our analysis made clear, it is not the implications of our analysis for the future of the mere rise in per capita income (created, for democracy in the contemporary Third World. example, by mineral wealth) that is of greatest Across the less developed countries, most U.S. importance, but rather the changes in the class intervention since World War II (at least) was and social structure caused by industrialization primarily motivated by geopolitical competition and urbanization which are most consequen- with the former Soviet Union, rather than by tial for democracy. In addition, the analysis of direct defense of economic interests. Concerns agrarian class relations leads us to the conclu- for national security were invariably invoked to sion that democratic prospects are much better justify support for authoritarian regimes. The in Third World countries without a significant end of the Cold War both alleviates these con- group of large landholders and with a significant cerns and greatly weakens them as a basis for agrarian middle class. foreign policy towards Latin America. The dis- crediting of the Soviet model has also dealt a mortal blow to Leninist socialism as a model References for opposition movements and a basis for legiti- mization of authoritarian regimes in the Third Rueschemeyer, Dietrich, Evelyne Huber Stephens, and World. These factors at least open the door for a John D. Stephens, Capitalist Development and Democ- more unambiguously pro-democratic policy to- racy. Cambridge. Polity Press, and Chicago: Chicago University Press, 1992. wards the Third World on the part of the United States and the other developed countries, all of Tilly, Charles, ‘‘Reflections on the History of Euro- pean State-making.’’ In Tilly, Charles ed., The Forma- which are now democracies. tion of National States in Western Europe. Princeton: But other factors lead to less optimism about Princeton University Press, 1975, 3–83. the chances for democracy in the Third World. Zolberg, Aristide R., ‘‘How Many Exceptionalisms?’’ In the case of both workers and businessmen, In Katznelson, Ira, and Aristide Zolberg, eds., Work- our analysis shows that their political posture ing Class Formation: Nineteenth Century Patterns in toward democratic institutions was motivated Western Europe and the United States. Princeton: in no small part by their perception of how Princeton University Press, 1986, 397–455. democracy would a¤ect their material interests. On this account, one can say that the current Democracy and the Market: Political and Economic Reforms in Eastern Europe and Latin America

Adam Przeworski

other. Hence, the struggle for democracy always Transitions to Democracy takes place on two fronts: against the authori- tarian regime for democracy and against one’s Democratization allies for the best place under democracy. Thus, even if they sometimes coincide tempo- Introduction rally, it is useful to focus separately on the two The problem that thrusts itself to the center of di¤erent aspects of democratization: extrication the political agenda once a dictatorship breaks from the authoritarian regime and the constitu- down is whether any institutions that will allow tion of a democratic one. The relative impor- open-ended, even if limited, contestation will be tance of extrication and constitution depends accepted by the relevant political forces. And as on the place within the authoritarian regime soon as these institutions are in place, the ques- of those political forces that control the appara- tion arises whether they will evoke spontaneous tus of repression, most often the armed forces.22 compliance; that is, whether, willing to subject Wherever the military remains cohesive in their interests to the uncertainty of competition defense of the regime, elements of extrication and to comply with its outcomes, they will ab- dominate the process of transition. and sorb the relevant political forces as participants. Poland are the paradigmatic cases of extrication, To organize the analysis, note that the con- but extrication also overshadowed the transitions flicts inherent in transitions to democracy often in Spain, Brazil, Uruguay, South Korea, and occur on two fronts: between the opponents and Bulgaria. In contrast, wherever military cohe- defenders of the authoritarian regime about de- sion disintegrated because of a failed foreign mocracy and among the proto-democratic actors adventure—Greece, Portugal, and Argentina— against one another for the best chance under and in regimes where the military were e¤ec- democracy. The image of the campaign for de- tively subjected to civilian control—all the other mocracy as a struggle of the society against the Eastern European countries—the process of state is a useful fiction during the first period constituting a new regime was less a¤ected by of transition, as a unifying slogan of the forces elements of extrication. opposed to the current authoritarian regime. But Extrication societies are divided in many ways, and the very essence of democracy is the competition among Since extrication has been extensively studied, political forces with conflicting interests. This I proceed schematically. First, let me follow situation creates a dilemma: to bring about O’Donnell (1979) and O’Donnell and Schmitter democracy, anti-authoritarian forces must unite (1986) in distinguishing four political actors: against , but to be victorious under democracy, they must compete with each 22. These need not be monolithic. Note that, as a leg- acy of the Stalin era, in Eastern Europe there have Excerpted from: Adam Przeworski, Democracy and been two organized forces of repression: the armed the Market: Political and Economic Reforms in Eastern forces for external defense under the control of the Europe and Latin America. New York: Cambridge Ministry of Defense, and the army for internal order University Press, 1991. 6 Cambridge University Press, under the control of the Ministry of Interior. The au- 1991. Reprinted with the permission of Cambridge Uni- tonomy of the secret police varied from country to versity Press. country and period to period. Sources of Democracy 77

Hardliners and Reformers (who may or may not di¤erent interests. They may be distinguished have been Liberalizers) inside the authoritarian only by risk aversion. Moderates may be those bloc and Moderates and Radicals in the opposi- who fear Hardliners, not necessarily those who tion. Hardliners tend to be found in the repres- have less radical goals.24 sive cores of the authoritarian bloc: the police, Extrication can result only from understand- the legal bureaucracy, censors, among journal- ings between Reformers and Moderates. Extri- ists, and so on. Reformers tend to be recruited cation is possible if (1) an agreement can be from among politicians of the regime and from reached between Reformers and Moderates to some groups outside the state apparatus: sectors establish institutions under which the social of the bourgeoisie under capitalism, and some forces they represent would have a significant economic managers under socialism.23 Moder- political presence in the democratic system, (2) ates and Radicals may but need not represent Reformers can deliver the consent of Hardliners or neutralize them, and (3) Moderates can con- 23. The attitudes of the bourgeoisie toward authori- trol Radicals. tarian regimes belie facile generalizations. The reason The last two conditions are logically prior, is the following. The bourgeoisie has three ways of since they determine the set of possible solutions defending its interests: (1) Under democracy, it can for Reformers and Moderates. Whatever agree- organize itself as a party and compete; (2) under any ment they reach, it must induce Hardliners to regime, it can organize itself as a pressure group and go along with Reformers and dissuade Radicals use privileged channels of access to the state; (3) under from mobilizing for a more profound transfor- any regime, decentralized pursuit of profit constitutes a mation. When can these conditions be satisfied? constraint on the actions of the state directed against its interests (‘‘structural dependence of the state on If the armed forces control extrication, they capital’’—see Przeworski and Wallerstein 1988). Now, must either opt for reforms or be cajoled into contrary to Marx, the last constraint may turn out to cooperation, or at least passivity, by Reformers. be insu‰cient to protect the bourgeoisie from the state. Moderates must pay the price. But if Reformers In fact, several military regimes in Latin America did are a viable interlocutor for Moderates only enormous damage to some sectors of the bourgeoisie: when they can control or deliver the armed Martı´nez de Hoz destroyed one-half of Argentine forces, Moderates have no political importance firms, and the Brazilian military built a state sector that unless they can restrain Radicals. Moderate competed with private firms. This is why by 1978 the gentlemen in cravats may lead civilized negotia- leading sectors of the Paulista bourgeoisie saw the mil- tions in government palaces, but if streets are itary regime as a threat. Thus, at least in Brazil, the anti-authoritarian posture arose from economic liber- filled with crowds or factories are occupied by alism. (For interpretations of this posture, see Bresser workers calling for the necks of their inter- Pereira 1978 and Cardoso 1983.) In turn, in countries locutors, their moderation is irrelevant. Hence, where popular mobilization is feeble, the bourgeoisie Moderates must either deliver terms tolerable can compete quite well under democratic conditions. to Radicals or, if they cannot obtain such terms This seems to be the case in Ecuador, where the from Reformers, they must leave enough power autonomy of the technobureaucrats—the style rather in the hands of the apparatus of repression to than the substance of economic policy making, intimidate Radicals. On the one hand, Moder- according to Conaghan (1983)—turned the bourgeoisie ates need Radicals to be able to put pressure against the military government and where the bour- on Reformers; on the other, Moderates fear that geoisie did not fear electoral competition. Similarly, in the socialist countries some factory managers saw relatively early the possibility of con- 24. In fact, in Poland in 1981 moderates were those verting their political power into economic power who perceived Soviet intervention as imminent; radi- (Hankiss 1989) and supported democratization. cals, those who saw it as unlikely. Chapter 2 78

Table 2.2

Moderates ally with Radicals Reformers 8 >Hardliners Authoritarian regime survives Authoritarian regime holds, > <> in old form: with concessions: Reformers ally with 2,1 4,2 > > :>Moderates Democracy without guarantees: Democracy with guarantees: 1,4 3,3

Radicals will not consent to the deal they work liberalization. They are entering in the sense used out with Reformers. No wonder the feasible set above. is often empty. Under such conditions, Reformers have a When can an agreement that satisfies all these dominant strategy, namely, always to ally with constraints be reached? Reformers face a strate- Hardliners. If Moderates ally with Radicals, the gic choice of remaining in an authoritarian alli- opposition is defeated and the authoritarian bloc ance with Hardliners or seeking a democratic survives intact, which is better for Reformers alliance with Moderates. Moderates, in turn, can than democracy brought about by a coalition seek all-out destruction of the political forces of Moderates and Radicals that o¤ers no guar- organized under the authoritarian regime by antees. If Moderates seek an alliance with allying with Radicals, or they can seek an ac- Reformers, some concessions are made, to the commodation by negotiating with Reformers. cost of Hardliners. These concessions are better Suppose the structure of the situation is as in for Reformers than democracy even with guar- table 2.2.25 antees. Hence, potential Reformers are always If Reformers ally with Hardliners and Moder- better o¤ defending the authoritarian regime in ates with Radicals, two opposing coalitions are alliance with Hardliners. formed, and they fight it out. If Reformers ally The defining feature of this situation is that with Moderates and Moderates with Reformers, Reformers have no political strength of their the outcome is democracy with guarantees. own and thus no prospect of being politically The o¤-diagonal outcomes should be read as successful under democracy. Without special follows: When Moderates ally with Radicals guarantees, they will do very badly under de- and Reformers with Moderates, Reformers are mocracy, and even with guarantees they are still accepting the democracy without guarantees that better o¤ under the protection of their authori- results from the Radical–Moderate coalition. tarian allies. This was the case of Poland in When Reformers ally with Hardliners and Mod- 1980–1.26 Any solution had to satisfy two con- erates with Reformers, Moderates are accepting ditions: (1) The opposition insisted on the prin- ciple of open electoral competition, and (2) the 25. The first number in each cell represents the value party wanted to have a guarantee that it could of this outcome to Reformers; the second number, win the electoral competition. The opposition to Moderates (4 is better than 3, and so on). These was willing to have the party win; it did not de- numbers are not interpersonally comparable; they only rank the alternatives. Hence, Moderates may be mis- 26. The Polish situation was analyzed in game theo- erable under their second-worst option, while Reform- retic terms by Stefan Nowak in Polityka, , ers may be quite happy with theirs. September 1981. Sources of Democracy 79

Table 2.3

Moderates ally with Radicals Reformers 8 >Hardliners Authoritarian regime survives Authoritarian regime holds, > <> in old form: with concessions: Reformers ally with 2,1 3,2 > > :>Moderates Democracy without guarantees: Democracy with guarantees: 1,4 4,3

mand a chance to win but only to compete. The Suppose that Reformers do have su‰cient party did not object to elections but wanted to political strength to be able to compete under have a good chance of winning.27 But in clan- democratic conditions if they are given institu- destine polls, the party was running at about 3 tional guarantees. Is this su‰cient for them to percent in voting intentions. No way was found opt for democracy? Consider table 2.3. Here to overcome this impediment. If the party had Reformers have political weight independent of been getting 35 percent, it would have been Hardliners: They can get some support under child’s play to invent an electoral system that competitive conditions, and they prefer democ- would be competitive and give it a good chance racy with guarantees over other alternatives. of winning. But not at 3 percent. No institutions Yet the outcome for Reformers depends on the existed to satisfy the constraints imposed by the actions of Moderates. If Moderates opt for interests and outside opportunities of the con- guarantees, Reformers are better o¤ under flicting political forces.28 Under such conditions, democracy, but if Moderates ally with Radi- Reformers could not venture into a democratic cals, Reformers lose.29 And Moderates prefer alliance with Moderates. democracy without guarantees. Examine this structure of conflict in the extensive form; that is, 27. This general posture was put forth rather directly assume that first Reformers decide what to do, by Jakub Berman, number-two man in Poland during anticipating the reaction of Moderates (see figure the Stalinist period, in a 1981 interview. Referring to 2.1). Reformers analyze the situation as follows: the postwar election, Berman said: ‘‘To whom were we If they ally with Hardliners, the result will be the supposed to yield power? Perhaps Mikołajczyk [leader status quo, which is the second-best outcome. of the Peasant party]? Or perhaps those standing even They would be better o¤ under democracy farther to the right of Mikołajczyk? Or who the hell with guarantees. But if they decide to negotiate knows who else? You will tell me immediately that this would represent respect for democracy. So what? Who needs such democracy! Now, by the way, we cannot 28. The same strategic situation was solved in March have free elections either, even less now than ten or 1989 by a stroke of genius. Someone suggested creating twenty years ago, because we would lose. There is no an upper chamber of the parliament and having com- doubt about this. So what is the sense of such elections? pletely free elections to this chamber while guarantee- Unless we would want to show ourselves to be such ing the Communist party and its allies a majority in super-democrats, such gentlemen, that we would take the lower house and hence the right to form the top hats o¤ our heads, bow down and say: ‘Be wel- government. come, we are retiring, take power for yourself’’’ (in- 29. In this game there is no equilibrium in pure terview in Toran´ska 1985: 290). strategies. Chapter 2 80

Figure 2.1 with Moderates, the latter will opt for an alliance Moderates to cooperate. Hence, if the original with Radicals, which will result in the worst situation is to be repeated, democracy can evolve outcome for Reformers. Hence, Reformers stay spontaneously. with the regime. But I do not think that situations in which Will not democracy come about nevertheless, regime change is at stake are repeatable. These as a result of repetitions of this situation?30 are unique situations; something cracks in the Imagine everyone knows that this strategic situ- authoritarian power apparatus; a group begins ation is almost certain to be repeated forever. to feel that perhaps it would prefer to share Moderates know that if they respond to the power with consent rather than monopolize it opening by embracing the demands of Radicals, by force, decides to make a move, and turns to Reformers will ally with Hardliners next time eventual partners outside the regime in quest of around. Hence, the payo¤ to Moderates from assurances about its role under democracy. Once defecting on the first round will be {4; 1; 1; ...} Reformers decide to make a move, alea iacta or another mixture of 4s and 1s, depending on est—they cannot go back to the status quo. the punishment strategy chosen by Reformers.31 Payo¤s for the future change as a result of But if Moderates decide to give guarantees on actions chosen now. To go back is to admit the the first round, Reformers will respond in kind, failure of the strategy of democratic opening and and the payo¤ to Moderates will be {3; 3; 3; ...}. to meet with the wrath of Hardliners. Reformers It is easy to see that there are many Reform- who decide to go back almost never survive their ers’ punishment strategies that should persuade failure; they are playing for broke.32 This does not mean that an opening may not be tried again 30. The paragraphs that follow result from a heated in the future by new Reformers; this is what did discussion with Jon Elster, who, as always, forced me happen in South Korea and in Poland. But these to decide what I really think. are new forces, facing new circumstances. And 31. Tit for tat, the strategy people tend to choose in if the Reformers’ strategy is successful and de- experimental situations, does maximize overtime pay- mocracy is institutionalized, the payo¤s change o¤, but it is not a strategy for perfect equilibrium. In as well. The devolution of power to democratic turn, there are a very large number of strategies that support the cooperative outcome. On this and many 32. I say ‘‘almost’’ because of Brazil, where the archi- other technicalities involved here, see the excellent tects of the failed ‘‘decompression’’ of 1974 succeeded textbook by Rasmusen 1989. in regrouping and trying again. Sources of Democracy 81

institutions is irreversible even if democracy can their chances, and skeptical that their victories be subverted anew.33 will ever be tolerated. Yet the attraction of an Does this argument imply that democracy is open-ended democratic interplay is irresistible, never established as an equilibrium but can only and Radicals find that to abstain is to forsake result from a normative commitment to democ- popular support. As the history of Socialist par- racy? No; it is su‰cient to tinker with the payo¤s ties in Western Europe demonstrates, all political to see that there can exist unique situations in forces face the alternatives of joining or vanish- which the equilibrium outcome is democracy. ing, and, except for the Anarchists, who persev- There are two possibilities. One is that Radi- ered in resisting ‘‘the siren song of elections,’’ cals will accept democracy with guarantees; the they all joined (see Przeworski 1985: ch. 1). other, that Moderates will continue to be pro- If Radicals refuse to participate in the insti- tected by the existence of autonomous armed tutions forged by Moderates and Reformers, forces. Moderates’ interests may still be such that they The first possibility—that Radicals will cease prefer a democracy in which the forces in the being radical—is not so farfetched as it may first civil society represented by Reformers have a appear. Until democracy is established, forces significant presence to one that is dominated that seek profound political or economic trans- by Radicals.34 Under such conditions, the pay- formation have no alternative to channeling o¤s in the game tree above will be interchanged: their actions into streets and factories; there are Moderates will prefer democracy with guaran- no political institutions where their demands tees for Reformers to an alliance with Radicals. will not meet with violent repression. Yet once What this often means is that some sectors asso- a competitive democratic framework is estab- ciated with the authoritarian regime continue lished because of an agreement between Moder- to enjoy the protection of the armed forces. If ates and Reformers, Radicals find that they too Reformers have some political strength of their can play the game, participate. They tend to be own and if Moderates prefer an institutional wary of democratic institutions, distrustful of arrangement in which the armed forces remain autonomous as a counterbalance to the demands 33. This is why I do not think that evolutionary of Radicals, then Reformers have little to fear theories of institutions (Schotter 1981, 1986) can ex- from democracy. Under such conditions, the plain transitions to democracy. equilibrium outcome will be democracy, but a Some technical issues are involved here. The results democracy in which the armed forces will remain concerning the emergence of cooperation in repeated free of civilian control and will exercise tutelage games govern only those situations that are repeated over the democratic process.35 exactly; specifically, with the same payo¤s. To the best of my knowledge, we know little about games in which component subgames change somewhat from 34. In Figure 2.1, let the payo¤ to Moderates in a de- one round to the next. Benhabib and Radner (1988) mocracy with guarantees be 4, with no. 3. analyzed a labor–capital game in which payo¤s 35. I realize that the game is in fact more complicated change and discovered that if they change greatly from than my analysis suggests, since I take the behavior of one subgame to the next, the equilibrium is non- Hardliners as parametric. Yet Hardliners may, for cooperative; if they change somewhat, the path of the example, provoke Radicals in order to undermine the equilibria moves monotonically to cooperative equilib- agreement between Moderates and Reformers. In rium, which reigns once the game becomes stationary. many cases of transition, there emerge shadowy groups This result makes intuitive sense, so the relevant ques- that appear to be Radicals but may be Provocateurs: tion is how much payo¤s change from one situation grapo in Spain provides one illustration; the Tablada to the next. My argument is that, at least for the a¤air in Argentina another. Reformers, they change drastically. Chapter 2 82

But why would Moderates tolerate military Table 2.4 autonomy? Why would they consent to military Probability that a coup will tutelage that restricts the possible range of dem- occur ocratic outcomes, at times humiliates civilian politicians, and introduces a source of instability Eventually into the democratic system?36 Immediately but not now Except in Poland, the communist systems With tutelage 0.20 0.60 of Eastern Europe produced civilian regimes. With civilian The military and most of the forces of order control 0.80 0.01 were subject to minute political control, which extended even to operational matters.37 Hence, it should not be surprising that in conflicts over ticularly poignant, since the impunity enjoyed the leading role of the Communist parties, the by kidnappers, torturers, and murderers has a armed forces in all Eastern European countries profoundly demoralizing e¤ect on all political placed themselves squarely on the side of those life. Among the recent transitions to democracy, who wanted to abolish the communist monopoly Spain and Greece are the only countries where on power. ‘‘The army wants to serve not a party democratic governments succeeded in establish- but the nation’’—this has been the generals’ ing e¤ective civilian control over the military and paradigmatic declaration. From a Latin Ameri- freed themselves from this tutelage. can perspective, this noble sentiment sounds One obvious answer is that Moderates fear ominous: not a pledge to democratic values but that any attempt to impose civilian control will an assertion of independence. immediately provoke exactly what it is intended In most Latin American countries, the mili- to eliminate: military intervention. The strategic tary have preserved their autonomy and have calculus involved must be the following. First, continued to exercise tutelage over the political the probability of an immediate coup after any system, not only in countries where the transition attempt to establish civilian control must be seen to democracy was a result of negotiations, but as higher than when the military are left alone. even in Argentina, where the armed forces suf- Hence, even if civilian control, once established, fered a humiliating external defeat. The specter would greatly reduce the likelihood of military of military intervention is a permanent con- intervention, the probability that the coup will straint on the political process, and the eventual ever occur is lower without civilian control. reaction of the military is a consideration that Consider table 2.4. The probability that the mil- permeates everyday political life in the new itary will step in now or in the future if they democracies. The Argentine experience is par- continue to exercise tutelage over the political system is 68 percent, while the probability that 36. In October 1987, the Brazilian government raised they will undertake a coup if the government military pay by more than 100 percent overnight in re- seeks to impose civilian control is 80.2 percent.38 action to a takeover of a city hall by a small military unit stationed in a provincial town—this after the minister of finance had publicly committed himself not 38. Let p be the probability of an immediate coup to do it. under tutelage, and t the probability of an eventual coup in the same case. Let q be the probability of 37. The secret police are a di¤erent matter. Conflicts an immediate coup if the government imposes civilian between the secret police and Communist parties have control, and c the probability of an eventual coup. punctuated much of the political life of communist Then the total probability of a coup under tutelage is regimes. The secret police are the group that had the p þ (1 p)t, and under attempted civilian control it is most to lose from the dismantling of communism, and q þ (1 q)c. they were the target of popular ire in several countries. Sources of Democracy 83

This is not the end of the di‰culty, for not all mobilizations, their tutelage is a bulwark for coups are the same. One argument for punishing established political parties. violations of human rights is that the e¤ect of Second, the problem in many countries with punishment is dissuasive: The military will think a long tradition of military intervention is the twice before stepping in again because they know absence of institutional models through which that once out of power they will be punished. civilian control over the military can be exer- That may be true, but if this argument is valid, it cised.40 Through the chain of command, the also implies that if the military are not deterred military are responsible directly to the president by the threat of punishment from stepping in, it rather than to parliamentary committees and will be less likely to give up power because of civilian bureaus that supervise particular aspects this threat. Thus, imposition of civilian control of their conduct. Without such an apparatus of may lower the probability of a coup but increase civilian control, the choice faced by democratic the conditional probability that, once it occurs, governments may be one of either tolerating the coup will be highly repressive, a golpe duro. military autonomy or destroying the military Thus, if a government is intent on not pro- altogether.41 And here, I suspect, nationalism voking a coup and not risking repression, it may plays a role: No president can a¤ord to commit swallow its moral outrage and its democratic himself or herself to actions that will undermine ideals and accept the limits set by military tute- the ability of the nation to defend itself. Perhaps lage.39 But I suspect that this reasoning is not when the choice of strategy vis-a`-vis the military su‰cient to explain the behavior of civilian poli- appears to be one of leaving it intact or dis- ticians vis-a`-vis the military. There are two rea- mantling it altogether, the perpetuation of mili- sons why democratic politicians may not want to tary domination turns out to be a lesser evil for dismantle the threat from the military even if nationalistic politicians. they could. The issue of civilian control over the mili- First, Fontana (1984: 121) observed that in tary is thus not only whether it is prudent to 1981 the Argentine political parties feared that if attempt it but also who wants to have it.42 Mili- the threat from the military was removed, a new tary tutelage may be preferred by some civilian wave of popular mobilization would push them, as in 1973, farther to the left than they wanted: 40. This observation is due to Jose´ Murilo de They feared radicals. To paraphrase an expres- Carvalho. sion Ernest Bevin once used about the Labour 41. For example, Delich (1984: 135) presents as fol- party, they ‘‘did not want to be put in the posi- lows the choice available to the Argentine demo- tion of having to listen to their own people.’’ If cratic government. Since the atrocities committed by the military can be counted on to repress popular the military constituted acts sanctioned by the military as an institution, under written orders and under con- trol by the military command, the democratic govern- 39. In a 1987 article entitled ‘‘La polı´tica militar del ment could only either condemn the armed forces as a gobierno constitucional argentino,’’ Fontana stresses whole or forget the whole matter. that in 1983 the government did not have a good pic- ture of the situation in the armed forces, that it believed 42. This is how in October 1987 Jose´ Murilo de Car- erroneously that the military would purify itself if given valho (1987: 18) characterized the attitudes of the Bra- a chance, and that it repeatedly underestimated the zilian political forces in the Constituent Assembly: ‘‘It solidarity among military generations. All of this may is more di‰cult to visualize a surge of solid political be true, but what strikes me is that the article fails will to construct the hegemony of civil power. As we to demonstrate that the government had any military have seen, such a will certainly does not exist in the policy. political action of the actual occupant of the presidency of the Republic, and it does not manifest itself in an Chapter 2 84

political forces as a protection from demands for committed between 1973 and 1978, (6) absten- greater representation, to ward o¤ pressure from tion by the political authorities from intervening those who seek a social as well as a political in the definition and application of defense poli- revolution.43 cies, including not modifying the powers of Extrications thus leave institutional traces. military courts, the command structure, and the Just note the price extorted by Pinochet for his military budget and not interfering in the pro- consent to free elections: (1) permanent o‰ce for motion of generals (normally a presidential pre- the current commanders in chief of the armed rogative), (7) the right to name nine members to forces and the police, (2) protection of the the Senate, (8) autonomy of the central bank, the ‘‘prestige of members of the military and the president of which was chosen by the military, police,’’ (3) an ‘‘energetic struggle against ter- (9) acceptance of privatizations conducted dur- rorism,’’ (4) respect for the opinions of a national ing the last months of the military regime with- security council to be formed of four military out investigation of how they were conducted, representatives and four civilians, (5) mainte- and (10) automatic allocation of 20 percent of nance of the amnesty covering political crimes copper revenues to the military budget. When the armed forces themselves are the Reformers unambivalent way in the majority party, the pmdb.Itis and the resistance comes from bureaucrats, the not even necessary to say that there are no traces of situation is simpler, even if at moments dra- such will in the pfl, the ptb, etc. Whoever observes the matic.44 Yet note that in Poland, where the political scene in the new Republic has the impression impetus for reforms came from the head of the that military tutelage is something normal and that it armed forces, the regime also succeeded in should continue to be exercised.’’ exacting several guarantees: (1) The Communist It should not be surprising, therefore, that the Latin party was guaranteed 35 percent of the seats in American Weekly Report of 15 September 1988 (WR– the more important house of the parliament 88–36) could report, under the title ‘‘Brazil’s Military Gain Quietly What Pinochet Demands Loudly,’’ that (Sejm), and its then allies were given another 30 ‘‘as some Brazilian military men have readily admitted percent: in principle, ample support to form a in private, whereas elsewhere civilians have worried government; (2) it was understood that the op- how much autonomy they could or should grant the position would not block the election of General military, in Brazil the military have carefully dosed Jaruzelski as president; and (3) matters of exter- [prescribed] the autonomy of the civilians.’’ nal defense and internal order were left under the 43. Jose´ Antonio Cheibub (personal communication) control of communists. o¤ered the following criticism of this hypothesis. ‘‘The Hence, the optimal strategy of extrication is explanation based on the elite’s fear of popular mobi- inconsistent. The forces pushing for democracy lization is not good for two reasons. First, because must be prudent ex ante, and they would like to leaders of countries that face a problem of civilian be resolute ex post. But decisions made ex ante control over the military learned (or should have create conditions that are hard to reverse ex post, learned) that the protection the military o¤ers (from one perspective) is also a threat (from another per- spective). In other words, their job as politicians is also 44. The program of political reforms proposed by threatened by the very tutelage they want to maintain General Jaruzelski at the party plenum in January 1989 to protect them from popular mobilization. . . . Second, failed to win a majority. At that moment, the general it seems to me that this explanation may be . . . trans- (who was the commander in chief ), the minister of de- formed into an argument that assumes the political fense, and the minister of interior (both also generals) elite in those countries to be inherently conservative; o¤ered their resignations and walked out of the meet- that it always prefers the risk of a military coup to a ing. Only then did the Central Committee deem desir- greater representativeness of the regime.’’ able the turn toward negotiations with the opposition. Sources of Democracy 85

since they preserve the power of forces associated True, in Chile, South Korea, and Pakistan with the ancien re´gime. Ex post the democratic attempts to modify the constitutions left as the forces regret their prudence, but ex ante they authoritarian legacy have thus far been abortive, have no choice but to be prudent.45 and in Uruguay a referendum failed to reverse Yet the conditions created by transitions the auto-amnesty declared by the military. In negotiated with the ancien re´gime are not irre- Poland, the initial agreement concluded in versible. The essential feature of democracy April 1989 unraveled immediately as a result of is that nothing is decided definitively. If sover- the elections of June 1989, and its remains were eignty resides with the people, the people can gradually destroyed. Transition by extrication decide to undermine all the guarantees reached generates incentives for the democratic forces to by politicians around a negotiating table. Even remove the guarantees left as the authoritarian the most institutionalized guarantees give at best legacy. Hence, it leaves an institutional legacy a high degree of assurance, never certainty.46 that is inherently unstable. . . .

45. Since democracy has been consolidated in a num- ber of countries, some North American intellectuals The Political Dynamics of Economic Reform now advise us that the protagonists in the struggles against authoritarianism should have been more radi- Introduction cal in pushing for social and economic transformation. For a fantasy of this kind, see Cumings 1989. The goal of recent economic reforms, under- 46. Moreover, this entire analysis assumes more taken in several countries around the globe, is knowledge than the protagonists normally have or can to organize an economy that rationally allocates have. In Poland, everyone miscalculated at several resources and in which the state is financially points: The party got so little electoral support in the solvent. first round of elections in June 1989 that the legitimacy These are market-oriented reforms. Ration- of the negotiated deal was undermined, the heretofore alizing the allocation of resources requires loyal allies of the communists decided to venture out on their own, and the whole carefully designed plan of organizing new markets, deregulating prices, transition unraveled. The opposition had to make last- attenuating monopolies, and lowering protec- minute additional concessions to keep the reformers in tion. Making the state solvent entails reducing the game. I suspect that if the party had known what public expenditures, increasing revenues, and at would happen, it would not have agreed to elections; times selling public assets. if the opposition had anticipated what happened, it Such reforms necessarily cause a temporary would not have made the concessions. fall in aggregate consumption. They are socially Party strategists cited all kinds of reasons why Soli- costly and politically risky. Perhaps in the long darity would do badly in the elections of June 1989. An run reforms do accomplish all one former Polish eminent reformer assured me that party candidates minister of the economy announced they would: would win a majority in the elections to the Senate. (In fact, they received 15.8 percent of the vote; see motivate, generate market clearing, and satisfy Ostrowski 1989.) But the other side was equally sur- social justice (Baka 1986: 46). Yet meanwhile prised. When asked whether political developments they hurt large social groups and evoke opposi- followed his plan, Wałe˛sa responded: ‘‘My project was tion from important political forces. And if di¤erent from what happened. With regard to politics, that happens, democracy may be undermined or I wanted to stop at the conquests of the round table: reforms abandoned, or both. make a pause and occupy ourselves with the economy Even if governments that launch such reforms and the society. But, by a stroke of bad luck, we won often hate to admit it, a temporary economic the elections’’ (interview in Le Figaro, Paris, 26 Sep- deterioration is inevitable. Inflation must flare up tember 1989, p. 4). Chapter 2 86

when prices are deregulated. Unemployment of One way to think about reforms is in the tra- capital and labor must increase when compe- ditional terms of international financial insti- tition is intensified. Allocative e‰ciency must tutions,11 distinguishing stabilization, structural temporarily decline when the entire economic adjustment, and privatization. Stabilization con- structure is being transformed. Structural trans- sists of short-term measures designed to slow formations of economic systems are costly. down inflation, reduce the balance-of-payments Can such transformations be accomplished deficit, and cut the government deficit. Structural under democratic conditions?1 The question adjustment is the set of measures designed to about the relationship of democracy and reforms make the economy competitive. It is the most concerns transitional e¤ects. The reason is the heterogeneous category, comprising everything following: Even if the post-reform system would from trade liberalization to price deregulation to be more e‰cient—more, even if the new steady tax reform. Privatization is self-explanatory. . . . state would be Pareto-superior to the status quo, that is, no one would be worse o¤ in the Conclusion new system and someone would be better o¤— Whatever their long-term consequences, in the a transient deterioration of material conditions short run reforms are likely to cause inflation, may be su‰cient to undermine either democracy unemployment, and resource misallocation as or the reform process. . . . well as to generate volatile changes in relative Structural economic transformations are being incomes. These are not politically popular con- undertaken in many countries, South and East, sequences anywhere. And under such conditions, under nascent democratic institutions. Four democracy in the political realm works against outcomes may occur under such conditions: (1) economic reforms. In Comisso’s (1988) words, Reforms may advance under democratic con- a hierarchy may reemerge because the market ditions, (2) reforms may be forced through by failed to deliver e‰cient results. a dictatorship, (3) democracy may survive by abandoning reforms, and (4) both reforms and Political Dynamics of Reforms: A Model democracy may be undermined. . . . Both political reactions to reform and their 1. By posing the question in this manner, I do not eventual success or failure depend not only on want to imply that they would in fact be accomplished their economic e¤ects but also on political con- under a dictatorship. Remmer (1986) provides per- ditions. In November 1987 a program of reforms imf suasive evidence that the rate of success of the ’s failed to win majority support in a referendum Standby Agreements, albeit not very high, was slightly organized by the communist government in higher for democratic than for authoritarian regimes in Latin America between 1954 and 1984. Haggard Poland. Yet economic reforms by the postcom- (1986) found that among the thirty cases of Extended munist government enjoyed overwhelming sup- Fund Facility programs he examined, imf disburse- port. The program was almost the same; it was ments were interrupted or canceled for noncompliance the government that changed. Hence, the ques- in all the democratic countries except for the special tion is not only how deep and wide is the valley case of India, but the rate of success among the ‘‘weak’’ of transition but also which political forces are authoritarian regimes he considered was not di¤erent. In turn, Stallings and Kaufman (1989) found in their 11. I say ‘‘traditional’’ because recently the World analysis of nine Latin American countries that whereas Bank has become much more concerned about income ‘‘established democracies’’ did about as well as au- distribution and, hence, taxation and poverty. See the thoritarian regimes with regard to stabilization, only 1989 Development Report. the latter progressed with regard to both stabilization and structural reform. Sources of Democracy 87

most apt to traverse it. This is the question particular, opposition parties and unions—are examined here. strong enough to be able to sabotage them and Three somewhat stylized facts organize this not large enough to internalize the entire cost analysis. First, it seems that reforms are almost of arresting them. As Haggard and Kaufman invariably launched by surprise. Second, they (1989: 269) put it, ‘‘The greatest di‰culty comes often generate widespread initial support that in intermediate cases where labor is capable of erodes as social costs set in. Last, reforms tend to defensive mobilization, but uncertain about its follow a stop-and-go pattern. . . . long-term place in the political system.’’54 To put it bluntly, reform-oriented governments face Political Consequences of Economic Reforms a choice of either cooperating with opposition parties and unions, as did the Spanish Socialist If reforms are to proceed under democratic government, or destroying them, as did the conditions, distributional conflicts must be insti- Bolivian government of Paz Estenssoro with re- tutionalized; all groups must channel their gard to unions. demands through democratic institutions and The role of unions is crucial for two reasons. abjure other tactics. Regardless of how pressing On the one hand, they organize the people whose their needs may be, the politically relevant demands are the potential source of wage pres- groups must be willing to subject their interests sure. If workers and salaried employees have to the verdict of democratic institutions. They market power, they can exercise this power to must be willing to accept defeat and to wait, push for wage increases. And during reforms, confident that these institutions will continue to wage pressure is a source of inertial inflation; it o¤er opportunities the next time around. They slows down the recovery and results in increasing must adopt the institutional calendar as the di¤erentials among di¤erent sectors and occupa- temporal horizon of their actions, thinking in tions. Wage restraint is a necessary condition for terms of forthcoming elections, contract nego- the success of reforms. On the other hand, union tiations, or at least fiscal years.53 They must federations can control the behavior of their assume the stance put forth by John McGurk, constituents. Whether by using coercive powers chairman of the British , in 1919: delegated by the state or by relying on their per- ‘‘We are either constitutionalists or we are not suasive powers, the leadership of a union can constitutionalists. If we are constitutionalists, if persuade the rank and file to wait for reforms to we believe in the e‰cacy of the political weapon bear fruit. Unions have what is best described by (and we do, or why do we have a Labour Party?) the Spanish term poder convocatorio: the power then it is both unwise and undemocratic because to discipline the behaviors of their constituents in we fail to get a majority at the polls to turn the collective interest. around and demand that we should substitute industrial action’’ (Miliband 1975: 69). 54. The best example of unions that are neither strong Reforms can progress under two polar con- enough nor large enough comes, again, from Argen- ditions of the organization of political forces: tina. As I am writing this text, the Argentine Union The latter have to be very strong and support the Federation (cgt) has called for price controls on all reform program, or they have to be very weak basic consumer goods, imposition of exchange con- and unable to oppose it e¤ectively. Reforms are trols, an end to the government’s plans for privatiza- least likely to advance when political forces—in tion, abandonment of the plans to streamline public administration, and massive wage increases (Latin American Weekly Report, WR–90–11, 22 March 53. This notion of institutional time is due to Norbert 1990). Lechner. Chapter 2 88

To function as partners, unions must consti- constituents as do unions. They may refuse to tute encompassing, centralized organizations and process demands they find untimely or inappro- must trust in the good faith of the government. priate, but they face competition from other Such organizations must be encompassing: They parties and the threat that popular mobilization must associate large parts of their potential con- will assume extraparliamentary forms. stituencies. And they must be centralized: They In sum, to advance reforms, governments must be able to control the behavior of their must either seek the broadest possible sup- constituents. Finally, they must have confidence port from unions, opposition parties, and other in the government: They must trust that the encompassing and centralized organizations, or government will not be unfair in distributing the they must work to weaken these organizations costs and the benefits of reforms and that it will and try to make their opposition ine¤ective. be competent in conducting reforms. Obviously, the latter strategy raises the question This assertion is supported not only by ex- of democracy. Is a government that resorts to a tensive evidence from the developed countries, state of siege to counter opposition to reforms where encompassing, centralized unions are democratic? Moreover, if a government adopts willing to restrain their wage demands when so- the strategy of forcing reforms against popu- cial democratic parties are in o‰ce, but also by lar opposition, the posture of the armed forces the experience of some newly democratic coun- becomes relevant. This posture largely defines tries. In post-1976 Spain, a Socialist govern- whether nondemocratic alternatives are per- ment has advanced a program of industrial ceived as feasible, either by those who are modernization under conditions of very high tempted to force reforms against democratically unemployment—until recently with the consent organized opposition or by the groups that are of the unions. In Poland, Solidarnos´c´ o¤ered a determined to defend their interests in any way striking moratorium to facilitate the reforms ini- possible against a democratically organized pro- tiated by the postcommunist government. In reform majority. When the armed forces are in- Brazil, a movement of ‘‘results-oriented union- dependent of civilian control and are present as a ism’’ was willing to do the same, and it is signif- political actor, various groups in the civil society icant that its general secretary is the first union engage in what Huntington (1968) termed prae- leader to become a minister of labor.55 torian politics: strategies such as ‘‘If you do not Political parties represent more heterogeneous moderate your demands, we will ask the military interests, and their impact is potentially wider. to intervene’’ or ‘‘If you do not concede to our They play the central role in presenting alter- demands, we will create a disorder which will natives and molding attitudes with regard to provoke the military to intervene.’’ The com- particular governments as well as with regard to petitive political process in the presence of an the very project of structural transformation. Yet autonomous military creates the permanent pos- parties, at least modern noncommunist parties, sibility of military intervention. do not have the same power to discipline their Responding to this bipolar choice, the new democratic governments can pursue two con- 55. Antonio Rogerio Magri broke ranks with Brazil- trasting political strategies to control economic ian unionism when, as president of the Electrical conflicts, placing di¤erent emphases on eco- Workers, he made statements such as ‘‘All we workers nomic logic and on participation. Reform- want is that firms invest, so that the economy will ex- oriented governments can insulate themselves pand. There is no better guarantee of employment than from popular demands and impose economic economic expansion’’ (Journal da Tarde,Sa˜o Paulo, 27 policies from above. Or, trying to mobilize sup- July 1987, p. 12). port for reform programs, they can seek to or- Sources of Democracy 89

chestrate consensus by engaging in widespread the bitter-pill strategy depends on its initial bru- concertation with parties, unions, and other tality, on proceeding as quickly as possible with organizations. Hence, governments face the the most radical measures, on ignoring all the choice of either involving a broad range of special interests and all immediate demands. political forces in the shaping of reforms, thus Any government that is resolute must proceed in compromising their economic soundness, or of spite of the clamor of voices that call for soften- trying to undermine all opposition to the pro- ing or slowing down the reform program. Since gram. Confronted with this dilemma and the reformers know what is good and since they resistance that the social costs of reforms inher- are eager to go ahead as fast as possible, politi- ently engender, governments tend to vacillate cal conflicts seem just a waste of time. Hence, between the technocratic political style inherent market-oriented reforms are introduced by de- in market-oriented reforms and the participatory cree or are rammed through legislatures. . . . style required to maintain consensus. . . . At the same time, reforms require polit- Market-oriented economic reforms are an ap- ical support from individuals at the polls, from plication of a technical economic blueprint based unions and professional associations in the on theories developed inside the walls of North workplaces, and at times from opposition parties American universities and often forced on gov- in the legislature. And since they engender tran- ernments by the international lending agencies. sitional costs, reforms inevitably provoke resis- They are based on a model of economic e‰- tance. Voices are raised to the e¤ect that social ciency that is highly technical. They involve costs are excessive and the program should be choices that are not easy to explain to the general moderated. Others point out that their situation public and decisions that do not always make is in some way special and that they should be sense to popular opinion. Moreover, they call for accorded special treatment. In this situation, some measures that are most successful if they governments are tempted to seek consensus, to are introduced by surprise.56 explain and justify their program, to listen and From the political point of view, reforms are to compromise. They seek to involve opposing thus a strategy of control from above. The par- parties, unions, and employers’ associations in ticular measures implement technicians’ ideas; economic policy making, hoping that this will they are adopted without consultation and reduce conflicts and induce economic actors to sometimes announced by surprise. A reform behave in ways consistent with continuation of policy is not one that emerges from broad par- at least the basic lines of the reform program. ticipation, from a consensus among all the af- The social pacts that are sought in bargaining fected interests, from compromises. As we have typically consist of the granting of wage restraint seen, parties that want to complete structural by the unions in return for some welfare transformation have an incentive to manipulate programs together with economic policies that the agenda in such a way as to push the elector- control inflation and encourage investment and ate to accept radical reforms. And the success of employment.58 . . . Yet there are several reasons why such pacts seem unlikely to succeed in most 56. If everyone knows that the price of a particular new democracies. commodity will be deregulated, there will be a rush on it before the measure is adopted; if everyone knows 58. The economic logic and the political preconditions that wages and prices will be frozen on a particular of such pacts are discussed by Lechner (1985) and day, they will be pushed as high as possible before the Przeworski (1987b). Reviews of experience from vari- freeze takes place; if everyone knows savings will be ous countries include Cordova 1985, Pappalardo 1985, frozen, money will be withdrawn from the banks. and dos Santos 1987. Chapter 2 90

(1) Social pacts are always exclusive. . . . pacts imperil reforms. They promise consultation and shock the eventual partners with decrees;61 (2) Unions will participate in such pacts only they pass decrees and hope for consensus. As a if they are strong: encompassing, centralized, result, governments appear to lack a clear con- and politically influential. Otherwise they have ception of reforms and the resolve to pursue no reason to expect that they will benefit in them. The state begins to be perceived as the future from the present underutilization of their principal source of economic instability.62 Then power. . . . comes the time for sorcerers with yet another (3) Even if unions in the private sector may magic formula. Once confidence in reforms is be willing to participate in a pact, public sector eroded, each new government tries to make a unions have no incentive to do so. In the profit clean break with the past by doing something sector, unions trade wage restraint for employ- that people have not yet learned to distrust. ment and investment, but neither employment Reforms are addictive; a stronger dosage is nor investment in public services depends on needed each time to soothe the accumulated their employees’ wage rates. Hence, public sector desperation. Market-oriented reforms may be unions face neither the stick of unemployment based on sound economics. But they breed voo- nor the carrot of investment. Moreover, reforms doo politics. normally involve measures to reduce public The e¤ect of this style is to undermine repre- spending, a threat to the public sector unions. sentative institutions. When candidates hide their economic programs during election campaigns These obstacles are so overwhelming that or when governments adopt policies diametri- most of the time attempts to conclude social cally opposed to their electoral promises, they pacts collapse. And even when such pacts are systematically educate the population that elec- ceremoniously signed, they are rarely observed. tions have no real role in shaping policies. When Since a temporary deterioration of material governments announce vital policies by decree or conditions is inherent in any reform process, ram them through legislatures without debate, neither decrees nor concertation generate im- they teach parties, unions, and other representa- mediate economic improvement. Governments tive organizations that they have no role to play learn that decrees evoke opposition and pacts in policy making. When they revert to bargain- do not result in what they wanted to achieve ing only to orchestrate support for policies al- by decree. They discover, in the words of a ready chosen, they breed distrust and bitterness. former Argentine vice-minister of the economy, Democracy is thus weakened. The political that ‘‘requirements of participation conflict process is reduced to elections, executive decrees, with those of competence.’’60 And as pressures and sporadic outbursts of protest. The govern- mount, governments begin to vacillate between ment rules by decree, in an authoritarian fashion decretismo and pactismo in search of a peaceful resolution of conflicts. Since the idea of resolving conflicts by agreement is alluring, they turn 61. The Pacote Bresser was announced on the eve of a meeting that was designed to investigate the feasibility to making bargains when opposition against of a social pact at the personal instigation of President reforms mounts; they turn back to the techno- Sarney. cratic style when the compromises involved in 62. For complaints about the inconstancy of govern- ment policies, see the presentations by both represen- 60. Juan Carlos Torre, speaking at the seminar Tran- tatives of employers’ associations and union leaders sic¸a˜o polı´tica: Necessidades e limites da negociac¸a˜o at during the Sa˜o Paulo seminar on social pacts (Guilhon the University of Sa˜o Paulo in June 1987. See Guilhon Albuquerque and Durham 1987). Albuquerque and Durham 1987. Sources of Democracy 91

but often without much repression. All the on procedures appear to be symptoms of irra- power in the state is concentrated in the execu- tionality. Technocracy hurls itself against de- tive, which is nevertheless ine¤ectual in manag- mocracy and breeds the inclination to proceed ing the economy. People get a regular chance to against popular resistance: to suppress glasnost vote, but not to choose. Participation declines. in order to continue with perestroika. And, on Political parties, unions, and other representative the other side, as su¤ering persists, confidence organizations face a choice between passive con- erodes, and the government seems less and sent and extraparliamentary outbursts. less competent, temptations are born to defend These consequences are perhaps not inevita- one’s interests at any cost, even at the cost of ble. Indeed, the reason why the whole pattern democracy. of stop–go reforms sets in is that democracy is incomplete to begin with. In a country with constitutional provisions that force the executive References to seek formal approval for policies before they are launched, with e¤ective representative insti- Baka, Władysław. 1986. Czas reformy. Warsaw: tutions and widespread political participation, Ksiazka i Wiedza. governments could not set out on the path of Benhabib, Je¤, and Roy Radner. 1988. ‘‘Joint Exploi- reform independent of the support they could tation of a Productive Asset: A Game-Theoretic muster. Reforms would have to emerge from Approach.’’ Manuscript, and A.T.&T. widespread consultation channeled through the representative institutions and ratified by elec- Bresser Pereira, Luiz Carlos. 1978. O colapso de uma alianca de classes.Sa˜o Paulo: Editora Brasiliense. tions. The Spanish Socialist government did proceed in this fashion and succeeded in con- Cardoso, Fernando Henrique. 1983. ‘‘O papel dos empresarios no proceso de transic¸a˜o: O caso brasi- ducting the country through a painful program leiro.’’ Dados 26: 9–27. of industrial reconversion with widespread sup- Comisso, Ellen. 1988. ‘‘Market Failures and Market port (Maravall 1990).63 But this seems an ex- Socialism: Economic Problems of the Transition.’’ ceptional case among new democracies. Eastern European Politics and Societies 2: 433–465. Once democracy is weakened, pursuit of Conaghan, Catherine M. 1983. ‘‘Industrialists and the reforms may become politically destabilizing. Reformist Interregnum: Dominant Class Political Be- At some point, the alternative may become havior and Ideology in Ecuador, 1972–1979.’’ Ph.D. either to abandon reforms or to discard the rep- dissertation, Yale University. resentative institutions altogether. Authoritarian Co´rdova, Efre´n. 1985. Pactos sociais; Experieˆncia temptations are inevitable. The clamor of dis- internacional, tipologia e modelos. Brasilia: Instituto cordant voices, the delay caused by having to Brasileiro de Relacoes do Trabalho. follow procedures, and the seeming irrationality Cumings, Bruce. 1989. ‘‘The Abortive Abertura: South of conflicts inescapably cause impatience and in- Korea in the Light of Latin American Experience.’’ tolerance among the proponents of reforms. For New Left Review 173: 5–33. them, reforms are obviously needed and trans- Delich, Francisco. 1984. ‘‘Estado, sociedad y fuerzas parently rational: Doubts, oppositions, insistence armadas en la transicio´n argentina.’’ In Transicio´nala democracia. Augusto Varas, ed. Santiago: Associatio´n Chilena de Investigaciones para la Paz. 63. Note that when the Italian Communist party de- cided in 1976 to support the austerity policy of the dos Santos, Mario R. 1987. Concertacio´n polı´tica-social government, it processed one million workers through y democratizacio´n. Buenos Aires: CLACSO. evening school for a course in economics that ex- Fontana, Andres. 1984. ‘‘Fuerzas armadas, partidos plained the need for austerity. polı´ticos y transicio´n a la democracia en la Argentina.’’ Chapter 2 92

In Transicio´n a la democracia. Augusto Varas, ed. Polish United Workers Party.’’ In Eastern Europe and Santiago: Associacio´n Chilena de Investigaciones para Democracy: The Case of Poland, pp. 15–28. New la Paz. York: Institute for East–West Security Studies. Guilhon Albuquerque, Jose´ A., and Eunice Ribeiro Pappalardo, Adriano. 1985. ll governo del salario nelle Durham, eds. 1987. Transic¸a˜o polı´tica: Necessidades democrazie industriali. Milan: Franco Agneli. e limites da Negociaciao.Sa˜o Paulo: Universidade de Przeworski, Adam. 1985. Capitalism and Social De- Sa˜o Paulo. mocracy. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Haggard, Stephan. 1986. ‘‘The Politics of Adjustment: ———. 1987b. ‘‘Capitalismo, democracia, pactos.’’ Lessons from the IMF’s Extended Fund Facility.’’ In In Transic¸a˜o polı´tica: Necessidades e limites da nego- The Politics of International Debt, pp. 157–186. Miles ciaciao. Jose´ A. Guilhon Albuquerque and Eunice Kahler, ed. Ithaca, N.Y.: Cornell University Press. Ribeiro Durham, eds. Sa˜o Paulo: Universidade de Sa˜o Haggard, Stephan and Robert Kaufman. 1989. ‘‘The Paulo. Politics of Stabilization and Structural Adjustment.’’ In Przeworski, Adam, and Michael Wallerstein. 1982. Developing Country Debt and the World Economy, pp. ‘‘The Structure of Class Conflicts under Democratic 263–274. Je¤rey D. Sachs, ed. Chicago: University of Capitalism.’’ American Political Science Review 76: Chicago Press. 215–238. Hankiss, Elemer. 1989. East European Alternatives: Rasmusen, Eric. 1989. Games and Information: An Are There Any? Budapest: Institute of Sociology, Introduction to . Oxford: Blackwell Hungarian Academy of Sciences. Publisher. Huntington, Samuel P. 1968. Political Order in Remmer, Karen L. 1986. ‘‘The Politics of Economic Changing Societies. New Haven, Conn.: Yale Univer- Stabilization.’’ Comparative Politics 19: 1–24. sity Press. Schotter, Andrew. 1981. The Economic Theory of Latin American Weekly Report. Published by Latin Social Institutions. Cambridge: Cambridge University American Newsletters, London. Press. Lechner, Norbert. 1985. ‘‘Pacto social nos processos Stallings, Barbara, and Robert Kaufman. 1989. ‘‘Debt de democratizac¸a˜o: A experieˆncia latino-americana.’’ and Democracy in the 1980s: The Latin American Ex- Novos Estudos 13: 29–44. perience.’’ In Debt and Democracy in Latin America, Maravall, Jose´ Marı´a. 1990. ‘‘Economic Reforms in pp. 201–223. Barbara Stallings and Robert Kaufman, New Democracies: The Southern European Experi- eds. Boulder, Colo.: Westview. ence.’’ University of Chicago, ESST Working Papers, Toran´ska, Teresa. 1985. Oni. London: Aneks. no. 2. Miliband, Ralph. 1975. Parliamentary Socialism: A Study in the Politics of Labour. 2d ed. London: Merlin Press. Murilo de Carvalho, Jose´. 1987. ‘‘Militares e civis: Um debate alem da contituinte.’’ Paper presented at the Eleventh Annual Meeting of ANPOCS, Aguas de Sa˜o Pedro. O’Donnell, Guillermo. 1979. ‘‘Notas para el estudio de procesos de democratizacio´n a partir del estado bur- ocra´tico-autoritario.’’ Estudios CEDES 5. O’Donnell, Guillermo, and Philippe C. Schmitter. 1986. Transitions from Authoritarian Rule: Tentative Conclusions about Uncertain Democracies. Baltimore: Johns Hopkins University Press. Ostrowski, Krzysztof. 1989. ‘‘The Decline of Power and Its E¤ects on Democratization: The Case of the Democracy’s Third Wave

Samuel P. Huntington

Between 1974 and 1990, at least 30 countries future expansion or contraction of democracy in made transitions to democracy, just about dou- the world and to pose the questions that seem bling the number of democratic governments in most relevant for the future of democratization. the world. Were these part of a One way to begin is to inquire whether the continuing and ever-expanding ‘‘global demo- causes that gave rise to the third wave are likely cratic revolution’’ that will reach virtually every to continue operating, to gain in strength, to country in the world? Or did they represent a weaken, or to be supplemented or replaced limited expansion of democracy, involving for by new forces promoting democratization. Five the most part its reintroduction into countries major factors have contributed significantly to that had experienced it in the past? the occurrence and the timing of the third-wave The current era of democratic transitions con- transitions to democracy: stitutes the third wave of democratization in the history of the modern world. The first ‘‘long’’ (1) The deepening legitimacy problems of au- wave of democratization began in the 1820s, thoritarian regimes in a world where democratic with the widening of the su¤rage to a large pro- values were widely accepted, the consequent portion of the male population in the United dependence of these regimes on successful per- States, and continued for almost a century until formance, and their inability to maintain ‘‘per- 1926, bringing into being some 29 democracies. formance legitimacy’’ due to economic (and In 1922, however, the coming to power of Mus- sometimes military) failure. solini in Italy marked the beginning of a first (2) The unprecedented global economic growth ‘‘reverse wave’’ that by 1942 had reduced the of the 1960s, which raised living standards, number of democratic states in the world to 12. increased education, and greatly expanded the The triumph of the Allies in World War II ini- urban middle class in many countries. tiated a second wave of democratization that (3) A striking shift in the doctrine and activities reached its zenith in 1962 with 36 countries gov- of the Catholic Church, manifested in the Sec- erned democratically, only to be followed by a ond Vatican Council of 1963–65 and the trans- second reverse wave (1960–1975) that brought formation of national Catholic churches from the number of democracies back down to 30. defenders of the status quo to opponents of At what stage are we within the third wave? authoritarianism. Early in a long wave, or at or near the end of a (4) Changes in the policies of external actors, short one? And if the third wave comes to a halt, most notably the European Community, the will it be followed by a significant third reverse United States, and the Soviet Union. wave eliminating many of democracy’s gains in the 1970s and 1980s? Social science cannot pro- (5) ‘‘Snowballing,’’ or the demonstration e¤ect vide reliable answers to these questions, nor can of transitions earlier in the third wave in stim- any social scientist. It may be possible, however, ulating and providing models for subsequent to identify some of the factors that will a¤ect the e¤orts at democratization. I will begin by addressing the latter three fac- Excerpted from: Samuel P. Huntington, ‘‘Democracy’s tors, returning to the first two later in this article. Third Wave.’’ Journal of Democracy 2, no. 2 (1991): Historically, there has been a strong correla- 6 12–34. The Johns Hopkins University Press and tion between Western Christianity and democ- National Endowment for Democracy. Chapter 2 94

racy. By the early 1970s, most of the Protestant ple around the world come to see the United countries in the world had already become dem- States as a fading power beset by political stag- ocratic. The third wave of the 1970s and 1980s nation, economic ine‰ciency, and social chaos, was overwhelmingly a Catholic wave. . . . its perceived failures will inevitably be seen as the failures of democracy, and the worldwide appeal of democracy will diminish. The Role of External Forces

During the third wave, the European Commu- Snowballing nity (EC) played a key role in consolidating de- mocracy in southern Europe. In Greece, Spain, The impact of snowballing on democratization and Portugal, the establishment of democracy was clearly evident in 1990 in Bulgaria, Roma- was seen as necessary to secure the economic nia, Yugoslavia, Mongolia, Nepal, and Albania. benefits of EC membership, while Community It also a¤ected movements toward liberalization membership was in turn seen as a guarantee of in some Arab and African countries. In 1990, the stability of democracy. In 1981, Greece be- for instance, it was reported that the ‘‘upheaval came a full member of the Community, and five in Eastern Europe’’ had ‘‘fueled demands for years later Spain and Portugal did as well. . . . change in the Arab world’’ and prompted leaders The withdrawal of Soviet power made possible in Egypt, Jordan, Tunisia, and Algeria to open democratization in Eastern Europe. If the Soviet up more political space for the expression of Union were to end or drastically curtail its sup- discontent.1 port for Castro’s regime, movement toward de- The East European example had its principal mocracy might occur in Cuba. Apart from that, e¤ect on the leaders of authoritarian regimes, not there seems little more the Soviet Union can do on the people they ruled. . . . or is likely to do to promote democracy outside If a country lacks favorable internal condi- its borders. The key issue is what will happen tions, however, snowballing alone is unlikely to within the Soviet Union itself. If Soviet control bring about democratization. The democratiza- loosens, it seems likely that democracy could be tion of countries A and B is not a reason for reestablished in the Baltic states. Movements democratization in country C, unless the con- toward democracy also exist in other republics. ditions that favored it in the former also exist in Most important, of course, is Russia itself. The the latter. . . . inauguration and consolidation of democracy in the Russian republic, if it occurs, would be the single most dramatic gain for democracy since A Third Reverse Wave? the immediate post-World War II years. . . . During the 1970s and 1980s the United States By 1990 at least two third-wave democracies, was a major promoter of democratization. Sudan and Nigeria, had reverted to authoritar- Whether the United States continues to play this ian rule; the di‰culties of consolidation could role depends on its will, its capability, and its lead to further reversions in countries with un- attractiveness as a model to other countries. . . . favorable conditions for sustaining democracy. What might happen, however, if the American The first and second democratic waves, however, model ceases to embody strength and success, were followed not merely by some backsliding no longer seems to be the winning model? At the end of the 1980s, many were arguing that 1. New York Times. 28 December 1989. A13: Interna- ‘‘American decline’’ was the true reality. If peo- tional Herald Tribune, 12–13 May 1990. 6. Sources of Democracy 95

but by major reverse waves during which most suggest some potential causes of a new reverse regime changes throughout the world were from wave. democracy to authoritarianism. If the third wave First, systemic failures of democratic regimes of democratization slows down or comes to a to operate e¤ectively could undermine their halt, what factors might produce a third reverse legitimacy. . . . wave? Second, a shift to authoritarianism by any Among the factors contributing to transitions democratic or democratizing great power could away from democracy during the first and sec- trigger reverse snowballing. . . . ond reverse waves were: If a nondemocratic state greatly increased its power and began to expand beyond its borders, (1) the weakness of democratic values among this too could stimulate authoritarian move- key elite groups and the general public; ments in other countries. . . . (2) severe economic setbacks, which intensified Finally, as in the 1920s and the 1960s, various social conflict and enhanced the popularity of old and new forms of authoritarianism that seem remedies that could be imposed only by authori- appropriate to the needs of the times could tarian governments; emerge. . . . (3) social and political polarization, often pro- duced by leftist governments seeking the rapid introduction of major social and economic Obstacles to Democratization reforms; Another approach to assessing democracy’s (4) the determination of conservative middle- prospects is to examine the obstacles to and class and upper-class groups to exclude populist opportunities for democratization where it has and leftist movements and lower-class groups not yet taken hold. As of 1990, more than one from political power; hundred countries lacked democratic regimes. (5) the breakdown of law and order resulting Most of these countries fell into four sometimes from terrorism or insurgency; overlapping geocultural categories: (6) intervention or conquest by a nondemocratic (1) Home-grown Marxist-Leninist regimes, in- foreign power; cluding the Soviet Union, where major liberal- (7) ‘‘reverse snowballing’’ triggered by the col- ization occurred in the 1980s and democratic lapse or overthrow of democratic systems in movements existed in many republics; other countries. . . . (2) Sub-Saharan African countries, which, with The overwhelming majority of transitions a few exceptions, remained personal dictator- from democracy, however, took the form either ships, military regimes, one-party systems, or of military coups that ousted democratically some combination of these three; elected leaders, or executive coups in which (3) Islamic countries stretching from Morocco democratically chosen chief executives e¤ectively to Indonesia, which except for Turkey and per- ended democracy by concentrating power in haps Pakistan had nondemocratic regimes; their own hands, usually by declaring a state of (4) East Asian countries, from Burma through emergency or martial law. . . . Southeast Asia to China and North Korea, Although the causes and forms of the first two which included communist systems, military reverse waves cannot generate reliable predic- regimes, personal dictatorships, and two semi- tions concerning the causes and forms of a pos- democracies (Thailand and Malaysia). sible third reverse wave, prior experiences do Chapter 2 96

The obstacles to democratization in these cultures are peculiarly hostile to democracy. The groups of countries are political, cultural, and two cultures most often cited in this regard are economic. One potentially significant political Confucianism and Islam. Three questions are obstacle to future democratization is the vir- relevant to determining whether these cultures tual absence of experience with democracy in now pose serious obstacles to democratization. most countries that remained authoritarian in First, to what extent are traditional Confucian 1990. . . . and Islamic values and beliefs hostile to democ- Another obstacle to democratization is likely racy? Second, if they are, to what extent have to disappear in a number of countries in the these cultures in fact hampered progress toward 1990s. Leaders who found authoritarian regimes democracy? Third, if they have significantly re- or rule them for a long period tend to become tarded democratic progress in the past, to what particularly staunch opponents of democratiza- extent are they likely to continue to do so in the tion. Hence some form of leadership change future? within the authoritarian system usually precedes movement toward democracy. . . . One serious impediment to democratization Confucianism is the absence or weakness of real commitment to democratic values among political leaders in Almost no scholarly disagreement exists regard- Asia, Africa, and the Middle East. . . . ing the proposition that traditional Confucian- Even when Asian, African, and Middle East- ism was either undemocratic or antidemocratic. ern leaders have more or less abided by the rules The only mitigating factor was the extent to of democracy, they often seemed to do so which the examination system in the classic Chi- grudgingly. . . . nese polity opened careers to the talented with- out regard to social background. Even if this were the case, however, a merit system of pro- Culture motion does not make a democracy. No one would describe a modern army as democratic It has been argued that the world’s great historic because o‰cers are promoted on the basis of cultural traditions vary significantly in the extent their abilities. Classic Chinese Confucianism and to which their attitudes, values, beliefs, and re- its derivatives in Korea, Vietnam, Singapore, lated behavior patterns are conducive to the Taiwan, and (in diluted fashion) Japan empha- development of democracy. A profoundly anti- sized the group over the individual, authority democratic culture would impede the spread of over liberty, and responsibilities over rights. democratic norms in the society, deny legiti- Confucian societies lacked a tradition of rights macy to democratic institutions, and thus greatly against the state; to the extent that individual complicate if not prevent the emergence and rights did exist, they were created by the state. e¤ective functioning of those institutions. The Harmony and cooperation were preferred over cultural thesis comes in two forms. The more re- disagreement and competition. The maintenance strictive version states that only Western culture of order and respect for hierarchy were central provides a suitable base for the development of values. The conflict of ideas, groups, and parties democratic institutions and, consequently, that was viewed as dangerous and illegitimate. Most democracy is largely inappropriate for non- important, Confucianism merged society and the Western societies. . . . state and provided no legitimacy for autono- A less restrictive version of the cultural obsta- mous social institutions at the national level. cle argument holds that certain non-Western Sources of Democracy 97

In practice Confucian or Confucian-influenced Second, great cultural traditions like Islam societies have been inhospitable to democracy. and Confucianism are highly complex bodies In East Asia only two countries, Japan and of ideas, beliefs, doctrines, assumptions, and the Philippines, had sustained experience with behavior patterns. Any major culture, including democratic government prior to 1990. In both Confucianism, has some elements that are com- cases, democracy was the product of an Amer- patible with democracy, just as both Protes- ican presence. The Philippines, moreover, is tantism and Catholicism have elements that are overwhelmingly a Catholic country. In Japan, clearly undemocratic. . . . Confucian values were reinterpreted and merged Third, cultures historically are dynamic, not with autochthonous cultural traditions. . . . stagnant. The dominant beliefs and attitudes in a Islamic doctrine . . . contains elements that society change. While maintaining elements of may be both congenial and uncongenial to de- continuity, the prevailing culture of a society mocracy. In practice, however, the only Islamic in one generation may di¤er significantly from country that has sustained a fully democratic what it was one or two generations earlier. . . . political system for any length of time is Turkey, where Mustafa Kemal Ataturk explicitly rejected Islamic concepts of society and politics and vig- Economics orously attempted to create a secular, modern, Western nation-state. And Turkey’s experience Few relationships between social, economic, and with democracy has not been an unmitigated political phenomena are stronger than that success. Elsewhere in the Islamic world, Pakistan between the level of economic development has made three attempts at democracy, none and the existence of democratic politics. Most of which lasted long. While Turkey has had wealthy countries are democratic, and most democracy interrupted by occasional military democratic countries—India is the most dra- interventions, Pakistan has had bureaucratic matic exception—are wealthy. The correlation and military rule interrupted by occasional between wealth and democracy implies that elections. . . . transitions to democracy should occur primarily in countries at the mid-level of economic devel- opment. In poor countries democratization is The Limits of Cultural Obstacles unlikely; in rich countries it usually has already occurred. In between there is a ‘‘political transi- Strong cultural obstacles to democratization thus tion zone’’: countries in this middle economic appear to exist in Confucian and Islamic soci- stratum are those most likely to transit to de- eties. There are, nonetheless, reasons to doubt mocracy, and most countries that transit to de- whether these must necessarily prevent demo- mocracy will be in this stratum. As countries cratic development. First, similar cultural argu- develop economically and move into the transi- ments have not held up in the past. At one point tion zone, they become good prospects for many scholars argued that Catholicism was an democratization. . . . obstacle to democracy. Others, in the Weberian tradition, contended that Catholic countries were unlikely to develop economically in the same Economic Development and Political Leadership manner as Protestant countries. Yet in the 1960s, 1970s, and 1980s Catholic countries became History has proved both optimists and pessi- democratic and, on average, had higher rates of mists wrong about democracy. Future events economic growth than Protestant countries. . . . will probably do the same. Formidable obstacles Chapter 2 98

to the expansion of democracy exist in many democracies to come into being, future political societies. The third wave, the ‘‘global democratic elites will have to believe, at a minimum, that revolution’’ of the late twentieth century, will not democracy is the least bad form of government last forever. It may be followed by a new surge for their societies and for themselves. They will of authoritarianism sustained enough to consti- also need the skills to bring about the transition tute a third reverse wave. That, however, would to democracy while facing both radical opposi- not preclude a fourth wave of democratization tionists and authoritarian hard-liners who inevi- developing some time in the twenty-first century. tably will attempt to undermine their e¤orts. Judging by the record of the past, the two most Democracy will spread to the extent that those decisive factors a¤ecting the future consolidation who exercise power in the world and in individ- and expansion of democracy will be economic ual countries want it to spread. For a century development and political leadership. and a half after Tocqueville observed the emer- Most poor societies will remain undemocratic gence of modern democracy in America, succes- so long as they remain poor. Poverty, however, sive waves of democratization have washed over is not inevitable. In the past, nations such as the shore of dictatorship. Buoyed by a rising South Korea, which were assumed to be mired tide of economic progress, each wave advanced in economic backwardness, have astonished the further—and receded less—than its predecessor. world by rapidly attaining prosperity. In the History, to shift the metaphor, does not sail 1980s, a new consensus emerged among devel- ahead in a straight line, but when skilled and opmental economists on the ways to promote determined leaders are at the helm, it does move economic growth. The consensus of the 1980s forward. may or may not prove more lasting and produc- tive than the very di¤erent consensus among economists that prevailed in the 1950s and 1960s. The new orthodoxy of neo-orthodoxy, however, already seems to have produced signif- icant results in many countries. Yet there are two reasons to temper our hopes with caution. First, economic development for the late, late, late developing countries—meaning largely Africa—may well be more di‰cult than it was for earlier developers because the advan- tages of backwardness come to be outweighed by the widening and historically unprecedented gap between rich and poor countries. Second, new forms of authoritarianism could emerge in wealthy, information-dominated, technology- based societies. If unhappy possibilities such as these do not materialize, economic development should create the conditions for the progres- sive replacement of authoritarian political sys- tems by democratic ones. Time is on the side of democracy. Economic development makes democracy possible; political leadership makes it real. For South Africa’s Negotiated Transition: Democracy, Opposition, and the New Constitutional Order

Courtney Jung and Ian Shapiro

Few seasoned observers of South African politics negotiations failed and were replaced by more ever expected to see Nelson Mandela inaugu- circumscribed elite negotiations, the fact that rated as the country’s president. When this the entire process commanded agreement among happened in May of 1994, it would have been the principal players was widely heralded as an di‰cult not to interpret it as a major democratic encouraging portent for the future. achievement. The April elections caught the The widespread popular enthusiasm for South world’s imagination. Democrats everywhere Africa’s democratic transition is in line with applauded as the apartheid regime began fading much recent academic orthodoxy in political into history, and the African National Congress science. Negotiated transitions to democracy took over the reins of power. In a country and are seen as desirable, if not necessary for demo- on a continent where democracy has seldom cratic survival. ‘‘Pacts are not always likely or fared well historically, the achievement seemed possible,’’ Guillermo O’Donnell and Philippe all the more remarkable. In an astonishingly Schmitter tell us, ‘‘but where they are a feature short time South Africa had been transformed of the transition they are desirable—that is they from a pariah nation, vilified around the world, enhance the possibility that the process will lead into a progressive multicultural democracy, to a viable political democracy.’’3 ‘‘How were identified in the Western press as a model democracies made?’’ asks Huntington of the throughout Africa and a symbol of hope for third wave of democratic transformations be- struggling democratizers elsewhere.1 tween 1974 and 1990. His answer is that they No less noteworthy than the result was the ‘‘were made by the methods of democracy, there process that led to it. Despite considerable vio- was no other way. They were made through lence there was no civil war, no military coup, negotiations, compromises and agreements.’’4 and the cooperation among the players whose Przeworski reiterates the view that democracy cooperation was needed was impressive. Starting ‘‘cannot be dictated; it emerges from bargain- in 1990, after the National Party (NP) gov- ing.’’5 From the vantage point of these opinions, ernment’s decision to release all political pris- South Africa is a textbook case of a well-crafted oners, legalize all opposition parties, and begin transition; despite various fits and starts, the genuine negotiations with them on the shape of principals made no serious mistakes and shep- the new South Africa, it was clear that real herded the country safely through its first demo- change was in the o‰ng. Multiparty negotiations cratic elections. for a new constitution seemed to exemplify both The worldwide attention to the South African the letter and spirit of a democratic transition transition, and to transition negotiations else- to democracy. Even when the all-party codesa where, has not been matched by comparable

Excerpted from: Courtney Jung and Ian Shapiro, 3. Guillermo O’Donnell and Philippe Schmitter, ‘‘South Africa’s Negotiated Transition: Democracy, Transitions from Authoritarian Rule (Baltimore: Johns Opposition, and the New Constitutional Order.’’ Hopkins University Press, 1986), p. 39. Politics and Society 23(3): 269–308. 6 1995 by 4. Samuel P. Huntington, The Third Wave: Democra- Sage Publications. Reprinted by permission of Sage tization in the Late Twentieth Century (Norman: Uni- Publications. versity of Oklahoma Press, 1991), p. 164. 1. See, e.g., New York Times, June 21, 1994, pp. A1, 5. Adam Przeworski, Democracy and the Market A8. (New York: Cambridge University Press, 1991), p. 80. Chapter 2 100

scrutiny of what the parties to the transition will lead them to see the costs and benefits of negotiations agreed to or why. Yet there are various institutional outcomes di¤erently. Nego- serious questions as to whether constitutional tiators representing a party that expects to be in orders that emerge from negotiations facilitate the minority in the new democratic order should democratic politics in the medium term. In par- be expected to prefer a power-sharing arrange- ticular, South Africa’s transitional constitution ment in which they are guaranteed some of the lacks a system of opposition institutions that spoils of o‰ce and veto powers on measures that any healthy democracy requires. Although terms a¤ect their critical interests. Leaders of parties such as group rights, consociationalism, and mi- that expect to alternate in government and op- nority vetoes are anathema in the South African position in the new regime might reasonably take political vocabulary, the political order that has a more mixed view of things: when they are in been created is consociational in many critical government, they will want the power to govern respects; as such it is designed to give every but when they are in opposition they will want to powerful player a say in government. The elec- be able to frustrate as much of the government’s toral system, the rules of parliamentary control, agenda as possible. Parties that anticipate being and the powers and composition of the cabinet able to win a majority can be expected to prefer and the executive all reinforce this reality. The an oppositional model that will give them the result is that there are no powerful actors to play power and authority to govern and to enact as the role of ‘‘loyal’’ opponents to the new gov- much of their agenda as they can. Consequently, ernment and its policies. A system designed to they should be expected to push for a majority involve every player of political consequence in system during the transition negotiations and government leaves no institutional space for a to be more resistant than any of the other players loyal opposition. . . . [W]e examine the disquieting possibility 6. The National Assembly and the Senate jointly form that the new South Africa’s lack of these basic the Constitutional Assembly, which was required to ingredients of a viable democracy is a direct adopt a final constitution with a two-thirds majority by result of the transition’s having been negotiated May 1996. This constitution comes into operation only between reformers in the NP government and if the Constitutional Court certifies that it complies the moderate leadership of the ANC. We explore with the constitutional principles laid down in the and evaluate the conjecture that the dynamics provisional constitution. These include a democratic system of government, universal franchise, regular of negotiated transitions such as South Africa’s elections, a multiparty system, one class of citizenship make it virtually impossible for the principal for all, recognition of individual rights, antidiscrimina- players to converge on an agreement that tion provisions, equality before the law, separation of includes provision for e¤ective opposition forces powers, three levels of government (national, provin- in the new democratic order. If our analysis is cial, and local), and an entrenched constitution that— persuasive, then it leads to the conclusion that as interpreted by the Constitutional Court—is the although the interim constitution may well have supreme law of the land. This last feature was a nota- been the best possible device to end apartheid ble change from the old British-style system of the su- without a civil war, it should not be replicated in premacy of parliament. Other features of the interim the permanent constitution.6 This means that the arrangements, such as the boundaries of the provinces, could not be changed in the final constitution. There advice of such analysts as Arend Lijphart, who was no requirement, however, that the interim system makes the contrary recommendation, should be of constitutionally mandated power sharing (the cen- ignored. . . . tral focus of this chapter) be retained in the final docu- Those who negotiate transitions to democracy ment. See South Africa 1995 (Johannesburg: South all bring to the bargaining table interests that Africa Foundation, 1995), pp. 14–15. Sources of Democracy 101

to power sharing and other consociational each has an interest in trying to get the upper arrangements. hand in the negotiations to secure the result most The story of the South African transition favorable to its future political fortunes. Second, partly belies these expectations. As anticipated, the negotiating partners (the reformers in the the National Party insisted on a consociational government and the moderates in the opposi- outcome throughout the negotiations and even- tion) have incentives to maximize grass roots tually prevailed, making few concessions. But support for themselves (thereby continuing to the ANC, with its overwhelming grass roots marginalize standpatters and extremists) while support and its well-founded expectation that causing their negotiating partner merely to sat- it would hold an absolute majority in the new isfice with respect to its grass roots supporters. parliament, made concession after concession, Each wants the other to retain enough constitu- eventually accepting constitutionally mandated ent support—but no more—to be able to deliver power sharing, for the rest of the century at least, an agreement, and each seeks to achieve this almost without a whimper. As power sharing result in an evolving context. Thus negotiators had been anathema to the ANC as late as mid- are bound by three constraints as they move 1992 and as most observers inside and outside toward an agreement: time, their respective con- South Africa seemed to think that the ANC stituencies, and the changing demands of the held most of the cards, this outcome needs an other party. . . . explanation. . . . Negotiations begin in earnest once negotiat- ing elites on both sides realize that they are approaching the point of no return: when retreat The Dynamics of Transition Negotiations from the negotiations would be followed by a collapse of support from which political recovery Transplacements, as Huntington describes nego- is unlikely. Both leaderships, and perhaps their tiated transitions,29 should be expected to occur political parties as well, will by then have be- only when two conditions are present. First, come so identified with the negotiated transition dominant groups in both government and oppo- that, if the negotiations collapse, they will lose sition must bargain with one another while their leadership positions, presumably to stand- recognizing that neither party is capable of patters and radicals. From this point on, political determining the future unilaterally. Second, at survival for reformers and moderates depends on critical junctures reformers must appear to be concluding a successful agreement. This is most stronger than standpatters in the government likely to occur if negotiators on both sides come while moderates seem stronger than extremists in to believe that their leverage to force concessions the opposition.30 Elites who negotiate transitions from the other side has reached its maximum are thus subject to constraints that arise both out or begun to diminish and that replacement and of the negotiations and out of their relations with transformation continue not to be viable options. their own grass roots constituencies. The negoti- These beliefs will give both sides strong incen- ating partners are concerned to maximize power tives to make the compromises necessary to along two dimensions. First, each tries to max- reach an agreement, once they face what appears imize power in relation to the other in the nego- to them to be secular erosion of their own grass tiations. Because both sides expect to lead parties roots support. that will compete in the new democratic regime, A transplacement, or negotiated transition, di¤ers from a Huntingtonian replacement in that 29. Huntington, Third Wave, pp. 113–114. . . . in the former the authoritarian regime does not 30. Huntington, Third Wave, pp. 124, 152. cede control of the armed forces until after the Chapter 2 102

agreement has been concluded. Both govern- In short, in negotiated transitions government ment reformers and opposition moderates know, reformers have more valuable cards going in therefore, that there are hard-liners in the mili- than do the opposition moderates, deriving from tary who will insist on security guarantees and their monopoly control of the state’s coercive also that grass roots support for government institutions. They may lack the power to impose reformers is likely to be critically reliant on their what Huntington describes as a transformation, being able credibly to claim that they can guar- but by the same token the opposition lacks the antee their constituents’ physical security. Thus power to impose a replacement. (Were this not the government reformers have a structural ad- so, negotiations would, presumably, not begin; vantage over the opposition moderates through- and should it not remain so, they would not out the negotiations, as we have noted. It also continue to an agreement.) The test of the gov- suggests that, if an agreement is reached, in the ernment reformers’ negotiating skill is how end it will involve more substantial concessions successfully they manage to use their structural from the opposition than from the government advantage to get the opposition moderates because the government retains control of the to concede the maximum possible while forcing means of coercion. Once the opposition moder- them to satisfice with respect to their grass roots ates realize that they have passed their point constituency. They must do this in a way that of no return, so that their political survival is alienates as few of the government’s own poten- contingent on reaching an agreement, they can tial supporters as possible. The test for the op- be expected to accept demands rejected earlier. position moderates is how successfully they can Even if the government reformers have passed undermine the government’s structural advan- their own point of no return, both sides are likely tage, reach an agreement with which their core to assume that, in the event of a terminal col- supporters can live, and make themselves attrac- lapse of negotiations, government reformers will tive to as many other potential voters as possible. turn control over to (or be pushed aside by) How these interacting imperatives were played standpatters rather than accept the complete loss out in the South African transition between 1990 of control suggested by replacement or civil war. and 1994 is the subject to which we now turn. The government will have an incentive not to force too many concessions out of the opposition moderates, however. It needs them to satisfice, to South Africa’s Negotiated Transition retain enough support among their grass roots to be able to sell the agreement and continue to The National Party’s grand design for apartheid marginalize the radical opposition elites waiting ran into trouble almost as soon as its leaders be- in the wings. The government must, therefore, gan to implement it when they came to power in simultaneously reassure its own constituent base, 1948. When basic tenets of separate racial and give the opposition just enough to crow about to ethnic development proved unworkable, parts of its supporters, and claim as credibly as possible the strategy were abandoned and others were to undecided potential voters to have made the redesigned.32 With various liberalizing fits and deal that is in their best interest. Opposition starts, South Africa was thus an unstable au- moderates confront the no less delicate task of convincing their core supporters that they have 32. See Hermann Giliomee, The Parting of the Ways: made the best possible bargain and concurrently South African Politics, 1976–1982 (Cape Town: Philip, presenting their concessions to others as evidence 1982), and Heribert Adam and Hermann Giliomee, of their moderation and lack of partisanship. The Rise and Crisis of Afrikaner Power (Cape Town: Philip, 1979). Sources of Democracy 103

thoritarian regime for some forty-two years it sought partly to remain a liberation move- before the NP government of F. W. De Klerk ment, demanding an interim government and decided, in 1990, to dismantle the apartheid an elected constituent assembly to write the first regime and create a new multiracial political constitution. ANC leaders sought to undermine order. . . . the legitimacy and strategic advantage of the NP by challenging its role as legitimate government Prenegotiations and primary negotiator. An interim government would assume (some undefined degree of ) re- The National Party Reformers sponsibility for governing while the two sides negotiated on what the ANC termed ‘‘a more Yet many observers were caught o¤ guard by the level playing field.’’ Additionally, ANC leaders speed and decisiveness with which change came argued that only an elected constituent assembly in February 1990. President De Klerk, a conser- would lead to a democratic process in which the vative Afrikaner by history and reputation who constitution would be drafted by democratically had been one of the mainstays of apartheid in elected delegates. Confident that they would win previous cabinets, surprised both the South a majority in elections for a constituent assem- African opposition and the world by unbanning bly, they expected that they would then have a the ANC, the Pan-Africanist Congress (PAC), free rein to draft the new constitution and con- and the South African Communist Party (which trol the new government.38 had been illegal since 1960). He simultaneously announced plans to release all political prisoners, The Central Issue: Majority Rule including Nelson Mandela, and to begin nego- tiations toward democracy. Given the NP’s The debate over majority rule plagued dis- history of relentlessly demonizing these groups cussions even in the prenegotiating phase. . . . while sustaining the apartheid order behind a The NP proposed that minority parties with sig- veil of cosmetic adjustments, these decisions left nificant support be assured of cabinet represen- little room for doubt that fundamental change tation, that the presidency rotate among three was at hand. to five members, and that decisions be based on The government’s decision to act suddenly consensus in both bodies.40 and release Mandela before his role within the Power sharing had been anathema to the ANC had been agreed upon seemed calculated ANC for its entire history. It seemed too obvi- to promote and capitalize on the ANC’s dis- ously to be a euphemism for ‘‘group rights,’’ in organization and to enable the NP to structure turn little more than a smoke screen for apart- the terms of future negotiations as much as heid by another name. Given this history and the possible. . . . ANC’s knowledge of the extent of its own grass The ANC was reluctant to let the negotiations roots support, it is not surprising that initially move rapidly. Whereas the NP pressed for a the ANC regarded all talk of power sharing substantive agreement on a postapartheid gov- as taboo. In his early campaigning and inter- ernment, the ANC focused on reaching agree- national travels, Mandela heaped scorn on as- ment on a procedure by which a democratic sertions by the government that South Africa 37 government could be formed. To this end, was unique in its ethnic and racial composition and that as a result it needed a political system 37. [Hermann Giliomee and Johannes Rantete, ‘‘Transition to Democracy through Transaction? Bi- 38. Ibid., p. 527. lateral Negotiations between the ANC and the NP in South Africa,’’ African A¤airs no. 91 (1992)], p. 526. 40. [Ibid.], p. 523. Chapter 2 104

tailored to its idiosyncrasies. The ANC rejected the white population, it committed him to some all such claims, insisting that they wanted no version of power sharing. This had been explicit more—but also no less—than an ‘‘ordinary in the referendum campaign, in e¤ect making the democracy.’’41 referendum a contract between De Klerk and the white minority that he would not devolve all Negotiations Begin power to the black majority.44 Had he ventured beyond the terms of this contract, his support Early in 1992, a series of Conservative Party would have fragmented and the far right would wins in local by-elections in former NP strong- likely have reemerged as a serious force. Within holds served to warn reformers in the NP that the constraints implied by the contract, however, substantial numbers of whites might not support De Klerk was now free to begin genuine nego- a transition. De Klerk responded by calling a tiations with the moderate leadership of the referendum, held in March 1992, in which white ANC. voters were asked whether they supported ne- The ANC leadership’s incentive and capacity gotiations. In so doing, he took a substantial to negotiate emerged gradually. In the June 1992 political risk. Had the referendum results been Boipatong massacre, thirty-nine unarmed ANC negative, he would certainly have had to reverse supporters were killed by apparent Inkatha policy, and he would likely have been deposed as members while South African police and vehicles leader of the NP and head of the government. stood idly by. Mandela immediately pulled out But he won a resounding two-thirds majority, of the talks in protest against the security forces’ revealing the white-right electoral threat to be unwillingness to stem so-called black-on-black chimerical. . . . violence as well as Inkatha attacks against the De Klerk was quick to declare that the refer- ANC, precipitating the end of the all-party endum result was a mandate to negotiate a round-table negotiations.45 The ANC backed up settlement, and he insisted throughout the re- its dramatic walkout by calling for mass action mainder of the negotiating process and the 1994 and popular protest. The leadership used this, election campaign that everything he agreed to its most valuable extra-institutional bargaining had been outlined in the referendum and thus chip, to demonstrate that it retained the capacity previously endorsed by an overwhelming major- to mobilize its following against the govern- ity of the whites.43 His freedom in this regard was not unlimited, however. Although the refer- 44. De Klerk launched the referendum campaign by endum gave De Klerk the political leverage he saying, ‘‘We will not say yes to a suicide plan. We will needed to negotiate a settlement on behalf of once again reiterate the importance that in such a new constitution, whether it be a first phase or a fully 41. In 1990, Mandela wrote in his best-selling autobi- encompassing constitution, how important we regard it that there must be e¤ective protection against domina- ography that there would be no peace until majority SABC Network rule was fully implemented; see Nelson Mandela, The tion of minorities’’; (Johannesburg), Struggle Is My Life (London: IDAF Publications, February 24, 1992. After his victory, De Klerk said, ‘‘We want to share power, we want a new dispensation, 1990), p. 206. As late as April 1992 he was still insisting we want it to be fair, we want it to be equitable’’; ibid., at press conferences that the ANC could never accept the various ‘‘fancy proposals’’ for power sharing that March 19, 1992. were on o¤er from the government: ‘‘We want an 45. These negotiations had been stalled for some time ordinary democracy as practiced elsewhere in the over the percentage of votes needed for acceptance of world.’’ ANC press conference, BBC Summary of the constitution, with the ANC advocating two-thirds, World Broadcasts, April 9, 1992. which it thought it might be able to win outright, and 43. SAPA (Johannesburg), June 8, 1993. the government insisting on 75 percent. Sources of Democracy 105

ment. . . . Although Mandela called repeatedly in secret, and both sides appeared determined to for peaceful demonstrations, South Africa’s fix the main terms of their agreement before highest levels of transitional violence occurred in multilateral talks would again be allowed to be- the month after Boipatong.46 gin. These terms were announced in the Record Three months after Boipatong, the Ciskei of Understanding, made public in February government opened fire on a group of ANC fol- 1993, between the ANC and the government.53 lowers marching in support of the mass-action campaign at Bisho. This event in particular From ‘‘Ordinary Democracy’’ to Power Sharing made the human cost of the transition graphi- cally evident to the ANC leadership. . . . Once the ANC leaders became convinced that all At the same time as social unrest was threat- the alternatives to a relatively quick negotiated ening to spiral out of the ANC leadership’s con- settlement were worse, they faced [a] Hobson’s trol, De Klerk was greatly increasing the stakes choice . . . and the government’s structural ad- for both sides by threatening to play the trans- vantage in the negotiations became manifest. formation card. Having faced down the hard De Klerk’s commitment to power sharing was right, he was now approaching his point of no nonnegotiable; this meant that the ANC would return; now he needed to get a settlement. Dur- make the principal concessions. A successful ing this period he declared repeatedly that he agreement thus came to hinge on whether the would negotiate with anyone or no one, that he moderate ANC leadership could move itself would arrange the transition by himself if need tactically and ideologically into a position where be, but that, no matter what, it would occur. . . . it could accept power sharing before its core The dual triggers of Boipatong and Bisho, and constituency support was lost. The leadership their repercussions, seem to have caused the had to shift its policy to accept power sharing ANC leadership to look into the abyss and real- and marginalize other elites inside and outside ize that time for a negotiated settlement over the ANC who might challenge its position as the which they could have substantial influence principal representative of the opposition. The was running out.52 In any event, ANC leaders government, which had been ready to negotiate returned to bilateral talks with the government seriously since mid-1992 but needed a serious immediately after the Ciskei massacre, and the partner, did everything it could to help with the real negotiations began. Unlike the two earlier second matter. Once the bilateral talks began codesa round-table negotiations, which had in September, government ministers began to been public events adorned by many marginal mute public criticism of the ANC leaders (who players, the post-Boipatong talks involved the responded in kind), and the government began government and the ANC only, they were held trying to marginalize opposition groups that were in competition with the ANC—most nota- 46. In that month, there were 1,535 incidents of polit- bly the IFP. This marked a distinct change in ical violence with 240 deaths, the highest number to government strategy. As late as May of 1992 that date; Southern Africa Report, May 14, 1993, p. 3. the government had seemed bent on pumping That number was to be exceeded only in the final up non-ANC opposition groups through such weeks before the April 1994 elections. actions as meeting with the PAC (which was 52. It is hard to believe that the daily news of civil war then boycotting codesa) outside the country and and ethnic slaughter in Bosnia and the recent memories disputing ANC claims about its own grass roots of what had happened in Angola had no impact, though it would be di‰cult to determine just what that New York Times impact was. 53. , February 19, 1993, pp. A1, A7. Chapter 2 106

support (insisting, for example, that the IFP had for the first time to defer some questions about more substantial support than the ANC among regional powers to the next parliament.57 But on the Zulu in Natal). The old strategy of seeking the central question of majority rule, the ANC to divide the opposition as much as possible— reversed its decades-old policy and accepted a consistent with a transformative strategy—was strong consociational arrangement, at least for now shelved in favor of finding, and to some the rest of the century. extent even creating, a negotiating partner with However accurate the militants’ portrayal of whom a deal could be made. the agreement as a sellout might have been, they By the end of 1992, the government and the were unable to secure the votes on the ANC’s ANC leadership were being criticized from the governing committee for a nationwide member- left and the right in ways that suggested that ship conference to debate the issue.58 The agree- the alliance necessary for transplacement to ment that had been negotiated was approved, occur was close to being cemented in place. . . . and from that point through the elections, the Both sides had managed to marshal su‰cient ANC leadership faced no serious threat from its support to sustain the negotiation process, and left. Although multiparty talks began the fol- both sides seemed aware that this support would lowing month, the bilateral agreement of Febru- not last indefinitely. Each side had maneuvered ary 1993 set the basic terms of the constitution itself into a position from which it could a¤ord that was adopted by the white parliament in its to reach an agreement and from which the costs final act in December of that year. In October, of failing to reach one were growing all the an act was passed creating the Transitional Ex- time.54 ecutive Council (TEC), a multiparty executive The other essential ingredient was that the body designed to oversee the government in ANC leadership subdue its radical wing and get the run-up to the elections of April 1994.59 Al- its core supporters to accept power sharing. . . . though the act limited the TEC’s powers to The fight over power sharing within the ANC matters having to do with ensuring a level play- lasted several months. It was not clear that the ing field for the elections, the TEC quickly radical wing had been subdued until the end of a became a kind of supercabinet. When the fractious three-day debate in February 1993. The TEC successfully ordered the military to go into issue was whether the Congress’s one hundred- Bophuthatswana to put down a white separatist member governing committee would endorse group that was supporting the local black leader the agreement that had been negotiated with in opposing the coming elections, two things be- the government. . . . The agreement called for a came clear for the first time: the army was loyal legally mandated five-year government of na- to the TEC, and the transition to multiracial tional unity regardless of the election outcome, government in South Africa was a fait accompli with cabinet representation for all parties that before a single black vote had been cast. won at least 5 percent of the vote, and a share of executive power for the strongest minority party. 57. The changes on regional powers were not really The government made marginal concessions on concessions because they mattered more to white sep- the size of supermajority thresholds and agreed aratists and the IFP, neither of whom were serious players by this time, than to the government, which never considered abandoning the concept of a unitary 54. The impression that these shifts in strategy had occurred is based on interviews with people close to the state once negotiations began. principal negotiating partners, conducted during visits 58. New York Times, February 19, 1993, pp. A1, A7. to South Africa in May and December 1992. 59. ‘‘Transitional Executive Council Act,’’ Act no. 151 (1993), Government Gazette, October 27, 1993. Sources of Democracy 107

The Absence of Democratic Opposition expressed was opposition to the end of the apartheid regime. But because the principals Huntington advises the leaders of authoritarian expected to be major players in the new political regimes who are engaged in negotiated transi- order, they were engaged in more than regime tions to begin planning for politics in opposi- building. And in ensuring that there could be tion.60 Not only did De Klerk fail to take this no serious opposition to the new order they were advice, he could not have taken it while still creating, they also ensured that there would be negotiating a transition to a multiracial state little scope for democratic opposition within with the ANC moderate leadership. The neces- it. . . . sary condition for his marginalizing the stand- patters to his right was that he commit to a power-sharing model that would ensure the white minority a role, if a junior one, in the next government. Once the moderate ANC leaders had passed their point of no return and needed an agreement, they had to accept this reality as well—hence the mutual convergence on power sharing. Beyond these constraints, the negotiat- ing principals had few incentives to pay attention to opposition institutions in the new order be- cause at no time did either of them intend not to be in the next government. Whether either would have found a di¤erent model more attractive had they considered the longer term turned out to be irrelevant; both were prisoners of the myopia that, in the last analysis, became the minimum price of a negotiated transition. As they moved closer together, the govern- ment and the ANC leadership developed a com- mon interest in marginalizing all opposition to their joint venture, so that there was no dissent, for example, when the TEC made the ominous decision to suspend the planned abolition of Section 29 of the Internal Security Act permit- ting detention without trial, which had been inherited from the apartheid regime.61 During the heady final months of the transition negotia- tions and the run-up to the elections, co-opting or marginalizing opposition seemed desirable to the principals and to most observers. This is understandable because the opposition being

60. Huntington, Third Wave, p. 162. 61. Southscan, February 11, 1994. Economic Development and Political Regimes

Adam Przeworski, Michael E. Alvarez, Jose´ Antonio Cheibub, and Fernando Limongi

and the incidence of democratic regimes is strong Introduction and tight. Indeed, one can correctly predict 77.5 percent of the 4,126 annual observations of Any casual glance at the world will show that regimes just by looking at per capita income.1 poor countries tend to have authoritarian What remains controversial, however, is the rel- regimes, and wealthy countries democratic ones. ative importance of the level of development as The question is why. What are the conditions compared with other factors, such as the political that determine whether democracy or dictator- legacy of a country, its past history, its social ship prevails? What causes political regimes to structure, its cultural traditions, the specific rise, endure, and fall? Can their transforma- institutional framework, and, last but not least, tions be explained generally, or are they caused the international political climate. . . . by circumstances idiosyncratic to each country . . . [T]he level of economic development, as or period? Are they driven by economic devel- measured by per capita income, is by far the opment or by other factors, such as the pre- best predictor of political regimes. Yet there are ceding political history, cultural traditions, countries in which dictatorships persist when all political institutions, or the international politi- the observable conditions indicate they should cal climate? . . . not; there are others in which democracies flour- ish in spite of all the odds. Thus some factors Development and Democracy influencing the incidence of the di¤erent kinds of regimes are not identified by this analysis. First advanced in 1959, S. M. Lipset’s observa- tion that democracy is related to economic 1. These predictions are derived from probit, a form of development has generated the largest body of non-linear regression, in which the probability that a research on any topic in comparative politics. country i will have had a dictatorial (as opposed to It has been supported and contested, revised and democratic) regime at time t is modeled as Pr(REGit ¼ Dictatorship) ¼ F(X b), where F( ) is the cumulative extended, buried and resuscitated. And yet, it distribution function (c.d.f.) of the normal distribution. though several articles in the Festschrift honor- A fair amount of ink has been spilled over the issue ing Lipset (Marks and Diamond 1992) proclaim whether or not the relationship between development conclusions, neither the theory nor the facts are and democracy is linear (Jackman 1973; Arat 1988). clear. We now know better. Democracy, however it is mea- Aggregate patterns . . . show that the relation- sured, is a qualitative or limited variable (it assumes ship between the level of economic development the value of 0 or 1 under our measurement, it ranges from 2 to 14 on the Freedom House scale, from 0 to 100 on the Bollen scale, and so on). Hence, no Excerpted from: Adam Przeworski, Michael E. predicted index of democracy can become negative as Alvarez, Jose´ Antonio Cheibub, and Fernando the level of development tends to zero, and no pre- Limongi, Democracy and Development: Political Insti- dicted index of democracy can exceed whatever is tutions and Well-Being in the World, 1950–1990. the maximum value of a particular scale as the level Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2000. 6 gets very large. Only a non-linear function, such as the Adam Przeworski, Michael E. Alvarez, Jose´ Antonio normal or logistic (as suggested by Dahl 1971), can Cheibub, and Fernando Limongi, 2000. Reprinted satisfy these constraints. This is why we use probit with the permission of Cambridge University Press. throughout. Sources of Democracy 109

causal chains consist in sequences of industrial- Regime Dynamics ization, urbanization, education, communica- tion, mobilization, political incorporation, and There are two distinct reasons that the incidence innumerable other ‘‘-ations’’: a progressive ac- of democracy may be related to the level of eco- cumulation of social changes that make a nomic development: Democracies may be more society ready to proceed to the final one, likely to emerge as countries develop economi- democratization. cally, or, having been established for whatever Modernization may be one reason that the reasons, democracies may be more likely to incidence of democracy is related to economic survive in developed countries. We call the first development, and this is the reading imputed to explanation ‘‘endogenous’’ and the second Lipset by most commentators (Diamond 1992: ‘‘exogenous.’’ 125; Huber, Rueschemeyer, and Stephens 1993: Because we are dealing with only two kinds of 711). His most influential critic, O’Donnell regimes, democracies emerge whenever dictator- (1973: 3), paraphrases Lipset’s thesis as saying ships die.6 Hence, to assert that democracies that ‘‘if other countries become as rich as the emerge as a result of economic development economically advanced nations, it is highly is the same as saying that dictatorships die as probable that they will become political democ- countries ruled by them become economically racies.’’ Democracy is endogenous, because developed. Democracy thus is said to be secreted it results from economic development under out of dictatorships by economic development. authoritarianism. The hypothesis is that if au- A story told about country after country is thoritarian countries develop, they become dem- that as a country develops, its social structure ocratic. The sequence of events we would thus becomes complex, new groups emerge and orga- expect to observe is one of poor authoritarian nize, labor processes require the active coopera- countries developing and becoming democratic tion of employees, and, as a result, the system once they reach some level of development, a can no longer be e¤ectively run by command: ‘‘threshold.’’ The society is too complex, technological change Yet suppose, just suppose, that dictatorships endows the direct producers with autonomy and are equally likely to die, and democracies to private information, civil society emerges, and emerge, at any level of development. They may dictatorial forms of control lose their e¤ective- die for so many di¤erent reasons that develop- ness. Various groups, whether the bourgeoisie, ment, with all its modernizing consequences, workers, or just the amorphous ‘‘civil society,’’ plays no privileged role. After all, as Therborn rise against the dictatorial regime, and it falls. (1977) emphasized, many European countries The endogenous explanation is a ‘‘moderniza- became democratized because of wars, not be- tion’’ theory. The basic assumption of this theory cause of ‘‘modernization,’’ a story repeated by is that there is one general process, of which the Argentine defeat in the Malvinas and else- democratization is but the final facet. Modern- where. Some dictatorships have fallen in the ization consists of a gradual di¤erentiation and aftermath of the death of the founding dictator, specialization of social structures culminating in a such as a Franco, uniquely capable of maintain- separation of the political from other structures, ing the authoritarian order. Some have collapsed and making democracy possible. The specific because of economic crises, some because of foreign pressures, and perhaps some for purely 6. This is not quite true of our data set, because dif- idiosyncratic reasons. ferent countries enter and exit the sample at di¤erent If dictatorships die and democracies emerge moments. For the moment, we consider the population randomly with regard to economic develop- of countries as fixed. Chapter 2 110

ment, is it still possible that there should be $4,000, and even less so between $4,001 and more democracies among wealthy countries than $7,000. But if income reaches the level of $7,000, among poor countries? If one is to judge Lipset the trend reverses and they become more likely (1959: 56) by his own words—‘‘The more well- to survive. . . . [T]ransitions to democracy are less to-do a nation, the greater the chances it will likely in poor countries and in rich ones, but they sustain democracy’’—then even if the emergence are more likely at the intermediate income levels. of a democracy is independent of the level If we take all the dictatorships, their probability of development, the chance that this regime will of dying during any year is 0.0198; for those survive will be greater if it is established in an with incomes over $1,000, this probability is a¿uent country. We would thus expect democ- 0.0280, over $5,000 it is 0.0526, over $6,000 it racies to appear randomly with regard to levels is 0.0441, and over $7,000 it is 0.0286; the two of development, and then to die in the poorer very wealthy dictatorships with incomes above countries and to survive in the wealthier coun- $8,000 still survived in 1990. Hence, it appears tries. And because every time a dictatorship that Huntington was correct, albeit only with happened to die in an a¿uent country democ- regard to authoritarian regimes, when he argued racy would be there to stay, history should that one should expect to observe ‘‘a bell-shaped gradually accumulate wealthy democracies. This pattern of instability’’ (1968: 43). Economic de- is no longer a modernization theory, because the velopment seems to destabilize dictatorships in emergence of democracy is not brought about by countries at intermediate levels of income, but development. Democracy appears exogenously, not in those that are poor nor in those that are deus ex machina. It tends to survive if a coun- wealthy. try is ‘‘modern,’’ but it is not a product of Indeed, dictatorships survived for years in ‘‘modernization.’’. . . countries that were wealthy by comparative Thus, to decide which mechanism generates standards. Whatever the threshold at which de- the relationship between development and de- velopment is supposed to dig the grave for an mocracy, we need to determine how the respec- authoritarian regime, it is clear that many dicta- tive transition probabilities change with the level torships must have passed it in good health. . . . of development. . . . Conversely, many dictatorships fell in coun- tries with low income levels. . . . Yet this may not be a fair test of moderniza- Level of Economic Development and Regime tion theory. After all, this theory supposes that Dynamics countries develop over a longer period, so that all the modernizing consequences have time Examine first some descriptive patterns. . . . If the to accumulate. Let us therefore examine more theory according to which the emergence of closely those countries that did develop under democracy is a result of economic development authoritarian regimes and that at some time be- is true, transitions to democracy should be more came ‘‘modern,’’ which we will take somewhat likely when authoritarian regimes reach higher arbitrarily to mean that they had a per capita levels of development. In fact, dictatorships sur- income of $4,115. . . . vive almost invariably in the very poor countries, Twenty dictatorships (to remind, out of 123) those whose per capita incomes are under did develop over longer periods of time and $1,000, or at least they succeed one another and reached ‘‘modernity.’’ Gabon, Mexico, Syria, the regime remains the same. They are less stable and Yugoslavia developed continuously for at in countries with incomes between $1,001 and least a decade, reached the level at which de- Sources of Democracy 111

mocracy would be expected to be the more likely involved, their motives and their beliefs, it regime, and, having remained under dictator- becomes apparent that these are situations laden ships, experienced a series of economic crises. with uncertainty (O’Donnell and Schmitter 1986; Singapore and Malaysia developed over a long Przeworski 1991). Game-theoretic analyses of period, became wealthy, and remained dicta- transitions to democracy make it apparent that torships. In East Germany, Taiwan, the Soviet the actors involved often do not know each Union, Spain, Bulgaria, and Hungary competi- other’s preferences, the relationships of physical tive elections eventually took place, but at very forces, or the outcomes of eventual conflicts di¤erent levels of income. Given its 1974 income (Wantchekon 1996; Zielinski 1997). And under level, Uruguay should have never been a dicta- such conditions, various equilibria can prevail: torship. The economic history of the Chilean Whereas transition to democracy is one feasible dictatorship is convoluted: Its income in 1974 outcome, so is the perpetuation of the dictatorial was $3,561; it climbed with downs and ups to status quo, or even a solidification of dictator- $4,130 by 1981, collapsed to $3,199 by 1983, ship. Hence, even if modernization may generate recovered to surpass the 1974 level only by 1986, conflicts over democracy, the outcomes of such and passed the threshold of $4,115 in 1989, conflicts are open-ended. exactly the year of transition. The history of But if modernization theory is to have any Poland is similar: By our criteria, it reached the predictive power, there must be some level of threshold of democracy in 1974; it experienced income at which one can be relatively sure that an economic crisis in 1979 and a mass move- the country will throw o¤ its dictatorship. And ment for democracy in 1980, passed the thresh- one is hard put to find this level: Even among the old again in 1985, and became a democracy in countries that satisfy the premise of the modern- 1989. In turn, Brazil, Czechoslovakia, Portugal, ization theory . . . the range of incomes at which and perhaps even South Korea and Greece are dictatorships survived is very wide. Few author- the dream cases for a modernization theorist. itarian regimes have developed over a long pe- Those countries developed under dictatorships, riod, and even if most of them should eventually became wealthy, and threw o¤ their dictator- become democracies, no level of income can ships more or less when their levels of develop- predict when that should occur. ment would have predicted. But they are few. Moreover, even if to predict is not the same as This is not to say that democracy did not to explain, ‘‘explaining’’ can easily entail an ex- emerge in some countries when they became post fallacy. Take Taiwan, which in 1952 had a modern. Indeed, perhaps in those countries that per capita income of $968. It developed rapidly, did develop over a long period, the very thought passing by 1979 our threshold of $4,115; it had of democracy appeared on the political agenda a probability of 0.10 of being a dictatorship in because they were too modern—not only in 1990, and in 1995, for the first time, elected its those countries that became democratic just president in contested elections. Suppose that when our model predicts but also those that during all that time the Taiwanese dictatorship waited much longer: Taiwan, the Soviet Union, had faced each year a probability of 0.02 of Spain, and Bulgaria. Modernization may create dying, for reasons not related to development. the ‘‘prerequisites’’ for political conflict over It thus would have had a cumulative chance of the form of regime. But the manner in which about 50 percent of not being around by 1995 these conflicts will develop remains unpredict- even if it had not developed at all. Thus we able. When conflicts over regimes are examined might erroneously attribute to development what at a micro level, by looking at the political actors may have been just a cumulation of random Chapter 2 112

hazards.9 And, indeed, the Taiwanese dicta- modernization’ characterized the ‘modernizing’ torship most likely democratized to mobilize areas. Instead of a trend toward competitiveness international support against the threat from and democracy, there was an ‘erosion of de- China: for geopolitical reasons, not for economic mocracy’ and a tendency to autocratic military reasons. regimes and one-party regimes. Instead of sta- In sum, the causal power of economic devel- bility, there were repeated coups and revolts.’’ opment in bringing down dictatorships appears We should expect ‘‘a bell-shaped pattern of paltry. The level of development, at least as political instability’’ (p. 43) among democratic as measured by per capita income, gives little well as authoritarian regimes. information about the chances of transition to O’Donnell dragged Lipset over the coals for democracy. various methodological transgressions. Reflect- On the other hand, per capita income has a ing on his criticisms in retrospect, he observed strong impact on the survival of democracies. . . . that ‘‘Chapter I is now an archeological Indeed, no democracy has ever been subverted, remnant—testimony of a debate that in 1971 not during the period we studied nor ever before had recently begun and today is finished: it is nor after, regardless of everything else, in a no longer necessary to lead the reader through country with a per capita income higher than tedious series of data to demonstrate that ‘socio- that of Argentina in 1975: $6,055. There is economic development’ does not foster ‘democ- no doubt that democracy is stable in a¿uent racy and/or political stability’ ’’ (1979: 204). countries. . . . What the data show, O’Donnell asserted, is that Huntington (1968: 1) was concerned with sta- ‘‘in contemporary South America, the higher bility and did not care whether regimes were and the lower levels of modernization are asso- democratic or authoritarian. ‘‘The most impor- ciated with non-democratic political systems, tant political distinction among countries,’’ he while political democracies are found at inter- thought, ‘‘concerns not their form of govern- mediate levels of modernization.’’ Hence, at least ment but their degree of government.’’ Hence, within the range observed by O’Donnell, we the United States, the United Kingdom, and the should observe that democracies fall as econ- Soviet Union were all systems in which ‘‘the omies develop. government governs.’’ Whether it was the Polit- Is there some level of development beyond buro, the cabinet, or the president mattered little. which democracies are more likely to die than ‘‘The problem,’’ he insisted, ‘‘was not to hold they were earlier? We have already seen . . . that elections but to create organizations.’’ Indeed, the probability of a democracy dying declines we were told, ‘‘the primary problem is not liberty monotonically with per capita income. Although but the creation of a legitimate public order’’ O’Donnell did cite a countercase against Lipset, (1968: 7). Though never explicitly referring to his account of the rise of bureaucratic authori- Lipset, Huntington (1968: 35–36) observed tarianism does not undermine Lipset’s theory.10 that ‘‘in actuality, only some of the tenden- O’Donnell studied a country that turns out to be cies encompassed in the concept of ‘political a distant outlier. . . . Thus, Lipset was right in

9. An analogy may be useful. Suppose that a woman 10. O’Donnell was careful not to make general claims: runs a risk of 0.01 of dying from accidental causes His purpose was to explain the downfall of democ- during each year of her life, and then at the age of 78 racies in the Southern Cone. But his theory of ‘‘bu- she gets hit by a falling brick. To attribute her death to reaucratic authoritarianism’’ captured the imaginations development would be to conclude that she died of old of scholars all around the world, who treated it as age. applicable almost everywhere. Sources of Democracy 113

thinking that the richer the country, the more wealth does make democracies more stable, likely it is to sustain democracy. independently of education. Clearly, this fact cries for an explanation. One Finally, we find no evidence of ‘‘consolida- possible account for the durability of democ- tion.’’ Democracies become ‘‘consolidated’’ if racies in wealthy countries, proposed already the conditional probability that a democratic by Lipset, is that, through various sociological regime will die during a particular year given mechanisms, wealth lowers the intensity of dis- that it has survived thus far (the ‘‘hazard rate’’) tributional conflicts. An alternative explanation declines with its age, so that, as Dahl (1990) has is that income is just a proxy for education, and argued, democracies are more likely to survive if more highly educated people are more likely to they have lasted for some time. Examining the embrace democratic values. Education, specifi- ages at which democracies die indicates that cally accumulated years of education for an av- this is true, but once the level of development is erage member of the labor force, does increase taken into account, the hazard rates become in- the probability of survival of democracy at each dependent of age, meaning that for a given level level of income.11 The probability that a de- of development, democracies are about equally mocracy will die in a country where the average likely to die at any age. . . . These findings indi- member of the labor force has fewer than three cate that the hazard rates uncorrected for the years of formal education is 0.1154; it is 0.0620 level of development decline because countries when the level of education is between three and develop, not because a democracy that has long six years, 0.0080 when it is six to nine years, and been around is more likely to continue. zero when the average worker has more than The conclusion reached thus far is that where- nine years of education. The highest level of as economic development under dictatorship has education under which a country experienced a at most a non-linear relationship to the emer- transition to dictatorship was 8.36 years in Sri gence of democracies, once they are established, Lanka in 1977, but that was an outlier. The next democracies are much more likely to endure in highest level of education when democracy fell more highly developed countries. Yet because was 6.85 years in Uruguay. our systematic observations begin in 1950, the But income is not a proxy for education. Even question arises whether or not these patterns also though these two variables are highly correlated characterize the earlier period. Studies in the (0.78), their e¤ects are to a large measure in- Lipset tradition have assumed that they do: They dependent. . . . [W]hereas at each income level have inferred the historical process from cross- the probability of democracy falling decreases sectional observations. Yet the validity of such with increasing education, the converse is also inferences is contested by followers of Moore true: At each level of education, the probability (1966), who claimed that the Western European of democracy dying decreases with income. route to democracy was unique, not to be re- Hence, for reasons that are not easy to identify, peated. Note that when Rustow (1970) pointed out that the levels of development at which 11. We have data only for 2,900 country-years of edu- di¤erent countries permanently established dem- cation. The mean is 4.85 years, and the standard devi- ocratic institutions varied widely, Lipset’s re- ation is 3.12, with a minimum of 0.03 (Guinea in 1966) joinder (1981) was that the thresholds at which and a maximum of 12.81 (United States in 1985); democracy was established were lower for the 27.6% of the sample had educational levels lower than early democracies. Is that true? three years, 64.4% lower than six years, and 90.8% Although economic data for the pre-war lower than nine years. Only 13.0% of the sample had period are not comparable to those at our dis- education levels higher than Sri Lanka in 1977, and posal after 1950, Maddison (1995) reconstructed 26.1% higher than Uruguay in 1973. Chapter 2 114

per capita income series for several countries Huntington, Samuel P. 1968. Political Order in going back to the nineteenth century. . . . The Changing Societies. New Haven, CT: Yale University levels at which democracies were established be- Press. fore 1950 vary as widely as they do for the later ———. 1993. The Clash of Civilizations? Foreign period; indeed, they cover almost the entire A¤airs 72(3): 22–49. range of incomes observed. . . . Jackman, Robert W. 1973. On the Relation of Eco- To conclude, there is no doubt that democ- nomic Development to Democratic Performance. racies are more likely to be found in the more American Journal of Political Science 17: 611–621. highly developed countries. Yet the reason is Lewis, Bernard. 1993. Islam and Liberal Democracy. not that democracies are more likely to emerge Atlantic Monthly 271(2): 89–98. when countries develop under authoritarianism, Lipset, Seymour Martin. 1959. Some Social Requisites but that, however they do emerge, they are more of Democracy: Economic Development and Political American Political Science Review likely to survive in countries that are already Legitimacy. 53(1): 69–105. developed. . . . ———. 1960. Political Man: The Social Bases of Poli- tics. Garden City, NY: Doubleday. References ———. 1981. Political Man: The Social Bases of Poli- tics, expanded edition. Baltimore: Johns Hopkins Uni- versity Press. Almond, Gabriel A., and . 1963. The Civic Culture: Political Attitudes and Democracy in Maddison, Angus. 1995. Monitoring the World Econ- Five Nations. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University omy, 1820–1992. Paris: Organization for Economic Press. Co-operation and Development. Arat, Zehra F. 1988. Democracy and Economic Marks, Gary, and Larry Diamond (eds.). 1992. Reex- Development: Modernization Theory Revisited. Com- amining Democracy: Essays in Honor of Seymour parative Politics 21(1): 21–36. Martin Lipset. Newbury Park, CA: Sage Publications. Dahl, Robert A. 1971. Polyarchy. New Haven, CT: Montesquieu. 1995. The Spirit of the Laws, translated Yale University Press. by Thomas Nugent. New York: Hafner Press. (Origi- nally published 1748.) ———. 1990. Transitions to Democracy. Paper read at the symposium Voices of Democracy, March 16–17, Moore, Barrington, Jr. 1966. Social Origins of Dicta- University of Dayton Center for International Studies. torship and Democracy: Lord and Peasant in the Mak- ing of the Modern World. Boston: Beacon Press. Diamond, Larry. 1992. Economic Development and Democracy Reconsidered. In Reexamining Democracy: O’Donnell, Guillermo. 1979. Postscript: 1979. In Essays in Honor of Seymour Martin Lipset, edited by Modernization and Bureaucratic-Authoritarianism: G. Marks and L. Diamond, pp. 93–139. Newbury Studies in South American Politics. Berkeley: Institute Park, CA: Sage Publications. of International Studies, University of California. Eisenstadt, S. N. 1968. The Protestant Ethic Theses O’Donnell, Guillermo, and Philippe C. Schmitter. in the Framework of Sociological Theory and Weber’s 1986. Transitions from Authoritarian Rule: Tentative Work. In The Protestant Ethic and Modernization: Conclusions about Uncertain Democracies. Baltimore: A Comparative View, edited by S. N. Eisenstadt, pp. Johns Hopkins University Press. 3–45. New York: Basic Books. Przeworski, Adam. 1991. Democracy and the Market. Gellner, Ernest. 1991. Civil Society in Historical Con- Cambridge University Press. text. International Social Science Journal 129: 495–510. Przeworski, Adam, Jose´ Antonio Cheibub, and Fer- Huber, Evelyne, Dietrich Rueschemeyer, and John D. nando Limongi. 1997. Culture and Democracy. In Stephens. 1993. The Impact of Economic Development World Culture Report, pp. 157–187. Paris: UNESCO. on Democracy. Journal of Economic Perspectives 7(3): Rustow, Dankwart A. 1970. Transitions to Democ- 71–86. racy: Toward a Dynamic Model. Comparative Politics 2(3): 337–364. Sources of Democracy 115

Therborn, Goran. 1977. The Rule of Capital and the Rise of Democracy. New Left Review 103 (May–June): 3–41. Wantchekon, Leonard. 1996. Political Coordination and Democratic Instability. Unpublished manuscript, Yale University. Weber, Max. 1958. The Protestant Ethic and the Spirit of Capitalism. New York: Scribner. (Originally pub- lished 1904.) Zielinski, Jakub. 1997. The Polish Transition to De- mocracy: A Game-Theoretic Approach. European Archives of Sociology 36: 135–158.

3 DEMOCRACY, CULTURE, AND SOCIETY

The Federalist No. 10 James Madison

The Federalist No. 14 James Madison

The Concept of a Liberal Society Louis Hartz

Pluralism and Social Choice Nicholas R. Miller

Consociational Democracy Arend Lijphart

The Contest of Ideas Donald Horowitz

The State of Democratic Theory Ian Shapiro

Democracy Robert D. Putnam

Modernization, Cultural Change, and the Persistence of Traditional Values Ronald Inglehart and Wayne E. Baker

Culture and Democracy Adam Przeworski, Jose´ Antonio Cheibub, and Fernando Limongi The Federalist No. 10

James Madison

ity.11 However anxiously we may wish that these To the People of the State of New York complaints had no foundation, the evidence of known facts will not permit us to deny that they Among the numerous advantages promised by are in some degree true. It will be found, indeed, a well-constructed Union, none deserves to be on a candid review of our situation, that some of more accurately developed than its tendency to the distresses under which we labor have been break and control the violence of faction. The erroneously charged on the operation of our friend of popular governments never finds him- governments; but it will be found, at the same self so much alarmed for their character and fate, time, that other causes will not alone account for as when he contemplates their propensity to this many of our heaviest misfortunes; and, particu- dangerous vice. He will not fail, therefore, to set larly, for that prevailing and increasing distrust a due value on any plan which, without violating of public engagements, and alarm for private the principles to which he is attached, provides a rights, which are echoed from one end of the proper cure for it. The instability, injustice, and continent to the other. These must be chiefly, if confusion introduced into the public councils, not wholly, e¤ects of the unsteadiness and injus- have, in truth, been the mortal diseases under tice with which a factious spirit has tainted our which popular governments have everywhere public administrations. perished; as they continue to be the favorite and By a faction, I understand a number of citi- fruitful topics from which the adversaries to lib- zens, whether amounting to a majority or mi- erty derive their most specious declamations. nority of the whole, who are united and actuated The valuable improvements made by the Ameri- by some common impulse of passion, or of in- can constitutions on the popular models, both terest, adverse to the rights of other citizens, or ancient and modern, cannot certainly be too to the permanent and aggregate interests of the much admired; but it would be an unwarrantable community.12 partiality, to contend that they have as e¤ectu- There are two methods of curing the mischiefs ally obviated the danger on this side, as was of faction: the one, by removing its causes; the wished and expected. Complaints are everywhere other, by controlling its e¤ects. heard from our most considerate and virtuous There are again two methods of removing the citizens, equally the friends of public and private causes of faction: the one, by destroying the lib- faith, and of public and personal liberty, that our erty which is essential to its existence; the other, governments are too unstable; that the public good is disregarded in the conflicts of rival parties; and that measures are too often decided, 11. Compare with Je¤erson’s First Inaugural: ‘‘. . . that not according to the rules of justice and the though the will of the majority is in all cases to prevail, that will, to be rightful, must be reasonable . . .’’ See rights of the minor party, but by the superior Herbert McClosky, ‘‘The Fallacy of Absolute Major- force of an interested and overbearing major- ity Rule,’’ Journal of Politics (Nov. 1949), 637–654, and Wilmoore Kendall’s response, ibid. (Nov. 1950), Excerpted from: Alexander Hamilton, James Madi- 694–713. son, and John Jay, The Federalist Papers: A Collec- 12. Both Federalists and anti-Federalists used ‘‘fac- tion of Essays Written in Support of the Constitution of tion’’ and ‘‘party’’ synonymously. And, as J. Allen the United States, second edition. Edited by Roy P. Smith pointed out, English conservatives had the same Fairfield. Garden City: Anchor, 1966. objections to factions; The Spirit of American Govern- ment (N.Y., 1912), 205. Democracy, Culture, and Society 119

by giving to every citizen the same opinions, the contending for pre-eminence and power; or to same passions, and the same interests. persons of other descriptions whose fortunes It could never be more truly said than of the have been interesting to the human passions, first remedy, that it is worse than the disease. have, in turn, divided mankind into parties, Liberty is to faction what air is to fire, an aliment inflamed them with mutual animosity, and ren- without which it instantly expires. But it could dered them much more disposed to vex and op- not be less folly to abolish liberty, which is es- press each other than to co-operate for their sential to political life, because it nourishes fac- common good.14 So strong is this propensity of tion, than it would be to wish the annihilation of mankind to fall into mutual animosities, that air, which is essential to animal life, because it where no substantial occasion presents itself, the imparts to fire its destructive agency.13 most frivolous and fanciful distinctions have The second expedient is as impracticable as been su‰cient to kindle their unfriendly passions the first would be unwise. As long as the reason and excite their most violent conflicts. But the of man continues fallible, and he is at liberty to most common and durable source of factions has exercise it, di¤erent opinions will be formed. As been the various and unequal distribution of long as the connection subsists between his rea- property.15 Those who hold and those who are son and his self-love, his opinions and his pas- without property have ever formed distinct sions will have a reciprocal influence on each interests in society. Those who are creditors, and other; and the former will be objects to which the those who are debtors, fall under a like discrimi- latter will attach themselves. The diversity in the nation. A landed interest, a manufacturing in- faculties of men, from which the rights of prop- terest, a mercantile interest, a moneyed interest, erty originate, is not less an insuperable obstacle with many lesser interests, grow up of necessity to a uniformity of interests. The protection of in civilized nations, and divide them into di¤er- these faculties is the first object of government. ent classes, actuated by di¤erent sentiments and From the protection of di¤erent and unequal views.16 The regulation of these various and faculties of acquiring property, the possession of di¤erent degrees and kinds of property immedi- 14. Adair points to this sentence as a compression of ately results; and from the influence of these on ‘‘the greater part of Hume’s essay on factions.’’ Adair, the sentiments and views of the respective pro- [‘‘That Politics May Be Reduced to a Science.’’ Hun- prietors, ensues a division of the society into dif- tington Library Quarterly (Aug. 1957), pp. 343–360], ferent interests and parties. 358. The latent causes of faction are thus sown in 15. Harold Laski, stressing Madison’s economic de- the nature of man; and we see them everywhere terminism, misquoted this passage as follows: ‘‘the only brought into di¤erent degrees of activity, ac- durable source of faction is property.’’ The Grammar of cording to the di¤erent circumstances of civil Politics (London, 1925), 162. society. A zeal for di¤erent opinions concerning 16. For Marxist comparisons other than Beard’s, see religion, concerning government, and many Saul K. Padover, ed., The Complete Madison, 14–15, and Jacques Barzun, Darwin, Marx, Wagner (Garden other points, as well of speculation as of practice; City, 1958), 146. For scholarly evaluations of the an attachment to di¤erent leaders ambitiously Marxist interpretation, see Diamond, [‘‘Democracy and The Federalist: A Reconsideration of the Framers’ 13. Contrast with Federalist, No. 9, in which Hamil- Intent.’’ American Political Science Review 53(1): 52– ton, arguing for union, says that, ‘‘The utility of a 68, March 1959], 65–66; Adair, ‘‘The Tenth Federalist Confederacy, as well to suppress faction and to guard Revisited,’’ Wm. & Mary Quarterly (Jan. 1951), 48–67; the internal tranquillity of States . . . is in reality not a Wright, [‘‘The Federalist on the Nature of Political new idea.’’ Man.’’ Ethics 59, no. 2 (Jan. 1949), pp. 1–31], 17. . . . Chapter 3 120

interfering interests forms the principal task of almost every case, be felt by a majority of the modern legislation, and involves the spirit of whole; a communication and concert result from party and faction in the necessary and ordinary the form of government itself; and there is noth- operations of the government. . . . ing to check the inducements to sacrifice the The inference to which we are brought is, that weaker party or an obnoxious individual. Hence the causes of faction cannot be removed, and it is that such democracies have ever been spec- that relief is only to be sought in the means of tacles of turbulence and contention; have ever controlling its e¤ects. been found incompatible with personal security If a faction consists of less than a majority, or the rights of property; and have in general relief is supplied by the republican principle, been as short in their lives as they have been vi- which enables the majority to defeat its sinister olent in their deaths. Theoretic politicians, who views by regular vote. It may clog the adminis- have patronized this species of government, have tration, it may convulse the society; but it will be erroneously supposed that by reducing mankind unable to execute and mask its violence under to a perfect equality in their political rights, they the forms of the Constitution. When a majority would, at the same time, be perfectly equalized is included in a faction, the form of popular and assimilated in their possessions, their opin- government, on the other hand, enables it to ions, and their passions. sacrifice to its ruling passion or interest both the A republic, by which I mean a government in public good and the rights of other citizens. To which the scheme of representation takes place, secure the public good and private rights against opens a di¤erent prospect, and promises the cure the danger of such a faction, and at the same for which we are seeking. . . . time to preserve the spirit and the form of popu- The two great points of di¤erence between lar government, is then the great object to which a democracy and a republic are: first, the dele- our inquiries are directed. . . . gation of the government in the latter to a From this view of the subject it may be con- small number of citizens elected by the rest; sec- cluded that a pure democracy, by which I mean ondly, the greater number of citizens and greater a society consisting of a small number of citizens, sphere of country over which the latter may be who assemble and administer the government in extended. person, can admit of no cure for the mischiefs of The e¤ect of the first di¤erence is, on the one faction.17 A common passion or interest will, in hand, to refine and enlarge the public views, by passing them through the medium of a chosen 17. Democracy had a bad name from early times. body of citizens,18 whose wisdom may best dis- Plato condemned it in The Republic (Book VIII), cern the true interest of their country, and whose Aristotle in Politics (Book IV). In more recent times, Montesquieu, who had a great impact upon the (By permission of the Wayne State University Press.) fathers, attacked it in Spirit of Laws (I, Book VIII). For two other valuable historical and philosophical For an account of the conservative-democratic contro- views, see Harold Laski’s essay on the concept in the versy in the 1763–87 period, see Merrill Jensen, The Encyclopedia of the Social Sciences (N.Y., 1931), V, Articles of Confederation and The New Nation; for a 76–84, and Henry B. Mayo, An Introduction to Demo- few typical eighteenth-century views of democracy, see cratic Theory (N.Y., 1960). Richard Hofstadter, The American Political Tradition 18. A variation on a theme? Also, see Jay’s reliance (N.Y., 1948), 4. As Ralph Ketcham points out, upon Providence in No. 2. Other ‘‘chosen people’’ [‘‘Notes on James Madison’s Sources,’’ Midwest Jour- concepts: Hebrew, England’s Whig oligarchy, New nal of Political Science (May 1957)], 25, ‘‘. . . there was England’s theocratic oligarchy, etc. Suggested by B. C. almost universal agreement in the eighteenth century Rodick, American Constitutional Custom (N.Y., 1953), that ‘democracy’ was a nasty word—it meant tumult, 136. violence, instability, mob rule, and bloody revolution.’’ Democracy, Culture, and Society 121

patriotism and love of justice will be least likely with all their local circumstances and lesser to sacrifice it to temporary or partial consid- interests: as by reducing it too much, you render erations. Under such a regulation, it may well him unduly attached to these, and too little fit happen that the public voice, pronounced by the to comprehend and pursue great and national representatives of the people, will be more con- objects. The federal Constitution forms a happy sonant to the public good than if pronounced by combination in this respect; the great and aggre- the people themselves, convened for the purpose. gate interests being referred to the national, the On the other hand, the e¤ect may be inverted. local and particular to the State legislatures. Men of factious tempers, of local prejudices, or The other point of di¤erence is, the greater of sinister designs, may by intrigue, by corrup- number of citizens and extent of territory which tion, or by other means, first obtain the suf- may be brought within the compass of republi- frages, and then betray the interests of the people. can than of democratic government; and it is this The question resulting is, whether small or ex- circumstance principally which renders factious tensive republics are more favorable to the elec- combinations less to be dreaded in the former tion of proper guardians of the public weal; and than in the latter. The smaller the society, the it is clearly decided in favor of the latter by two fewer probably will be the distinct parties and obvious considerations. interests composing it; the fewer the distinct In the first place, it is to be remarked that, parties and interests, the more frequently will a however small the republic may be, the repre- majority be found of the same party; and the sentatives must be raised to a certain number in smaller the number of individuals composing a order to guard against the cabals of a few; and majority, and the smaller the compass within that, however large it may be, they must be which they are placed, the more easily will they limited to a certain number in order to guard concert and execute their plans of oppression. against the confusion of a multitude. Hence, the Extend the sphere, and you take in a greater va- number of representatives in the two cases not riety of parties and interests; you make it less being in proportion to that of the two con- probable that a majority of the whole will have a stituents, and being proportionally greater in the common motive to invade the rights of other small republic, it follows that, if the proportion citizens; or if such a common motive exists, it of fit characters be not less in the large than in will be more di‰cult for all who feel it to dis- the small republic, the former will present a cover their own strength and to act in unison greater option and consequently a greater prob- with each other. Besides other impediments, it ability of a fit choice. may be remarked that, where there is a con- In the next place, as each representative will be sciousness of unjust or dishonorable purposes, chosen by a greater number of citizens in the communication is always checked by distrust in large than in the small republic, it will be more proportion to the number whose concurrence is di‰cult for unworthy candidates to practise with necessary.19 success the vicious arts by which elections are too often carried; and the su¤rages of the people 19. It might be asked, Where does Madison acquire his being more free, will be more likely to centre in faith in the magic of numbers? Does he come to grips men who possess the most attractive merit and with the problem of the demagogue? And does he dis- the most di¤usive and established characters. cuss comprehensively the fact that the impediments It must be confessed that in this, as in most eliminating the dire e¤ects of faction might also pre- other cases, there is a mean, on both sides of vent positive action? Is Louis Hartz correct when he which inconveniences will be found to lie. By claims that Madison did not solve the problem of fac- tion as related to economic factors? The Liberal Tradi- enlarging too much the number of electors, you tion in America (N.Y., 1955), 84–85. render the representative too little acquainted Chapter 3 122

Hence, it clearly appears that the same ad- The influence of factious leaders may kindle a vantage which a republic has over a democracy flame within their particular States, but will be in controlling the e¤ects of faction is enjoyed by unable to spread a general conflagration through a large over a small republic,—is enjoyed by the the other States. A religious sect may degenerate Union over the States composing it.20 Does the into a political faction in a part of the Confed- advantage consist in the substitution of repre- eracy; but the variety of sects dispersed over the sentatives whose enlightened views and virtuous entire face of it must secure the national councils sentiments render them superior to local preju- against any danger from that source. A rage for dices and to schemes of injustice? It will not be paper money, for an abolition of debts, for an denied that the representation of the Union will equal division of property, or for any other im- be most likely to possess these requisite endow- proper or wicked project, will be less apt to per- ments. Does it consist in the greater security vade the whole body of the Union than a a¤orded by a greater variety of parties, against particular member of it; in the same proportion the event of any one party being able to out- as such a malady is more likely to taint a partic- number and oppress the rest? In an equal degree ular county or district, than an entire State. does the increased variety of parties comprised In the extent and proper structure of the within the Union, increase this security. Does Union, therefore, we behold a republican remedy it, in fine, consist in the greater obstacles op- for the diseases most incident to republican gov- posed to the concert and accomplishment of the ernment. And according to the degree of plea- secret wishes of an unjust and interested major- sure and pride we feel in being republicans, ity? Here, again, the extent of the Union gives it ought to be our zeal in cherishing the spirit and the most palpable advantage. supporting the character of Federalists.

20. Aristotle said that ‘‘the size of a state . . . should be Publius determined by the range of a man’s voice,’’ quoted by Cousins, [‘‘World Citizenship—When?’’ in Lyman Bryson, ed. Approaches to World Peace (New York: Harper, 1944)], 523. And such remained the thought and experience of the eighteenth century, that a repub- lic was feasible only in a small geographic area. Thus it is not surprising to find the anti-Federalists attacking the concept of the extensive republic found in the Constitution and Federalist, No. 10; Ford, Essays,4, 74, 76, 91, 255–256. Adair, tracing the sources for No. 10, suggests that Madison may have been ‘‘electrified’’ by the following comments in Hume: In a large government, which is modelled with masterly skill, there is compass and room enough to refine the democracy, from the lower people, who may be ad- mitted into the first elections or first concoction of the commonwealth, to the higher magistrates, who direct all the movements. At the same time, the parts are so distant and remote, that it is very di‰cult, either by intrigue, prejudice, or passion, to hurry them into any measure against the public interest. Op. cit., 351. The Federalist No. 14

James Madison

ble and administer it by their representatives and To the People of the State of New York agents. A democracy, consequently, will be con- fined to a small spot. A republic may be ex- We have seen the necessity of the Union, as our tended over a large region. bulwark against foreign danger, as the conserva- To this accidental source of the error may be tor of peace among ourselves, as the guardian of added the artifice of some celebrated authors, our commerce and other common interests, as whose writings have had a great share in form- the only substitute for those military establish- ing the modern standard of political opinions. ments which have subverted the liberties of Being subjects either of an absolute or limited the Old World, and as the proper antidote for monarchy, they have endeavored to heighten the the diseases of faction, which have proved fatal advantages, or palliate the evils of those forms, to other popular governments, and of which by placing in comparison the vices and defects of alarming symptoms have been betrayed by our the republican, and by citing as specimens of own. All that remains, within this branch of our the latter the turbulent democracies of ancient inquiries, is to take notice of an objection that Greece and modern Italy. Under the confusion may be drawn from the great extent of country of names, it has been an easy task to transfer to a which the Union embraces. A few observations republic observations applicable to a democracy on this subject will be the more proper, as it is only; and among others, the observation that perceived that the adversaries of the new Con- it can never be established but among a small stitution are availing themselves of the prevailing number of people living within a small compass prejudice with regard to the practicable sphere of of territory. republican administration, in order to supply, Such a fallacy may have been the less per- by imaginary di‰culties, the want of those solid ceived, as most of the popular governments of objections which they endeavor in vain to find. antiquity were of the democratic species; and The error which limits republican government even in modern Europe, to which we owe the to a narrow district has been unfolded and great principle of representation, no example is refuted in preceding papers. I remark here only seen of a government wholly popular, and that it seems to owe its rise and prevalence founded at the same time wholly on that princi- chiefly to the confounding of a republic with a ple. If Europe has the merit of discovering this democracy, applying to the former reasonings great mechanical power in government, by the drawn from the nature of the latter. The true simple agency of which the will of the largest distinction between these forms was also ad- political body may be concentred, and its force verted to on a former occasion. It is, that in a directed to any object which the public good democracy, the people meet and exercise the requires, America can claim the merit of making government in person; in a republic, they assem- the discovery the basis of unmixed and extensive republics. It is only to be lamented that any of Excerpted from: Alexander Hamilton, James Madi- her citizens should wish to deprive her of the son, and John Jay, The Federalist Papers: A Collec- additional merit of displaying its full e‰cacy in tion of Essays Written in Support of the Constitution of the establishment of the comprehensive system the United States, second edition. Edited by Roy P. Fairfield. Garden City: Anchor, 1966. now under her consideration. As the natural limit of a democracy is that distance from the central point which will just Chapter 3 124

permit the most remote citizens to assemble as arrangements that may be necessary for those often as their public functions demand, and will angles and fractions of our territory which lie on include no greater number than can join in those our northwestern frontier, must be left to those functions; so the natural limit of a republic is whom further discoveries and experience will that distance from the centre which will barely render more equal to the task. allow the representatives to meet as often as may Let it be remarked, in the third place, that the be necessary for the administration of public af- intercourse throughout the Union will be facili- fairs. Can it be said that the limits of the United tated by new improvements. Roads will every- States exceed this distance? It will not be said by where be shortened and kept in better order; those who recollect that the Atlantic coast is the accommodations for travellers will be multiplied longest side of the Union, that during the term and meliorated; an interior navigation on our of thirteen years the representatives of the States eastern side will be opened throughout, or nearly have been almost continually assembled, and throughout, the whole extent of the thirteen that the members from the most distant States States. The communication between the Western are not chargeable with greater intermissions of and Atlantic districts, and between di¤erent attendance than those from the States in the parts of each, will be rendered more and more neighborhood of Congress. easy by those numerous canals with which the That we may form a juster estimate with re- beneficence of nature has intersected our coun- gard to this interesting subject, let us resort to try, and which art finds it so little di‰cult to the actual dimensions of the Union. . . . connect and complete. . . . [I]t is to be remembered that the general A fourth and still more important consider- government is not to be charged with the whole ation is, that as almost every State will on one power of making and administering laws. Its ju- side or other be a frontier, and will thus find, in a risdiction is limited to certain enumerated objects regard to its safety, an inducement to make some which concern all the members of the republic, sacrifices for the sake of the general protection; but which are not to be attained by the separate so the States which lie at the greatest distance provisions of any. The subordinate governments, from the heart of the Union, and which, of which can extend their care to all those other course, may partake least of the ordinary circu- objects which can be separately provided for, lation of its benefits, will be at the same time will retain their due authority and activity. Were immediately contiguous to foreign nations, and it proposed by the plan of the convention to will consequently stand, on particular occasions, abolish the governments of the particular States, in greatest need of its strength and resources. It its adversaries would have some ground for their may be inconvenient for Georgia, or the States objection; though it would not be di‰cult to forming our western or northeastern borders, to show that if they were abolished the general send their representatives to the seat of govern- government would be compelled, by the princi- ment; but they would find it more so to struggle ple of self-preservation, to reinstate them in their alone against an invading enemy, or even to proper jurisdiction. support alone the whole expense of those pre- A second observation to be made is that the cautions which may be dictated by the neigh- immediate object of the federal Constitution is to borhood of continual danger. If they should secure the union of the thirteen primitive States, derive less benefit, therefore, from the Union which we know to be practicable; and to add to in some respects than the less distant States, them such other States as may arise in their own they will derive greater benefit from it in other bosoms or in their neighborhoods, which we respects, and thus the proper equilibrium will be cannot doubt to be equally practicable. The maintained throughout. Democracy, Culture, and Society 125

I submit to you, my fellow-citizens, these con- nations, they have not su¤ered a blind venera- siderations, in full confidence that the good sense tion for antiquity, for custom, or for names to which has so often marked your decisions will overrule the suggestions of their own good sense, allow them their due weight and e¤ect; and that the knowledge of their own situation, and the you will never su¤er di‰culties, however formi- lessons of their own experience? To this manly dable in appearance, or however fashionable the spirit posterity will be indebted for the posses- error on which they may be founded, to drive sion, and the world for the example, of the nu- you into the gloomy and perilous scene into merous innovations displayed on the American which the advocates for disunion would conduct theatre in favor of private rights and public you. Hearken not to the unnatural voice which happiness. Had no important step been taken by tells you that the people of America, knit to- the leaders of the Revolution for which a prece- gether as they are by so many cords of a¤ection, dent could not be discovered, no government can no longer live together as members of the established of which an exact model did not same family; can no longer continue the mutual present itself, the people of the United States guardians of their mutual happiness; can no might at this moment have been numbered longer be fellow-citizens of one great, respect- among the melancholy victims of misguided able, and flourishing empire. Hearken not to the councils, must at best have been laboring under voice which petulantly tells you that the form of the weight of some of those forms which have government recommended for your adoption is a crushed the liberties of the rest of mankind. novelty in the political world;21 that it has never Happily for America, happily, we trust, for the yet had a place in the theories of the wildest whole human race, they pursued a new and more projectors; that it rashly attempts what it is im- noble course. They accomplished a revolution possible to accomplish. No, my countrymen, which has no parallel in the annals of human shut your ears against this unhallowed language. society. They reared the fabrics of governments Shut your hearts against the poison which it which have no model on the face of the globe. conveys; the kindred blood which flows in the They formed the design of a great Confederacy veins of American citizens, the mingled blood which it is incumbent on their successors to which they have shed in defence of their sacred improve and perpetuate. If their works betray rights, consecrate their Union and excite horror imperfections, we wonder at the fewness of them. at the idea of their becoming aliens, rivals, ene- If they erred most in the structure of the Union, mies. And if novelties are to be shunned, believe this was the work most di‰cult to be executed; me, the most alarming of all novelties, the most this is the work which has been new modelled by wild of all projects, the most rash of all attempts, the act of your convention, and it is that act on is that of rending us in pieces in order to preserve which you are now to deliberate and to decide. our liberties and promote our happiness. But why is the experiment of an extended republic to Publius be rejected, merely because it may comprise what is new? Is it not the glory of the people of America, that, whilst they have paid a decent regard to the opinions of former times and other

21. Diamond, op. cit., 60, argues that the novelty ‘‘consisted in solving the problems of popular govern- ment by means which yet maintain the government ‘wholly popular.’’’ The Concept of a Liberal Society

Louis Hartz

light of that fact. There are a number of reasons 1. America and Europe for this which we shall encounter before we are through, but one is obvious at the outset: the The analysis which this book contains is based separation of the study of American from Euro- on what might be called the storybook truth pean history and politics. Any attempt to un- about American history: that America was set- cover the nature of an American society without tled by men who fled from the feudal and clerical feudalism can only be accomplished by studying oppressions of the Old World. If there is any- it in conjunction with a European society where thing in this view, as old as the national folklore the feudal structure and the feudal ethos did in itself, then the outstanding thing about the fact survive. This is not to deny our national American community in Western history ought uniqueness, one of the reasons curiously given to be the nonexistence of those oppressions, or for studying America alone, but actually to af- since the reaction against them was in the firm it. How can we know the uniqueness of broadest sense liberal, that the American com- anything except by contrasting it with what is munity is a liberal community. We are con- not unique? The rationale for a separate Ameri- fronted, as it were, with a kind of inverted can study, once you begin to think about it, Trotskyite law of combined development, explodes the study itself. . . . America skipping the feudal stage of history as Russia presumably skipped the liberal stage. I know that I am using broad terms broadly here. 2. ‘‘Natural Liberalism’’: The Frame of Mind ‘‘Feudalism’’ refers technically to the institutions of the medieval era, and it is well known that One of the central characteristics of a nonfeudal aspects of the decadent feudalism of the later society is that it lacks a genuine revolutionary period, such as primogeniture, entail, and qui- tradition, the tradition which in Europe has been trents, were present in America even in the eigh- linked with the Puritan and French revolutions: teenth century. ‘‘Liberalism’’ is an even vaguer that it is ‘‘born equal,’’ as Tocqueville said. And term, clouded as it is by all sorts of modern so- this being the case, it lacks also a tradition of cial reform connotations, and even when one reaction: lacking Robespierre it lacks Maistre, insists on using it in the classic Lockian sense, as lacking Sydney it lacks Charles II. Its liberalism I shall insist here, there are aspects of our origi- is what Santayana called, referring to American nal life in the Puritan colonies and the South democracy, a ‘‘natural’’ phenomenon. But the which hardly fit its meaning. But these are the matter is curiously broader than this, for a soci- liabilities of any large generalization, danger ety which begins with Locke, and thus trans- points but not insuperable barriers. What in the forms him, stays with Locke, by virtue of an end is more interesting is the curious failure of absolute and irrational attachment it develops American historians, after repeating endlessly for him, and becomes as indi¤erent to the chal- that America was grounded in escape from the lenge of socialism in the later era as it was un- European past, to interpret our history in the familiar with the heritage of feudalism in the earlier one. It has within it, as it were, a kind of Excerpted from: Louis Hartz, The Liberal Tradition self-completing mechanism, which insures the in America: An Interpretation of American Political universality of the liberal idea. . . . It is not acci- Thought Since the Revolution. New York: Harcourt, dental that America which has uniquely lacked a Brace & World, 1955. Reprinted by permission. Democracy, Culture, and Society 127

feudal tradition has uniquely lacked also a so- At bottom it is riddled with paradox. Here is a cialist tradition. The hidden origin of socialist Lockian doctrine which in the West as a whole is thought everywhere in the West is to be found the symbol of rationalism, yet in America the in the feudal ethos. The ancien re´gime inspires devotion to it has been so irrational that it has Rousseau; both inspire Marx. not even been recognized for what it is: liberal- Which brings us to the substantive quality of ism. There has never been a ‘‘liberal movement’’ the natural liberal mind. . . . And yet if we study or a real ‘‘liberal party’’ in America: we have the American liberal language in terms of inten- only had the American Way of Life, a national- sity and emphasis, if we look for silent omissions ist articulation of Locke which usually does not as well as explicit inclusions, we begin to see a know that Locke himself is involved; and we did pattern emerging that smacks distinctively of not even get that until after the Civil War when the New World. It has a quiet, matter of fact the Whigs of the nation, deserting the Hamil- quality, it does not understand the meaning of tonian tradition, saw the capital that could be sovereign power, the bourgeois class passion is made out of it. This is why even critics who have scarcely present, the sense of the past is altered, noticed America’s moral unity have usually and there is about it all, as compared with the missed its substance. Ironically, ‘‘liberalism’’ is a European pattern, a vast and almost charming stranger in the land of its greatest realization and innocence of mind. . . . America has presented fulfillment. But this is not all. Here is a doctrine the world with the peculiar phenomenon, not of which everywhere in the West has been a glori- a frustrated middle class, but of a ‘‘frustrated ous symbol of individual liberty, yet in America aristocracy’’—of men, Aristotelian-like, trying its compulsive power has been so great that it to break out of the egalitarian confines of middle has posed a threat to liberty itself. . . . class life but su¤ering guilt and failure in the I believe that this is the basic ethical problem process. The South before the Civil War is the of a liberal society: not the danger of the ma- case par excellence of this, though New England jority which has been its conscious fear, but of course exemplifies it also. . . . the danger of unanimity, which has slumbered Surely, then, it is a remarkable force: this unconsciously behind it: the ‘‘tyranny of opin- fixed, dogmatic liberalism of a liberal way of life. ion’’ that Tocqueville saw unfolding as even the It is the secret root from which have sprung pathetic social distinctions of the Federalist era many of the most puzzling of American cultural collapsed before his eyes. But in recent times this phenomena. Take the unusual power of the Su- manifestation of irrational Lockianism, or of preme Court and the cult of constitution worship ‘‘Americanism,’’ to use a favorite term of the on which it rests. Federal factors apart, judicial American Legion, one of the best expounders of review as it has worked in America would be the national spirit that Whiggery discovered after inconceivable without the national acceptance the Civil War, has neither slumbered nor been of the Lockian creed, ultimately enshrined in unconscious. It has been very much awake in a the Constitution, since the removal of high red scare hysteria which no other nation in the policy to the realm of adjudication implies a West has really been able to understand. And prior recognition of the principles to be legally this suggests a very significant principle: that interpreted. . . . when a liberal community faces military and . . . [L]aw has flourished on the corpse of phi- ideological pressure from without it transforms losophy in America, for the settlement of the ul- eccentricity into sin, and the irritating figure of timate moral question is the end of speculation the bourgeois gossip flowers into the frightening upon it. . . . The moral unanimity of a liberal so- figure of an A. Mitchell Palmer or a Senator ciety reaches out in many directions. McCarthy. Do we not find here, hidden away at Chapter 3 128

the base of the American mind, one of the rea- cultures outside it. It asks whether American sons why its legalism has been so imperfect a liberalism can acquire through external experi- barrier against the violent moods of its mass ence that sense of relativity, that spark of phi- Lockianism? If the latter is nourished by the losophy which European liberalism acquired former, how can we expect it to be strong? . . . through an internal experience of social diversity The decisive domestic issue of our time may and social conflict. But if the final problem posed well lie in the counter resources a liberal society by the American liberal community is bizarre, can muster against this deep and unwritten this is merely a continuation of its historic rec- tyrannical compulsion it contains. They exist. ord. That community has always been a place Given the individualist nature of the Lockian where the common issues of the West have taken doctrine, there is always a logical impulse within strange and singular shape. it to transcend the very conformitarian spirit it breeds in a Lockian society: witness the spirit of Holmes and Hand. Given the fact, which we 3. The Dynamics of a Liberal Society shall study at length later, that ‘‘Americanism’’ oddly disadvantages the Progressive despite the So far I have spoken of natural liberalism as a fact that he shares it to the full, there is always psychological whole, embracing the nation and a strategic impulse within him to transcend it: inspiring unanimous decisions. We must not as- witness the spirit of Brandeis, Roosevelt, and sume, however, that this is to obscure or to min- Stevenson. In some sense the tragedy of these imize the nature of the internal conflicts which movements has lain in the imperfect knowledge have characterized American political life. We they have had of the enemy they face, above all can hardly choose between an event and its con- in their failure to see their own unwitting contri- text, though in the study of history and politics bution to his strength. . . . there will always be some who will ask us to do But the most powerful force working to so. What we learn from the concept of a liberal shatter the American absolutism is, paradoxi- society, lacking feudalism and therefore social- cally enough, the very international involvement ism and governed by an irrational Lockianism, is which tensifies it. This involvement is complex in that the domestic struggles of such a society have its implications. If in the context of the Russian all been projected with the setting of Western Revolution it elicits a domestic redscare, in the liberal alignments. And here there begin to context of diplomacy it elicits an impulse to emerge, not a set of negative European correla- impose Locke everywhere. The way in which tions, but a set of very positive ones which have ‘‘Americanism’’ brings McCarthy together with been almost completely neglected. Wilson is of great significance and it is, needless We can thus say of the right in America that it to say, another one of Progressivism’s neglected exemplifies the tradition of big propertied liber- roots in the Rousseauan tide it often seeks to alism in Europe, a tradition familiar enough stem. Thus to say that world politics shatters though, as I shall suggest in a moment, much ‘‘Americanism’’ at the moment it intensifies it is still remains to be done in studying it along to say a lot: it is to say that the basic horizons of transnational lines. . . . Similarly the European the nation both at home and abroad are drasti- ‘‘petit-bourgeois’’ tradition is the starting point cally widened by it. . . . for an understanding of the American left. Here, Historically the issue here is one for which we to be sure, there are critical problems of identifi- have little precedent. It raises the question of cation, since one of the main things America did whether a nation can compensate for the unifor- was to expand and transform the European mity of its domestic life by contact with alien ‘‘petit-bourgeois’’ by absorbing both the peas- Democracy, Culture, and Society 129

antry and the proletariat into the structure of his but those rural and urban elements which the personality. . . . American liberal community has transformed. One of the reasons these European liberal Ultimately, as with the Whigs, for all of the correlations have gone neglected is quite obvious magical chemistry of American liberal society, once you try to make them. America represents we are dealing with social materials common to the liberal mechanism of Europe functioning the Western world. without the European social antagonisms, but That society has been a triumph for the liberal the truth is, it is only through these antagonisms idea, but we must not assume that this ideologi- that we recognize the mechanism. We know the cal victory was not helped forward by the mag- European liberal, as it were, by the enemies he nificent material setting it found in the New has made: take them away in American fashion World. The agrarian and proletarian strands and he does not seem like the same man at of the American democratic personality, which all. . . . After 1840, when the American Whig in some sense typify the whole of American gives up his Hamiltonian elitism and discovers uniqueness, reveal a remarkable collusion be- the Horatio Alger ethos of a liberal society, dis- tween Locke and the New World. Had it been covers ‘‘Americanism,’’ the task of identification merely the liberal spirit alone which inspired the is even harder. For while it is true that the lib- American farmer to become capitalistically ori- erals of England and France ultimately accepted ented, to repudiate save for a few early remnants political democracy, Algerism and ‘‘American- the village organization of Europe, to produce ism’’ were social ideologies they could hardly for a market and even to enter capitalist occu- exploit. So that the continuing problem of a pations on the side such as logging and railroad missing Toryism, which is enough to separate building, then the di‰culties he encountered the American Republicans from the reactionary would have been greater than they were. But liberals of Victorian England and the Neo- where land was abundant and the voyage to the Girondins of the Third Republic, is complicated New World itself a claim to independence, the further by the unique ideological shape that the spirit which repudiated peasantry and tenantry Whig tradition is destined to take in a liberal flourished with remarkable ease. Similarly, had it society. merely been an aspect of irrational Lockianism The American democrat, that ‘‘petit-bour- which inspired the American worker to think in geois’’ hybrid of the American world, raises terms of the capitalist setup, the task would have even more intricate questions. To take away the been harder than it was. Social Republic from the French Montagnards But social fluidity was peculiarly fortified by changes their appearance just about as much as the riches of a rich land, so that there was no taking away the feudal right from the English small amount of meaning to Lincoln’s claim in Whigs. But the American democrat, alas, devi- 1861 that the American laborer, instead of ‘‘be- ated sharply from the Montagnards to begin ing fixed to that condition for life,’’ works for with, since in addition to being ‘‘petit-bourgeois’’ ‘‘a while,’’ then ‘‘saves,’’ then ‘‘hires another be- in their sense he was a liberal peasant and a lib- ginner’’ as he himself becomes an entrepreneur.1 eral proletarian as well: indeed the whole of the And even when factory industrialism gained nation apart from the Whig, a condition hardly sway after the Civil War, and the old artisan and vouchsafed to the Montagnards. And yet even in cottage-and-mill mentality was definitely gone, it the face of such tremendous variations, compar- ative analysis can continue. We have to tear the 1. L. Hacker, The Triumph of American Capitalism giant figure of Jackson apart, sorting out not (New York, 1940), p. 279. only the ‘‘petit-bourgeois’’ element of the man Chapter 3 130

was still a Lockian idea fortified by material So one cannot say of the liberal society analy- resources which inspired the triumph of the job sis that by concentrating on national unities mentality of Gompers rather than the class it rules out the meaning of domestic conflict. mentality of the European worker. The ‘‘petit- Actually it discovers that meaning, which is bourgeois’’ giant of America, though ultimately obscured by the very Progressive analysis that a triumph for the liberal idea, could hardly have presumably concentrates on conflict. You do not chosen a better material setting in which to get closer to the significance of an earthquake by flourish. ignoring the terrain on which it takes place. On But a liberal society does not merely produce the contrary, that is one of the best ways of old Whig and new democrat, does not merely making sure that you will miss its significance. cast a strange set of lights and shadows on them. The argument over whether we should ‘‘stress’’ More crucially it shapes the outcome of the solidarity or conflict in American politics mis- struggle in which they engage. . . . leads us by advancing a false set of alternatives. Firstly America, by making its ‘‘petit- bourgeois’’ hybrid the mass of the nation, makes him unconquerable, save in two instances: when 4. The Problem of a Single Factor he is disorganized, as prior to Je¤erson and Jackson, or when he is enchanted with the dream It will be said that this is a ‘‘single factor’’ anal- of becoming a Whig himself, as prior to the ysis of American history and politics, and prob- crash of 1929. Which is merely another way of ably the only way of meeting this charge is to saying that the historic Whig technique of divide admit it. Technically we are actually dealing et impera which comes out perhaps most vividly with two factors: the absence of feudalism and at the time of the First Reform Act and the July the presence of the liberal idea. The escape from Revolution—of playing the mass against the the old European order could be accompanied ancien re´gime, the ancien re´gime against the by other ideas, as for instance the Chartist con- mass, and the mass against itself—cannot work cept which had some e¤ect in the settlement of in a society where the mass embraces everything Australia.* But in terms of European history it- but Whiggery. This is what the Hamiltonian Federalists, who actually tried to pursue this *What is needed here is a comparative study of new course in America, ultimately had to learn. And societies which will put alongside the European insti- this is also why, when they learned it, even their tutions left behind the positive cultural concepts existing resemblance to European Whiggery dis- brought to the various frontier settings. There are an appeared and they became distinctively Ameri- infinite variety of combinations possible, and an infi- nite variety of results. Veblen, in a sentence he never can operators. What they learned was the Alger followed up, caught some of the significance of this mechanism of enchanting the American demo- problem when he said that ‘‘it was the fortune of the crat and the ‘‘Americanistic’’ mechanism of ter- American people to have taken their point of departure rifying him, which was the bounty they were from the European situation when the system of Nat- destined to receive for the European strategies of ural Liberty was still ‘obvious and simple,’’’ while which they were deprived. For the defeat of other colonial enterprises ‘‘have had their institutional Hamilton, so long as the economy boomed, they point of departure blurred with a scattering of the were bound to get the victory of McKinley. One holdovers that were brought in again by the return might call this the great law of Whig compensa- wave of reaction in Europe, as well as by these later- tion inherent in American politics. The record of come stirrings of radical discontent that have ques- tioned the eternal fitness of the system of Natural its functioning takes up a large part of American Liberty itself.’’ What Veblen Taught, ed. W. Mitchell history. (New York, 1947), pp. 368–369. Democracy, Culture, and Society 131

self the abstraction of the feudal force implies the in England and France, and on a larger scale, natural development of liberalism, so that for all so that the theory advanced to supplant Turner practical purposes we are dealing with a single fares no better than his own. Indeed if we check factor. . . . back to the comparative analysis yielded by the Viewed in these terms the feudal issue is one liberal society concept we see that it was the whose consideration in American history is long nonproletarian outlook of the early American overdue. This is not only because of the chain of working class, the fact that it did not frighten the insights it yields, as long as the course of our mass of small property owners above it, as the national development itself, but also because Social Republic frightened the French Mountain without it other elements have been burdened in 1848, which saved the democratic forces of with work which it alone can do. Consider that the nation from being split to the advantage of ancient question: the early triumph of American Whiggery, as they so often were in Europe. Or democracy. Turner’s frontier, of course, has been take the explanation from capitalist growth of advanced to explain this phenomenon but, dis- the national Alger ideology after the Civil War. covering alas that frontiers are to be found in Capitalism was surely related to Alger, but if it Canada where feudalism was originally imported produced him, why did it not do so in Germany and in Russia, historians have revolted against where it was booming at the same time or in the Turner approach. Actually, as I have sug- England where it boomed earlier? Actually the gested on the basis of the comparative European Alger spirit is the peculiar instinct of a Lockian data, the speedy victory of manhood su¤rage world, and what capitalist growth did, once the in America was dictated by the inevitable frus- Whigs began to articulate it, was to fortify their tration of elitist Whiggery in a liberal context. case. . . . Which suggests that Turner was not wrong but, These sample instances illustrate the utility of in a way he scarcely understood, half right, for the liberal society concept in relation to familiar how could American liberalism flourish as it problems. Though concerned with a ‘‘single fac- did without a frontier terrain free of Old World tor,’’ its e¤ect is actually to balance distorted feudal burdens?2 By claiming its own, in other emphases that we have traditionally lived with in words, the liberal society concept puts the fron- the study of American history and politics. tier in proper perspective, dissolving both the exaggerated enthusiasms and the exaggerated hostilities that it has engendered. 5. Implications for Europe It does the same thing with other factors, as for example capitalist growth. Reacting against If Europe provides data for checking America, Turner (to continue with the democratic illustra- America provides data for checking Europe: we tion) some recent historians have pointed to the are dealing with a two-way proposition. So that growth of industrialism and an Eastern urban the liberal society analysis, at the same moment proletariat to explain the swift appearance of it stresses the absence of the feudal factor in American manhood su¤rage. Certainly there America, stresses its presence abroad. Modern were pressures here. But if we do not find them European historians have never evolved an in- in Canada and Russia prior to Jackson, we do terpretation of their subject from precisely this point of view. To some extent, no doubt, this is 2. See the brilliant comments of B. F. Wright in because they have been no more transatlantic in ‘‘Political Institutions and the Frontier,’’ Sources of their orientation than their American brethren. American Culture, ed. D. R. Fox (New York, 1934), But there is also a superficial logical reason for pp. 15–39. this: if modern history begins with liberalism, Chapter 3 132

why stress feudalism, which after all is ‘‘medieval does not see itself at all, while a uniform feu- history’’? And yet, quite apart from the lessons dalism sees itself considerably by virtue of the of the American experience, is not the fallacy of antagonisms it engenders, one might even argue this reasoning patent? Merely to state that the for a certain similarity between America and feudal structure was the target of modern forces Europe on this very score. Here Locke has been is to a‰rm the fact, by any sophisticated logic, so basic that we have not recognized his signifi- that it determined the shape these forces took. cance, there Filmer. And the two issues dovetail: One hardly needs to read Mannheim to realize to discover the one yields the perspective for that the status quo determines the categories of discovering the other. . . . revolution, or Hegel to realize that the thesis is not unrelated to the sort of antithesis that arises. If the feudal factor is the mother factor of modern life, how can its influence be anything less than permanent and inescapable? ...... [T]he American experience suggests that a study of modern European history from the feu- dal angle might yield interesting results. One of these, curiously enough, is a point of departure, not merely for the comparative study of America and Europe, but for the comparative study of European nations themselves. With the crystalli- zation of national states, the European nations have been studied almost as independently as America itself, the idea being apparently that since the ‘‘medieval unity’’ had broken down there was no use preserving it in historical study. The result is that many of the most primitive correlations among the European countries, in economics and politics, have not been made. But if the ‘‘medieval unity’’ is found actually to be a decisive factor in the epoch that followed it, the basis for these correlations automatically appears. Now this is not to suggest that national di¤erences in Western Europe are not crucial. As in the case of America we must be careful to avoid useless debate over a situation and its context. To stress feudalism in Europe is no more to deny that wide variations take place within it than to stress liberalism in America is to deny that wide variations take place within that. One can still emphasize the di¤erences between Burke and Haller, or Jaure`s and Bernstein, just as one can still emphasize the di¤erences be- tween Bryan and William Howard Taft. Indeed, were it not for the fact that a uniform liberalism Pluralism and Social Choice

Nicholas R. Miller

This article considers together two theoretical is reasonably evident (but I think sometimes traditions in political analysis—pluralist theory missed)—but they are very close to being logi- and social choice theory, argues that there is cally incompatible. The existence of one kind of an implicit normative contradiction between the stability typically entails the nonexistence of the two, and attempts to resolve that contradiction. other kind. Thus, also, the (explicit or implicit) I believe that the argument is of some signifi- normative criteria in the two theories are incom- cance for political theory generally and for a patible. Finally, this incompatibility suggests theoretical understanding of the bases of politi- that the social choice ideal of collective ratio- cal stability in particular. The argument may be nality may not be one that we should endorse. summarized as follows. Indeed, the generic instability of the pluralist Pluralist political theory identifies certain pat- political process, and its consequent collective terns of political preferences (reflecting certain irrationality, may in fact contribute to the rela- social and economic structures) as promoting the tive stability of pluralist political systems. . . . ‘‘stability’’ of democratic political systems; con- versely, it identifies other patterns as threatening to such stability. Social choice theory likewise Pluralist Theory and Political Stability identifies certain patterns of political preferences as leading to ‘‘stability’’ in social choice under Pluralism as Dispersed Preferences majority rule and related collective choice rules; The variant of pluralist theory that is of concern conversely, it identifies other patterns as lead- to us here relates the pattern of group a‰liations ing to unstable social choice. In the context of and conflict in society with patterns of political each theory, stability is characterized—at least preferences and in turn relates these preference implicitly—as desirable. Thus on the face of patterns to the stability of the political system, things, the two theoretical traditions appear to i.e., whether there is widespread acceptance of run in parallel, and in a sense they do—but in existing constitutional arrangements or whether opposite directions, because the preference pat- the political system is threatened by such fac- terns identified by pluralist theory as promoting tors as civil war, revolution, separatism, wide- desired stability are essentially those identified spread discontent, organized violence, and deep by social choice theory as entailing instability. alienation. Conversely, the preference patterns identified The fundamental postulates of this variant of by social choice theory as leading to stable pluralism theory are that (1) all societies are choice are essentially those identified by pluralist divided along one or more lines of fundamental theory as destabilizing for the system. Thus, not conflict or cleavage that partition its members only are the notions of stability associated with into di¤erent sets, and (2) the preferences of the two theories logically distinct—a point that members of society, with respect to alternative public policies, are largely determined by the set Excerpted from: Nicholas R. Miller, ‘‘Pluralism and to which those members belong—individuals in Social Choice.’’ American Political Science Review 77, the same set having (more or less) the same po- no. 3 (1983): 734–747. 6 American Political Science litical preferences and individuals in di¤erent sets Association, 1983. Reprinted with the permission of the American Political Science Association and Cam- having (in one respect or other) conflicting pref- bridge University Press. erences. We can refer to these sets, therefore, as preference clusters. Chapter 3 134

All societies are divided to some degree. But tributed much more equally. No majority-sized some societies, especially larger and more com- preference cluster can exist. . . . plex ones, are divided by a pluralism of cleavages that are often related to one another in a cross- Pluralism Encourages Political Strategems cutting rather than reinforcing pattern. The That the prevalence of such political maneuvers superposition of this multiplicity of crosscutting as logrolling, vote trading, coalition building and partitions is a fine partition of society into a splitting, agenda manipulation, strategic voting, large number of relatively small preference clus- patronage, and pork barrel constitutes an im- ters. Two random individuals, therefore, most portant feature of political life, and especially so likely belong to di¤erent preference clusters and, in pluralist systems, is often noted. Although the if so, have conflicting preferences with respect to prevalence of such political strategems is not one or more issues but almost certainly agree on usually associated with political stability in the many issues as well. (For a far more extended academic literature,3 I believe that such a con- and precise discussion along these lines, see Rae nection can be made. But before doing this, we & Taylor, 1970.) . . . must turn our attention to the second theoretical . . . There are, I think, at least four di¤erent tradition with which this article is concerned. arguments—logically distinct but by no means mutually exclusive—supporting the proposition that pluralistic preferences lead to political sta- Social Choice Theory and Collective Rationality bility. Three of these arguments are standard in academic political science literature and are The ‘‘Problem’’ of Cyclical Majorities summarized below. The fourth is merely noted below and is then developed further in the last It is now fairly well known to political scientists part of this essay. —although it was not a few decades ago—that, even if every individual in a group has a consis- Pluralism Causes Moderate Attitudes tent preference ordering over a set of alternatives The first argument is that, in a pluralist society, (e.g., candidates, policies, platforms), majority individuals tend to have more moderate or less preference may be inconsistent or intransitive— intense preferences than in a nonpluralist society. that is, alternative X may be preferred by a ma- This moderation results from the cross-pressure jority to alternative Y, Y may be preferred by a mechanism operating at the level of individual majority to Z, and yet Z may be preferred by a attitudes and interactions. . . . majority to X. This ‘‘paradox of voting’’ was evidently first discovered some 200 years ago by Pluralism Causes Moderate Behavior Even if a pluralist society is not characterized 3. The function of such strategems in promoting polit- by moderate preferences, its structure generates ical stability seems to be more clearly implied in the writings of some political figures who draw on their incentives for moderate political behavior on practical experience (e.g., Savile, First Marquess of the part of both individuals and organized Halifax, 1700; Burke, 1790; Smith, 1940), or in biog- groups. . . . raphies of such figures (e.g., Oliver, 1930, on Sir Rob- ert Walpole; Foxcroft, 1946, on the First Marquis of Pluralism Distributes Political Satisfaction Halifax) and some broader histories (e.g., Plumb, . . . In a pluralist society, crosscut by many 1967), and in some political novels (e.g., Trollope, cleavages and partitioned into a multiplicity of 1869). I am indebted to Lewis Dexter for impressing this point on me and for providing references. preference clusters, political satisfaction is dis- Democracy, Culture, and Society 135

the French philosopher, the Marquis de Con- necessarily say that only a subset of all logically dorcet, and it was then alternately forgotten and possible profiles are admissible. At least roughly, rediscovered until about thirty-five years ago. . . . such conditions can be divided into three cate- By about 1960, the paradox of cyclical major- gories. With respect to social choice from finite ity preference had been clearly embedded into sets of discrete alternatives, most attention has the consciousness of a small group of political focused on conditions in the first (especially) scientists and economists concerned with social and second categories, which in di¤erent ways choice. And the paradox was—I think it is fair point to the advantage of social homogeneity in to say—almost universally regarded as a ‘‘prob- avoiding cycles. lem’’ by those who were aware of it. . . . 1. Exclusion conditions simply prohibit certain The Consequences of Cyclical Majorities combinations of orderings from ever occurring. The best known of these is Black’s (1958) single- Cyclical majority preference has these more spe- peakedness condition. This is also the most cific and concrete consequences in varying polit- plausible such condition, although its reverse, ical contexts. single-troughedness or single-cavedness (Vick- rey, 1960, p. 514), also precludes majority cycles 1. The ‘‘core’’ of the political process is empty. and may be plausible in certain contexts. Both This is the most fundamental consequence: for conditions require that voters commonly per- every possible political outcome, there is some ceive alternatives to be arrayed over a single di- coalition of actors who jointly prefer some other mension and evaluate them accordingly. . . . outcome and have the power to get it. . . . 2. Popularity conditions point out that prefer- 2. Electoral competition between two power- ence profiles exhibiting su‰cient consensus, even oriented political parties or candidates cannot if exclusion conditions are violated, map into lead to equilibrium. . . . No matter what plat- transitive social preference under majority rule. form or set of policies one party selects, it can Most obviously, perfect consensus (all orderings always be defeated, and the outcome of electoral are identical) precludes majority cycles (but such competition—even if modelled under the as- consensus satisfies all exclusion conditions as sumption of complete information—is intrinsi- well). Hardly less obviously, so does majority cally indeterminate and unpredictable, and the consensus (a majority of orderings are identical). resulting electoral victories and attendant out- 3. Balance conditions do not exclude any comes are thus arbitrary. combination of orderings or require any level 3. Noncooperative voting decisions depend on of consensus but require a certain symmetry of what particular (majoritarian) voting procedure disagreement, as it were, so that opposing pref- is used, on whether voting is sincere or sophisti- erences ‘‘balance out.’’ For example, if in a cated, and (if the procedure is sequential) on the given profile all individual orderings but one order in which alternatives are voted on.... can be paired (assume n is odd) so that the orderings in each pair are the opposite of each 4. Social choices from varying agendas vary in other, then majority preference is transitive, an erratic and unreasonable fashion.... since the majority vote between each pair of al- ternatives is everywhere a tie broken by the one Escape from Paradox remaining unpaired ordering, and majority pref- erence is identical to that ordering (and hence All conditions on preference profiles that logi- transitive). . . . cally preclude the paradox of majority cycles Chapter 3 136

peakedness into substantive political terms of a Pluralist Preferences versus Collective systemwide nature is politics fought out on a Rationality single left-right (or other) ideological dimension. This also is a circumstance condemned in plu- We now consider the two theoretical traditions ralist theory, although for a population to be —pluralism and social choice—together. The arrayed over a one-dimensional ideological con- fundamental point that quickly becomes evident tinuum (especially in a unimodal fashion) would is that pluralistic preference profiles and prefer- be viewed as preferable to polarization of the ence profiles entailing collective rationality under population into two totally opposed ideological majority rule are virtually disjoint sets. camps. Thus, in e¤ect, pluralist theory argues that As we have seen, reinforcing divisions of a cyclical majority preference is desirable because population into majority and minority groups such preference profiles are associated with the (on di¤erent issues) preclude the possibility of stability of political systems. Of course, writers in cyclical majority preference, regardless of the the pluralist tradition have not directly argued distribution of intensity. On the other hand, that majority cycling is desirable. Indeed, it is crosscutting divisions of the population into ma- almost certain that only a very few of them have jority and minority groups (on di¤erent issues) been aware of the phenomenon. . . . But they permit cyclical majorities, which will actually have argued that certain preference patterns occur if intensity is distributed appropriately. promote, and others threaten, political stability, Consider, for example, the diagrams shown in and it turns out that the former typically entail, figure 3.1, each of which shows a population whereas the latter preclude, majority cycling. divided 60%–40% on two issues, one in a more That is, the sorts of conditions identified in formal or less reinforcing fashion and one in a more or social choice theory as su‰cient to avoid majority less crosscutting fashion (cf. the diagrams in cycles are just those sorts of patterns viewed un- Schattschneider, 1960, pp. 62¤ ). The table below favorably in the pluralist literature. Conversely, each diagram shows the partition of the popula- pluralistic preference patterns are those that most tion into clusters in terms of first preferences for typically result in cyclical majorities. both issues (from which last preferences can be Let us review the situation. The most obvious inferred).4 The diagrams, and a fortiori the con- condition that assures transitivity of majority cept of reinforcing versus cross-cutting cleavages, rule is the popularity condition of majority con- do not allow us to infer the second (and third) sensus, i.e., one preference cluster includes more preferences, which are determined by ‘‘intensity’’ than half the population. Such a condition would (i.e., for each individual, which issue he would be fulfilled in a dualist society, and it would re- rather get his way on, given that he can get his sult in what Madison (1787) and others would way on only one). But, whatever the unspecified call majority faction or even majority tyranny preferences, majority preference is transitive in and which typically (although not as a logical the reinforcing case, there being a majority fac- necessity) entails a large set of universal losers tion. On the other hand, in the crosscutting case, likely to be deeply alienated from the political majority preference may be cyclical—and indeed system. It is, in any case, a nonpluralistic pat- is, if most voters (precisely, 70% of them) in the tern, resulting from a single cleavage or from two middle clusters care more about the issue in multiple reinforcing cleavages. terms of which they are in the minority than Next, the exclusion condition of single-peaked about the issue in terms of which they are in the preferences assures transitive majority prefer- ence. But the most plausible translation of single- 4. This again assumes ‘‘separability.’’ . . . Democracy, Culture, and Society 137

Figure 3.1 majority. However, if there is (contrary to the More generally, given multiple issues and subsidiary theme in pluralist theory identified separable preferences, cyclical majorities exist if earlier) a consensus of intensities—put other- and only if logrolling situations exist (Kadane, wise, if the majorities on the respective issues are 1972; Miller, 1975, 1977b; Oppenheimer, 1972; ‘‘passionate’’ (cf. Downs, 1957, pp. 64¤ )—no coalition of minorities can form, and majority distributive component, losers, being fewer in number, transitivity is assured.5 lose more per capita than winners win. (If, as public choice theorists often suggest, redistributive transfers 5. There is some reason to believe that majorities are are typically ine‰cient, the argument is reinforced.) usually not ‘‘passionate’’ and coalitions of minorities This argument can only be suggestive, for the relevant are often e¤ective. Many political issues are essentially comparison is not between majority versus minority (re)distributive, and others have a significant distribu- intensity on a given issue, but between issues for given tive component. Insofar as dichotomous issues have a voters. Chapter 3 138

Schwartz, 1977). Thus, Dahl’s (1956) well- Nothing in the previous section, of course, known assertion that ‘‘specific policies tend to be bears on what choice we should make between products of ‘minorities rule’’’ (p. 128), justifying these evidently conflicting values. On the whole, the conclusion that ‘‘majority tyranny is mostly a it seems clear that we should choose political myth, . . . for if the majority cannot rule, surely it stability, although we must recognize that col- cannot be tyrannical’’ (p. 133), is an assertion lective rationality is not a merely technical con- that cyclical majorities are prevalent. dition, but one that has important implications, Although a single ideological dimension, im- both normative (i.e., for the terms in which we plying single-peaked preferences, precludes cy- can justify democracy; cf. Nelson, 1980, espe- clical majorities, the existence of two or more cially chap. 4; Riker, 1978, 1982) and empirical ideological dimensions almost guarantees. . . . (discussed above). This section partially justifies Next, it was demonstrated long ago that such a choice by arguing further that cyclical purely allocative or distributive issues (such as majority preference is not merely an otherwise patronage, spoils division, and pork barrel) of undesirable phenomenon that happens to come the sort often associated with pluralist politics along with pluralistic preference patterns and and political stability entail massive majority that we must accept as the unavoidable cost of cycles (Ward, 1961; cf. Miller, 1982b; Schofield, achieving the great benefit of political stability, 1982). . . . but that the ‘‘generic instability’’ (cf. Schofield, Finally, we may note that pluralism implies a 1978a) of the pluralist political process is itself an large number of distinct preference clusters (i.e., important contributing factor to the stability of entities with distinct preference orderings), as pluralist political systems.6 well as a complex political environment (i.e., Politics is important—it is played for high many alternatives for political choice); and, stakes. Politics concerns how the coercive power according to the probabilistic literature on social of government is to be used in the ‘‘authoritative choice, both factors—a larger number of indi- allocation of values for a society’’ (Easton, 1953, viduals and a larger number of alternatives— p. 129). And the values at stake are not merely make cyclical majorities more likely. . . . material. For various reasons, political conflicts are inevitably overlaid with powerful symbols, emotions, and loyalties, making the stakes even Paradox Welcomed: Autonomous Politics and a higher than they would otherwise be. Critique of Collective Rationality Political conflict inevitably produces losers as well as winners. A fundamentally important The conclusion of the previous section was question (and the question of political stability) that pluralistic preference patterns entail cycli- is how to induce losers to continue to play the cal majority preference, and conversely, that political game, to continue to work within the those conditions that assure or make more system rather than to try to overthrow it. . . . likely majority transitivity virtually always entail Elections likewise arouse passions and like- nonpluralistic preferences. Thus, if pluralist wise inevitably produce both winners and losers. theory is correct that pluralistic preference pat- And the losers (both politicians and their fol- terns entail—and nonpluralistic preferences lowers) can likewise console themselves with the threaten—political stability, there is a clear con- thought: ‘‘Wait till the next election.’’ But once flict between the value of collective rationality again this prospect is comforting to the losers (transitivity of social preference and stable social choice) and the value of political stability 6. My reading of Riker (1982, especially chap. 8) was (widespread acceptance of existing constitutional very important in developing the thoughts expressed arrangements). below. Democracy, Culture, and Society 139

only insofar as there is some reasonable prospect sues. Given a majoritarian constitution, if pref- that the next election may produce a di¤erent erences are nonpluralistically distributed, the outcome with di¤erent winners and losers.10 same people will tend to win and others lose Commonly in pluralist democracies, there is across successive issues. If preferences are plu- indeed fairly regular alternation of winners and ralistically distributed, then—whether or not this losers in successive elections. It is very impor- distribution entails cyclical majority preference— tant to try to understand what brings about this di¤erent people will win and lose on di¤erent alternation. issues. Thus, as argued earlier, political disa¤ec- The most obvious answer is that there are tion plausibly is reduced. substantial shifts in the distribution of political But now we can make this further argument. preferences over time. Although the assertion If preferences are pluralistically distributed, involves great methodological and conceptual then—as argued in the previous section— complexities, I am inclined to argue that empiri- majority preference is typically cyclical and, if cal research on public opinion generally supports this distribution does entail cyclical majority the conclusion that the distribution of political preference, the present losers on a particular is- preferences—as that term is used in social choice sue can yet hope to become winners on the same theory, i.e., complete preference orderings or issue—perhaps by entering into some new alli- utility functions over all alternatives—changes ance, by trading away their votes on some other only slowly over time (mostly as a result of gen- issue, or generally by engaging in the kinds of erational replacement) and does not account for political strategems identified at the end of the alternation in electoral victories. second section as associated with pluralist poli- Suppose, in any case, that the distribution of tics, and which are e‰cacious only given cyclical political preferences is essentially constant from majorities, i.e., in the absence of collective ratio- election to election. Then, if collective rationality nality. Precisely because social choice is not holds and preference profiles map into stable so- stable, i.e., not uniquely determined by the dis- cial choice, all elections would have the same tribution of preferences, there is some range outcome,11 and the thought ‘‘wait till the next for autonomous politics to hold sway, and plu- election’’ would o¤er no solace to the losers. ralist politics o¤ers almost everybody hope of This argument can be extended and related victory. . . . more closely to our earlier discussion. Let us Thus, a pluralist political system does not think of politics as a series of dichotomous is- authoritatively allocate values in a stable fash- ion. Rather, it sets political competitors—who 10. An even more fundamental requirement, of course, might otherwise be bashing heads instead of is that there is a reasonable prospect of having a next (repeatedly) counting them (and seemingly get- election. And a corollary is that results of a one-shot ting di¤erent counts each time)—running election to determine the political future of a nation around ‘‘one of Escher’s stairways leading al- apparently for all time, or of a referendum to decide ways up yet always coming back to its own some essentially irreversible question, are less likely to foundation’’ (to use Rae’s metaphor; 1980, be accepted by the losers. p. 454). Not only does each competitor ‘‘win 11. At least the winning platform would remain con- some and lose some,’’ but most wins and losses stant. In the established formal theory of electoral are themselves reversible. Thus the competitors competition (without party loyalty), the two parties, can never be confident of their victories, nor having fully ‘‘converged,’’ would alternate victories in a random manner. But if there were any degree of need they resign themselves to their defeats. Of party loyalty in the electorate, unequally distributed, course, since considerable resources are devoted the same party would always win. to this competitive treadmill, pluralist politics is Chapter 3 140

somewhat ine‰cient in economic terms. But the developed. First, greater technical precision is state of a¤airs associated with severe political clearly needed at several points. Second and instability is far more profoundly ine‰cient. more important, the argument at present is very abstract and needs more concrete specification in terms of recognizable political phenomena. For Conclusion example, a distinction should be made between micro-level politics (e.g., a legislative assembly The argument of this essay has been that the considering a particular bill or set of proposals) pluralist political process leads to unstable polit- and macro-level politics (e.g., the broad structure ical choice, and that such instability of choice of electoral politics over time). There are a vari- in fact fosters the stability of pluralist political ety of reasons why potential instabilities are systems. likely to be submerged at the micro-level (cf. The question remains of whether political Shepsle, 1979; Shepsle & Weingast, 1981; Tul- outcomes in a pluralist democracy are ‘‘arbi- lock, 1981). My sense is that the present argu- trary’’ and unrelated to public opinion. If so, ment pertains primarily at the macro-level and this might be a high price to pay for political could profitably be linked with the established stability. literature on critical realignment and electoral In this connection, it is significant that a vari- dynamics (e.g., Burnham, 1970; Key, 1955; cf. ety of recent results in positive political theory Riker, 1982, chap. 9). have suggested plausible ways in which the outcomes of a competitive political process are likely to be restricted or bounded in a ‘‘reason- References able’’ fashion even in the face of massive or all- inclusive majority cycles. These notions include Black, D. The theory of committees and elections. the ‘‘minmax set’’ (Kramer, 1977), the ‘‘compet- Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1958. itive solution’’ (McKelvey et al., 1978), the ‘‘ad- Burke, E. Reflections on the revolution in France. New missible set’’ (McKelvey & Ordeshook, 1976) York: Library of Liberal Arts, 1955. (Originally pub- and the related ‘‘uncovered set’’ (Miller, 1980), lished, 1790.) as well as various probabilistic notions (e.g., Burnham, W. D. Critical elections and the mainsprings Ferejohn, McKelvey & Packel, 1981). All these of American politics. New York: W. W. Norton, 1970. notions have the common characteristic of set- Dahl, R. A. A preface to democratic theory. Chicago: ting reasonable bounds on social choice, yet University of Chicago Press, 1956. preserving some more or less large range of in- Downs, A. An economic theory of democracy. New determinacy within which autonomous politics York: Harper & Row, 1957. can hold sway. It is also worth noting that ex- Easton, D. The political system. New York: Alfred A. perimental studies (e.g., Fiorina & Plott, 1978; Knopf, 1953. McKelvey et al., 1978) do not show outcomes Ferejohn, J. A., McKelvey, R. D., & Packel, E. W. randomly scattered about the entire alternative Limiting distributions for continuous state Markov space. Finally, of course, most of us would voting models. Social Science Working Paper No. 394, view political outcomes in the real world of California Institute of Technology, July, 1981. pluralism as considerably unpredictable but Fiorina, M. P., & Plott, C. R. Committee decisions clearly confined within certain bounds of ‘‘polit- under majority rule: An experimental study. American Political Science Review, 1978, 72, 575–598. ical feasibility.’’ In conclusion, I should emphasize that the Foxcroft, H. C. A character of the trimmer: Being a short life of the first Marquis of Halifax. Cambridge: argument presented here needs to be further Cambridge University Press, 1946. Democracy, Culture, and Society 141

Kadane, J. B. On division of the question. Public Rae, D., & Taylor, M. The analysis of political cleav- Choice, 1972, 13, 47–54. ages. New Haven, Conn.: Yale University Press, 1970. Kent, F. R. The great game of politics. Garden City, Riker, W. H. A confrontation between the theory of N.Y.: Doubleday, 1923. social choice and the theory of democracy. Paper pre- Key, V. O., Jr. A theory of critical elections. Journal of sented at the Annual Meeting of the American Political Politics, 1955, 17, 3–18. Science Association, New York, September, 1978. Kramer, G. A. A dynamical model of political equi- Riker, W. H. Liberalism against populism: A confron- librium. Journal of Economic Theory, 1977, 16, 310– tation between the theory of democracy and the theory 334. of social choice. San Francisco: Freeman, 1982. Madison, J. Federalist Paper No. 10, 1787. Schattschneider, E. E. The semisovereign people. New McKelvey, R. D., & Ordeshook, P. C. Symmetric spa- York: Holt, Rinehart and Winston, 1960. tial games without majority rule equilibria. American Schofield, N. Generic instability of voting games. Political Science Review, 1976, 70, 1172–1184. Paper presented at the Annual Meeting of the Public McKelvey, R. D., Ordeshook, P. C., & Winer, M. The Choice Society, New Orleans, March, 1978a. competitive solution for n-person games without Schofield, N. Instability and development in the politi- transferable utility, with an application to committee cal economy. In P. C. Ordeshook & K. A. Shepsle games. American Political Science Review, 1978, 72, (Eds.), Political equilibrium. Boston: Kluwer-Nijho¤, 599–615. 1982. Miller, N. R. Logrolling and the Arrow paradox: A Schwartz, T. Collective choice, separation of issues and note. Public Choice, 1975, 21, 107–110. vote trading. American Political Science Review, 1977, 71 Miller, N. R. Logrolling, vote trading, and the paradox , 999–1010. of voting: A game-theoretical overview. Public Choice, Shepsle, K. A. Institutional arrangements and equilib- 1977b, 30, 51–75. rium in multidimensional voting models. American Journal of Political Science 23 Miller, N. R. A new solution set for tournaments and , 1979, , 27–59. majority voting: Further graph-theoretical approaches Shepsle, K. A., & Weingast, B. R. Structure-induced to the theory of voting. American Journal of Political equilibrium and legislative choice. Public Choice, 1981, Science, 1980, 24, 68–96. 37, 503–519. Miller, N. R. The complete structure of majority rule Smith, T. V. The legislative way of life. Chicago: Uni- on distributive politics. Paper presented at the Annual versity of Chicago Press (Midway Reprint), 1940. Meeting of the Public Choice Society, San Antonio, Trollope, A. Phineas Finn: The Irish member. Oxford: Texas, March, 1982. Oxford University Press, 1951. (Originally published, Nelson, W. N. On justifying democracy. London: 1869.) Routledge & Kegan Paul, 1980. Tullock, G. Why so much stability? Public Choice, Oliver, F. S. The endless adventure. London: Macmil- 1981, 37, 189–202. lan, 1930. Vickrey, W. Utility, strategy, and social decision rules. Oppenheimer, J. A. Relating coalitions of minorities Quarterly Journal of Economics, 1960, 74, 507–535. to the voters’ paradox or putting the fly in the demo- Ward, B. Majority rule and allocation. Journal of cratic pie. Paper presented at the Annual Meeting of Conflict Resolution, 1961, 5, 379–389. the Southwest Political Science Association, San An- tonio, Texas, March–April 1972. Plumb, J. H. The origins of political stability: England, 1675–1725. Boston: Houghton Mi¿in, 1967. Rae, D. An altimeter for Mr. Escher’s stairway: A comment on William H. Riker’s ‘‘Implications from the disequilibrium of majority rule for the study of institutions.’’ American Political Science Review, 1980, 74, 451–455. Consociational Democracy

Arend Lijphart

constructed, and possibly fragile, system of co- Fragmented but Stable Democracies operation. This may apply to a single election or to a number of successive elections...... The political stability of a system can appar- Consociational democracy violates the princi- ently not be predicted solely on the basis of the ple of majority rule, but it does not deviate very two variables of political culture and role struc- much from normative democratic theory. Most ture. According to the theory of crosscutting democratic constitutions prescribe majority rule cleavages, one would expect [countries] with for the normal transaction of business when subcultures divided from each other by mutually the stakes are not too high, but extraordinary reinforcing cleavages, to exhibit great immobil- majorities or several successive majorities for the ism and instability. But they do not. These devi- most important decisions, such as changes in the ant cases of fragmented but stable democracies constitution. In fragmented systems, many other will be called ‘‘consociational democracies.’’14 In decisions in addition to constituent ones are per- general, deviant case analysis can lead to the ceived as involving high stakes, and therefore discovery of additional relevant variables, and require more than simple majority rule. Simi- in this particular instance, a third variable can larly, majority rule does not su‰ce in times of account for the stability of the consociational grave crisis in even the most homogeneous and democracies: the behavior of the political elites. consensual of democracies. Great Britain and The leaders of the rival subcultures may engage Sweden, both highly homogeneous countries, in competitive behavior and thus further aggra- resorted to grand coalition cabinets during the vate mutual tensions and political instability, but Second World War. Julius Nyerere draws the they may also make deliberate e¤orts to counter- correct lesson from the experience of the Western act the immobilizing and unstabilizing e¤ects of democracies, in which, he observes, ‘‘it is an cultural fragmentation. As a result of such over- accepted practice in times of emergency for op- arching cooperation at the elite level, a country position parties to sink their di¤erences and join can, as Claude Ake states, ‘‘achieve a degree of together in forming a national government.’’20 political stability quite out of proportion to its And just as the formation of a national unity social homogeneity.’’15 ... government is the appropriate response to an The desire to avoid political competition may external emergency, so the formation of a grand be so strong that the cartel of elites may decide coalition cabinet or an alternative form of elite to extend the consociational principle to the cartel is the appropriate response to the internal electoral level in order to prevent the passions crisis of fragmentation into hostile subcultures. aroused by elections from upsetting the carefully

15. Claude Ake, A Theory of Political Integration Excerpted from: Arend Lijphart, ‘‘Consociational De- (Homewood 1967), 113. This possibility exists not only mocracy.’’ World Politics 21, no. 2 (1969): 207–225. in the fragmented democracies, but also in fragmented 6 Center of International Studies, Princeton Univer- predemocratic or nondemocratic systems, of course. sity. Reprinted by permission of The Johns Hopkins See also Arend Lijphart, The Politics of Accommoda- University Press. tion: Pluralism and Democracy in the Netherlands 14. Cf. Johannes Althusius’ concept of consociatio in (Berkeley 1968), 1–15, 197–211. his Politica Methodice Digesta, and the term ‘‘con- 20. Nyerere, ‘‘One-Party Rule,’’ in Paul E. Sigmund, sociational’’ used by David E. Apter, The Political Jr., ed., The Ideologies of the Developing Nations (New Kingdom in Uganda: A Study in Bureaucratic Nation- York 1963), 199. alism (Princeton 1961), 24–25. Democracy, Culture, and Society 143

Furthermore, the concept of consociational a fragmented political culture into a stable de- democracy is also in agreement with the empiri- mocracy. E¤orts at consociationalism are not cal ‘‘size principle,’’ formulated by William H. necessarily successful, of course: consociational Riker. This principle, based on game-theoretic designs failed in Cyprus and Nigeria, and Uru- assumptions, states: ‘‘In social situations similar guay abandoned its Swiss-style consociational to n-person, zero-sum games with side-payments system. Successful consociational democracy [private agreements about the division of the requires: (1) That the elites have the ability to payo¤ ], participants create coalitions just as accommodate the divergent interests and de- large as they believe will ensure winning and no mands of the subcultures. (2) This requires that larger.’’ The tendency will be toward a ‘‘mini- they have the ability to transcend cleavages and mum winning coalition,’’ which in a democracy to join in a common e¤ort with the elites of rival will be a coalition with bare majority support— subcultures. (3) This in turn depends on their but only under the conditions specified in the size commitment to the maintenance of the system principle. The most important condition is the and to the improvement of its cohesion and sta- zero-sum assumption: ‘‘only the direct conflicts bility. (4) Finally, all of the above requirements among participants are included and common are based on the assumption that the elites advantages are ignored.’’21 Common advantages understand the perils of political fragmentation. will be completely ignored only in two diametri- These four requirements are logically implied by cally opposite kinds of situations: (1) when the the concept of consociational democracy as de- participants in the ‘‘game’’ do not perceive any fined in this paper. Under what conditions are common advantages, and when, consequently, they likely to be fulfilled? An examination of they are likely to engage in unlimited warfare; the successful consociational democracies in the and (2) when they are in such firm agreement on Low Countries, Switzerland, Austria, and Leba- their common advantages that they can take non suggests a number of conditions favorable them for granted. In the latter case, politics lit- to the establishment and the persistence of this erally becomes a game. In other words, the zero- type of democracy. These have to do with sum condition and the size principle apply only inter-subcultural relations at the elite level, inter- to societies with completely homogeneous politi- subcultural relations at the mass level, and elite- cal cultures and to societies with completely mass relations within each of the subcultures. fragmented cultures. To the extent that political cultures deviate from these two extreme con- Relations among the Elites of the Subcultures ditions, pressures will exist to fashion coalitions and other forms of cooperation that are more It is easier to assess the probability of continued inclusive than the bare ‘‘minimum winning co- success of an already established consociational alition’’ and that may be all-inclusive grand democracy than to predict the chance of suc- coalitions. . . . cess that a fragmented system would have if it were to attempt consociationalism. In an existing consociational democracy, an investigation of Factors Conducive to Consociational Democracy the institutional arrangements and the opera- tional code of inter-elite accommodation can Consociational democracy means government throw light on the question of how thorough a by elite cartel designed to turn a democracy with commitment to cooperation they represent and how e¤ective they have been in solving the 21. William H. Riker, The Theory of Political Coali- problems caused by fragmentation. The length tions (New Haven 1962), 29, 32–33. of time a consociational democracy has been in Chapter 3 144

operation is also a factor of importance. As inter- ity at the polls. Robert Dahl argues that for this elite cooperation becomes habitual and does not reason it is doubtful that the consociational ar- represent a deliberate departure from competi- rangement in Colombia will last, because ‘‘the tive responses to political challenges, consocia- temptation to shift from coalition to competition tional norms become more firmly established. is bound to be very great.’’24 When political And, as Gerhard Lehmbruch states, these norms parties in a fragmented society are the organized may become an important part of ‘‘the political manifestations of political subcultures, a multi- socialization of elites and thus acquire a strong party system is more conducive to consociational degree of persistence through time.’’23 democracy and therefore to stability than a two- There are three factors that appear to be party system. This proposition is at odds with strongly conducive to the establishment or the generally high esteem accorded to two-party maintenance of cooperation among elites in a systems. In an already homogeneous system, fragmented system. The most striking of these two-party systems may be more e¤ective, but a is the existence of external threats to the coun- moderate multiparty system, in which no party is try. In all of the consociational democracies, close to a majority, appears preferable in a con- the cartel of elites was either initiated or greatly sociational democracy. . . . strengthened during periods of international Consociational democracy presupposes not crisis, especially the First and Second World only a willingness on the part of elites to coop- Wars. . . . In all cases, the external threats im- erate but also a capability to solve the political pressed on the elites the need for internal unity problems of their countries. Fragmented soci- and cooperation. External threats can also eties have a tendency to immobilism, which strengthen the ties among the subcultures at the consociational politics is designed to avoid. mass level and the ties between leaders and fol- Nevertheless, decision-making that entails ac- lowers within the subcultures. commodation among all subcultures is a di‰- A second factor favorable to consociational cult process, and consociational democracies are democracy, in the sense that it helps the elites to always threatened by a degree of immobilism. recognize the necessity of cooperation, is a mul- Consequently, a third favorable factor to inter- tiple balance of power among the subcultures in- elite cooperation is a relatively low total load stead of either a dual balance of power or a clear on the decision-making apparatus. The stability of hegemony by one subculture. When one group is Lebanon is partly due to its productive economy in the majority, its leaders may attempt to dom- and the social equilibrium it has maintained so inate rather than cooperate with the rival mi- far, but it may not be able to continue its suc- nority. Similarly, in a society with two evenly cessful consociational politics when the burdens matched subcultures, the leaders of both may on the system increase. . . . hope to achieve their aims by domination rather than cooperation, if they expect to win a major- Inter-Subcultural Relations at the Mass Level

23. Lehmbruch, ‘‘A Non-Competitive Pattern of Con- The political cultures of the countries belonging flict Management in Liberal Democracies: The Case of to Almond’s Continental European type and to Switzerland, Austria and Lebanon’’ (paper presented the consociational type are all fragmented, but at the Seventh World Congress of the International the consociational countries have even clearer Political Science Association, Brussels, 1967), 6. See boundaries among their subcultures. Such dis- also Lehmbruch, Proporzdemokratie: Politisches Sys- tem und politische Kultur in der Schweiz und in O¨ ster- 24. Dahl, Political Oppositions in Western Democ- reich (Tu¨ bingen 1967). racies (New Haven 1966), 337. Democracy, Culture, and Society 145

tinct lines of cleavage appear to be conducive to certain conditions. Secondly, the view that any consociational democracy and political stability. severe discontinuity in overlapping patterns of The explanation is that subcultures with widely membership and allegiance is a danger to politi- divergent outlooks and interests may coexist cal stability needs to be restated in more refined without necessarily being in conflict; conflict form. A distinction has to be made between es- arises only when they are in contact with each sentially homogeneous political cultures, where other. As states: ‘‘Ideologies increased contacts are likely to lead to an in- accepted by di¤erent groups within a society crease in mutual understanding and further may be inconsistent without creating tension; but homogenization, and essentially heterogeneous if . . . the groups with inconsistent ideologies are cultures, where close contacts are likely to lead in close contact . . . the tension will be great.’’29 to strain and hostility. This is the distinction that also endorses the thesis that good Walker Connor makes when he argues that ‘‘in- social fences may make good political neighbors, creased contacts help to dissolve regional cul- when he suggests a kind of voluntary apartheid tural distinctions within a state such as the policy as the best solution for a divided society: United States. Yet, if one is dealing not with ‘‘Greater success may be attained through steps minor variations of the same culture, but with that conduce to the development of a deeper two quite distinct and self-di¤erentiating cul- sense of mutual awareness and responsiveness tures, are not increased contacts between the two among encapsulated cultural units.’’ This is ‘‘the apt to increase antagonisms?’’32 This proposition major hope of avoiding stress.’’30 And Sidney can be refined further by stating both the degree Verba follows the same line of reasoning when of homogeneity and the extent of mutual con- he argues that political and economic modern- tacts in terms of continua rather than dichoto- ization in Africa is bringing ‘‘di¤ering subcul- mies. In order to safeguard political stability, the tures into contact with each other and hence into volume and intensity of contacts must not exceed conflict.’’31 the commensurate degree of homogeneity. Karl This argument appears to be a direct refuta- W. Deutsch states that stability depends on a tion of the overlapping-memberships proposi- ‘‘balance between transaction and integration’’ tion, but by adding two amendments to this because ‘‘the number of opportunities for possi- proposition the discrepancy can be resolved. In ble violent conflict will increase with the volume the first place, the basic explanatory element in and range of mutual transactions.’’33 Hence, it the concept of consociational democracy is that may be desirable to keep transactions among political elites may take joint actions to counter antagonistic subcultures in a divided society— the e¤ects of cultural fragmentation. This means or, similarly, among di¤erent nationalities in a that the overlapping-memberships propositions multinational state—to a minimum. may become a self-denying hypothesis under Elite-Mass Relations within the Subcultures 29. Wright, ‘‘The Nature of Conflict,’’ Western Politi- cal Quarterly, iv (June 1951), 196. Distinct lines of cleavage among the subcultures 30. Easton, A Systems Analysis of Political Life (New are also conducive to consociational democracy York 1965), 250–51 (italics added). See also G. H. because they are likely to be concomitant with a Scholten, ‘‘Het vergelijken van federaties met behulp van systeem-analyse,’’ Acta Politica, II (1966–67), 32. Connor, ‘‘Self-Determination: The New Phase,’’ 51–68. World Politics, xx (October 1967), 49–50. 31. Verba, ‘‘Some Dilemmas in Comparative Re- 33. Deutsch, Political Community at the International xx search,’’ World Politics, (October 1967), 126 (italics Level (Garden City 1954), 39. added). Chapter 3 146

high degree of internal political cohesion of the subcultures. This is vital to the success of con- sociational democracy. The elites have to coop- erate and compromise with each other without losing the allegiance and support of their own rank and file. When the subcultures are cohesive political blocs, such support is more likely to be forthcoming. As Hans Daalder states, what is important is not only ‘‘the extent to which party leaders are more tolerant than their followers’’ but also the extent to which they ‘‘are yet able to carry them along.’’34 A second way in which distinct cleavages have a favorable e¤ect on elite-mass relations in a consociational democracy is that they make it more likely that the parties and interest groups will be the organized representatives of the po- litical subcultures. If this is the case, the politi- cal parties may not be the best aggregators, but there is at least an adequate articulation of the interests of the subcultures. Aggregation of the clearly articulated interests can then be per- formed by the cartel of elites. . . . A final factor which favors consociational de- mocracy is widespread approval of the principle of government by elite cartel. This is a very obvious factor, but it is of considerable importance and deserves to be mentioned briefly. For example, Switzerland has a long and strong tradition of grand coalition executives, and this has immea- surably strengthened Swiss consociational de- mocracy. On the other hand, the grand coalition in Austria was under constant attack by critics who alleged that the absence of a British-style opposition made Austrian politics ‘‘undemo- cratic.’’ This attests to the strength of the British system as a normative model even in fragmented political systems, where the model is inappropri- ate and undermines the attempt to achieve polit- ical stability by consociational means. . . .

34. [Hans Daalder, ‘‘Parties, Elites, and Political Developments in Western Europe,’’ in Joseph La- Palombara and Myron Weiner, eds., Political Parties and Political Development (Princeton: Princeton Uni- versity Press, 1996)], 69. The Contest of Ideas

Donald Horowitz

If there is a subject called constitutional design, No treatment of the contest of ideas can avoid then there must be alternative constitutional an encounter with consociational democracy. designs. Assuredly there are, but even now most There is much to admire in the e¤orts of Arend constitutional drafters and reformers are, at best, Lijphart in behalf of managing inter-group con- only vaguely informed by anything resembling flict, most notably his realism about group divi- an articulate theory of their enterprise. Most act sions (they are not to be wished away) and his on the basis of inchoate and partially worked- optimism (they do not need to produce civil out ideas, such as the notion that assuring legis- war). Yet Lijphart . . . is right to identify me as a lative representation for minorities is the crucial dissenter from the consociational approach, al- step in inter-group accommodation: a notion though, as I shall point out, completely wrong to that has animated many judicial and legislative identify me as an opponent of either power- determinations under the Voting Rights Act in sharing or territorial devolution. I want to move the United States. Politicians have their own on to a brief statement of a more promising ideas, and these are not so easily dislodged, even approach and to a fuller treatment of the gap with the growth of constitutional design and between constitutional design and the constitu- various sub-fields, such as electoral-system de- tions that actually emerge from processes of sign, as matters for experts. Individual politi- constitutional innovation, but I need first to state cians can still make their influence felt, even in why I think consociational theory is not a fruit- very large countries.3 Before we even reach the ful path for constitutional designers. contest of explicitly stated theories, we need to To avoid restating objections to consocia- recognize the more significant, albeit often sub- tionalism that I have advanced in several pre- liminal, contest between explicit theories and vious publications (Horowitz 1985: 568–576; the more influential, implicit theories espoused 1991: 137–145, 167–171; 1997: 439–440; 2000: by practitioners. The inarticulate theories call 256–259), I shall resort to a list of the main out for study. As of now, we lack a theory of objections. their theories. We also lack a consensus emerging from 1. The consociational approach is motiva- the articulate theories, whether these relate to tionally inadequate. Lijphart (1977: 53, 165) electoral systems, presidential or parliamentary identifies statesmanship as the reason elites will structure, or the costs and benefits of centralized form a cartel across group lines to resolve inter- or devolved power. Lack of consensus is the first ethnic di¤erences. In his view, leaders are moti- obstacle. vated by a desire to avert the danger of mutual destruction. But why should majority-group leaders, with 60 percent support, and the ability Excerpted from: Donald Horowitz, ‘‘Constitutional to gain all of political power in a majoritarian Design: Proposals versus Processes.’’ In The Architec- ture of Democracy: Constitutional Design. Edited by democracy, be so self-abnegating as to give some Andrew Reynolds. Oxford: Oxford University Press, of it away to minority-group leaders? There may 2002. Reprinted by permission of Oxford University be instances of this sort of generosity, in the face Press. of the attractiveness of a less-than-maximal co- 3. I am thinking here of the singular part played by alition (see Riker 1962: 32–33), but the motive of Viktor Shaynis, a parliamentarian, in designing the avoiding ultimate mutual destruction is based on Russian electoral system. a time horizon longer than that employed by Chapter 3 148

most political leaders, who, in any case, are apt own group is extremely dubious. Studies of eth- to think that retaining control for themselves is nocentrism show educated elites in some coun- the best way to avoid disaster. On this point, tries to be less ethnocentric than their followers, Lijphart . . . now contends that the motive is not in others more, in some others neither less nor statesmanship but the desire to enter into a co- more, and in still others more with respect to alition. This, of course, does not account for the some groups and less or the same with respect to motives of leaders of majorities, who do not need other groups (see Horowitz 1997: 457 n. 31; coalitions, much less the all-inclusive or grand 1991: 140–141 nn. 44–50). It is very risky to coalitions that Lijphart (1977) specifies as a cen- count on statesmanship (see Reilly and Reynolds tral element of the consociational prescription.4 1999: 13). The failure to make the elementary distinction 3. When leaders compromise across ethnic between the di¤erent incentives of majorities lines in the face of severe divisions, there is usu- and minorities, to which I shall return, is cru- ally a high price to pay. Counter-elites arise who cial. Even states that start out multipolar, with make an issue of the compromise, referring to several ethnic groups, can become bipolar and it as a sell-out. Consociational theory assumes bifurcated—witness the growth of northern ver- the existence of ‘‘group leaders,’’ but, even when sus southern groups in many African states— groups begin with a single set of leaders, com- thus obviating the need for a coalition across promise across group lines is likely to show those group lines for the group that is slightly larger. leaders to be merely party leaders opposed by In general, bipolar states, with a majority and a leaders of other parties seeking the support of minority, are the more seriously conflicted. A the same group. The centrifugal competition for theory of conflict reduction that cannot cope group allegiance is an enormous constraint on with hard cases is of limited utility.5 compromise across group lines, and it renders 2. To the extent that the imputed motive is the grand coalition, under conditions of free still statesmanship rather than self-interest, the elections, a contradiction in terms. Not one of assumption that elites in divided societies are the four developing countries cited by Lijphart likely to be more tolerant of other ethnic groups (1977) as consociational—Lebanon, Malaysia, or less inclined to pursue advantage for their Surinam, and the Netherlands Antilles—had a grand coalition. Each had an inter-ethnic coali- 4. Lijphart sometimes includes and sometimes omits tion of some parties, opposed by other parties the grand-coalition requirement. The tendency to shift representing the same groups. Some of the four ground about the indispensable requisites of the theory also violated other core conditions of consocia- is one of the main reasons why consociationalism tional theory, such as proportionality in alloca- attracts such strong criticism (see, for example, Dixon tions, proportionality in executive participation, 1997; Halpern 1986). and cultural autonomy, but were claimed for the In the actual experience of constitutional innovators, theory nonetheless. For reasons I shall enumer- there are some examples of motivation to accept con- ate later, it is not amiss to refer to consociational sociational arrangements, but these are idiosyncratic and cannot be assumed to be widely distributed. Moti- elements or consociational practices, but con- vation always needs to be treated as an issue, not a sociational regimes in the developing world are, given. to be generous about it, few and far between.6 5. The claim that the bipolar (60–40) problem is rare (which Lijphart made in an earlier version of the paper 6. The tendency to shift the goal posts and to claim published in this volume) cannot be sustained. In many countries for the theory is palpable. Whenever a di- developing countries, bipolar alignments emerge as a vided society seems to be more or less democratic and result of the amalgamation of group identities. more or less lacking in the most severe forms of con- Democracy, Culture, and Society 149

Consociational theory exaggerates the latitude superiority and primacy. To accord equal rec- enjoyed by leaders in ethnically divided societies ognition is, finally, to concede the issue of the where free elections prevail. identity of who will get ahead, which otherwise would be regulated by limitations on languages 4. If the grand coalition, proportional re- and educational streams associated with com- source allocations and shares of executive power, petitors. In short, cultural autonomy, with its and the minority veto all encounter the moti- implication of equality, is the product of the vational problem mentioned earlier, cultural reduction of inter-ethnic conflict, not an ingredi- autonomy encounters a di¤erent problem. Pre- ent of a conflict-regulating prescription at the sumably, groups are to find satisfaction—and threshold. power—in the ability to manage their own af- fairs, and that will contribute to stable democ- 5. Lijphart fails to make a critical distinction racy (Lijphart 1977: 42 . . .). But those who work between pre-electoral and post-electoral coali- on the sources of conflict in ethnically-divided tions. The coalitions recommended by consocia- societies know there is more to it than that. Cul- tional theory are post-electoral coalitions, which tural matters, such as the designation of o‰cial no doubt entail compromise over the division of languages and o‰cial religions, and educational cabinet portfolios, but typically not compromise issues, such as languages of instruction, the con- over divisive inter-ethnic issues. A better analysis tent of curricula, and the o‰cial recognition of of Lebanon and Malaysia during their most degrees from various educational streams asso- accommodative periods would have put the em- ciated with various ethnic groups, are habitually phasis on the need of candidates, parties, and divisive issues in severely divided societies. These coalitions to attract votes across group lines, issues go straight to the heart of the conflict in rather than on post-electoral compromise. In three of its most important respects. To accord those cases and others, pre-electoral coalitions equal recognition to all cultures, religions, and across group lines required compromise on languages is to concede equal ownership of the ethnic issues. The combination of list-system state, contrary to what groups are very often proportional representation and political parties willing to concede (see Wimmer 1997). To ac- based on ethnic-group support does nothing cord equal recognition is also to concede another to foster compromise on ethnic issues. The core issue: the issue of group superiority, which zero-sum relation of party lists to each other is contested by reference to disputes over cultural translates into a zero-sum electoral competition between ethnic groups (see Horowitz 1991: flict, the reason must be that it is consociational. India, 167–176). the leading example of adversary democracy in Asia— and adversary democracy is the form of democracy to These criticisms suggest that when consocia- which consociationalism is juxtaposed as an alterna- tional arrangements are adopted a conflict is tive—is said to be consociational (Lijphart 1996). If probably already on the wane, and they also South Africa settles its di¤erences peacefully and elec- point the way towards alternative power-sharing torally, even if it lacks central elements of consocia- prescriptions. Certainly, to conflate consocia- tionalism, such as minority vetoes, then South Africa tion with all of power-sharing is completely must be consociational (Lijphart 1994b). unwarranted.7 ... To be perfectly clear at the outset, it is not possible to identify states that have adopted an incentives 7. Others have also pointed out that the appropriation approach—or any other coherent, conflict-reducing of the term ‘‘power-sharing’’ to refer exclusively to the approach—across the board either. The di‰culty of adopting constitutional designs in toto is precisely the consociational approach is confusing and conceptually point of this chapter. constricting (see, for example, Dixon 1997: 23, 32). Chapter 3 150

Several points follow from what has already A recent instance in which a vote-pooling elec- been said. If it is true that inter-group conflict toral system was used successfully to induce the involves a conflict for control and ownership of formation of a multi-ethnic coalition that won the state, for group superiority, and for group the election was the alternative vote (AV), success, all measured in relative terms, then adopted in the 1997 Fijian constitution. The compromise will be di‰cult to achieve. The di- electoral incentives in Fiji were weak, but they visive issues are not easy to compromise. No had a powerful e¤ect.8 A severely divided soci- single formula will assure the reduction of con- ety, Fiji elected a thoroughly multi-ethnic gov- flict. Progress will be, in most cases, incremental ernment, led by its first-ever Indian prime and, in many of these, reversible. When elec- minister (see Lal 1999). A year later, that gov- torates are alert to ethnic issues, as they typically ernment was overthrown, but not because the are, exhortations to leaders to compromise are incentives did not work. likely to be futile in the absence of rewards for Incentives, then, are the key to accommoda- compromise. Attention needs to be devoted, tion in di‰cult conditions, but the di‰cult con- therefore, to maximizing incentives for accom- ditions imply that the incentives approach will modative behaviour. For elected politicians, not be attractive to everyone or attractive at all those incentives are likely to be found in the times. Some times are more propitious than electoral system. Electoral systems that reward others, and the problem of motives does not dis- inter-ethnic accommodation can be identified appear by invoking the incentives approach. The and can be made to work more or less as in- incentives approach has had no more success tended (see Reilly 1997; see also International in securing full-blown acceptance than has any Crisis Group 1998; 1999). Where electoral re- other. . . . wards are present, they can provide the motiva- If political leaders are likely to be more willing tion ethnic leaders otherwise lack, they can to compromise under some electoral systems operate even in the presence of ethnocentrism, than under others, it follows that the electoral and they can o¤set electoral losses that leaders system is the central feature of the incentives anticipate as a result of making concessions approach to accommodation. Indeed, di¤ering to other groups. Where these rewards are pres- electoral logics can create di¤ering ethnic out- ent, they typically operate by means of vote- comes, reversing even favourable and unfav- pooling arrangements: the exchange of votes ourable starting points, an argument I have by ethnically-based parties that, because of the made in a comparison of Sri Lanka, which began electoral system, are marginally dependent for with a relatively easy ethnic problem, and Ma- victory on the votes of groups other than their laysia, which began with a very di‰cult one own and that, to secure those votes, must be- (Horowitz 1989a). have moderately on the issues in conflict. The Vote pooling is the major, but not the only, electoral rewards provided to a moderate mid- goal of the incentives approach. As the di‰culty dle compensate for the threat posed by opposi- of reconciling majorities to nonmajoritarian tion from those who can benefit from the institutions suggests, multipolar fluidity makes aversion of some group members to inter-ethnic inter-ethnic accommodation easier, since, by compromise. definition, it lacks a majority. The presence of Where vote pooling takes place, as it did in Lebanon and Malaysia, it promotes pre-electoral 8. By way of disclosure, I should report that I served coalitions, coalitions that need to compromise in as a consultant to the Fijian Constitution Review order to attract voters across group lines but that Commission that recommended the AV system (see may be opposed by ethnic parties on the flanks. FCRC 1996). Arend Lijphart was also consulted by the Commission. Democracy, Culture, and Society 151

many groups, no one of which can lay claim to devolution, coupled with a view at the centre majority status, in Tanzania and India is condu- that members of a group residing in the autono- cive to the mitigation of conflict. But group mous territory should henceforth look exclu- identities can change: as I mentioned earlier, a sively to the regional unit for their satisfaction, is large number of groups can consolidate into a far more likely to encourage departure from the smaller number, and the formal institutional state. Hesitation about devolution creates a self- structure can facilitate the change from multi- fulfilling prophecy. Because of hesitation, devo- polar fluidity to bipolar opposition. Where lution often comes too late. multipolarity prevails, another purpose of the The incentives approach is as di‰cult as, or electoral system is to preserve it against con- more di‰cult than, the consociational to adopt, solidating tendencies. Among others, the Leba- but, once adopted, it has an important advan- nese system did this for a long time. By tage. Consociation is certainly easier to under- acknowledging the plasticity of group identities, stand: one size fits all. But, even if adopted, which consociational theory completely neglects, consociation is far from self-executing, because the incentives approach can prevent the crystal- compromise is not likely to be rewarded by the lization of identities and the emergence of more electorate. The matter will not be left in elite severe conflict. hands. By contrast, politicians who benefit from It is not usually recognized, however, that ter- electoral incentives to moderation have continu- ritory can act in aid of or in lieu of electoral ing reason to try to reap those rewards, whatever mechanisms for such purposes. Territory can their beliefs and whatever their inclination to partition groups o¤ from each other and direct toleration and statesmanship. Politicians who are their political ambitions at one level of gov- merely exhorted to behave moderately may be ernment rather than another. Federalism, and left with mere exhortations. especially the proliferation of federal units, or regional autonomy can act in e¤ect as an elec- toral reform and can preserve multipolar fluidity. References There is very good evidence of this in the case of the proliferation of Nigerian federal units. Dixon, Paul (1997). ‘‘Consociationalism and the Federalism and regional autonomy have other Northern Ireland Peace Process: The Glass Half Full conflict-reducing functions as well. If the units or Half Empty?’’ Nationalism and Ethnic Politics, 3/3: 20–36. are homogeneous, they may foster intra-group competition, at the expense of an exclusive focus FCRC (Fiji Constitution Review Commission, ‘‘Reeves Commission’’) (1996). Towards A United Fu- on inter-group competition. If the units are het- ture: Report of the Fiji Constitution Review Commission erogeneous, they may provide an experience in (Parliamentary Paper 13). Suva: FCRC. political socialization for politicians of di¤erent Halpern, Sue (1986). ‘‘The Disorderly Universe of groups who become habituated to dealing with Consociational Democracy.’’ West European Politics, each other at lower levels before they need to do 9/2: 181–197. so at the centre. Horowitz, Donald L. (1985). Ethnic Groups in Conflict. Does devolution lead to secession, as central- Berkeley: University of California Press. level politicians so often fear? The intervening ——— (1989a). ‘‘Incentives and Behaviour in the Eth- variables here are timing and the ties woven with nic Politics of Sri Lanka and Malaysia.’’ Third World the centre. Early, generous devolution, coupled Quarterly, 11/4: 18–35. with carefully crafted connections of the regional ——— (1991). A Democratic South Africa? Constitu- population with the centre, is likely to avert tional Engineering in a Divided Society. Berkeley: Uni- rather than produce separatism. Late, grudging versity of California Press. Chapter 3 152

——— (1997a). ‘‘Self-Determination: Politics, Philos- ophy, and Law.’’ NOMOS, 39: 421–463. ——— (2000). ‘‘Constitutional Design: An Oxymo- ron?’’ NOMOS, 42: 253–284. International Crisis Group (1998). ‘‘Changing the Logic of Bosnian Politics: Discussion Paper on Elec- toral Reform.’’ Brussels (10 March). ——— (1999). ‘‘Breaking the Mould: Electoral Re- form in Bosnia and Herzegovina.’’ Brussels (4 March). Lal, Brij (1993). ‘‘Chiefs and Indians: Elections and Politics in Contemporary Fiji.’’ The Contemporary Pa- cific: A Journal of Island A¤airs, 5: 275–301. ——— (1999a). ‘‘Towards a United Future: Report of the Fiji Constitution Review Commission.’’ Journal of Pacific History, 32: 71–84. ——— (1999b). ‘‘The Voice of the People: Ethnic Identity and Nation Building in Fiji.’’ Journal of the Pacific Society, 22/3/4: 1–12. ——— (1999c). A Time to Change: The Fiji General Elections of 1999 (Discussion Paper 23). Canberra: Department of Political and Social Change, The Aus- tralian National University. Lijphart, Arend (1969). ‘‘Consociational Democracy.’’ World Politics, 21: 207–225. ——— (1977). Democracy in Plural Societies: A Com- parative Exploration. New Haven: Yale University Press. ——— (1994b). ‘‘Prospects for Power-Sharing in the New South Africa,’’ in Andrew Reynolds (ed.), Elec- tion ’94 South Africa. London: James Currey. ——— and Waisman, Carlos (1996). Institutional De- sign in New Democracies. Boulder, CO: Westview Press. Reilly, Ben (1997). ‘‘Preferential Voting and Political Engineering: A Comparative Study.’’ Journal of Com- monwealth and Comparative Politics, 35/1: 1–19. ——— and Reynolds, Andrew (1999). Electoral Sys- tems and Conflict in Divided Societies. Washington, DC: National Academy Press. Riker, William H. (1962). The Theory of Political Coalitions. New Haven: Yale University Press. Wimmer, Andreas (1997). ‘‘Who Owns the State? Un- derstanding Ethnic Conflict.’’ Nations and Nationalism: Journal of the Association for the Study of Ethnic Con- flict, 3: 631–665. The State of Democratic Theory

Ian Shapiro

Even if democracy might in principle operate polity. Further along are systems that engineer anywhere, it becomes plain from the literature around ethnic di¤erences to produce diversity on its durability . . . that this does not mean de- in legislatures, as is the case with gerrymander- mocracy is easily instituted, or, once installed, ing to create majority minority districts in the destined to survive. These, too, are subjects American south. These reactive responses all about which empirically well-supported general- take ethnic di¤erence as given, hoping to work izations are hard to come by . . . notwithstanding around it. Toward the center of the continuum the confident assertions of various commenta- we come to reflective responses: those that are tors, we are mainly in the dark about the cultural sensitive to ethnic di¤erence but neutral in the and institutional factors that influence demo- sense of being biased neither in favor nor against cracy’s viability. Little is known about which it. The various cumulative voting schemes dis- democratic institutional arrangements are best, cussed by Lani Guinier fit this description.32 and, although prudence suggests that it is wise to Here the principle is to give each voter as many try to inculcate support for democracy among votes as there are seats. If a state is to have eight those who operate it, it is far from clear how congressional representatives, every voter gets important this is or how to achieve it. . . . eight votes that can be cast however they wish: Electoral systems are potential instruments all for one candidate or spread among several. If for undermining ethnic conflict in the service there are intense minority ethnic preferences, of promoting competitive politics, but . . . it is members of a particular group can cast all eight unclear how e¤ective they can be. Assuming votes for ‘‘their’’ representative; if not, not. opinion to be at least partly mobilized and Unlike racial gerrymandering and consocia- shaped from above, a logical place to start is tionalism, reflective schemes respond to ethnic the incentives facing candidates for o‰ce. In a preferences without doing anything to produce Schumpeterian spirit the goal should be to avoid or reinforce them. As a result, they avoid the encouraging aspiring leaders to foment group- critique of reactive systems that they promote based hatred as they seek power. From this per- balkanization. Yet by the same token cumulative spective we can array electoral systems on an voting does nothing to ameliorate or undermine ethnic engineering continuum, ranging from re- potentially polarizing forms of aspirational dif- active systems that cater to ethnic di¤erence, ference where these are present. through reflective systems that are neutral with For engineered responses aimed at reducing respect to existing preferences, to proactive that such conflicts we move to the proactive part of seek to alter it in ways that promote competitive the continuum: arrangements that supply would- democracy. Secession or partition anchors the be leaders with incentives to avoid mobilizing reactive pole. Next to it come apartheid and consociationalism . . . where the aspiration is to 32. For Guinier’s proposals see Guinier (1991: 1077– achieve functional partition within a unified 1154; 1994a: 109–137). On the battle over her confir- mation as Assistant Attorney General for Civil Rights, Excerpted from: Ian Shapiro, ‘‘The State of Demo- which she lost for her advocacy of this scheme, see cratic Theory.’’ Political Science: The State of the Dis- Guinier (1994b). Her fate suggests a criterion, in addi- cipline. Edited by and Helen Milner. tion to representative fairness, for evaluating proposed Washington, D.C.: American Political Science Associ- decision rules: whether they can be widely understood ation, 2001. 6 APSA. Reprinted by permission. and perceived as democratic. Chapter 3 154

support in ways that exacerbate cultural compe- tition and to devise, instead, ideologies that can appeal across the divisions of relevant groups. Hence Donald Horowitz’s contention that, when group-based antipathies are strong, electoral systems are needed that give elites incentives to compete for votes among politicized groups other than their own, and so promote ac- commodation rather than exclusionary politics (Horowitz 1991: 155; 1985). He describes a suc- cessful example of this kind from Malaysia, in which Malay and Chinese politicians were forced to rely in part on votes delivered by politicians belonging to the other ethnic group. . . . Another possible device is geographical distri- bution requirements, such as the Nigerian for- mula for presidential elections employed in 1979 and 1983, in which the winning candidate had to get both the largest number of votes and at least 25 percent of the vote in two thirds of the then- nineteen states of the Nigerian Federation. This type of system would not work in countries like South Africa, however, given the territorial dis- persion of politicized groups. In such circum- stances, the two most promising candidates are proportional representation utilizing the single transferable vote system, and an alternative vote rule that also lists more than one ordered pref- erence, but declares elected only candidates who receive a majority, rather than a plurality, of votes. Both systems require politicians to cater to voters’ choices other than their first preferences, assuming heterogeneous constituencies, so that the politicians’ incentives work in the appropri- ate moderating directions. This will be further accentuated by the alternative vote system, as- suming that parties proliferate (Horowitz 1985: 184, 166, 187–196). In many circumstances such vote-pooling systems are more likely to achieve interethnic political cooperation than consociational arrangements or systems, whether first-past-the-post or proportional, that merely require seat-pooling by politicians in coalition Figure 3.2 Ethnic engineering continuum. governments. As reactive systems, they do nothing to moderate group antipathies. On the Democracy, Culture, and Society 155

contrary, they give politicians incentives to max- some circumstances, they involve manifestly pa- imize their ex-ante bargaining position by in- ternalistic institutional design that is unlikely to creasing what economists might describe as their win legitimacy unless there is widespread ac- group’s reservation price for cooperation. knowledgment that a minority has been unjustly Proactive incentives to avoid appealing to treated over a long time and that it will not oth- inter-group antipathies will not always work. erwise be represented.35 Even then, such pro- Parties might proliferate within politicized posals will likely be attacked on many of the groups in ways that undermine this dimension same grounds as are reverse discrimination and of the logic behind weighted vote schemes.33 a‰rmative action. They can also be expected to Moreover, some of the worst of what often provoke the charge, if from a di¤erent ideologi- (misleadingly) gets labeled inter-ethnic violence cal quarter, that those competing for the des- is actually intra-ethnic violence that results when ignated minority spots will lack the incentive to di¤erent parties seek to mobilize support from represent the relevant minority interests. . . . the same ethnic group. . . . There are limits to the The further institutional designers try to move degree that intra-ethnic competition of this sort along the continuum toward explicit proactive can be ameliorated by weighted vote mecha- systems that force integration in exclusionary nisms. If parties have incentives to mobilize and racist societies, the more they will learn support in more than one ethnic constituency, about how much redesign of ethnic antipathy is they should avoid campaigning as ethnic parties feasible in them. At present the only statement any more than they have to. In practice, how- that can be made with much confidence is that ever, parties . . . whose raison d’eˆtre is ethnic— there is no particular reason to think any society may have little scope to campaign on any other inherently incapable of Schumpeterian electoral basis. Accordingly, they may resist—perhaps competition. As the Indian and Japanese exam- violently—any inroads into their ‘‘traditional’’ ples underscore, even societies with profoundly sources of support. They can only play a zero- inegalitarian cultures and undemocratic histories sum ethnic game. have adapted to the demands of democratic pol- When relying on the logic of cross-group mo- itics in ways that many would have insisted was bilization does not lead to ethnic accommoda- impossible before the fact. South Africa might tion, it may be possible to move further along turn out to be another such case in the making, the continuum and become more explicitly pro- though the jury must remain out until ANC he- active, as in the 1931 Poona Pact in India. It gemony faces a serious challenge. requires that Untouchables be the representative in 148 designated constituencies, a number cor- responding roughly to their proportion in the References population (Van Parijis 1996: 111–112). This both ensures that the specified number of Un- Guinier, Lani. 1991. ‘‘The Triumph of Tokenism: The touchables become parliamentary representa- Voting Rights Act and the Theory of Black Educa- tives and it gives aspirants for o‰ce an incentive tional Success.’’ Michigan Law Review 89: 1077–1154. to seek support from all sectors of heterogeneous ———. 1994a. ‘‘(E)racing Democracy: The Voting constituencies, not merely ‘‘their own’’ ethnic Rights Cases.’’ Harvard Law Review 108: 109–137. group. . . . Attractive as such solutions can be in 35. According to Nagel (1993: 11), a comparable so- lution operates with respect to four seats reserved for 33. For elaboration of these and related di‰culties New Zealand’s Maoris, who are also geographically confronting Horowitz’s proposals, see Shapiro (1993: dispersed. 145–147). Chapter 3 156

———. 1994b. The Tyranny of the Majority: Funda- mental Fairness in Representative Democracy. New York: Free Press. Horowitz, Donald L. 1985. Ethnic Groups in Conflict. Berkeley and Los Angeles: University of California Press. ———. 1991. A Democratic South Africa? Constitu- tional Engineering in a Divided Society. Berkeley and Los Angeles: University of California Press. Nagel, Jack. 1993. ‘‘Lessons of the impending electoral reform in New Zealand.’’ PEGS Newsletter 3(1): 9–10. Shapiro, Ian. 1993. ‘‘Democratic Innovation: South Africa in Comparative Context.’’ World Politics 46: 121–150. Van Parijs, Philippe. 1996. ‘‘Justice and democracy: Are they incompatible?’’ Journal of Political Philoso- phy 4(2): 101–117. Democracy

Robert D. Putnam

. . . That democratic self-government requires an their political leaders. Political information flows actively engaged citizenry has been a truism for through social networks, and in these networks centuries. . . . I consider both the conventional public life is discussed. . . . claim that the health of American democracy When people associate in neighborhood requires citizens to perform our public duties and groups, PTAs, political parties, or even national the more expansive and controversial claim that advocacy groups, their individual and other- the health of our public institutions depends, at wise quiet voices multiply and are amplified. . . . least in part, on widespread participation in pri- Citizen connectedness does not require formal vate voluntary groups—those networks of civic institutions to be e¤ective. A study of the de- engagement that embody social capital. mocracy movement in East Germany before the The ideal of participatory democracy has deep collapse of the Berlin Wall, for example, found roots in American political philosophy. . . . that recruitment took place through friendship Many of America’s Founding Fathers, how- networks and that these informal bonds were ever, didn’t think much of voluntary associa- more important than ideological commitment, tions. They were famously opposed to political fear of repression, or formal organizing e¤orts in parties and local political committees, as well as determining who joined the cause.12 to any other group whose members might com- Internally, associations and less formal net- bine to threaten political stability. . . . works of civic engagement instill in their Echoing Tocqueville’s observations, many members habits of cooperation and public- contemporary students of democracy have come spiritedness, as well as the practical skills nec- to celebrate ‘‘mediating’’ or ‘‘intermediary’’ as- essary to partake in public life. Tocqueville sociations, be they self-consciously or only indi- observed that ‘‘feelings and ideas are renewed, rectly political, as fundamental to maintaining a the heart enlarged, and the understanding devel- vibrant democracy.9 Voluntary associations and oped only by the reciprocal action of men one the social networks of civil society that we have upon another.’’13 Prophylactically, community been calling ‘‘social capital’’ contribute to de- bonds keep individuals from falling prey to ex- mocracy in two di¤erent ways: they have ‘‘ex- tremist groups that target isolated and unteth- ternal’’ e¤ects on the larger polity, and they have ered individuals. Studies of political psychology ‘‘internal’’ e¤ects on participants themselves. over the last forty years have suggested that Externally, voluntary associations, from ‘‘people divorced from community, occupation, churches and professional societies to Elks clubs and association are first and foremost among the and reading groups, allow individuals to express supporters of extremism.’’14 their interests and demands on government and More positively, voluntary associations are to protect themselves from abuses of power by places where social and civic skills are learned—

Reprinted with the permission of Simon & Schuster 12. Karl-Dieter Opp and Christiane Gern, ‘‘Dissident from Bowling Alone: The Collapse and Revival of Groups, Personal Networks, and Spontaneous Coop- American Community by Robert D. Putnam. Copy- eration: The East German Revolution of 1989,’’ right 6 2000 by Robert D. Putnam. American Sociological Review 58 (1993): 659–680. 9. See, for example, Peter L. Berger and Richard John 13. Tocqueville, Democracy in America, 515. Neuhaus, To Empower People: From State to Civil So- 14. William Kornhauser, The Politics of Mass Society ciety (Washington, D.C.: AEI Press, 1977; 1996). (Glencoe, Ill.: Free Press, 1959), 73. Chapter 3 158

‘‘schools for democracy.’’ Members learn how to cosms of the nation, economically, ethnically, run meetings, speak in public, write letters, or- and religiously.21 Others argue that even homo- ganize projects, and debate public issues. . . . geneous organizations can enhance deliberative The most systematic study of civic skills democracy by making our public interactions in contemporary America suggests that for more inclusive. When minority groups, for ex- working-class Americans voluntary associations ample, push for nondiscrimination regulations and churches o¤er the best opportunities for and mandatory inclusion of ethnic interests in civic skill building, and even for professionals school curricula and on government boards, they such groups are second only to the workplace as are in e¤ect widening the circle of participants.22 sites for civic learning. Two-thirds or more of Voluntary associations may serve not only as the members of religious, literary, youth, and forums for deliberation, but also as occasions for fraternal/service organizations exercised such learning civic virtues, such as active participation civic skills as giving a presentation or running in public life.23 A follow-up study of high school a meeting.17 Churches, in particular, are one seniors found that regardless of the students’ so- of the few vital institutions left in which low- cial class, academic background, and self-esteem, income, minority, and disadvantaged citizens of those who took part in voluntary associations in all races can learn politically relevant skills and school were far more likely than nonparticipants be recruited into political action.18 The implica- to vote, take part in political campaigns, and tion is vitally important to anyone who values discuss public issues two years after graduat- egalitarian democracy: without such institutions, ing.24 Another civic virtue is trustworthiness. the class bias in American politics would be Much research suggests that when people have much greater.19 repeated interactions, they are far less likely to Just as associations inculcate democratic hab- shirk or cheat.25 A third civic virtue acquired its, they also serve as forums for thoughtful deliberation over vital public issues. Political 20. Jon Elster, ed., Deliberative Democracy (Cam- theorists have lately renewed their attention to bridge, UK: Cambridge University Press, 1998); Amy the promise and pitfalls of ‘‘deliberative democ- Gutmann and Dennis Thompson, Democracy and Dis- racy.’’20 Some argue that voluntary associations agreement (Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University best enhance deliberation when they are micro- Press, 1996): J. Bohman, Public Deliberation (Cam- bridge, Mass.: MIT Press, 1996); C. Nino, The Consti- tution of Deliberative Democracy (New Haven, Conn.: Voice and Equality 17. Verba, Schlozman, Brady, , Yale University Press, 1996). 378. 21. Gutmann ‘‘Freedom of Association,’’ 25. 18. Frederick C. Harris, ‘‘Religious Institutions and African American Political Mobilization,’’ in Paul 22. See, for example, Will Kymlicka, ‘‘Ethnic Associ- ations and Democratic Citizenship,’’ in Gutmann, Peterson, ed., Classifying by Race (Princeton, N.J.: Freedom of Association Princeton University Press, 1995), 299. The evidence , 177–213. suggests that churches organized congregationally, 23. See Michael Walzer, ‘‘The Civil Society Argu- such as Protestant denominations, tend to provide ment,’’ in Ronald Beiner, ed., Theorizing Citizenship more opportunities for parishioners to build civic skills (Albany: State University of New York Press, 1995). than do hierarchically organized churches, including 24. Michael Hanks, ‘‘Youth, Voluntary Associations, Catholic and evangelical denominations. Protestants and Political Socialization,’’ Social Forces 60 (1981): are three times as likely as Catholics to report oppor- 211–223. tunities to exercise civic skills. Verba, Schlozman, 25. David Sally, ‘‘Conversation and Cooperation in Brady, Voice and Equality, 321–322, 329. Social Dilemmas: A Meta-Analysis of Experiments 19. Verba, Schlozman, Brady, Voice and Equality, from 1958 to 1992,’’ Rationality and Society 7, no. 1 385. (1995): 58–92. Democracy, Culture, and Society 159

through social connectedness is reciprocity. . . . ‘‘factions’’ would profit at the expense of the [T]he more people are involved in networks of commonweal. Contrary to the pluralists’ ideal, civic engagement (from club meetings to church wherein bargaining among diverse groups leads picnics to informal get-togethers with friends), to the greatest good for the greatest number, we the more likely they are to display concern for end up instead with the greatest goodies for the the generalized other—to volunteer, give blood, best-organized few. contribute to charity, and so on. To political A second concern is that associational ties theorists, reciprocity has another meaning as benefit those who are best equipped by nature or well—the willingness of opposing sides in a circumstance to organize and make their voices democratic debate to agree on the ground rules heard. People with education, money, status, and for seeking mutual accommodation after su‰- close ties with fellow members of their commu- cient discussion, even (or especially) when they nity of interest will be far more likely to benefit don’t agree on what is to be done.26 Regular politically under pluralism than will the unedu- connections with my fellow citizens don’t ensure cated, the poor, and the unconnected.29 In our that I will be able to put myself in their shoes, words, social capital is self-reinforcing and ben- but social isolation virtually guarantees that I efits most those who already have a stock on will not. which to trade. As long as associationalism is On the other hand, numerous sensible critics class biased, as virtually every study suggests it have raised doubts about whether voluntary is,30 then pluralist democracy will be less than associations are necessarily good for democ- egalitarian. In the famous words of the political racy.27 Most obviously, some groups are overtly scientist E. E. Schattschneider: ‘‘The flaw in the antidemocratic—the KKK is everyone’s favorite pluralist heaven is that the heavenly chorus sings example. No sensible theorist has ever claimed with a strong upper-class accent.’’31 that every group works to foster democratic Finally, critics of pluralism have suggested values. But even if we restrict our attention to that it can trigger political polarization and cyn- groups that act within the norms of democracy, icism. Political scientists concerned about the one common concern is that associations—or decline in mass political parties as forces for interest groups—distort governmental decision organizing politics argue that citizen group poli- making. From Theodore Lowi’s End of Liber- alism in the 1960s to Jonathan Rauch’s Demo- 28. Theodore J. Lowi, The End of Liberalism: Ideol- sclerosis in the 1990s, critics of American ogy, Policy, and the Crisis of Public Authority (New pluralism have argued that the constant and York: Norton, 1969); Jonathan Rauch, Demosclerosis: conflicting pleas of ever more specialized lobbies The Silent Killer of American Government (New York: have paralyzed even well-intentioned public o‰- Times Books, 1994). cials and stifled e¤orts to cut or improve ine¤ec- 29. Michael Walzer, ‘‘The Civil Society Argument,’’ in tive government programs.28 This complaint is Ronald Beiner, ed., Theorizing Citizenship (Albany: reminiscent of Madison’s worry that mischievous State University of New York Press, 1995). 30. See, for example, Hausknecht, The Joiners; Verba, Scholzman, Brady, Voice and Equality; and David 26. Gutmann and Thompson, Democracy and Dis- Horton Smith, ‘‘Determinants of Voluntary Associa- agreement, 52–53. tion Participation and Volunteering: A Literature Re- 27. See, for example, Nancy Rosenblum, Membership view,’’ Nonprofit and Voluntary Sector Quarterly 23, and Morals (Princeton, N.J.: Princeton University no. 3 (fall 1994): 243–263. Press, 1998); Daniel Schulman, ‘‘Voluntary Organiza- 31. E. E. Schattschneider, The Semisovereign People: tion Involvement and Political Participation,’’ Journal A Realist’s View of Democracy in America (New York: of Voluntary Action Research 7 (1978): 86–105. Holt, Rinchart & Winston, 1960). Chapter 3 160

tics is almost by nature extremist politics, since Voluntary groups are not a panacea for what people with strongly held views tend to be the ails our democracy. And the absence of social leaders and activists. Evidence from the Roper capital—norms, trust, networks of association— Social and Political Trends archives indeed sug- does not climinate politics. But without social gests that ideological extremism and civic par- capital we are more likely to have politics of a ticipation are correlated, although as we shall certain type. American democracy evolved his- shortly see, that fact turns out to have unex- torically in an environment unusually rich in pected implications for our current predicament. social capital, and many of our institutions and If participation and extremism are linked, practices—such as the unusual degree of de- there are a number of important repercussions. centralization in our governmental processes, First, voluntary organizations that are ideologi- compared with that of other industrialized cally homogeneous may reinforce members’ countries—represent adaptations to such a set- views and isolate them from potentially enlight- ting. Like a plant overtaken by climatic change, ening alternative viewpoints.32 In some cases our political practices would have to change if such parochialism may nurture paranoia and social capital were permanently diminished. obstruction. In a polarized voluntary group uni- How might the American polity function in a verse, reasonable deliberation and bargaining setting of much lower social capital and civic toward a mutually acceptable compromise is engagement? well nigh impossible, as each side refuses ‘‘on A politics without face-to-face socializing and principle’’ to give ground. Moreover, political organizing might take the form of a Perot-style polarization may increase cynicism about gov- electronic town hall, a kind of plebiscitary de- ernment’s ability to solve problems and de- mocracy. Many opinions would be heard, but crease confidence that civic engagement makes only as a muddle of disembodied voices, neither any di¤erence.33 engaging with one another nor o¤ering much These are all serious concerns. Voluntary as- guidance to decision makers. TV-based politics is sociations are not everywhere and always good. to political action as watching ER is to saving They can reinforce antiliberal tendencies; and someone in distress. Just as one cannot restart a they can be abused by antidemocratic forces. heart with one’s remote control, one cannot Further, not everyone who participates will walk jump-start republican citizenship without direct, away a better person: some people who join self- face-to-face participation. Citizenship is not a help groups, for example, will learn compassion spectator sport. and cooperation, while others will become more Politics without social capital is politics at narcissistic. In the words of political theorist a distance. Conversations among callers to a Nancy Rosenblum: ‘‘The moral uses of associa- studio in Dallas or New York are not re- tional life by members are indeterminate.’’34 sponsible, since these ‘‘participants’’ need never meaningfully engage with opposing views and 32. Seymour Martin Lipset, Political Man: The Social hence learn from that engagement. Real con- Bases of Politics (Garden City, N.Y.: Doubleday, versations—the kind that take place in com- 1960); Samuel Stou¤er, Communism, Conformity and munity meetings about crack houses or school Civil Liberties (New York: Doubleday, 1955); Sheri budgets—are more ‘‘realistic’’ from the perspec- Berman, ‘‘Civil Society and the Collapse of the tive of democratic problem solving. Without Weimar Republic,’’ World Politics 49 (April 1997): such face-to-face interaction, without immediate 401–429. feedback, without being forced to examine our 33. Samuel P. Huntington, ‘‘The Democratic Distem- per,’’ The Public Interest 41 (fall 1975): 9–38. 34. Rosenblum, Membership and Morals, 155. Democracy, Culture, and Society 161

opinions under the light of other citizens’ scru- zations, and even attend church than their fel- tiny, we find it easier to hawk quick fixes and to low citizens of more moderate views. Moreover, demonize anyone who disagrees. Anonymity is this correlation between ideological ‘‘extremism’’ fundamentally anathema to deliberation. and participation strengthened over the last If participation in political deliberation quarter of the twentieth century, as people who declines—if fewer and fewer voices engage in characterize themselves as being ‘‘middle of the democratic debate—our politics will become road’’ ideologically have disproportionately dis- more shrill and less balanced. When most people appeared from public meetings, local organiza- skip the meeting, those who are left tend to be tions, political parties, rallies, and the like.36 more extreme, because they care most about In the 1990s self-described middle-of-the- the outcome. Political scientist Morris Fiorina roaders were about one-half as likely to partici- describes, for example, how a generally popular pate in public meetings, local civic organizations, proposal to expand a nature reserve in Concord, and political parties as in the mid-1970s. Partici- Massachusetts, where he lived, became bogged pation by self-described ‘‘moderate’’ liberals or down in protracted and costly controversy per- conservatives declined by about one-third. The petuated by a tiny group of environmentalist declines were smallest—averaging less than one- ‘‘true believers.’’35 fifth—among people who described themselves The Roper Social and Political Trends surveys as ‘‘very’’ liberal or ‘‘very’’ conservative. Writing show that Fiorina’s experience is typical: Ameri- to a newspaper, writing to Congress, or even cans at the political poles are more engaged giving a speech declined by a scant 2 percent in civic life, whereas moderates have tended to among people who described themselves as drop out. Controlling for all the standard demo- ‘‘very’’ liberal or conservative, by about 15 per- graphic characteristics—income, education, size cent among people who described themselves as of city, region, age, sex, race, and job, marital, ‘‘moderately’’ liberal or conservative, and by and parental status—Americans who describe about 30 percent among self-described ‘‘middle- themselves as ‘‘very’’ liberal or ‘‘very’’ conserva- of-the-roaders.’’37 tive are more likely to attend public meetings, write Congress, be active in local civic organi- 36. Generalizations in this and the following para- graph are drawn from the author’s analysis of Roper 35. Morris P. Fiorina, ‘‘Extreme Voices: The Dark Social and Political Trends archives. Ideological self- Side of Civic Engagement,’’ in Skocpol and Fiorina, description is based on this question: ‘‘Now, thinking eds., Civic Engagement in American Democracy. Fior- politically and socially, how would you describe your ina’s anecdote is insightful, and his concluding call for general outlook—as being very conservative, moder- more civic engagement is correct. Unfortunately, some ately conservative, middle-of-the-road, moderately lib- passages of his essay confuse a) a high degree of citizen eral, or very liberal?’’ participation in a community with b) a system of rep- 37. I have calculated the linear trend between 1974 resentation or a decision-making process that privileges and 1994 for each of the twelve basic forms of partici- citizen participation, however few the participants may pation for each of the five categories of ideological self- be. The former is a behavioral characteristic, the latter identification and expressed the net change over the an institutional one. (The two may be linked causally twenty-one years as a fraction of the participation rate or historically, but they are not the same thing.) Con- in 1974. This approach is less sensitive to annual out- fusingly, Fiorina uses the term civic engagement to liers than other possible measures and allows easier refer to both, but his essay demonstrates the ‘‘dark comparisons across the di¤erent forms of participation, side’’ of b), not the dark side of a). Contrary to the but any reasonable metric yields the same conclusion: essay’s title, his evidence shows the dark side of civic The more extreme the self-declared ideological posi- disengagement. tion, the smaller the relative decline in participation rates over these two decades. Chapter 3 162

Ironically, more and more Americans describe everyone. African Americans who live in clusters their political views as middle of the road or of poverty in American inner cities su¤er not moderate, but the more polarized extremes on only from economic deprivation, but also from the ideological spectrum account for a bigger a dearth of political information and opportu- and bigger share of those who attend meetings, nity. Their study of Detroit neighborhoods with write letters, serve on committees, and so on. concentrated poverty found that even residents The more extreme views have gradually become not themselves destitute are far less likely to more dominant in grassroots American civic life attend church, belong to a voluntary organiza- as more moderate voices have fallen silent. In tion, attend public meetings, and talk about pol- this sense civic disengagement is exacerbating the itics than similar people in more advantaged classic problem of ‘‘faction’’ that worried the neighborhoods.39 People in high-poverty neigh- Founders. borhoods feel cut o¤ from their political repre- Just as important as actual engagement is sentatives and see political and community psychic engagement. Social capital is also key engagement as futile. In part a realistic assess- here. Surveys show that most of our political ment of the nation’s long-standing inattention to discussions take place informally, around the the truly disadvantaged, this alienated apathy dinner table or the o‰ce water cooler. We learn also reflects the fact that inner-city neighbor- about politics through casual conversation. You hoods often lack institutions to mobilize citi- tell me what you’ve heard and what you think, zens into political action. In other words, people and what your friends have heard and what they don’t participate because they’re not mobilized, think, and I accommodate that new information and not mobilized, they can never savor the into my mental database as I ponder and revise fruits of participation. my position on an issue. In a world of civic net- But perhaps face-to-face mobilization isn’t works, both formal and informal, our views are necessary for e¤ective democracy. It is su‰cient, formed through interchange with friends and the argument goes, for large national member- neighbors. Social capital allows political infor- ship groups, such as the American Association of mation to spread.38 Retired Persons, the Audubon Society, and the However, as political scientists Cathy J. NAACP, to represent the interests of their dif- Cohen and Michael C. Dawson have pointed fuse membership. Just as you and I hire a me- out, these informal networks are not available to chanic to fix our cars and money managers to husband our wealth, so, too, one might argue, it 38. Gabriel Weimann, ‘‘On the Importance of Mar- is simply a sensible division of labor for us to ginality: One More Step in the Two-Step Flow of hire the AARP to defend our interests as pro- Communication,’’ American Sociological Review 47 spective retirees, the Audubon Society our envi- (December 1982): 764–773; Gabriel Weimann. ‘‘The ronmentalist views, the NAACP our sympathies Strength of Weak Conversational Ties in the Flow of on racial issues, and so on. ‘‘This is not Tocque- Information and Influence,’’ Social Networks 5 (1983): villian democracy,’’ concedes Michael Schudson, 245–267; Matthew A. Crenson, ‘‘Social Networks and ‘‘but these organizations may be a highly e‰- Political Processes in Urban Neighborhoods,’’ Ameri- cient use of civic energy. The citizen who joins can Journal of Political Science 22, no. 3 (August 1978): 578–594. Michael MacKuen and Courtney them may get the same civic payo¤ for less Brown, ‘‘Political Context and Attitude Change,’’ personal hassle. This is especially so if we con- American Political Science Review 81 (June 1987): ceive of politics as a set of public policies. The 471–490; Robert Huckfeldt and John Sprague, Citi- zens, Politics, and Social Communication: Information 39. Cathy J. Cohen and Michael C. Dawson, ‘‘Neigh- and Influence in an Election Campaign (New York: borhood Poverty and African American Politics,’’ Cambridge University Press, 1995). American Political Science Review 87 (1993): 286–302. Democracy, Culture, and Society 163

citizen may be able to influence government homes and voted were (holding constant many more satisfactorily with the annual membership other factors) less likely to get hazardous waste in the Sierra Club or the National Rifle Associ- plants than neighborhoods where people rented ation than by attending the local club lun- and rarely voted. He concluded that in deciding cheons.’’40 To some intellectuals, citizenship by where to locate, hazardous waste companies proxy has a certain allure.41 look to locate in places in which they can ex- But if we have a broader conception of politics pect the least locally organized opposition.44 and democracy than merely the advocacy of In this way, civic disengagement at the local narrow interests, then the explosion of sta¤-led, level undermines neighborhood empowerment. professionalized, Washington-based advocacy Of course, the reverse is true as well, for disen- organizations may not be as satisfactory, for it gagement and disempowerment are two sides of was in those local luncheons that civic skills were the same coin. honed and genuine give-and-take deliberation occurred. . . . Social capital a¤ects not only what goes into Peter Skerry has argued that broad national politics, but also what comes out of it. The best membership organizations tend to be dominated illustration of the powerful impact of civic en- not by member input—which is, after all, usu- gagement on government performance comes ally just a check sent in for their dues—but by not from the United States, but from an investi- headquarters sta¤. These people are inevitably gation that several colleagues and I conducted pulled toward the wishes of their major patrons: on the seemingly arcane subject of Italian re- wealthy individuals, foundations, even the gov- gional government.45 ernment agencies that indirectly fund many of Beginning in 1970, Italians established a na- them. Because the voluntary organizations’ tionwide set of potentially powerful regional members are geographically dispersed, these or- governments. These twenty new institutions were ganizations also tend to rely on media strategies virtually identical in form, but the social, eco- to push their agendas. Media strategies to gen- nomic, political, and cultural contexts in which erate more contributions often emphasize threats they were implanted di¤ered dramatically, rang- from the group’s ‘‘enemies’’ and in the process ing from the preindustrial to the postindustrial, give us a politics fraught with posturing and from the devoutly Catholic to the ardently confrontation, rather than reasoned debate.43 Communist, from the inertly feudal to the fre- There is another reason why large ‘‘tertiary’’ netically modern. Just as a botanist might in- organizations are no substitute for more personal vestigate plant development by measuring the forms of political engagement: Most political growth of genetically identical seeds sown in decision making does not take place in Wash- di¤erent plots, we sought to understand gov- ington. To be e¤ective, therefore, political activ- ernment performance by studying how these ity cannot be confined to mailing one’s dues to new institutions evolved in their diverse set- an inside-the-Beltway interest group. For exam- tings. As we expected, some of the new govern- ple, economist James T. Hamilton discovered that neighborhoods where people owned their 44. James T. Hamilton, ‘‘Testing for Environmental Racism: Prejudice, Profits, Political Power?,’’ Journal 40. Michael Schudson, ‘‘What If Civic Life Didn’t of Policy Analysis and Management 14, no. 1 (1995): Die?’’ The American Prospect 25 (1996): 17–20, quo- 107–132. tation at 18. 45. Robert D. Putnam with Robert Leonardi and 41. Tarrow, Power in Movement, 133. Ra¤aella Nanetti, Making Democracy Work: Civic Traditions in Modern Italy 43. Peter Skerry, ‘‘The Strange Polities of A‰rmative (Princeton, N.J.: Princeton University Press, 1993). Action,’’ Wilson Quarterly (Winter 1997): 39–46. Chapter 3 164

ments proved to be dismal failures—ine‰cient, but fearing others’ lawlessness, everyone de- lethargic, and corrupt. Others were remarkably mands sterner discipline. Trapped in these in- successful, however, creating innovative day care terlocking vicious circles, nearly everyone feels programs and job training centers, promoting powerless, exploited, and unhappy. It is hardly investment and economic development, pio- surprising that representative government here is neering environmental standards and family less e¤ective than in more civic communities. clinics—managing the public’s business e‰- The historical roots of the civic community are ciently and satisfying their constituents. astonishingly deep. Enduring traditions of civic What could account for these stark di¤erences involvement and social solidarity can be traced in quality of government? Some seemingly obvi- back nearly a millennium to the eleventh cen- ous answers turned out to be irrelevant. Gov- tury, when communal republics were established ernment organization was too similar from in places like Florence, Bologna, and Genoa, region to region for that to explain the contrasts exactly the communities that today enjoy civic in performance. Party politics or ideology made engagement and successful government. At the little di¤erence. A¿uence and prosperity had no core of this civic heritage are rich networks direct e¤ect. Social stability or political harmony of organized reciprocity and civic solidarity— or population movements were not the key. guilds, religious fraternities, and tower societies None of these factors was correlated with good for self-defense in the medieval communes; co- government as we had anticipated. Instead the operatives, mutual aid societies, neighborhood best predictor is one that Alexis de Tocqueville associations, and choral societies in the twentieth might have expected. Strong traditions of civic century. engagement—voter turnout, newspaper reader- Civic engagement matters on both the demand ship, membership in choral societies and literary side and the supply side of government. On the circles, Lions Clubs, and soccer clubs—were the demand side, citizens in civic communities expect hallmarks of a successful region. better government, and (in part through their Some regions of Italy, such as Emilia- own e¤orts) they get it. As we saw earlier in Romagna and Tuscany, have many active com- the hazardous waste study, if decision makers munity organizations. Citizens in these regions expect citizens to hold them politically account- are engaged by public issues, not by patronage. able, they are more inclined to temper their They trust one another to act fairly and obey the worst impulses rather than face public protests. law. Leaders in these communities are relatively On the supply side, the performance of repre- honest and committed to equality. Social and sentative government is facilitated by the social political networks are organized horizontally, infrastructure of civic communities and by the not hierarchically. These ‘‘civic communities’’ democratic values of both o‰cials and citizens. value solidarity, civic participation, and integ- In the language of economics, social capital rity. And here democracy works. lowers transaction costs and eases dilemmas of At the other pole are ‘‘uncivic’’ regions, like collection action. Where people know one an- Calabria and Sicily, aptly characterized by the other, interact with one another each week at French term incivisme. The very concept of citi- choir practice or sports matches, and trust one zenship is stunted there. Engagement in social another to behave honorably, they have a model and cultural associations is meager. From the and a moral foundation upon which to base point of view of the inhabitants, public a¤airs is further cooperative enterprises. Light-touch gov- somebody else’s business—that of i notabili, ‘‘the ernment works more e‰ciently in the presence bosses,’’ ‘‘the politicians’’—but not theirs. Laws, of social capital. Police close more cases when almost everyone agrees, are made to be broken, citizens monitor neighborhood comings and Democracy, Culture, and Society 165

goings. Child welfare departments do a better tive studies have found that the social capital– job of ‘‘family preservation’’ when neighbors rich ‘‘moralistic’’ states tend to be unusually and relatives provide social support to trou- innovative in public policy and to have merit bled parents. Public schools teach better when systems governing the hiring of government parents volunteer in classrooms and ensure that employees. Politics in these states is more issue kids do their homework. When community oriented, focused on social and educational involvement is lacking, the burdens on govern- services, and apparently less corrupt. Preliminary ment employees—bureaucrats, social workers, studies suggest that states high in social capital teachers, and so forth—are that much greater sustain governments that are more e¤ective and and success that much more elusive. innovative.49 Civic traditions seem to matter in the United At the municipal level, too, research has found States as well. . . . [I]n the 1950s political scien- that high levels of grass-roots involvement tend tist Daniel Elazar did a pathbreaking study of to blunt patronage politics50 and secure a American ‘‘political cultures.’’46 He concluded fairer distribution of federal community devel- that there were three cultures: a ‘‘traditional- opment grants.51 And cities that have institu- istic’’ culture in the South; an ‘‘individualistic’’ culture in the mid-Atlantic and western states; 49. Charles A. Johnson, ‘‘Political Culture in Ameri- and a ‘‘moralistic’’ culture concentrated in the can States: Elazar’s Formulation Examined,’’ Ameri- Northeast, upper Midwest, and Pacific North- can Journal of Political Science 20 (1976): 491–509; Ira west. Strikingly, Elazar’s political-culture map Sharkansky, Regionalism in American Politics (Indian- looks much like the distribution of social capital apolis, Ind.: Bobbs-Merrill, 1970); Richard A. Joslyn, .... The traditionalistic states, where politics ‘‘Manifestations of Elazar’s Political Subcultures: State tends to be dominated by elites resistant to in- Public Opinion and the Content of Political Campaign novation, are also the states that tend to be low- Advertising,’’ John Kincaid. ‘‘Political Culture and the Quality of Urban Life,’’ and Susan Welch and John G. est in social capital. The individualistic states, Peters, ‘‘State Political Culture and the Attitudes of where politics is run by strong parties and pro- State Senator Toward Social, Economic Welfare, fessional politicians and focused on economic and Corruption Issues,’’ all in Political Culture, Public growth, tend to have moderate levels of social Policy and the American States, John Kincaid, ed. capital. The moralistic states—in which ‘‘good (Philadelphia: Institute for the Study of Human Issues, government,’’ issue-based campaigning, and so- 1982), 59–80; 121–149; 151–159; Tom W. Rice and cial innovation are prized—tend to have com- Alexander F. Sumberg, ‘‘Civic Culture and Govern- paratively high levels of social capital. The ment Performance in the American States,’’ Publius 27 correlation between the political-culture index (1997): 99–114; Maureen Rand Oakley, ‘‘Explaining derived from Elazar’s study47 and our Social the Adoption of Morality Policy Innovations: The Case of Fetal Homicide Policy,’’ paper presented at the Capital Index is strikingly large.48 Annual Meeting of the American Political Science As- Do civic traditions also predict the character sociation (Atlanta, Ga., September 1999). of governments in the United States? Sugges- 50. Patronage politics are often based on bonding so- cial capital. While they may lead to ine‰cient govern- 46. Daniel Elazar, American Federalism: A View from ment and reinforce ethnic cleavages, they are often the States (New York: Crowell, 1966). highly e¤ective at political mobilization. 47. Ira Sharkansky, ‘‘The Utility of Elazar’s Political 51. Margaret Weir, ‘‘Power, Money, and Politics in Culture,’’ Polity 2 (1969): 66–83. Community Development,’’ in Ronald F. Ferguson 48. The Pearson’s r correlation coe‰cient is 0.77, and William T. Dickens, eds., Urban Problems and where 1.0 signifies a perfect linear relationship. Community Development (Washington, D.C.: Brook- ings Institution Press, 1999). Chapter 3 166

tionalized neighborhood organizations, such as are dishonest or are distrustful of government Portland (Oregon) and St. Paul (Minnesota), are more likely themselves to cheat.54 My will- are more e¤ective at passing proposals that ingness to pay my share depends crucially on my local people want. These cities also enjoy higher perception that others are doing the same. In ef- levels of support for and trust in municipal fect, in a community rich in social capital, gov- government.52 ernment is ‘‘we,’’ not ‘‘they.’’ In this way social The connection between high social capital capital reinforces government legitimacy: I pay and e¤ective government performance begs an my taxes because I believe that most other peo- obvious question: Is there a similar link between ple do, and I see the tax system as basically declining social capital and declining trust in working as it should. Conversely, in a commu- government? Is there a connection between our nity that lacks bonds of reciprocity among its democratic discontent and civic disengagement? inhabitants, I won’t feel bound to pay taxes It is commonly assumed that cynicism toward voluntarily, because I believe that most people government has caused our disengagement from cheat, and I will see the tax system as yet an- politics, but the converse is just as likely: that we other broken government program, instituted by are disa¤ected because as we and our neighbors ‘‘them,’’ not ‘‘us.’’ have dropped out, the real performance of gov- In this context it is not surprising that one ernment has su¤ered. As Pogo said, ‘‘We have of the best predictors of cooperation with the met the enemy and he is us.’’ decennial census is one’s level of civic participa- Social capital a¤ects government in many tion. Even more striking is the finding that com- ways. We all agree that the country is better o¤ munities that rank high on measures of social when everyone pays the taxes they owe. Nobody capital, such as turnout and social trust, pro- wants to subsidize tax cheats. The legitimacy of vide significantly higher contributions to public the tax system turns in part on the belief that we broadcasting, even when we control for all the all do our share. Yet we know that the IRS can- other factors that are said to a¤ect audience not possibly audit everyone, so rational citizens preferences and expenditures—education, a¿u- have every reason to believe that if they pay their ence, race, tax deductibility, and public spend- share, they will indeed be subsidizing those who are not so honor bound. It is a recipe for disillu- 53. In a regression analysis predicting compliance sionment with the IRS and the tax system in rates across states, only the Social Capital Index general. proved to be a statistically significant variable. Other Yet not everyone is equally disillusioned. It variables—per capita income, income inequality, racial turns out that in states where citizens view other composition, urbanism, education—were not signifi- people as basically honest, tax compliance is cant. On the role of social capital and trust in under- higher than in low-social-capital states. . . . If we girding compliance, see Tyler, ‘‘Trust and Democratic Governance.’’ consider state di¤erences in social capital, per capita income, income inequality, racial compo- 54. Young-dahl Song and Tinsley E. Yarbrough, ‘‘Tax Ethics and Taxpayer Attitudes: A Survey,’’ Public Ad- sition, urbanism, and education levels, social ministration Review 38 (1978): 442–452; Steven M. capital is the only factor that successfully predicts She¤rin and Robert K. Triest, ‘‘Can Brute Deterrence 53 tax compliance. Similarly, surveys have found Backfire: Perceptions and Attitudes in Taxpayer Com- that individual taxpayers who believe that others pliance,’’ in Why People Pay Taxes: Tax Compliance and Enforcement, Joel Slemrod, ed. (Ann Arbor: Uni- 52. Je¤rey M. Berry, Kent E. Portney, and Ken versity of Michigan Press, 1992), 193–222; Scholz and Thomson, The Rebirth of Urban Democracy (Wash- Lubell, ‘‘Trust and Taxpaying,’’ and Scholz, ‘‘Trust, ington, D.C.: Brookings Institution Press, 1993). Taxes, and Compliance.’’ Democracy, Culture, and Society 167

ing.55 Public broadcasting is a classic example of interest requires actions that violate our imme- a public good—I obtain the benefit whether or diate self-interest and that assume our neighbors not I pay, and my contribution in itself is un- will act collectively, too. Modern society is re- likely to keep the station on the air. Why should plete with opportunities for free-riding and op- any rational, self-interested listener, even one portunism. Democracy does not require that addicted to Jim Lehrer, send o¤ a check to the citizens be selfless saints, but in many modest local station? The answer appears to be that, at ways it does assume that most of us much of least in communities that are rich in social capi- the time will resist the temptation to cheat. So- tal, civic norms sustain an expanded sense of cial capital, the evidence increasingly suggests, ‘‘self-interest’’ and a firmer confidence in reci- strengthens our better, more expansive selves. procity. Thus if our stocks of social capital di- The performance of our democratic institutions minish, more and more of us will be tempted to depends in measurable ways upon social capital. ‘‘free-ride,’’ not merely by ignoring the appeals to ‘‘viewers like you,’’ but by neglecting the myriad civic duties that allow our democracy to work. Similarly, research has found that military units are more e¤ective when bonds of solidar- ity and trust are high, and that communities with strong social networks and grassroots as- sociations are better at confronting unexpected crises than communities that lack such civic resources.56 In all these instances our collective

55. Martha E. Kropf and Stephen Knack, ‘‘Viewers Like You: Community Norms and Contributions to Public Broadcasting,’’ unpub. ms. (Kansas City: Uni- versity of Missouri, Kansas City Department of Politi- cal Science, 1999). 56. Jennifer M. Coston, Terry Cooper, and Richard A. Sundeen, ‘‘Response of Community Organizations to the Civil Unrest in Los Angeles,’’ Nonprofit and Vol- untary Sector Quarterly 22 (1993): 357, and Krzysztof Kaniasty and Fran H. Norris, ‘‘In Search of Altruistic Community: Patterns of Social Support Mobilization Following Hurricane Hugo,’’ American Journal of Community Psychology, 23 (1995): 447–477. The liter- ature on small-group solidarity and military e¤ective- ness is enormous, and much of it is directly relevant to social-capital theory. See Edward A. Shils and Morris Janowitz, ‘‘Cohesion and Disintegration in the Wehr- macht in World War II,’’ Public Opinion Quarterly 12 (1948): 280–315; Samuel A. Stou¤er et al., The Ameri- can Soldier (Princeton, N.J.: Princeton University Press, 1949); and Anthony Kellett, Combat Motivation: The Behavior of Soldiers in Battle (Boston: Kluwer- Nijho¤, 1982). Modernization, Cultural Change, and the Persistence of Traditional Values

Ronald Inglehart and Wayne E. Baker

The last decades of the twentieth century were This school predicts the decline of traditional not kind to modernization theory, once widely values and their replacement with ‘‘modern’’ considered a powerful tool for peering into the values. The other school of thought emphasizes future of industrial society. . . . the persistence of traditional values despite eco- Nevertheless, a core concept of modernization nomic and political changes. This school as- theory seems valid today: Industrialization pro- sumes that values are relatively independent of duces pervasive social and cultural conse- economic conditions (DiMaggio 1994). Conse- quences, from rising educational levels to chang- quently, it predicts that convergence around ing gender roles. Industrialization is seen as the some set of ‘‘modern’’ values is unlikely and that central element of a modernization process that traditional values will continue to exert an inde- a¤ects most other elements of society. . . . pendent influence on the cultural changes caused Our thesis is that economic development has by economic development. . . . systematic and, to some extent, predictable cul- The central claim of modernization theory is tural and political consequences. These conse- that economic development is linked with co- quences are not iron laws of history; they are herent and, to some extent, predictable changes probabilistic trends. Nevertheless, the probabil- in culture and social and political life. Evidence ity is high that certain changes will occur, once a from around the world indicates that economic society has embarked on industrialization. We development tends to propel societies in a explore this thesis using data from the World roughly predictable direction: Industrialization Values Surveys. These surveys include 65 soci- leads to occupational specialization, rising edu- eties and more than 75 percent of the world’s cational levels, rising income levels, and even- population. They provide time-series data from tually brings unforeseen changes—changes in the earliest wave in 1981 to the most recent wave gender roles, attitudes toward authority and completed in 1998, o¤ering new and rich insights sexual norms; declining fertility rates: broader into the relationships between economic devel- political participation; and less easily led publics. opment and social and political change. Determined elites in control of the state and the military can resist these changes, but in the long run, it becomes increasingly costly to do so and Modernization or the Persistence of Traditional the probability of change rises.1 Values? 1. Paradoxically, modernization can actually strength- In recent years, research and theory on socio- en traditional values. Elites in underdeveloped nations economic development have given rise to two who attempt to mobilize a population for social contending schools of thought. One school em- change often use traditional cultural appeals, as in phasizes the convergence of values as a result of Japan’s Meiji Restoration. More recently, radical ‘‘modernization’’—the overwhelming economic reformist groups in Algeria used Islam to gain peasant and political forces that drive cultural change. support, but as an unintended result strengthened fun- damentalist religious values (Stokes and Marshall 1981). Thus, cultural identity can be used to promote Excerpted from: Ronald Inglehart and Wayne E. the interests of a group (Bernstein 1997) and in the Baker, ‘‘Modernization, Cultural Change, and the process may strengthen cultural diversity. Generally, American Socio- Persistence of Traditional Values.’’ ‘‘[a]s global integration intensifies, the currents of mul- logical Review 65 (Feb. 2000): 19–51. Reprinted by ticulturalism swirl faster. Under these conditions, permission. which include the juxtaposition of ethnically distinct Democracy, Culture, and Society 169

But cultural change does not take the simple tage, also shape how a particular society devel- linear path envisioned by Marx, who assumed ops. Weber ([1904] 1958) argued that traditional that the working class would continue to grow religious values have an enduring influence on until a proletarian revolution brought an end to the institutions of a society. Following this tra- history. In 1956, the United States became the dition. Huntington (1993, 1996) argues that the world’s first society to have a majority of its world is divided into eight major civilizations or labor force employed in the service sector. Dur- ‘‘cultural zones’’ based on cultural di¤erences ing the next few decades, practically all OECD that have persisted for centuries. These zones (Organization for Economic Cooperation and were shaped by religious traditions that are still Development) countries followed suit, becoming powerful today, despite the forces of moderniza- ‘‘post-industrial’’ societies, in Bell’s (1973) terms. tion. The zones are Western Christianity, the These changes in the nature of work had major Orthodox world, the Islamic world, and the political and cultural consequences (Bell 1973, Confucian, Japanese, Hindu, African, and Latin 1976; Dahrendorf 1959). In marked contrast to American zones. the growing materialism linked with the indus- Scholars from various disciplines have ob- trial revolution, the unprecedented existential served that distinctive cultural traits endure over security of advanced industrial society gave rise long periods of time and continue to shape a to an intergenerational shift toward postmate- society’s political and economic performance. rialist and postmodern values (Inglehart 1977, For example, Putnam (1993) shows that the 1990, 1997). While industrialization was linked regions of Italy in which democratic institutions with an emphasis on economic growth at almost function most successfully today are those in any price, the publics of a¿uent societies placed which civil society was relatively well developed increasing emphasis on quality-of-life, environ- in the nineteenth century and even earlier. mental protection, and self-expression. Bell Fukuyama (1995) argues that a cultural heritage emphasized changes in the nature of work, while of ‘‘low-trust’’ puts a society at a competitive Inglehart emphasized the consequences of eco- disadvantage in global markets because it is less nomic security; but they and others agreed that able to develop large and complex social institu- cultural change in postindustrial society was tions. Hamilton (1994) argues that, although moving in a new direction. Accordingly, we sug- capitalism has become an almost universal way gest that economic development gives rise to of life, civilizational factors continue to structure not just one, but two main dimensions of cross- the organization of economies and societies. . . . cultural di¤erentiation: a first dimension linked Thus, there are striking cross-cultural variations with early industrialization and the rise of the in the organization of capitalist production and working class; a second dimension that reflects associated managerial ideologies (DiMaggio the changes linked with the a¿uent conditions of 1994; Guille´n 1994). . . . advanced industrial society and with the rise of the service and knowledge sectors. . . . Di¤erent societies follow di¤erent trajecto- Findings and Discussion ries even when they are subjected to the same forces of economic development, in part because Global Cultural Map, 1995–1998 situation-specific factors, such as cultural heri- Figure 3.3 shows the location of 65 societies on labor forces and communities, the politics of identity the two dimensions. . . . The vertical axis on our tends to substitute for the civic (universalist) politics of global cultural map corresponds to the polariza- nation-building’’ (McMichael 1996: 42). tion between traditional authority and secular- Chapter 3 170

Figure 3.3 Locations of 65 societies on two dimensions of cross-cultural variation: world values surveys, 1990 to 1991 and 1995 to 1998. Note: The scales on each axis indicate the country’s factor scores on the given dimension. The positions of Columbia and Pakistan are estimated from incomplete data. Democracy, Culture, and Society 171

rational authority associated with the process of of homosexuality, a highly sensitive indicator of industrialization. The horizontal axis depicts the tolerance toward outgroups in general). polarization between survival values and self- Economic development seems to have a pow- expression values related to the rise of post- erful impact on cultural values: The value sys- industrial society.5 The boundaries around tems of rich countries di¤er systematically from groups of countries in figure 3.3 are drawn using those of poor countries. Figure 3.3 reflects a Huntington’s (1993, 1996) cultural zones as a gradient from low-income countries in the lower guide.6 left quadrant, to rich societies in the upper right Cross-cultural variation is highly constrained. quadrant. Figure 3.4 redraws figure 3.3 showing As the traditional/secular-rational dimension’s the economic zones into which these 65 societies loadings indicate . . . if the people of a given so- fall. All 19 societies with an annual per capita ciety place a strong emphasis on religion, that gross national product over $15,000 rank rela- society’s relative position on many other vari- tively high on both dimensions and fall into a ables can be predicted—from attitudes toward zone at the upper right-hand corner. This eco- abortion, level of national pride (highly religious nomic zone cuts across the boundaries of the nations rank high on national pride), the desir- Protestant, ex-Communist, Confucian, Catholic, ability of more respect for authority (religious and English-speaking cultural zones. All soci- nations place much more emphasis on respect eties with per capita GNPs below $2,000 fall into for authority), to attitudes toward childrearing. a cluster at the lower left of figure 3.4, in an The survival/self-expression dimension reflects economic zone that cuts across the African, another wide-ranging but tightly correlated clus- South Asian, ex-Communist, and Orthodox cul- ter of variables involving materialist values (such tural zones. The remaining societies fall into two as maintaining order and fighting inflation) ver- intermediate cultural-economic zones. Economic sus postmaterialist values (such as freedom and development seems to move societies in a com- self-expression), subjective well-being, interper- mon direction, regardless of their cultural heri- sonal trust, political activism, and tolerance of tage. Nevertheless, distinctive cultural zones outgroups (measured by acceptance or rejection persist two centuries after the industrial revolu- tion began. 5. This cultural map is consistent with an earlier one GNP per capita is only one indicator of a by Inglehart (1997: 334–337) based on the 1990–1991 society’s level of economic development. As World Values Surveys. Although our Figure 3.3 is Marx argued, the rise of the industrial working based on a factor analysis that uses less than half as class was a key event in modern history. Fur- many variables as Inglehart used (1997), and adds 22 thermore, the changing nature of the labor force societies that were not included in the earlier map, the defines three distinct stages of economic devel- overall pattern is strikingly similar to the cultural maps opment: agrarian society, industrial society, and in Inglehart (1997, chaps. 3 and 11). These similarities postindustrial society (Bell 1973, 1976). Thus, demonstrate the robustness of the two key dimensions of cross-cultural variation. The same broad cultural another set of boundaries could be superimposed zones appear in essentially the same locations, even on the societies in figure 3.3: Societies with a though some zones now contain many more societies. high percentage of the labor force in agriculture 6. An alternative strategy would be to use one of the would fall near the bottom of the map, societies many available clustering techniques to identify groups with a high percentage of industrial workers of nations and draw boundaries. We prefer to use the would fall near the top, and societies with a high theoretical classifications proposed by Huntington and percentage in the service sector would be located then test for their explanatory power. near the right-hand side of the map. Chapter 3 172

Figure 3.4 Economic zones for 65 societies superimposed on two dimensions of cross-cultural variation. Note: All but one of the 65 societies shown in figure 3.3 fit into the economic zones indicated here; only the Dominican Republic is mislocated. Source: GNP per capita is based on the World Bank’s purchasing power parity estimates as of 1995, in U.S. dollars (World Bank 1997: 214–215). Democracy, Culture, and Society 173

The traditional/secular-rational dimension is tems of 65 societies, as Weber, Huntington, and associated with the transition from agrarian so- others have argued. But a society’s culture ciety to industrial society. Accordingly, this di- reflects its entire historical heritage. A central mension shows a strong positive correlation with historical event of the twentieth century was the the percentage in the industrial sector (r ¼ :65) rise and fall of a Communist empire that once and a negative correlation with the percentage ruled one-third of the world’s population. Com- in the agricultural sector (r ¼:49) but it is munism left a clear imprint on the value systems weakly linked with the percentage in the service of those who lived under it. East Germany re- sector (r ¼ :18). Thus, the shift from an agrarian mains culturally close to West Germany despite mode of production to industrial production four decades of Communist rule, but its value seems to bring with it a shift from traditional system has been drawn toward the Communist values toward increasing rationalization and zone. And although China is a member of the secularization. Nevertheless, a society’s cultural Confucian zone, it also falls within a broad heritage also plays a role. Thus, all four of the Communist-influenced zone. Similarly Azerbai- Confucian-influenced societies have relatively jan, though part of the Islamic cluster, also falls secular values, regardless of the proportion of within the Communist superzone that dominated their labor forces in the industrial sector. The it for decades. former Communist societies also rank relatively The influence of colonial ties is apparent in the high on this secularization dimension, despite existence of a Latin American cultural zone. varying degrees of industrialization. Conversely, Former colonial ties also help account for the the historically Roman Catholic societies display existence of an English-speaking zone. All seven relatively traditional values when compared with of the English-speaking societies included in this Confucian or ex-Communist societies with the study show relatively similar cultural character- same proportion of industrial workers. istics. Geographically, they are halfway around The survival/self-expression dimension is the world from each other, but culturally Aus- linked with the rise of a service economy: It tralia and New Zealand are next-door neighbors shows a .73 correlation with the relative size of of Great Britain and Canada. The impact of the service sector, but is unrelated to the relative colonization seems especially strong when rein- size of the industrial sector (r ¼ :03). While forced by massive immigration from the colonial the traditional/secular-rational values dimension society—thus, Spain, Italy, Uruguay, and Ar- and the survival/self-expression values dimen- gentina are all near each other on the border sion reflect industrialization and the rise of post- between Catholic Europe and Latin America: industrial society, respectively, this is only part The populations of Uruguay and Argentina are of the story. Virtually all of the historically largely descended from immigrants from Spain Protestant societies rank higher on the survival/ and Italy. Similarly, Rice and Feldman (1997) self-expression dimension than do all of the his- find strong correlations between the civic values torically Roman Catholic societies, regardless of of various ethnic groups in the United States, the extent to which their labor forces are en- and the values prevailing in their countries of gaged in the service sector. Conversely, virtually origin—two or three generations after their all of the former Communist societies rank families migrated to the United States. low on the survival/self-expression dimension. Figure 3.3 indicates that the United States is Changes in GNP and occupational structure not a prototype of cultural modernization for have important influences on prevailing world- other societies to follow, as some moderniza- views, but traditional cultural influences persist. tion writers of the postwar era naively assumed. Religious traditions appear to have had an In fact, the United States is a deviant case, enduring impact on the contemporary value sys- having a much more traditional value system Chapter 3 174

than any other advanced industrial society. On self-expression values. The percentage of the the traditional/secular-rational dimension, the labor force in the industrial sector seems to in- United States ranks far below other rich soci- fluence traditional/secular-rational values even eties, with levels of religiosity and national pride more consistently than does GDP per capita, comparable to those found in developing soci- showing a significant impact in seven of the eight eties. The phenomenon of American exception- regressions. The percentage of the labor force in alism has been discussed by Lipset (1990, 1996). the service sector has a significant impact in six Baker (1999), and others; our results support of the eight regressions predicting survival/self- their argument. The United States does rank expression. . . . among the most advanced societies along the The impact of a society’s historical-cultural survival/self-expression dimension, but even heritage persists when we control for GDP per here, it does not lead the world, as the Swedes capita and the structure of the labor force. Thus, and the Dutch seem closer to the cutting edge of the ex-Communist dummy variable shows a cultural change than do the Americans. . . . strong and statistically significant impact on Modernization theory implies that as societies traditional/secular-rational values, controlling develop economically, their cultures tend to shift for economic development. The secularizing ef- in a predictable direction, and our data fit the fect of Communism is even greater than that of implications of this prediction. Economic dif- the relative size of the industrial sector and ferences are linked with large and pervasive cul- almost as great as that for GDP per capita. tural di¤erences (see figure 3.4). Nevertheless, we The ex-Communist dummy variable also has a find clear evidence of the influence of long- strong significant ( p <:001) negative impact established cultural zones. Using data from the on survival/self-expression values. Similarly, the latest available survey for each society, we cre- Protestant Europe dummy variable has strong ated dummy variables to reflect whether a given and significant impacts on both of the major society is predominantly English-speaking, ex- cultural dimensions. English-speaking culture Communist, and so on for each of the clusters has a strong and significant impact on the outlined in figure 3.3. Empirical analysis of these traditional/secular-rational dimension: Control- variables shows that the cultural locations of ling for level of development, it is linked with a given societies are far from random. . . . Eight relatively traditional outlook. But although the of the nine zones outlined on figure 3.3 show English-speaking societies are clustered near the statistically significant relationships with at right-hand pole of the survival/self-expression least one of the two major dimensions of cross- dimension, this tendency disappears when we cultural variation. . . . control for the fact that they are relatively Do these cultural clusters simply reflect eco- wealthy and have a high percentage of the work nomic di¤erences? For example, do the societies force in the service sector. All but one of the of Protestant Europe have similar values simply dummy variables for cultural zones . . . show a because they are rich? The answer is no. . . . [A] statistically significant impact on at least one of society’s Catholic or Protestant or Confucian or the two dimensions. . . . Communist heritage makes an independent con- When we combine the clusters shown in figure tribution to its position on the global cultural 3.3 into broader cultural zones with large sample map. The influence of economic development is sizes, we generate variables having even greater pervasive. GDP per capita shows a significant explanatory power. . . . impact in five of the eight multiple regressions To illustrate the coherence of these clusters, we predicting traditional/secular-rational values, examine one of the key variables in the literature and in all of the regressions predicting survival/ on cross-cultural di¤erences—interpersonal trust Democracy, Culture, and Society 175

(one component of the survival/self-expression has important long-term consequences for in- dimension). Coleman (1990), Almond and Verba terpersonal trust. Clearly, these cross-cultural (1963), Putnam (1993), and Fukuyama (1995) di¤erences do not reflect the contemporary in- argue that interpersonal trust is essential for fluence of the respective churches. The Catholic building the social structures on which democ- church has changed a great deal in recent de- racy depends and for creating the complex social cades, and in many countries, especially Prot- organizations on which large-scale economic estant ones, church attendance has dwindled to enterprises are based. Figure 3.5 demonstrates the point where only a small minority of the that most historically Protestant societies rank population attends church regularly. While the higher on interpersonal trust than do most his- majority of individuals have little or no contact torically Catholic societies. This holds true even with the church today, the impact of living in a after controlling for levels of economic develop- society that was historically shaped by once- ment: Interpersonal trust is significantly corre- powerful Catholic or Protestant institutions lated with a society’s level of GDP per capita persists today, shaping everyone—Protestant, (r ¼ :60), but even rich Catholic societies rank Catholic, or other—to fit into a given national lower than equally prosperous historically Prot- culture. estant societies. A heritage of Communist rule The individual-level data provide additional also has an impact on interpersonal trust, with insights concerning the transmission of religious virtually all ex-Communist societies ranking rel- traditions today. There are two main possibil- atively low (in italic type in figure 3.5): thus, the ities: (1) that contemporary religious institu- historically Protestant societies that had experi- tions instill distinctively Protestant, Catholic, or enced Communist rule (e.g., East Germany and Islamic values in their respective followers within Latvia) show relatively low levels of interper- each society; or (2) that given religious traditions sonal trust. Of the 19 societies in which more have historically shaped the national culture of than 35 percent of the public believe that most given societies, but that today their impact is people can be trusted, 14 are historically Protes- transmitted mainly through nationwide institu- tant, three are Confucian-influenced, one (India) tions, to the population of that society as a is predominantly Hindu, and only one (Ireland) whole—even to those who have little or no con- is historically Catholic. Of the 10 societies rank- tact with religious institutions. As figure 3.6 ing lowest on trust in figure 3.5, 8 are historically indicates, the empirical evidence clearly supports Catholic and none is historically Protestant. the latter interpretation. Although historically Within given societies, Catholics rank about Catholic or Protestant or Islamic societies show as high on interpersonal trust as do Protes- distinctive values, the di¤erences between Cath- tants. The shared historical experience of given olics and Protestants or Muslims within given nations, not individual personality, is crucial. societies are relatively small. In Germany, for As Putnam (1993) argues, horizontal, locally example, the basic values of German Catholics controlled organizations are conducive to inter- resemble those of German Protestants more than personal trust, whereas rule by large, hierarchi- they resemble Catholics in other countries. This cal, centralized bureaucracies seems to corrode is true in the United States, Switzerland, The interpersonal trust. Historically, the Roman Netherlands, and other religiously mixed soci- Catholic Church was the prototype of a hierar- eties: Catholics tend to be slightly more tradi- chical, centrally controlled institution; Protestant tional than their Protestant compatriots, but they churches were relatively decentralized and more do not fall into the historically Catholic cultural open to local control. The contrast between local zone. Rather surprisingly, this also holds true of control and domination by a remote hierarchy the di¤erences between Hindus and Muslims in Chapter 3 176

Figure 3.5 Locations of 65 societies on dimensions of interpersonal trust and economic development, by cultural/religious tradition. Note: GNP per capita is measured by World Bank purchasing power parity estimates in 1995 U.S. dollars. Trust is correlated with GNP per capita at r ¼ :60 (p <:001). Democracy, Culture, and Society 177

Figure 3.6 Di¤erences between the religious groups within religiously mixed societies on two dimensions of cross-cultural variation. Chapter 3 178

India, and between Christians and Muslims in distinct to a remarkable degree. Identifying the Nigeria: The basic values of Nigerian Muslims specific mechanisms through which these path- are closer to those of their Christian compatriots dependent developments have occurred would than they are to those of Indian Muslims. On require detailed historical analyses that we will questions that directly evoked Islamic or Chris- not attempt here, but survey evidence from soci- tian identity, this would probably not hold true; eties around the world supports this conclusion. but on these two dimensions of basic values More detailed regression analyses that control as measured in the World Values Surveys, the for the structure of the work force and simulta- cross-national di¤erences dwarf within-nation neously test the impact of various cultural zones, di¤erences. provide additional support for the conclusion Protestant or Catholic societies display dis- that a society’s value system is systematically tinctive values today mainly because of the his- influenced by economic development—but that torical impact their respective churches had on a Protestant or Catholic or Confucian or ex- their societies, rather than through their con- Communist heritage also exerts a persistent and temporary influence. For this reason, we classify pervasive influence on contemporary values and Germany, Switzerland, and The Netherlands as beliefs. . . . historically Protestant societies—historically, Protestantism shaped them, even though today (as a result of immigration, relatively low Prot- Conclusion estant birth rates, and higher Protestant rates of secularization) they may have more practicing Evidence from the World Values Surveys dem- Catholics than practicing Protestants. onstrates both massive cultural change and the These findings suggest that, once established, persistence of distinctive traditional values. Eco- the cross-cultural di¤erences linked with religion nomic development is associated with pervasive, have become part of a national culture that is and to some extent predictable, cultural changes. transmitted by the educational institutions and Industrialization promotes a shift from tradi- mass media of given societies to the people of tional to secular-rational values, while the rise of that nation. Despite globalization, the nation re- postindustrial society brings a shift toward more mains a key unit of shared experience, and its trust, tolerance, well-being, and postmaterialist educational and cultural institutions shape the values. Economic collapse tends to propel soci- values of almost everyone in that society. eties in the opposite direction. If economic de- The persistence of distinctive value systems velopment continues, we expect a continued suggests that culture is path-dependent. Protes- decline of institutionalized religion. The influ- tant religious institutions gave rise to the Protes- ence of traditional value systems is unlikely to tant Ethic, relatively high interpersonal trust, disappear, however, as belief systems exhibit re- and a relatively high degree of social pluralism— markable durability and resilience. Empirical all of which may have contributed to earlier evidence from 65 societies indicates that values economic development in Protestant countries can and do change, but also that they continue than in the rest of the world. Subsequently, the to reflect a society’s cultural heritage. fact that Protestant societies were (and still are) Modernization theorists are partly right. The relatively prosperous has probably shaped them rise of industrial society is linked with coherent in distinctive ways. Although they have experi- cultural shifts away from traditional value sys- enced rapid social and cultural change, histori- tems, and the rise of postindustrial society is cally Protestant and Catholic (and Confucian, linked with a shift away from absolute norms Islamic, Orthodox, and other) societies remain and values toward a syndrome of increasingly Democracy, Culture, and Society 179

rational, tolerant, trusting, postindustrial values. attend church in Protestant Europe today, his- But values seem to be path dependent: A history torically Protestant societies remain distinctive of Protestant or Orthodox or Islamic or Con- across a wide range of values and attitudes. The fucian traditions gives rise to cultural zones with same is true for historically Roman Catholic distinctive value systems that persist after con- societies, for historically Islamic or Orthodox trolling for the e¤ects of economic development. societies, and for historically Confucian societies. Economic development tends to push societies in Fourth, it is misleading to view cultural a common direction, but rather than converging, change as ‘‘Americanization.’’ Industrializing they seem to move on parallel trajectories shaped societies in general are not becoming like the by their cultural heritages. We doubt that the United States. In fact, the United States seems to forces of modernization will produce a homo- be a deviant case, as many observers of Ameri- genized world culture in the foreseeable future. can life have argued (Lipset 1990, 1996)—its We propose several modifications of modern- people hold much more traditional values and ization theory. First, modernization does not beliefs than do those in any other equally pros- follow a linear path. The rise of the service sector perous society (Baker 1999). If any societies ex- and the transition to a knowledge society are emplify the cutting edge of cultural change, it linked with a di¤erent set of cultural changes would be the Nordic countries. from those that characterized industrialization. Finally, modernization is probabilistic, not Moreover, protracted economic collapse can re- deterministic. Economic development tends to verse the e¤ects of modernization, resulting in a transform a given society in a predictable direc- return to traditional values, as seems to be hap- tion, but the process and path are not inevitable. pening in the former Soviet Union. Many factors are involved, so any prediction Second, the secularization thesis is over- must be contingent on the historical and cultural simplified. Our evidence suggests that it applies context of the society in question. mainly to the industrialization phase—the shift Nevertheless, the central prediction of mod- from agrarian society to industrial society that ernization theory finds broad support: Economic was completed some time ago in most advanced development is associated with major changes in industrial societies. This shift was linked with prevailing values and beliefs: The worldviews of major declines in the role of the church, which rich societies di¤er markedly from those of poor led Marx and others to assume that, in the long societies. This does not necessarily imply cultural run, religious beliefs would die out. The shift convergence, but it does predict the general di- from agrarian to urban industrial society reduces rection of cultural change and (in so far as the the importance of organized religion, but this is process is based on intergenerational population counterbalanced by growing concerns for the replacement) even gives some idea of the rate at meaning and purpose of life. Religious beliefs which such change is likely to occur. persist, and spiritual concerns, broadly defined, are becoming more widespread in advanced in- dustrial societies. References Third, cultural change seems to be path de- pendent. Economic development tends to bring Almond, Gabriel and Sidney Verba. 1963. The Civic pervasive cultural changes, but the fact that a Culture. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press. society was historically shaped by Protestantism Baker, Wayne E. 1999. North Star Falling: The Amer- or Confucianism or Islam leaves a cultural heri- ican Crisis of Values at the New Millennium. School of tage with enduring e¤ects that influence sub- Business, University of Michigan, Ann Arbor, MI. Unpublished manuscript. sequent development. Even though few people Chapter 3 180

Bell, Daniel. 1973. The Coming of Post-Industrial So- Putnam, Robert. 1993. Making Democracy Work: ciety. New York: Basic Books. Civic Traditions in Modern Italy. Princeton NJ: ———. 1976. The Cultural Contradictions of Capital- Princeton University Press. ism. New York: Basic Books. Rice, Tom W. and Jan L. Feldman. 1997. ‘‘Civic Cul- Bernstein, Mary. 1997. ‘‘Celebration and Suppression: ture and Democracy from Europe America.’’ Journal The Strategic Uses of Identity by the Lesbian and of Politics 59: 1143–72. Gay Movement.’’ American Journal of Sociology 103: Rokeach, Milton. 1968. Beliefs, Attitudes, and Values. 531–565. San Francisco: Jossey-Bass. Coleman, James S. 1990. Foundations of Social Theory. Rokeach, Milton. 1973. The Nature of Human Values. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press. New York: Free Press. Dahrendorf, Ralf. 1959. Class and Class Conflict in Schuman, Howard and Jacqueline Scott. 1989. ‘‘Gen- Industrial Society. Stanford, CA: Stanford University erations and Collective Memories. American Sociolog- Press. ical Review 54: 359–81. DiMaggio, Paul. 1994. ‘‘Culture and Economy.’’ Pp. Smith, Tom. 1999. ‘‘Church Attendance Declining in 27–57 in The Handbook of Economic Sociology, edited the U.S.’’ National Opinion Center press release, June by N. J. Smelser and R. Swedberg. Princeton, NJ: 8, 1999. Princeton University Press. Spier, Fred. 1996. The Structure of Big History: From Fukuyama, Francis. 1995. Trust: The Social Virtues the Big Bang until Today. Amsterdam, Holland: and the Creation of Prosperity. New York: Free Press. Amsterdam University Press. Guille´n, Mauro. 1994. Models of Management: Work, Stokes, Randall G. and Susan Marshall. 1981. ‘‘Tradi- Authority, and Organization in a Comparative Perspec- tion and the Veil: Female Status in Tunisia and Alge- tive. Chicago, IL: University of Chicago Press. ria.’’ Journal of Modern African Studies 19: 625–46. Hamilton, Gary G. 1994. ‘‘Civilizations and Organi- U.S. Census Bureau. 1996. World Population Profile: zation of Economies.’’ Pp. 183–205 in The Handbook 1996. Washington, DC: U.S. Census Bureau. of Economic Sociology, edited by N. J. Smelser and R. Wallerstein, Immanuel. 1974. The Modern World Sys- Swedberg. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press. tem. Vol. 1. New York: Academic Press. Huntington, Samuel P. 1993. ‘‘The Clash of Civiliza- ———. 1976. ‘‘Modernization: Requiescat in Pace.’’ tions?’’ Foreign A¤airs 72(3): 22–49. Pp. 131–135 in The Uses of Controversy in Sociology, ———. 1996. The Clash of Civilizations and the edited by L. A. Coser and O. N. Larsen. New York: Remaking of World Order. New York: Simon and Free Press. Schuster. Watson, James, ed. 1998. Golden Arches East: McDon- Inglehart, Ronald. 1977. The Silent Revolution: ald’s in East Asia. Stanford, CA: Stanford University Changing Values and Political Styles in Advanced In- Press. dustrial Society. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Weber, Max. [1904] 1958. The Protestant Ethnic and Press. the Spirit of Capitalism. Translated by T. Parsons. Re- ———. 1990. Culture Shift in Advanced Industrial So- print, New York: Charles Scribner’s Sons. ciety. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press. Weiner, Myron, ed. 1966. Modernization: The Dynam- ———. 1997. Modernization and Postmodernization: ics of Growth. New York: Basic. Cultural, Economic, and Political Change in 43 Soci- Williams, Rhys H., ed. 1997. Cultural Wars in Ameri- eties. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press. can Politics. New York: Aldine de Gruyter. Lipset, Seymour Martin. 1990. ‘‘American Exception- World Bank. 1997. World Development Report. New alism Rea‰rmed.’’ Toqueville Review 10: 23–45. York: Oxford University Press. ———. 1996. American Exceptionalism. New York: Wuthnow, Robert. 1998. After Heaven: Spirituality in Norton. America Since the 1950s. Berkeley, CA: University of McMichael, Philip. 1996. ‘‘Globalization: Myths and California Press. Realities.’’ Rural Sociology 61: 25–56. Culture and Democracy

Adam Przeworski, Jose´ Antonio Cheibub, and Fernando Limongi

Our general conclusion is sceptical. We think Democracy and a ‘‘Democratic Culture’’ that economic and institutional factors are su‰- cient to generate a convincing explanation of the Does democracy have to rely on a ‘‘democratic dynamic of democracies without any recourse to culture’’ in order to exist and endure? And, if culture. And we find empirically that at least so, are particular cultural patterns either more the most obvious cultural traits, such as the or less compatible with such a ‘‘democratic cul- dominant religion, have little relevance for the ture’’ and accordingly conductive or counter to emergence and durability of democracies. Hence, democracy? while there may be good reasons one should ex- In one view, i.e. ‘‘non-culturalist,’’ culture pect cultures to matter, the available empirical exerts no causal power with regard to democ- evidence provides little support for the view that racy. No democratic culture is needed for a democracy requires a democratic culture. country to establish democratic institutions and We begin with a brief history of culturalist none to sustain them. In the ‘‘weakly culturalist’’ views and then analyse them more systemati- view, a democratic culture is required for de- cally. The question here is whether democracy mocracy to emerge or to endure, but the ques- can emerge and endure only if it is supported by tion of the compatibility of this democratic some definite cultural patterns. Are some specific culture with the traditions of particular societies aspects of culture necessary for democracy and, is moot, since these traditions are malleable, if so, which and how? We also develop an ex- subject to being invented and reinvented. Thus, planation that does not rely on culture and show the democratic culture can flourish even in those that this explanation is supported by some facts. cultural settings that appear hostile to it. Finally, Later, we ask whether particular cultures can be in the ‘‘strongly culturalist’’ view, some cultures assessed to be more or less compatible with de- are simply incompatible with democracy. Di¤er- mocracy and then examine empirically whether ent countries, therefore, must seek di¤erent po- these cultures, crudely identified in terms of litical arrangements. dominant national religions, a¤ect the emer- What is thus at stake is whether democratic gence and the survival of democratic regimes. A institutions can function in all cultural environ- discussion of some normative issues closes the ments or whether we must accept that some cul- chapter. . . . tures are compatible only with various forms of authoritarianism. What Is It about Culture That Matters, and This is a hard question to answer. It is subject How? to strongly held conflicting beliefs and the evi- dence required to adjudicate between them is . . . [T]he view that democracy requires a definite di‰cult to come by. All we can do is to recon- cultural basis has many lives. Something about struct these rival views and to cite some facts. culture seems necessary for democracy to emerge or endure. But what? Montesquieu thought it Excerpted from: Adam Przeworski, Jose´ Antonio was an irrational motive force (‘‘les passions Cheibub, and Fernando Limongi, ‘‘Culture and De- humaines qui le font mouvoir,’’ EL, III, 1)— mocracy.’’ World Culture Report: Culture, Creativity, fear; honour, virtue—which, in turn, reflect reli- and Markets. Paris: UNESCO Publishing, 1998. 6 UNESCO 1998. Reproduced by permission of gions, mores and manners. Stage theorists UNESCO. looked for feelings, habits, as well as for a ratio- Chapter 3 182

nal sense of public utility. Mill was more sys- mocracy, they must specify what it is about tematic, distinguishing between a preference for culture that matters and how. Let us first dis- democracy, the temperamental characteristics tinguish di¤erent aspects of culture that may necessary to sustain it and a sense of community. matter.4 Almond and Verba looked at beliefs, a¤ects and First, people value democracy per se, regard- evaluations of the political process and political less of the outcomes it generates. . . . They believe outcomes. Inglehart wanted to know whether that democracy is unconditionally the best (or people are satisfied with their lives, whether they the least bad) system of government, they say so trust each other, and whether they like revolu- when asked, or act as if they so believed. tionary changes. Other survey researchers in- Second, people see it as their duty to obey quired whether people value democracy per se, outcomes resulting from rules to which they regardless of the conditions with which it has to ‘‘agreed.’’5 We put ‘‘agree’’ in quotation marks, cope and the outcomes it generates. since the agreement in question can be putative: This ambiguity, and the confusions it engen- people would have chosen these rules had they ders, are most apparent in Weingast’s (1997) at- been consulted. Democracy is then legitimate in tempt to reconcile apparently rival explanations the sense that people are ready to accept deci- of democratic stability. Weingast set himself to sions of as yet undetermined content, as long as demonstrate that for democracy to be stable, these decisions result from applying the rules. citizens must adopt a shared view of what con- Even if they do not like them, people comply stitutes illegitimate actions by the state and must with the outcomes of the democratic interplay be prepared to act against the transgressions of these limits were they to occur. . . . 4. A new fashion among game theorists is to interpret What, then, is the role of culture in sup- culture as ‘‘out-of-equilibrium’’ beliefs: beliefs about porting this democratic equilibrium? Weingast what would happen if something that never happens (p. 253) is careful to emphasize that his is not a actually transpired. Suppose the bourgeoisie is consid- causal story, in which values would make de- ering whether to accede to workers’ demands or to turn mocracy stable, nor the reverse. A particular to the military with the request to suppress them. The culture and democratic stability are just di¤erent bourgeoisie believes that the military would not sup- press and, therefore, accedes to workers’ demands. aspects of situations in which a society resolves Hence, the belief that the military is non-political, its co-ordination dilemmas. But what exactly are an out-of-equilibrium belief, underlies democratic the aspects of culture that support these situa- stability. Or suppose that workers believe that the tions? At the first level, two are prominent: a military would suppress them if requested to do so by consensus about the limits of legitimate state the bourgeoisie: then the bourgeoisie, knowing that actions and a common sense of ‘‘duty’’ to defend workers would moderate their demands out of the fear it.3 ... of military intervention, would not turn to the military. Yet if culturalist views are to furnish a com- Now it is workers’ out-of-equilibrium belief that the pelling explanation of the origins and life of de- military are prone to intervention that supports de- mocracy. The problem with such explanations is that while equilibrium beliefs can be based on observations 3. Weingast assumes implicitly that the state is a po- of past events, and can be thus updated rationally, out- tential threat to everyone: the possibility of a stable al- of-equilibrium beliefs are completely arbitrary. Hence, liance between the state and particular classes is ruled ‘culture’ becomes just a name for the black box of out. As a result, he misinterprets his own conclusions beliefs. This does not seem to us a fruitful line of when he says that citizens act out of a sense of ‘‘duty’’ investigation. when they oppose the state. What kind of ‘‘duty’’ is it 5. On the di‰culties of this conception as a positive that is driven only by self-interest? theory of action, see Dunn (1996, Chap. 4). Democracy, Culture, and Society 183

because they result from applying rules they ac- mocracy about and others in making it last, any cept. . . . ‘‘Participatory culture’’ is then the key or all of them may be necessary for people to to democratic stability. struggle for democracy when they live under Third, people have values and perhaps tem- dictatorship and to support it actively once it is peramental characteristics (‘‘democratic person- established. But if culturalist views are to have ality,’’ in the language of the 1950s) that support an explanatory power, they must distinguish and it. . . . These characteristics may include ‘republi- specify. Otherwise, it will never be possible to can virtue’, trust,6 empathy, tolerance, modera- conclude that culture does not matter. tion, or patience. People may love the collectivity The second issue concerns causality. For even above themselves; they may trust that the gov- if all the enduring democracies were found to ernment will not take an unfair advantage of share a definite ‘‘democratic culture,’’ this ob- them even if it is in the hands of their adversa- servation would not be su‰cient to determine ries; they may be ready to respect the validity of which, if either, comes first: democratic culture views and interests di¤erent from theirs; they or democratic institutions. At the risk of being may be willing to accept that others should also pedantic, we need to distinguish causal chains have rights; or they may be willing to wait for that may connect economic development, cul- their turn. tural transformations, and political institutions. Fourth, what may matter for democracy to be First, culture causes both development and possible is not so much what people share but democracy, whatever the causal connection be- that they do: ‘‘consensus.’’7 . . . Unless people tween the latter two elements. This is what we share basic characteristics, such as language, re- mean by a ‘‘strongly culturalist’’ view. . . . ligion, or ethnicity, they do not have enough in Second, both development and culture are common to sustain democracy. But homogeneity needed independently for democracy to be pos- with regard to such basic characteristics is not sible. And even if development generates some su‰cient: ‘‘agreement’’ about some basic values, cultural transformations, these transformations rules of the game, or what not is required for are not su‰cient to generate the democratic democracy to function (Dahl 1956; Lipset 1959; culture, which is, in turn, necessary for democ- Eckstein 1961).8 ... racy to emerge and survive. This was the view Clearly, these cultural underpinnings of de- of Almond and Verba, discussed above, still a mocracy need not be mutually exclusive. Even if strongly culturalist view. some may be more important in bringing de- Third, a particular culture is necessary for democracy to be possible, but this culture is 6. Trust is the recent fashion of democratic theorists. automatically generated by economic develop- But one might wonder if democratic citizens should ment. . . . Clearly, in this view cultures, in plural, trust their governments too much: should they not, in- are su‰ciently malleable to become ‘‘modern- stead, monitor what governments are doing and sanc- ized’’ along with other aspects of societies as an tion them appropriately? e¤ect of economic development. Thus, the causal 7. Such a consensus may be ‘‘overlapping’’ (Rawls, chain goes from development, through culture, 1993) in the sense that the reasons people accept the to democracy. This is a ‘‘weakly culturalist’’ particular institutional framework may be di¤erent view. among groups holding di¤erent ‘‘fundamental’’ values. Fourth, a particular culture is necessary for 8. Eckstein (1961), as well as Eckstein and Gurr democracy to endure but this culture emerges as (1975), are among those who claim that democratic an e¤ect of democratic institutions once they are politics also require democratic value to permeate less in place. . . . In this view, we should expect all inclusive social units such as families, communities or workplaces. For a contrary view, see Linz (1996). enduring democracies to have the same political Chapter 3 184

culture, and for such culture to emerge as a con- Examine now some empirical patterns con- sequence of democratic institutions and support cerning almost all democracies that existed at them in turn. any time between 1950 and 1990.12 Fifth, in the non-culturalist view, democracy The most striking fact is that no democracy emerges and endures independently of culture. ever fell, during the period under our scrutiny, Democracy may or may not generate cultural regardless of everything else, in a country with a homogeneity but culture has no causal impact on per capita income higher than that of Argentina the durability of democratic institutions. in 1976. Given the paucity of data about culture, the The probability that democracy survives first three explanations cannot be tested sys- increases monotonically with per capita in- tematically for a large number of countries. come. . . . However, the non-culturalist explanations can Several other factors a¤ect the survival of indeed be. democracies but they all pale in comparison with per capita income. Two are particularly relevant A Non-Culturalist Explanation for the rational choice perspective. First, it turns out that democracies are more likely to endure The non-culturalist view is strongly supported by when no party controls a large share of legisla- evidence. In this view, democracy persists be- tive seats, i.e. more than two-thirds. Secondly, cause the relevant political forces are better o¤, democracies are most stable when the heads of in terms of pure self-interest, complying with its governments change every so often, more fre- verdicts rather than doing anything else. Even quently than once in five but less frequently than if the losers in the democratic competition would once in two years. These two observations—and be better o¤ in the short run rebelling rather than both are statistically justified in multivariate accepting the outcome of the current round, analyses—add up to the second fact: democracy they face su‰ciently large benefits in the future is more likely to survive when no political force rounds and a su‰cient chance to win and are dominates completely and permanently. When therefore better o¤ continuing to comply with one party has unchecked control over the legis- the democratic verdicts. Similarly for the win- lature or when chief executives stay in o‰ce for a ners. Democracy is then an equilibrium because long time, democracies are less stable. the conflicting political forces find it in their best Finally, the instances in which democracies interest to comply with its verdicts (Przeworski, were subverted follow the pattern predicted by 1991, Chap. 1).10 ... the model: poor democracies (those under $1,000 per capita income) are overthrown by incum- 10. For a technical reader, we need to raise a caveat. bents as well as by those out of power, democ- In most situations, there are several equilibria. One is racies in countries with incomes between $1,000 ‘‘war’’: the winner expects the loser to rebel, the loser and $6,000 are much more likely to be subverted expects the winner not to hold elections, and they fight it out. Another is dictatorship without a war: the dic- 12. All the statistical results presented here are based tator does not put down so much as provoke the op- on Przeworski et al. (in preparation). Published results position and the opposition finds that it is better o¤ include Przeworski et al. (1996) and Przeworski and acquiescing to the dictatorship than fighting. Thus, a Limongi (1997). The data cover 135 countries and a democratic equilibrium, if one exists, is just one of total of 4,126 years. Among them, there were 100 several, which means that Weingast (1997) is correct to democracies which together lasted 1,645 years. All the emphasize the importance of co-ordination. Yet if the income figures are expressed in 1985 purchasing power choice of equilibrium depends on economic develop- parity United States dollars. ment, then culture plays no role in this choice. Democracy, Culture, and Society 185

by outsiders, and wealthy democracies are not causes the ‘‘market culture’’ to emerge, and so overthrown by anyone.14 ... forth. Hence, we stop here. Finally, we find no evidence of habituation to democracy. The fact that a democracy has been around does not increase its chances of remain- Cultures, the Democratic Culture, and ing around. . . . [E]ven if habituation to democ- Democracy racy generates a democratic culture, it is wealth that keeps democracies going, not culture. Are particular, otherwise identifiable cultures, As a glance at table 3.1 indicates, economic conducive or detrimental to the rise and dura- factors do not have an equally strong e¤ect on bility of democratic institutions? The question is the survival of dictatorships and thus on tran- the following: Suppose we were to observe that, sitions to democracy. The probability that a de- independently of their wealth and other factors, mocracy is established increases as countries all countries with a high proportion of Protes- become wealthier but then declines again once tants are democracies and no countries with a they become wealthy enough. Economic crises low proportion of Protestants are. We would have a weaker e¤ect on the survival of dictator- then have prima facie evidence that, whatever ships. Indeed, statistical analyses indicate that the ‘‘democratic culture’’ is, Protestantism fur- transitions to democracy are almost impossible nishes its necessary ingredients. But note that if to predict, even with the entire panopticum of we fail to find such patterns, it may be for two observable factors, economic or cultural. Dicta- distinct reasons: either because the rise and du- torships just seem to run many risks and to die rability of democracy need not call for a partic- for a broad variety of reasons. . . . ular set of cultural patterns or because, while Hence, the evidence in favour of economic democracy does have cultural requisites and cul- factors is overwhelming. No recourse to culture tural barriers, all cultures are, or at least can be is necessary to reproduce the actually observed made, compatible with these patterns. patterns of regime dynamics. True, one could We first discuss the issue of compatibility of still defend the culturalist view by claiming that particular cultures, in plural, with the demo- some culture, say ‘‘market culture,’’ is what cratic culture. Then we examine some empirical causes development in the first place and that the patterns. ultimate explanation is thus still cultural. That may well be, but this line of inquiry leads to in- Cultures and the Democratic Culture finite regress, since one could ask in turn what Historically, the discussion of this topic revolved 14. Transitions to dictatorship are coded di¤erently in mainly around cultures identified by dominant table 3.4 and in table 3.3. In table 3.3, regimes in which religions. . . . the incumbents perpetuated an autogolpe at any time There are several reasons to doubt that cul- during their tenure in o‰ce are classified as dictator- tures, or civilizations, as Mazrui (1997, p. 118) ships throughout. In table 3.2, such regimes are classi- prefers to think of Islam, furnish requisites for or fied as democracies until the autogolpe occurred. constitute irremovable barriers to democracy. Hence, the transitions in table 3.4 include all those in First, the arguments relating civilizations to de- table 3.3 plus the transitions by incumbents. For details mocracy appear terribly ex-post: if many coun- see Alvarez et al. (1996). Note that what we observe tries dominated by Protestants are democratic, are the outcomes of conflicts rather than their initia- we look for features of Protestantism that pro- tion: hence, an inference is entailed in interpreting these results. mote democracy; if no Muslim countries are Chapter 3 186

Table 3.1 Observed rates of transitions (by lagged per capita income and lagged rate of economic growth) All Dictatorships Democracies Level growth PJK TJK N PAD TAD N PDA TDA N

1000 0.0147 15 1019 0.0063 6 945 0.1216 9 74 G U 0 0.0193 9 467 0.0091 4 440 0.1852 5 27 G > 0 0.0109 6 552 0.0040 2 505 0.0851 4 47 1001–2000 0.0321 32 997 0.0242 18 745 0.0556 14 252 G U 0 0.0447 14 313 0.0313 7 224 0.0787 7 89 G > 0 0.0263 18 684 0.0211 11 521 0.0429 7 163 2001–3000 0.0325 16 493 0.0261 8 306 0.0428 8 187 G U 0 0.0522 7 134 0.0341 3 88 0.0870 4 46 G > 0 0.0251 9 359 0.0229 5 218 0.0284 4 141 3001–4000 0.0201 7 349 0.0146 3 205 0.0278 4 144 G U 0 0.0303 3 99 0.0172 1 58 0.0488 2 41 G > 0 0.0160 4 250 0.0136 2 147 0.0194 2 103 4001–5000 0.0339 8 236 0.0469 6 128 0.0185 2 108 G U 0 0.0500 3 60 0.0588 2 34 0.0385 1 26 G > 0 0.0284 5 176 0.0426 4 94 0.0122 1 82 5001–6000 0.0308 6 195 0.0595 5 84 0.0090 1 111 G U 0 0.0541 2 37 0.0952 2 21 0.0000 0 16 G > 0 0.0253 4 158 0.0476 3 63 0.0105 1 95 6001–7000 0.0190 3 158 0.0606 2 33 0.0080 1 125 G U 0 0.0857 3 35 0.3333 2 6 0.0345 1 29 G > 0 0.0000 0 123 0.0000 0 27 0.0000 0 96 7001– 0.0015 1 679 0.0286 1 35 0.0000 0 644 G U 0 0.0000 0 120 0.0000 0 3 0.0000 0 117 G > 0 0.0018 1 559 0.0313 1 32 0.0000 0 527 Total 0.0213 88 4126 0.0198 49 2481 0.0237 39 1645 G U 0 0.0324 41 1265 0.0240 21 874 0.0512 20 391 G > 0 0.0164 47 2861 0.0174 28 1607 0.0152 19 1254 Key: ‘‘Level’’ stands for per capita income, in 1985 purchasing power parity US$. PJK is the probability of tran- sitions, TJK is their total number, N is the number of annual observations, PAD is the probability of transitions from authoritarianism to democracy and TAD their number, PDA is the probability of transitions from democracy to authoritarianism and TDA their number. Democracy, Culture, and Society 187

Table 3.2 that these traditions are quite flexible with regard Cases when democracy was overthrown (by per capita to the political arrangements with which they income and the perpetuators) can be made compatible. Number of transitions Finally, and most importantly, traditions are not given once and for all: they are continu- By Not by ally invented and reinvented (Hobsbawm and Income Total incumbents incumbents Ranger, 1983), a point stressed by Eickelman 1000 17 10 7 and Piscatori (1996) in their analysis of Islam. In 1001–3000 29 12 17 fact, the very analyses of the Confucian tradition 3001–6055 9 1 8 cited above are best seen as attempts to invent a 6066– 0 0 0 democratic Confucianism. Cultures are made of cloth but the fabric of culture drapes di¤erently Total 55 23 32 in the hands of di¤erent tailors. . . .

Empirical Evidence democratic, obviously there must be something about Islam that is anti-democratic. Eisenstadt What, then, is the empirical evidence concerning (1968), for example, finds that the Indian civili- the impact of religions on the dynamic of politi- zation has what it takes but Confucianism and cal regimes? Protestants, and Catholics, are more Islam do not, and one wonders what he would frequent in democracies; Moslems and others in have found if China were democratic and India dictatorships. But this prima facie observation not.16 does not su‰ce to establish a causal link. . . . Secondly, one can find elements in every cul- Hence, to test the importance of religions for ture, Protestantism included, that appear com- regime dynamics, we calculated the impact of patible and others that seem incompatible with di¤erent variables on the probabilities that de- democracy. Protestant legitimation of economic mocracy will be established and that it will col- inequality, not to speak of the very ethic of self- lapse. We considered first the three variables that interest, o¤er a poor moral basis for living to- made our non-cultural model: per capita income, gether and resolving conflicts in a peaceful way. its rate of growth, and the rate of turnover of Other cultures are authoritarian but egalitarian, heads of government accumulated during the hierarchical but respectful of the right of rebel- life of the regime.18 As table 3.3 shows, all lion, communal but tolerant of diversity, and so these variables are statistically significant. The forth. So one can pick and choose.17 wealthier a democracy, the less likely it is to col- Thirdly, each of the religious traditions has lapse; while wealthier dictatorships are some- been historically compatible with a broad range what more likely to collapse. Both regimes are of practical political arrangements. This range is much less likely to collapse if their economy not the same for di¤erent religious traditions, grew during the preceding year. Democracies in but broad enough in each case to demonstrate which heads of government change more fre- quently are somewhat more likely to collapse, 16. The ex-post method is even more apparent in cul- while dictatorships are much more likely to die tural analyses of economic growth. See Sen (1997). under such conditions. 17. Thus Nathan and Shi (1993) find elements of democratic culture in China, while Gibson, Duch and 18. The proportion of legislative seats held by the Tedin (1992) discover them in Russia. largest party is not significant in statistical analyses. Chapter 3 188

Table 3.3 Religions and regime transitions: Dynamic probit model

Log-likelihood 355.9044 Restricted (Slopes ¼ 0) Log-L. 2685.421 Chi-squared (13) 4659.033 Significance level 0.0000000 Transitions to dictatorship Transitions to democracy

Variable Coe‰cient t-ratio Prob jtj b x Coe‰cient t-ratio Prob jtj b x Constant 0.53859 5.676 0.00000 2.46014 11.762 0.00000 Income 0.84880E 04 3.935 0.00008 0.102732E 03 1.814 0.06961 Growth 0.16626E 01 2.942 0.00327 0.222413E 01 3.764 0.00017 Turnover 0.17583 1.938 0.05262 0.636220 3.585 0.00034 Catholic 0.83732E 03 0.781 0.43487 0.497148E 02 1.941 0.05221 Protestant 0.84245E 03 0.418 0.67630 0.512016E 02 0.962 0.33593 Muslim 0.18935E 02 1.360 0.17386 0.186515E 02 0.657 0.51107 Frequencies of actual and predicted outcomes. Predicted outcome has maximum probability. Predicted Actual DEM DIC Total DEM 1546 49 1595 DIC 38 2358 2396 Total 1584 2407 3991 Key: Coe‰cients are partial derivatives of the respective probabilities with regard to the variables, evaluated at the mean. DEM represents democracy, and DIC dictatorship.

When added to this non-culturalist model, To test the hypothesis about the impact of the frequency of the three religions for which cultural heterogeneity, we used indices of ethno- we have data—Catholics, Protestants and linguistic and religious fractionalization.19 Eth- Moslems—in the population of each country nolinguistic fractionalization makes democracies has no impact whatever on the durability of less likely to survive: this much confirms com- democracy and only Catholicism has some— negative—impact on the stability of dictator- 19. Fractionalization indices measure the probability ships. Moreover, when other variables are that two randomly chosen individuals do not belong to introduced into the analysis—the colonial leg- the same group. The index of ethnolingistic fractional- acy, religious and ethnic heterogeneity, or the ization is taken from Easterly and Levine (1997; from proportion of countries in the world that are the Web). Their data set also contains indices measur- democracies during the particular year—none of ing the percentage of the population not speaking the the religions matter for anything. o‰cial and the most widely used language. These two indices have no e¤ect on regime stability. Democracy, Culture, and Society 189

Table 3.4 Ethnolinguistic fractionalization and regime transitions: Dynamic probit model

Log-likelihood 306.7057 Restricted (Slopes ¼ 0) Log-L. 2382.604 Chi-squared (13) 4151.797 Significance level 0.0000000 Transitions to dictatorship Transitions to democracy

Variable Coe‰cient t-ratio Prob jtj b x Coe‰cient t-ratio Prob jtj b x Constant 1.4462 5.822 0.00000 2.08905 11.480 0.00000 Income 0.22950E 03 4.090 0.00004 0.11891E 03 1.567 0.11709 Growth 0.43770E 01 2.750 0.00596 0.25457E 01 3.565 0.00036 Turnover 0.53737 2.273 0.02305 0.53882 3.428 0.00061 Elf60 0.90067 2.517 0.01185 0.16581 2.390 0.01684 Newc 0.20553E 01 0.060 0.95183 0.85350 2.106 0.03517 Britcol 0.47802 1.402 0.16103 0.35732 0.303 0.76211 Frequencies of actual and predicted outcomes. Predicted outcome has maximum probability. Predicted Actual DEM DIC Total DEM 1475 43 1518 DIC 36 1924 1960 Total 1511 1967 3478 Key: ELF60 stands for ethnolinguistic fractionalization, as of 1960. NEWC is a dummy variable, indicating that the country was not independent as of 1945. BRITCOL is a dummy variable indicating that it was a British colony. Coe‰cients are partial derivatives of the respective probabilities with regard to the variables, evaluated at the mean. mon wisdom. But, when the colonial legacy of a This is scant evidence, but cultures just do not country is considered, it makes dictatorships less lend themselves to simple classifications. Hence, likely to survive as well. Hence, it seems that the opportunity for statistical analyses is limited. ethnolinguistic heterogeneity just makes political We would have obviously liked to be able to regimes less stable and, indeed, its e¤ects on both classify cultures as hierarchical or egalitarian, regimes vanish when controlled for past political universalistic and particularistic, religious and instability. Thus, the claim that common values secular, consensual or conflictuous, and so on. are needed to support democracy reduces to the But the evidence we do have does not support observation that regime transitions are more fre- the claim that some cultures are incompatible quent in heterogeneous countries. In turn, reli- with democracy. They seem to have little e¤ect gious heterogeneity has no e¤ect on the stability on whether democracy is established and none of either regime. on whether it endures. Chapter 3 190

Sen, A. 1997. Culture and Development: Global Per- References spectives and Constructive Criticism. (Paper prepared for UNESCO’s World Culture Report 1998.) Dahl, R. 1956. A Preface to Democratic Theory. Chi- Weingast, B. R. 1997. Political Foundations of De- cago, University of Chicago Press. mocracy and the Rule of Law. American Political Dunn, J. 1996. The History of Political Theory and Science Review, No. 91, pp. 245–263. Other Essays. Cambridge, Cambridge University Press. Eckstein, H. 1961. A Theory of Stable Democracy. Princeton, New Jersey, Princeton University Center for International Studies. Eckstein, H.; Gurr, T. R. 1975. Patterns of Inquiry: A Structural Basis for Political Inquiry. New York, Wiley. Eickelman, D. F.; Piscatori, J. 1996. Muslim Politics. Princeton, Princeton University Press. Eisenstadt, S. N. 1968. The Protestant Ethic Theses in the Framework of Sociological Theory and Weber’s Work. In: S. N. Eisenstadt (ed.), The Protestant Ethic and Modernization: A Comparative View, pp. 3–45. New York, Basic Books. Gibson, J. L.; Duch, R. M.; Tedin, K. L. 1992. Dem- ocratic Values and the Transformation of the Soviet Union. Journal of Politics, No. 54. Hobsbawm, E.; Ranger, T. (eds.). 1983. The Invention of Tradition. Cambridge, Cambridge University Press. Lipset, S. M. 1959. Some Social Requisites of Democ- racy: Economic Development and Political Legiti- macy. American Political Science Review, No. 53, pp. 69–105. Mazrui, A. A. 1997. Islamic and Western Values. For- eign A¤airs, Vol. 76, No. 5, pp. 118–132. Nathan, A. J.; Shi, T. 1993. Cultural Requisites for Democracy in China: Findings from a Survey. Deda- lus, No. 122. Przeworski, A. 1991. Democracy and the Market. New York, Cambridge University Press. Przeworski, A.; Alvarez, M.; Cheibub, J. A.; Limongi, F. 1996. What Makes Democracy Endure? Journal of Democracy, Vol. 7, No. 1, pp. 39–56. Przeworski, A.; Limongi, F. 1997. Modernization: Theories and Facts. World Politics, No. 49, pp. 155– 184. Rawls, J. 1993. The Domain of the Political and Overlapping Consensus. In: D. Copp, J. Hampton and J. E. Roemer (eds.), The Idea of Democracy. Cam- bridge, Cambridge University Press. 4 DEMOCRACY AND CONSTITUTIONALISM

The Federalist No. 23 Alexander Hamilton

The Federalist No. 47 James Madison

The Federalist No. 48 James Madison

The Federalist No. 62 James Madison

The Federalist No. 70 Alexander Hamilton

The Federalist No. 78 Alexander Hamilton

Madisonian Democracy Robert Dahl

A Bill of Rights for Britain Ronald Dworkin

A Rights-Based Critique of Constitutional Rights Jeremy Waldron

The Political Origins of Judicial Empowerment through Constitutionalization: Lessons from Four Constitutional Revolutions Ran Hirschl

Decision Making in a Democracy: The Supreme Court as a National Policymaker Robert Dahl

Democratic Justice Ian Shapiro The Federalist No. 23

Alexander Hamilton

committed. This power ought to be co-extensive To the People of the State of New York with all the possible combinations of such cir- cumstances; and ought to be under the direction The necessity of a Constitution, at least equally of the same councils which are appointed to energetic with the one proposed, to the preser- preside over the common defence. . . . vation of the Union, is the point at the exami- Every view we may take of the subject, as nation of which we are now arrived. candid inquirers after truth, will serve to con- This inquiry will naturally divide itself into vince us, that it is both unwise and dangerous to three branches—the objects to be provided for deny the federal government an unconfined au- by the federal government, the quantity of power thority, as to all those objects which are intrusted necessary to the accomplishment of those ob- to its management. It will indeed deserve the jects, the persons upon whom that power ought most vigilant and careful attention of the people, to operate. Its distribution and organization will to see that it be modelled in such a manner as to more properly claim our attention under the admit of its being safely vested with the requisite succeeding head. powers. If any plan which has been, or may be, The principal purposes to be answered by o¤ered to our consideration, should not upon a union are these—the common defence of the dispassionate inspection be found to answer this members; the preservation of the public peace, as description, it ought to be rejected. A govern- well against internal convulsions as external ment, the constitution of which renders it unfit to attacks; the regulation of commerce with other be trusted with all the powers which a free peo- nations and between the States; the superinten- ple ought to delegate to any government, would dence of our intercourse, political and commer- be an unsafe and improper depositary of the cial, with foreign countries. national interests. Wherever these can with The authorities essential to the common de- propriety be confided, the coincident powers fence are these: to raise armies; to build and may safely accompany them. This is the true equip fleets; to prescribe rules for the govern- result of all just reasoning upon the subject. . . . ment of both; to direct their operations; to pro- . . . If we embrace the tenets of those who op- vide for their support. These powers ought to pose the adoption of the proposed Constitution exist without limitation, because it is impossible as the standard of our political creed, we cannot to foresee or define the extent and variety of na- fail to verify the gloomy doctrines which predict tional exigencies, or the correspondent extent and the impracticability of a national system pervad- variety of the means which may be necessary to ing entire limits of the present Confederacy. satisfy them. The circumstances that endanger the safety of nations are infinite, and for this Publius reason no constitutional shackles can wisely be imposed on the power to which the care of it is

Excerpted from: Alexander Hamilton, James Madi- son, and John Jay. The Federalist Papers: A Collection of Essays Written in Support of the Constitution of the United States, second edition. Edited by Roy P. Fairfield. Garden City: Anchor, 1966. The Federalist No. 47

James Madison

form, when he pleases to consult them, one of his To the People of the State of New York constitutional councils. One branch of the legis- lative department forms also a great constitu- . . . The accumulation of all powers, legislative, tional council to the executive chief as . . . it is the executive, and judiciary, in the same hands, sole depositary of judicial power in cases of im- whether of one, a few, or many, and whether peachment, and is invested with the supreme ap- hereditary, self-appointed, or elective, may justly pellate jurisdiction in all other cases. The judges, be pronounced the very definition of tyranny. again, are so far connected with the legislative Were the federal Constitution, therefore, really department as often to attend and participate in chargeable with the accumulation of power, or its deliberations, though not admitted to a legis- with a mixture of powers having a dangerous lative vote. tendency to such an accumulation, no further From these facts, by which Montesquieu was arguments would be necessary to inspire a uni- guided, it may clearly be inferred that, in saying versal reprobation of the system. I persuade ‘‘There can be no liberty where the legislative myself, however, . . . that the charge cannot be and executive powers are united in the same supported, and that the maxim on which it relies person, or body of magistrates,’’ or, ‘‘if the has been totally misconceived and misapplied. In power of judging be not separated from the leg- order to form correct ideas on this important islative and executive powers’’ [sic], he did not subject, it will be proper to investigate the sense mean that these departments ought to have no in which the preservation of liberty requires that partial agency in, or no control over, the acts of the three great departments of power should be each other.61 His meaning . . . can amount to no separate and distinct. more than this, that where the whole power of The oracle who is always consulted and cited one department is exercised by the same hands on this subject is the celebrated Montesquieu. . . . which possess the whole power of another de- On the slightest view of the British Consti- partment, the fundamental principles of a free tution, we must perceive that the legislative, ex- constitution are subverted. . . . ecutive, and judiciary departments are by no The reasons on which Montesquieu grounds means totally separate and distinct from each his maxim are a further demonstration of his other. The executive magistrate forms an integral meaning. ‘‘When the legislative and executive part of the legislative authority. He alone has the prerogative of making treaties with foreign sovereigns, which, when made, have, under cer- 61. Montesquieu actually said: tain limitations, the force of legislative acts. All When the legislative and executive powers are united in the members of the judiciary department are the same person or in the same body of magistrates, appointed by him, can be removed by him on the there can be no liberty, because apprehensions may arise, lest the same monarch or senate should enact ty- address of the two Houses of Parliament, and rannical laws, to execute them in a tyrannical manner. Were it joined with the legislative, the life and liberty of Excerpted from: Alexander Hamilton, James Madi- the subject would be exposed to arbitrary control; for son, and John Jay. The Federalist Papers: A Collection the judge would then be the legislator. Were it joined to of Essays Written in Support of the Constitution of the executive power, the judge might behave with vio- the United States, second edition. Edited by Roy P. lence and oppression. Fairfield. Garden City: Anchor, 1966. Nugent translation (London, 1894), I, 163. Madison provided the italics. Chapter 4 194

powers are united in the same person or body,’’ says he, ‘‘there can be no liberty, because appre- hensions may arise lest the same monarch or senate should enact tyrannical laws to execute them in a tyrannical manner.’’ . . . In citing these cases in which the legislative, executive, and judiciary departments have not been kept totally separate and distinct, I wish not to be regarded as an advocate for the partic- ular organizations of the several State govern- ments. I am fully aware that among the many excellent principles which they exemplify, they carry strong marks of the haste, and still stronger of the inexperience, under which they were framed. It is but too obvious that in some in- stances the fundamental principle under consid- eration has been violated by too great a mixture, and even an actual consolidation, of the di¤erent powers; and that in no instance has a competent provision been made for maintaining in prac- tice the separation delineated on paper. What I have wished to evince is, that the charge brought against the proposed Constitution, of violating the sacred maxim of free government, is warranted neither by the real meaning annexed to that maxim by its author, nor by the sense in which it has hitherto been understood in America. The Federalist No. 48

James Madison

the extent and the duration of its power; and To the People of the State of New York where the legislative power is exercised by an assembly, which is inspired, by a supposed influ- It was shown in the last paper that the political ence over the people, with an intrepid confidence apothegm there examined does not require that in its own strength; which is su‰ciently numer- the legislative, executive, and judiciary depart- ous to feel all the passions which actuate a mul- ments should be wholly unconnected with each titude, yet not so numerous as to be incapable of other. I shall undertake, in the next place, to pursuing the objects of its passions, by means show that unless these departments be so far which reason prescribes; it is against the enter- connected and blended as to give to each a con- prising ambition of this department that the stitutional control over the others, the degree of people ought to indulge all their jealousy and separation which the maxim requires, as essential exhaust all their precautions. to a free government, can never in practice be The legislative department derives a superi- duly maintained. ority in our governments from other circum- It is agreed on all sides that the powers prop- stances. Its constitutional powers being at once erly belonging to one of the departments ought more extensive and less susceptible of precise not to be directly and completely administered limits, it can with the greater facility mask by either of the other departments. It is equally under complicated and indirect measures the evident that none of them ought to possess, di- encroachments which it makes on the coo¨rdinate rectly or indirectly, an overruling influence over departments. It is not unfrequently a question of the others in the administration of their respec- real nicety in legislative bodies, whether the tive powers. . . . operation of a particular measure will, or will Will it be su‰cient to mark with precision the not, extend beyond the legislative sphere. On the boundaries of these departments in the constitu- other side, the executive power being restrained tion of the government, and to trust to these within a narrower compass and being more sim- parchment barriers against the encroaching spirit ple in its nature, and the judiciary being de- of power? This is the security which appears to scribed by landmarks still less uncertain, projects have been principally relied on by the compilers of usurpation by either of these departments of most of the American constitutions. But ex- would immediately betray and defeat them- perience assures us that the e‰cacy of the provi- selves. Nor is this all; as the legislative depart- sion has been greatly overrated; and that some ment alone has access to the pockets of the more adequate defence is indispensably neces- people, and has in some constitutions full dis- sary for the more feeble, against the more pow- cretion, and in all a prevailing influence, over the erful, members of the government. . . . pecuniary rewards of those who fill the other . . . [I]n a representative republic, where the departments, a dependence is thus created in executive magistracy is carefully limited, both in the latter, which gives still greater facility to encroachments of the former. Excerpted from: Alexander Hamilton, James Madi- I have appealed to our own experience for the son, and John Jay. The Federalist Papers: A Collection truth of what I advance on this subject. Were it of Essays Written in Support of the Constitution of necessary to verify this experience by particular the United States, second edition. Edited by Roy P. Fairfield. Garden City: Anchor, 1966. proofs, they might be multiplied without end. I might find a witness in every citizen who has Chapter 4 196

shared in, or been attentive to, the course of public administrations. I might collect vouchers in abundance from the records and archives of every State in the Union. But as a more concise, and at the same time equally satisfactory, evi- dence, I will refer to the example of two States, attested by two unexceptionable authorities. . . . The conclusion which I am warranted in drawing from these observations is, that a mere demarcation on parchment of the constitutional limits of the several departments, is not a su‰- cient guard against those encroachments which lead to a tyrannical concentration of all the powers of government in the same hands.

Publius The Federalist No. 62

James Madison

Another advantage accruing from this ingre- To the People of the State of New York dient in the constitution of the Senate is the ad- ditional impediment it must prove against I. The qualifications proposed for senators, as improper acts of legislation. No law or resolu- distinguished from those of representatives, con- tion can now be passed without the concurrence, sist in a more advanced age and a longer period first, of a majority of the people, and then, of a of citizenship. A senator must be thirty years of majority of the States. . . . age at least; as a representative must be twenty- five. And the former must have been a citizen IV. The number of senators and the duration nine years; as seven years are required for the of their appointment come next to be considered. latter. The propriety of these distinctions is ex- In order to form an accurate judgment on both plained by the nature of the senatorial trust, these points, it will be proper to inquire into the which, requiring greater extent of information purposes which are to be answered by a senate; and stability of character, requires at the same and in order to ascertain these, it will be neces- time that the senator should have reached a pe- sary to review the inconveniences which a re- riod of life most likely to supply these advan- public must su¤er from the want of such an tages; and which, participating immediately in institution. transactions with foreign nations, ought to be First. It is a misfortune incident to republican exercised by none who are not thoroughly government, though in a less degree than to weaned from the prepossessions and habits inci- other governments, that those who administer it dent to foreign birth and education. . . . may forget their obligations to their constituents II. It is equally unnecessary to dilate on and prove unfaithful to their important trust. the appointment of senators by the State In this point of view, a senate, as a second legislatures. . . . branch of the legislative assembly, distinct III. The equality of representation in the from and dividing the power with a first, must be Senate is another point, which, being evidently in all cases a salutary check on the govern- the result of compromise between the opposite ment. . . . pretensions of the large and the small States, Secondly. The necessity of a senate is not less does not call for much discussion. . . . indicated by the propensity of all single and nu- In this spirit it may be remarked, that the merous assemblies to yield to the impulse of equal vote allowed to each State is at once a sudden and violent passions, and to be seduced constitutional recognition of the portion of by factious leaders into intemperate and perni- sovereignty remaining in the individual States, cious resolutions. . . . and an instrument for preserving that residuary Thirdly. Another defect to be supplied by a sovereignty. . . . senate lies in a want of due acquaintance with the objects and principles of legislation. . . . A good government implies two things: first, Excerpted from: Alexander Hamilton, James Madi- fidelity to the object of government, which is the son, and John Jay. The Federalist Papers: A Collection of Essays Written in Support of the Constitution of happiness of the people; secondly, a knowledge the United States, second edition. Edited by Roy P. of the means by which that object can be best Fairfield. Garden City: Anchor, 1966. attained. . . . Chapter 4 198

Fourthly. The mutability in the public councils arising from a rapid succession of new members, however qualified they may be, points out, in the strongest manner, the necessity of some stable institution in the government. . . . In the first place, it forfeits the respect and confidence of other nations and all the advan- tages connected with national character. . . . The internal e¤ects of a mutable policy are still more calamitous. It poisons the blessing of liberty itself. . . . Another e¤ect of public instability is the unreasonable advantage it gives to the saga- cious, the enterprising, and the moneyed few over the industrious and uninformed mass of the people. . . . In another point of view, great injury results from an unstable government. The want of confidence in the public councils damps every useful undertaking, the success and profit of which may depend on a continuance of existing arrangements. . . . But the most deplorable e¤ect of all is that diminution of attachment and reverence which steals into the hearts of the people towards a political system which betrays so many marks of infirmity, and disappoints so many of their flat- tering hopes. No government, any more than an individual, will long be respected without being truly respectable; nor be truly respectable, with- out possessing a certain portion of order and stability.

Publius The Federalist No. 70

Alexander Hamilton

legislature promptitude of decision is oftener an To the People of the State of New York evil than a benefit. The di¤erences of opinion and the jarrings of parties in that department of . . . The ingredients which constitute energy in the government, though they may sometimes the Executive are, first, unity; secondly, duration; obstruct salutary plans, yet often promote delib- thirdly, an adequate provision for its support; eration and circumspection, and serve to check fourthly, competent powers. excesses in the majority. When a resolution too is The ingredients which constitute safety in the once taken, the opposition must be at an end. republican sense are, first, a due dependence on That resolution is a law, and resistance to it the people; secondly, a due responsibility. punishable. But no favorable circumstances pal- Those politicians and statesmen who have liate or atone for the disadvantages of dissension been the most celebrated for the soundness of in the executive department. Here, they are pure their principles and for the justice of their views and unmixed. There is no point at which they have declared in favor of a single Executive and cease to operate. They serve to embarrass and a numerous legislature. They have with great weaken the execution of the plan or measure to propriety considered energy as the most neces- which they relate, from the first step to the final sary qualification of the former, and have re- conclusion of it. They constantly counteract garded this as most applicable to power in a those qualities in the Executive which are the single hand; while they have with equal propriety most necessary ingredients in its composition, considered the latter as best adapted to delibera- —vigor and expedition, and this without any tion and wisdom, and best calculated to concili- counterbalancing good. In the conduct of war, in ate the confidence of the people and to secure which the energy of the Executive is the bulwark their privileges and interests. of the national security, everything would be to That unity is conducive to energy will not be be apprehended from its plurality. . . . disputed. Decision, activity, secrecy, and des- But one of the weightiest objections to a patch will generally characterize the proceedings plurality in the Executive . . . is that it tends to of one man in a much more eminent degree than conceal faults and destroy responsibility. Re- the proceedings of any greater number; and in sponsibility is of two kinds—to censure and to proportion as the number is increased, these punishment. The first is the more important of qualities will be diminished. . . . the two, especially in an elective o‰ce. Man, in Upon the principles of a free government, in- public trust, will much oftener act in such a convenience . . . must necessarily be submitted to manner as to render him unworthy of being any in the formation of the legislature; but it is un- longer trusted, than in such a manner as to make necessary, and therefore unwise, to introduce him obnoxious to legal punishment. But the them into the constitution of the Executive. It is multiplication of the Executive adds to the di‰- here too that they may be most pernicious. In the culty of detection in either case. It often becomes impossible, amidst mutual accusations, to deter- Excerpted from: Alexander Hamilton, James Madi- mine on whom the blame or the punishment of son, and John Jay. The Federalist Papers: A Collection a pernicious measure, or series of pernicious of Essays Written in Support of the Constitution of measures, ought really to fall. It is shifted from the United States, second edition. Edited by Roy P. Fairfield. Garden City: Anchor, 1966. one to another with so much dexterity and under such plausible appearances, that the public Chapter 4 200

opinion is left in suspense about the real author. The circumstances which may have led to any national miscarriage of misfortune are some- times so complicated that, where there are a number of actors who may have had di¤erent degrees and kinds of agency, though we may clearly see upon the whole that there has been mismanagement, yet it may be impracticable to pronounce to whose account the evil which may have been incurred is truly chargeable. . . . It is evident from these considerations, that the plurality of the Executive tends to deprive the people of the two greatest securities they can have for the faithful exercise of any delegated power: first, the restraints of public opinion, which lose their e‰cacy, as well on account of the division of the censure attendant on bad measures among a number, as on account of the uncertainty on whom it ought to fall; and, sec- ondly, the opportunity of discovering with facil- ity and clearness the misconduct of the persons they trust, in order either to e¤ect their removal from o‰ce or . . . their actual punishment in cases which admit of it. . . . I will only add that, prior to the appearance of the Constitution, I rarely met with an intelligent man from any of the States, who did not admit, as the result of experience, that the UNITY of the executive of this State was one of the best of the distinguish- ing features of our constitution.

Publius The Federalist No. 78

Alexander Hamilton

of the modern improvements in the practice of To the People of the State of New York government. In a monarchy it is an excellent barrier to the despotism of the prince; in a re- We proceed now to an examination of the judi- public it is a no less excellent barrier to the ciary department of the proposed government. encroachments and oppressions of the represen- In unfolding the defects of the existing Con- tative body. And it is the best expedient which federation, the utility and necessity of a federal can be devised in any government to secure a judicature have been clearly pointed out. . . . steady, upright, and impartial administration of The manner of constituting it seems to em- the laws. brace these several objects: 1st. The mode of Whoever attentively considers the di¤erent appointing the judges. 2d. The tenure by which departments of power must perceive, that, in a they are to hold their places. 3d. The partition of government in which they are separated from the judiciary authority between di¤erent courts, each other, the judiciary, from the nature of its and their relations to each other. functions, will always be the least dangerous to First. As to the mode of appointing the judges; the political rights of the Constitution; because it this is the same with that of appointing the o‰- will be least in a capacity to annoy or injure cers of the Union in general, and has been so them. The Executive not only dispenses the fully discussed in the two last numbers, that honors, but holds the sword of the community. nothing can be said here which would not be The legislature not only commands the purse, useless repetition. but prescribes the rules by which the duties and Second. As to the tenure by which the judges rights of every citizen are to be regulated. The are to hold their places: this chiefly concerns judiciary, on the contrary, has no influence over their duration in o‰ce; the provisions for their either the sword or the purse;97 no direction support; the precautions for their responsibility. either of the strength or of the wealth of the so- According to the plan of the convention, all ciety; and can take no active resolution what- judges who may be appointed by the United ever. It may truly be said to have neither force States are to hold their o‰ces during good nor will, but merely judgment; and must ulti- behavior; which is conformable to the most mately depend upon the aid of the executive arm approved of the State constitutions, and among even for the e‰cacy of its judgments. the rest, to that of this State. Its propriety having This simple view of the matter suggests sev- been drawn into question by the adversaries of eral important consequences. It proves incontest- that plan, is no light symptom of the rage for ably that the judiciary is beyond comparison objection, which disorders their imaginations and judgments. The standard of good behavior for the continuance in o‰ce of the judicial 97. Hamilton’s judgment seemed to be borne out a magistracy is certainly one of the most valuable half century later when Andrew Jackson, disagreeing with the court in Worcester v. Georgia (1832), allegedly remarked, ‘‘John Marshall has made his decision, now Excerpted from: Alexander Hamilton, James Madi- let him enforce it.’’ Mason and Leach, [In Quest of son, and John Jay. The Federalist Papers: A Collection Freedom: American Political Thought and Practice. of Essays Written in Support of the Constitution of Englewood Cli¤s, N.J.: Prentice-Hall, 1959], 262. The the United States, second edition. Edited by Roy P. 1954–55 desegregation decisions and their subsequent Fairfield. Garden City: Anchor, 1966. application continue to raise questions about the rela- tionships between the Executive and judiciary. Chapter 4 202

the weakest of the three departments of power as an indispensable ingredient in its constitution, [sic];98 that it can never attack with success either and, in a great measure, as the citadel of the of the other two; and that all possible care is public justice and the public security. requisite to enable it to defend itself against their The complete independence of the courts of attacks. It equally proves that though individual justice is peculiarly essential in a limited Consti- oppression may now and then proceed from the tution. By a limited Constitution, I understand courts of justice, the general liberty of the people one which contains certain specified exceptions can never be endangered from that quarter; I to the legislative authority; such, for instance, as mean so long as the judiciary remains truly dis- that it shall pass no bills of attainder, no ex-post- tinct from both the legislature and the Executive. facto laws, and the like. Limitations of this kind For I agree, that ‘‘there is no liberty, if the power can be preserved in practice no other way than of judging be not separated from the legislative through the medium of courts of justice, whose and executive powers.’’99 And it proves, in the duty it must be to declare all acts contrary to the last place, that as liberty can have nothing to manifest tenor of the Constitution void. Without fear from the judiciary alone, but would have this, all the reservations of particular rights or every thing to fear from its union with either privileges would amount to nothing. of the other departments; that as all the e¤ects Some perplexity respecting the rights of the of such a union must ensue from a dependence courts to pronounce legislative acts void, because of the former on the latter, notwithstanding a contrary to the constitution, has arisen from an nominal and apparent separation; that as, from imagination that the doctrine would imply a su- the natural feebleness of the judiciary it is in periority of the judiciary to the legislative power. continual jeopardy of being overpowered, awed, It is urged that the authority which can declare or influenced by its coo¨rdinate branches; and the acts of another void must necessarily be su- that as nothing can contribute so much to its perior to the one whose acts may be declared firmness and independence as permanency in of- void. As this doctrine is of great importance in fice, this quality may therefore be justly regarded all the American constitutions, a brief discus- sion of the ground on which it rests cannot be 98. At this point in the text Hamilton ran a footnote: unacceptable.100 ‘‘The celebrated Montesquieu, speaking of them, says: ‘Of the three powers above mentioned, the judiciary is 100. Next to No. 10, this essay has probably been next to nothing.’ ‘Spirit of Laws,’ vol. i., page 186.— studied more than any other because it sets forth a Publius’’ A close check of the Nugent text, which systematic argument for the doctrine of judicial review. Hamilton used, reveals that Montesquieu actually said, Marshall gave it living force in Marbury v. Madison ‘‘Of the three powers above mentioned, the judiciary is (1803) and other precedent-forming decisions, and it in some measure next to nothing.’’ (Edinburgh edition, remains today among the most discussed American ju- 1772; I, 193.) I have provided the italics to indicate that dicial practices. Even the Europeans, long skeptical of Montesquieu made a qualified judgment about the the doctrine, seem to be considering it more seriously; power of the judiciary, not an unqualified one, as see Arnold J. Zurcher, ed., Constitutions and Constitu- Hamilton indicated. A few pages later Montesquieu tional Trends since World War II (N.Y., 1951), 20–22, did say that ‘‘the national judges are no more than the 216. mouth that pronounces the words of the law, mere Although it is generally agreed that Sir Edward passive beings, incapable of moderating either its force Coke probably originated the doctrine in the Dr. Bon- or rigour’’ (197). He seemed to regard the power of ham Case (1610), there is controversy as to whether or judging with some awe, referring to it as ‘‘. . . a power not the founding fathers intended to include judicial so terrible to mankind . . .’’ (166). review in the new system of government. Serious stu- 99. This quote is accurate. Ibid., 165. dents of this question, as well as other problems per- Democracy and Constitutionalism 203

There is no position which depends on clearer proper and peculiar province of the courts. A principles than that every act of a delegated au- constitution is, in fact, and must be regarded by thority, contrary to the tenor of the commission the judges, as a fundamental law. It therefore under which it is exercised, is void. No legislative belongs to them to ascertain its meaning, as well act, therefore, contrary to the Constitution, can as the meaning of any particular act proceeding be valid. To deny this would be to a‰rm that the from the legislative body. If there should happen deputy is greater than his principal; that the ser- to be an irreconcilable variance between the two, vant is above his master; that the representatives that which has the superior obligation and va- of the people are superior to the people them- lidity ought, of course, to be preferred; or, in selves; that men acting by virtue of powers may other words, the Constitution ought to be pre- do not only what their powers do not authorize, ferred to the statute, the intention of the people but what they forbid. to the intention of their agents.101 If it be said that the legislative body are Nor does this conclusion by any means sup- themselves the constitutional judges of their own pose a superiority of the judicial to the legisla- powers, and that the construction they put upon tive power. It only supposes that the power of them is conclusive upon the other departments, it the people is superior to both; and that where may be answered that this cannot be the natural the will of the legislature, declared in its stat- presumption where it is not to be collected from utes, stands in opposition to that of the people, any particular provisions in the Constitution. It declared in the Constitution, the judges ought to is not otherwise to be supposed that the Consti- be governed by the latter rather than the former. tution could intend to enable the representatives They ought to regulate their decisions by the of the people to substitute their will to that of fundamental laws, rather than by those which their constituents. It is far more rational to sup- are not fundamental. pose that the courts were designed to be an in- This exercise of judicial discretion, in deter- termediate body between the people and the mining between two contradictory laws, is legislature, in order, among other things, to keep exemplified in a familiar instance. It not uncom- the latter within the limits assigned to their au- monly happens that there are two statutes exist- thority. The interpretation of the laws is the ing at one time, clashing in whole or in part with each other, and neither of them containing any taining to judicial review, will not only wish to consult repealing clause or expression. In such a case, it the bibliography in Belo¤’s ed. of the Federalist, 483, is the province of the courts to liquidate and fix but they will also find the following helpful: Robert K. their meaning and operation. So far as they can, Carr, The Supreme Court and Judicial Review (N.Y., by any fair construction, be reconciled to each 1942), 54–55; Gottfried Dietze, The Federalist; Far- other, reason and law conspire to dictate that rand, Records, II, 73–80; Crosskey, op. cit., II, 941– this should be done; where this is impracticable, 945; Miller, op. cit., 204; Robert J. Harris, ‘‘The it becomes a matter of necessity to give e¤ect to Decline of Judicial Review,’’ Journal of Politics one in exclusion of the other. The rule which has (Feb. 1948), 1–19, Corwin’s survey in Encyclopedia of the Social Sciences, VIII, 456, and Corwin, Court obtained in the courts for determining their rela- over Constitution (Princeton, 1938). Also see ‘‘Luther tive validity is, that the last in order of time shall Martin’s Letter,’’ Elliot, Debates, I, 380, in which Martin said, ‘‘Whether . . . any laws or regulations of 101. For Justice David Brewer’s famous statement the Congress, any acts of its President or other o‰cers, indicating the way in which the court employs the are contrary to, or not warranted by, the Constitution, Constitution as a higher law, see Ralph Gabriel, The rests only with the judges, who are appointed by Con- Course of American Democratic Thought (N.Y., 1940), gress, to determine; by whose determinations every 233. state must be bound.’’ Chapter 4 204

be preferred to the first. But this is a mere rule of This independence of the judges is equally construction, not derived from any positive law requisite to guard the Constitution and the but from the nature and reason of the thing. It is rights of individuals from the e¤ects of those ill a rule not enjoined upon the courts by legislative humors, which the arts of designing men or the provision but adopted by themselves, as conso- influence of particular conjunctures sometimes nant to truth and propriety for the direction of disseminate among the people themselves; and their conduct as interpreters of the law. They which, though they speedily give place to better thought it reasonable, that between the interfer- information and more deliberate reflection, have ing acts of an equal authority, that which was a tendency, in the meantime, to occasion dan- the last indication of its will should have the gerous innovations in the government, and preference. serious oppressions of the minor party in the But in regard to the interfering acts of a supe- community. Though I trust the friends of the rior and subordinate authority, of an original proposed Constitution will never concur with and derivative power, the nature and reason of its enemies102 in questioning that fundamen- the thing indicate the converse of that rule as tal principle of republican government, which proper to be followed. They teach us that the admits the right of the people to alter or abolish prior act of a superior ought to be preferred to the established Constitution whenever they find the subsequent act of an inferior and subordinate it inconsistent with their happiness; yet it is not authority; and that accordingly, whenever a to be inferred from this principle that the repre- particular statute contravenes the Constitution, sentatives of the people, whenever a momentary it will be the duty of the judicial tribunals to ad- inclination happens to lay hold of a majority of here to the latter and disregard the former. their constituents, incompatible with the provi- It can be of no weight to say that the courts, sions in the existing Constitution, would, on that on the pretence of a repugnancy, may substitute account, be justifiable in a violation of those their own pleasure to the constitutional inten- provisions; or that the courts would be under a tions of the legislature. This might as well hap- greater obligation to connive at infractions in pen in the case of two contradictory statutes; or this shape, than when they had proceeded wholly it might as well happen in every adjudication from the cabals of the representative body. Until upon any single statute. The courts must declare the people have by some solemn and authorita- the sense of the law; and if they should be dis- tive act annulled or changed the established posed to exercise will instead of judgment, the form, it is binding upon themselves collectively, consequence would equally be the substitution of as well as individually; and no presumption, or their pleasure to that of the legislative body. The even knowledge, of their sentiments, can warrant observation, if it prove any thing, would prove their representatives in a departure from it, prior that there ought to be no judges distinct from to such an act. But it is easy to see that it would that body. require an uncommon portion of fortitude in the If, then, the courts of justice are to be consid- judges to do their duty as faithful guardians of ered as the bulwarks of a limited Constitution the Constitution, where legislative invasions of it against legislative encroachments, this consider- had been instigated by the major voice of the ation will a¤ord a strong argument for the per- community. manent tenure of judicial o‰ces, since nothing will contribute so much as this to that indepen- 102. Hamilton’s footnote: ‘‘Vide ‘Protest of the Mi- dent spirit in the judges which must be essen- nority of the Convention of Pennsylvania,’ Martin’s tial to the faithful performance of so arduous a Speech, etc.—Publius’’ The former may be found in duty. McMaster and Stone, op. cit., 454–82; the latter, Elliot’s Debates, I, 344–89. Democracy and Constitutionalism 205

But it is not with a view to infractions of the committed either to the Executive or legislature, Constitution only that the independence of the there would be danger of an improper complai- judges may be an essential safeguard against sance to the branch which possessed it; if to the e¤ects of occasional ill humors in the society. both, there would be an unwillingness to hazard These sometimes extend no farther than to the the displeasure of either; if to the people or to injury of the private rights of particular classes of persons chosen by them for the special purpose, citizens by unjust and partial laws. Here also the there would be too great a disposition to consult firmness of the judicial magistracy is of vast im- popularity, to justify a reliance that nothing portance in mitigating the severity and confining would be consulted but the Constitution and the the operation of such laws. It not only serves to laws. moderate the immediate mischiefs of those which There is yet a further and a weightier reason may have been passed, but it operates as a check for the permanency of the judicial o‰ces, which upon the legislative body in passing them; who, is deducible from the nature of the qualifications perceiving that obstacles to the success of iniq- they require. It has been frequently remarked, uitous intention are to be expected from the with great propriety, that a voluminous code of scruples of the courts, are in a manner compelled laws is one of the inconveniences necessarily by the very motives of the injustice they meditate connected with the advantages of a free govern- to qualify their attempts. This is a circumstance ment. To avoid an arbitrary discretion in the calculated to have more influence upon the courts, it is indispensable that they should be character of our governments, than but few may bound down by strict rules and precedents, be aware of. The benefits of the integrity and which serve to define and point out their duty in moderation of the judiciary have already been every particular case that comes before them; felt in more States than one; and though they and it will readily be conceived from the variety may have displeased those whose sinister ex- of controversies which grow out of the folly and pectations they may have disappointed, they wickedness of mankind, that the records of those must have commanded the esteem and applause precedents must unavoidably swell to a very of all the virtuous and disinterested. Considerate considerable bulk, and must demand long and men of every description ought to prize whatever laborious study to acquire a competent knowl- will tend to beget or fortify that temper in the edge of them. Hence it is, that there can be but courts; as no man can be sure that he may not be few men in the society who will have su‰cient tomorrow the victim of a spirit of injustice by skill in the laws to qualify them for the stations which he may be a gainer today. And every man of judges. And making the proper deductions for must now feel that the inevitable tendency of the ordinary depravity of human nature, the such a spirit is to sap the foundations of public number must be still smaller of those who unite and private confidence, and to introduce in its the requisite integrity with the requisite knowl- stead universal distrust and distress. edge. These considerations apprise us that the That inflexible and uniform adherence to the government can have no great option between rights of the Constitution and of individuals, fit character; and that a temporary duration in which we perceive to be indispensable in the o‰ce, which would naturally discourage such courts of justice, can certainly not be expected characters from quitting a lucrative line of prac- from judges who hold their o‰ces by a tempo- tice to accept a seat on the bench, would have a rary commission. Periodical appointments, how- tendency to throw the administration of justice ever regulated or by whomsoever made, would, into hands less able, and less well qualified, to in some way or other, be fatal to their necessary conduct it with utility and dignity. In the present independence. If the power of making them was circumstances of this country and in those in Chapter 4 206

which it is likely to be for a long time to come, the disadvantages on this score would be greater than they may at first sight appear; but it must be confessed that they are far inferior to those which present themselves under the other aspects of the subject. Upon the whole, there can be no room to doubt that the convention acted wisely in copy- ing from the models of those constitutions which have established good behavior as the tenure of their judicial o‰ces, in point of duration; and that so far from being blamable on this account, their plan would have been inexcusably defective if it had wanted this important feature of good government. The experience of Great Britain a¤ords an illustrious comment on the excellence of the institution.

Publius Madisonian Democracy

Robert Dahl

This proposition in turn presupposes at least two I implied definitions:

Democracy, it is frequently said, rests upon Definition 1: An ‘‘external check’’ for an compromise. But democratic theory itself is full individual consists of the application of rewards of compromises—compromises of clashing and and penalties, or the expectation that they will antagonistic principles. What is a virtue in social be applied, by some source other than the given life, however, is not necessarily a virtue in social individual himself.1 theory. What I am going to call the ‘‘Madisonian’’ Definition 2: ‘‘Tyranny’’ is every severe theory of democracy is an e¤ort to bring o¤ a deprivation of a natural right. compromise between the power of majorities and Three comments need to be made about the the power of minorities, between the political definition of tyranny supplied here. First, it is not equality of all adult citizens on the one side, and the same as Madison’s explicit definition of tyr- the desire to limit their sovereignty on the other. anny in The Federalist, No. 47, where he states As a political system the compromise, except for that ‘‘the accumulation of all powers, legislative, one important interlude, has proved to be dura- executive, and judiciary, in the same hands, ble. What is more, Americans seem to like it. As whether of one, a few, or many, may justly be a political theory, however, the compromise del- pronounced the very definition of tyranny.’’2 It icately papers over a number of cracks without seems to me that Madison’s explicit definition quite concealing them. It is no accident that has been derived from Definition 2 by the inser- preoccupation with the rights and wrongs of tion of an empirical premise, i.e., the accu- majority rule has run like a red thread through mulation of all powers in the same hands would American political thought since 1789. For if lead to severe deprivations of natural rights and most Americans seem to have accepted the le- hence to tyranny. It seems reasonable, therefore, gitimacy of the Madisonian political system, to reconstruct Madison’s explicit argument into criticism of its rather shaky rationale never quite the following Madisonian reasoning: dies down; and as a consequence, no doubt, the Madisonian theses must themselves be con- stantly reiterated or even, as with Calhoun, 1. Hypothesis 1 and Definition 1 are a paraphrase, but I think a reasonably accurate paraphrase, of numerous enlarged upon. . . . references in Madison’s writings. My language may be The central proposition of the Madisonian more modern, but the ideas are, I think, expressed by theory is partly implicit and partly explicit, Madison, e.g., in his ‘‘Observations’’ of April, 1787, namely: in The Complete Madison, His Basic Writings, ed. Saul K. Padover (New York: Harper & Bros., 1953), pp. Hypothesis 1: If unrestrained by external 27–29. Cf. also his letter to Je¤erson, October 24, 1787, checks, any given individual or group of pp. 40–43. individuals will tyrannize over others. 2. The Federalist, ed. Edward Mead Earle (‘‘The Modern Library’’ [New York: Random House, Excerpted from: Robert Dahl, A Preface to Democratic n.d.]), p. 313. For another analysis of Madison see Theory. Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1956. Mark Ashin, ‘‘The Argument of Madison’s ‘Federal- 6 1956 by the University of Chicago. Reprinted by ist’ No. 10,’’ College English, XV (October, 1953), 37– permission. 45. Chapter 4 208

Hypothesis 2: The accumulation of all powers, II legislative, executive, and judiciary in the same hands implies the elimination of external checks Clearly Hypothesis 1 is an empirical proposition. (empirical generalization). Its validity can therefore be tested only by expe- The elimination of external checks produces rience. Madison’s own methods of validating tyranny (from Hypothesis 1). the hypothesis seem to be representative of the Therefore the accumulation of all powers in widespread American style of thought that in the same hands implies tyranny. this book is called ‘‘Madisonian.’’ Madison’s ... first method of proof is to enumerate historical . . . [T]he natural rights are not clearly speci- examples drawn, for example, from the history fied. Among Madison’s contemporaries as of Greece and Rome.6 His second method of among his predecessors there was by no means a proof is to derive the hypothesis from certain perfect agreement as to what ‘‘rights’’ are ‘‘nat- psychological axioms that were widely accepted ural rights.’’ . . . As will be seen, the absence in his day—and perhaps are now. These axioms of an agreed definition of natural rights is one are Hobbesian in character and run something of the central di‰culties of the Madisonian like this: Men are instruments of their desires. theory. They pursue their desires to satiation if given the . . . I have used the expression ‘‘severe depri- opportunity. One such desire is the desire for vation’’ to cover an ambiguity in the thought of power over other individuals, for not only is Madison and his contemporaries. How far could power directly satisfying but it also has great in- governments go in limiting natural rights with- strumental value because a wide variety of sat- out becoming tyrannical? Here again, neither isfactions depend upon it. . . . Madison nor any other Madisonian, so far as I am aware, has provided wholly satisfactory criteria. However, Madison no doubt agreed III with his contemporaries that, at a minimum, any curtailment of natural rights without one’s If Hypothesis 1 is accepted as validated by these ‘‘consent’’ was a su‰ciently severe deprivation to two methods (or others), then Hypotheses 3 and constitute tyranny.4 ... 4, which are merely derived from Hypothesis 1, As corollaries of Hypothesis 1 two additional are also valid. Nevertheless, Hypothesis 4 seems 11 hypotheses need to be distinguished: to play a special role in Madisonian thought.

Hypothesis 3: If unrestrained by external 6. E.g., Madison’s remarks at the Convention, [The checks, a minority of individuals will tyrannize Debates in the Several State Conventions on the Adop- over a majority of individuals. tion of the Federal Constitution as Recommended by the General Convention at Philadelphia, in 1787, To- Hypothesis 4: If unrestrained by external gether with the Journal of Federal Convention ..., ed. checks, a majority of individuals will tyrannize Jonathan Elliot (2nd ed.; Philadelphia: Lippincott, over a minority of individuals. 1941), V], p. 162. 11. For example, see Padover, op. cit., pp. 28, 37–38, ... 41, 45–47. But see also Madison’s ‘‘comment’’ in 1833, ibid., p. 49. In later years Madison seems to have had a 4. [Clinton Rossiter, Seedtime of the Republic (New more tender regard for the majority principle. Like York: Harcourt Brace, 1953)], p. 383. Rossiter de- most Americans, Madison seems never to have felt any scribes the consensus on this point. logical contradiction in his position. Democracy and Constitutionalism 209

Neither at the Constitutional Convention nor ours. To some extent it was associated with rad- in the ‘‘Federalist Papers’’ is much anxiety dis- ical equalitarianism; it was also ambiguous be- played over the dangers arising from minority cause many writers had defined it to mean what tyranny; by comparison, the danger of majority we today would call ‘‘direct’’ democracy, i.e., tyranny appears to be a source of acute fear. non-representative democracy. The term ‘‘re- The ‘‘Federalist Papers,’’ for example, reveal no public’’ was frequently used to refer to what we deep-seated distrust of the executive branch, would be more inclined to call ‘‘representative’’ which was regarded by the authors (wrongly, as democracy.16 It will do no harm, therefore, to it turned out) as the strong point for the minority adhere to Madison’s own term ‘‘republic,’’ which of wealth, status, and power.12 By contrast, a he defined as follows: central theme of Madison’s is the threat from the legislature, supposedly the stronghold of the Definition 3: A republic is a government majority. . . . which (a) derives all of its powers directly or And it follows from Definition 2, as well as indirectly from the great body of the people and from Madison’s own explicit definition of tyr- (b) is administered by persons holding their anny, that legislative or majority tyranny is not o‰ce during pleasure, for a limited period, or 17 any less tyrannical than executive or minority during good behavior. tyranny. They are equally undesirable. . . . It is now possible to state the central ethical Both majorities and minorities, then, are goal of the Madisonian system, which can con- weighed on the same scales. For the objective veniently be called the Madisonian axiom: test of non-tyranny is not the size of the ruling The goal that ought to be attained, at least in group; it is whether the ruling group, whatever the United States, is a non-tyrannical republic. its size, imposes severe deprivations on the ‘‘nat- This goal was taken as a postulate. Because it ural rights’’ of citizens. was not seriously questioned at the Constitu- tional Convention or elsewhere and has never been seriously questioned in this country since IV that time, the goal has pretty much remained an unexamined axiom.18 ... So far, the propositions in the Madisonian sys- tem are definitional or empirical. With the ad- mission of one more definition, it now becomes 16. On this question, however, see the comment of Elisha P. Douglas, Rebels and Democrats (Chapel Hill: possible to state the goals to be used in guiding University of North Carolina Press, 1955), p. viii. the choice among possible political systems. 17. The Federalist, No. 39. ‘‘It is essential to such a What is needed at this point is a definition of government that it is derived from the great body of ‘‘democracy.’’ However, in Madison’s day the society, not from an unconsiderable proportion, or a term ‘‘democracy’’ was less common than in favored class of it. . . . It is su‰cient for such a govern- ment that the persons administering it be appointed, 12. Hamilton appears to have written the relevant either directly or indirectly, by the people; and that papers, Nos. 67–77; given his political views, he might they hold their appointments by either of the tenures be expected to deprecate the dangers of tyranny just specified. . . .’’ from this branch. Moreover, it must never be for- 18. Cf. Louis Hartz, ‘‘The Whig Tradition in America gotten that the ‘‘Federalist Papers’’ were polemical and and Europe,’’ American Political Science Review, propagandistic writing, reflecting a highly partisan XLVI (December, 1952), 989–1002. viewpoint. Chapter 4 210

every severe deprivation of natural rights and to V propose the empirical hypothesis that the accu- mulation of all powers, etc., will eliminate exter- . . . What conditions are necessary for attaining nal checks (Hypothesis 2) and hence produce the goal of a non-tyrannical republic? tyranny (by Hypothesis 1 and Definition 2). Hypothesis 5: At least two conditions are Yet if we now attempt to retrieve the Madi- necessary for the existence of a non-tyrannical sonian system from a trivial argument by the republic: addition of these implicit hypotheses and defi- nitions, we are faced with a dilemma. For if by First Condition: The accumulation of all ‘‘power’’ we mean constitutionally prescribed powers, legislative, executive, and judiciary, in authority, then the First Condition is demon- the same hands, whether of one, a few, or strably false, for it is pretty clearly not nec- many, and whether hereditary, self-appointed, essary to every non-tyrannical republic, as an or elective, must be avoided.19 examination of parliamentary, but certainly non- tyrannical, democratic systems like that of Great Second Condition: Factions must be so Britain readily prove. Let us suppose, then, that controlled that they do not succeed in acting by ‘‘power’’ we mean to describe a more realistic adversely to the rights of other citizens or to the relationship, such as A’s capacity for acting in permanent and aggregate interests of the such a manner as to control B’s responses. Then community.20 it is plain that ‘‘legislative, executive, and judi- ciary’’ by no means comprise all the power rela- VI tions or control processes in a society. For example, electoral processes make it possible for In attempting to prove that the first condition is some individuals to control others; certainly they an essential prerequisite of every non-tyrannical assist non-leaders in controlling leaders. Hence it republic, the Madisonian system becomes so is not obvious that the mere accumulation of deeply ambiguous that it is di‰cult to know legislative, executive, and judicial power must precisely how to do justice to the argument. lead to tyranny, in the sense of severe depriva- We are faced at the outset with two alternative tion of rights. Popular elections (and competing possibilities. The first I rejected a moment ago as parties) might be su‰cient to prevent such inva- essentially trivial. For if we accept Madison’s sions of basic rights. That is, Madison’s argu- explicit definition of tyranny, and if we postulate ment now seems to require proof of at least one that tyranny is to be avoided, then the first con- additional hypothesis, namely: dition is necessary merely by definition: (1) Tyr- Hypothesis 6: Frequent popular elections will anny means the accumulation of all powers, etc. not provide an external check su‰cient to (definition). (2) Tyranny is undesirable (axiom). prevent tyranny. (3) Therefore the accumulation of all powers, etc., is undesirable. Yet to solve the problem by For if this last hypothesis is false, and frequent definition leaves open many major questions. . . . popular elections will provide an external check Another possibility, therefore, is to accept su‰cient to prevent tyranny, then Madison’s ar- Madison’s implicit definition that tyranny is gument about the need to keep the legislative, executive, and judicial powers constitutionally or 19. The Federalist, No. 47, p. 313. otherwise separate in order to prevent tyranny is 20. The Federalist, No. 10, pp. 57 ¤. also patently false. . . . Democracy and Constitutionalism 211

The Federalist, No. 49,22 to be sure, does Yet the necessity for this condition for a non- attempt to prove that the check provided by tyrannical republic is an article of faith in the electoral processes is inadequate to prevent all American political credo. From it Madison, and powers, legislative, executive, and judiciary, successors who out-Madisoned Madison, have from accumulating in the same hands. Two deduced the necessity for the whole complicated observations can be made about this argument. network of constitutional checks and balances: First, even if the proposition is valid, it cannot the separate constituencies for electing President, establish the necessity of the First Condition ex- senators, and representatives; the presidential cept by the trivial definitional route rejected veto power; a bicameral Congress; presidential above. For, except by definition, it does not fol- control over appointments, senatorial confirma- low that the accumulation of ‘‘all powers, legis- tion; and, in part, federalism. Over the years still lative, executive, and judiciary’’ leads to tyranny. other checks and balances within the political Second, the specific arguments in support of the system have developed and have been rational- proposition in The Federalist, No. 49, seem to ized by the same arguments: judicial review, me patently invalid or highly inconclusive. They decentralized political parties, the Senate fili- are (1) that frequent appeals would indicate buster, senatorial ‘‘courtesy,’’ the power of defects in government and so weaken the ven- committee chairmen, and indeed almost every eration necessary to stability; (2) that public organizational technique that promises to pro- tranquillity would be dangerously disturbed by vide an additional external check on any identi- interesting public passions too strongly; (3) that fiable group of political leaders. being few in number, members of the executive and judiciary can be known only to a small part of the electorate; the judiciary are far removed, VII the executive are objects of jealousy and unpop- ularity. By contrast, members of the legislature Let us now turn to the Second Condition: Fac- dwell among the people and have connections of tions must be so controlled that they do not blood and friendship. Hence the contest for succeed in acting adversely to the rights of power would be an unequal one in which the other citizens or to the permanent and aggregate legislature would swallow up the others.23 interests of the community. I am afraid, then, that the validity of the First How is this state of a¤airs to be attained? In Condition is not established. answering this question, Madison produced one of the most lucid and compact sets of political 22. Although the authorship of this paper was once propositions ever set forth by an American: the contested, it is now established that Madison, not now familiar argument of The Federalist, No. Hamilton, was the author. (Irving Brant, James Madi- 10.24 I shall here attempt no more than to set son, Vol. III: Father of the Constitution, 1787–1800 forth the bare skeleton of his argument. [New York: Bobbs-Merrill Co., 1950], p. 184.) Obviously a definition is needed at the outset: 23. Madison also appends an argument more common among antidemocrats, namely, that issues in popular Definition 4: A faction is ‘‘a number of elections would not be decided on ‘‘the true merits of citizens, whether amounting to a majority or a the question’’ but on a partisan basis. Unlike the first minority of the whole, who are united and three, which seem to me plainly false, this one is merely meaningless—at least without a very considerable 24. This represents a refinement of ideas Madison had philosophical and empirical inquiry not attempted by already expounded at the Convention and earlier. Cf., Madison. Cf. The Federalist, No. 49, pp. 327–332. for example, Elliot’s Debates, V, 242–243. Chapter 4 212

actuated by some common impulse of passion, Hypothesis 9 is proved by an argument that or of interest, adverse to the rights of other contains a number of exceedingly doubtful citizens, or to the permanent and aggregate statements and some that, if true, raise serious interests of the community.’’25 questions as to the validity of other basic hypotheses in the Madisonian system. Madison Given this definition, it is easy to show from argues that there are only two possible ways of Hypothesis 1 that a faction will produce tyranny controlling the e¤ects of a majority faction. if unrestrained by external checks. Thus the Sec- First, the existence of the same passion or in- ond Condition is proved to be necessary. terest in a majority at the same time must be How, then, can factions be controlled? In prevented. But because in this case no ma- brief, Madison argues with elegant rigor and jority faction would exist, Madison seems to economy that the latent causes of faction are have reversed his earlier argument that the sown in the nature of man: they stem from dif- causes of faction cannot be controlled. Second, ferences of opinion based on the fallibility of even though a majority faction exists, its mem- man’s reason, from attachments to di¤erent bers must be made incapable of acting together leaders, and from di¤erences in property, that e¤ectually. are in turn a result of ‘‘the diversity in the facul- Both ways of controlling the e¤ects of a ma- ties of men.’’ If people cannot be made alike, the jority faction, Madison argues, are provided by a causes of faction could be controlled only by large republic. There ensues an extremely dubi- destroying liberty—a solution obviously barred ous and probably false set of propositions pur- to anyone seeking a non-tyrannical republic. porting to show that representation in a large Hence it follows that factions cannot be con- republic will provide ‘‘better’’ politicians and re- trolled by eliminating their causes. In this fash- duce the probability of success of ‘‘the vicious ion Madison proves the validity of arts by which elections are too often carried.’’ Hypothesis 7: If factions are to be controlled Then Madison states a final and exceptionally and tyranny is to be avoided, this must be important proposition. . . . Let us then para- attained by controlling the e¤ects of faction. phrase Madison: Can the e¤ects of faction be controlled so as to Hypothesis 10: To the extent that the elector- avoid tyranny? Yes, Madison tells us, provided ate is numerous, extended, and diverse in two further conditions are present: interests, a majority faction is less likely to exist, and if it does exist, it is less likely to act as a Hypothesis 8: If a faction consists of less than unity. a majority, it can be controlled by the operation of ‘‘the republican principle’’ of voting in the legislative body, i.e., the majority can vote VIII down the minority. ... Hypothesis 9: The development of majority The first hypothesis, it will be recalled, is faction can be limited if the electorate is implicit rather than explicit in the Madisonian numerous, extended, and diverse in interests. argument. . . . The validity of Hypothesis 8 must have Inter alia, the first hypothesis implies: seemed self-evident to Madison, for he made no 1. That control over others by means of gov- e¤ort to prove it. . . . ernmental processes is a highly valued goal, i.e., such control is believed to be either directly or indirectly rewarding to those who exercise it. 25. The Federalist, No. 10, p. 54. Democracy and Constitutionalism 213

2. That it is impossible by social training to IX create through conscience a self-restraint su‰- cient to inhibit impulses to tyranny among po- . . . What kinds of external checks does the litical leaders. . . . Madisonian have in mind as restraints on 3. That the range of sympathetic identification tyranny? of one individual with another is too narrow to . . . Madison evidently had in mind a basic eliminate impulses to tyranny. concept, namely, that of reciprocal control Many political theorists prior to Madison among leaders. But in several ways, the Madiso- placed heavy emphasis on the role of social nian argument is inadequate: indoctrination and habituation in creating atti- tudes, habits, and even personality types requi- 1. It does not show, and I think cannot be site to a given type of political system. . . . used to show, that reciprocal control among . . . [P]resent evidence suggests that ‘‘internal leaders, su‰cient to prevent tyranny, requires checks’’—the conscience (super-ego), attitudes, constitutionally prescribed separation of powers, and basic predispositions—are crucial in deter- as in the American Constitution. mining whether any given individual will seek to tyrannize over others; that these internal checks 2. Either the significance of constitutional vary from individual to individual, from social prescription as an external check is exaggerated group to social group, and from time to time; or the argument misunderstands the psychologi- and that the probability of tyranny emerging in a cal realities implied by the concept of a check on, society is a function of the extent to which vari- or control over, behavior. And the inferences ous types of internalized responses are present from either type of incorrect premise to proposi- among members of that society. tions about political behavior or the requisites of Yet we should make Madison and his present- a non-tyrannical democracy are false. day followers seem fools if we were to assume 3. The Madisonian argument exaggerates the that they were oblivious to these or similar importance, in preventing tyranny, of specified facts. . . . Thus we might try to save one of Mad- checks to governmental o‰cials by other speci- ison’s basic implicit hypotheses by casting it in fied governmental o‰cials; it underestimates the probability terms: importance of the inherent social checks and

0 balances existing in every pluralistic society. Hypothesis 1 : The probability that any given Without these social checks and balances, it is individual or group will tyrannize over others if doubtful that the intragovernmental checks on unrestrained by external checks is su‰ciently o‰cials would in fact operate to prevent tyr- high so that if tyranny is to be avoided over a anny; with them, it is doubtful that all of the long period, the constitutionally prescribed intragovernmental checks of the Madisonian machinery of any government must maintain system as it operates in the United States are some external checks on all o‰cials. necessary to prevent tyranny. That is, it seems reasonable to propose that even if internal checks might frequently inhibit X impulses to tyranny, they may not always do so with all individuals likely to be in a position to In the preceding discussion I have assumed that tyrannize. Hence, if tyranny is to be avoided, ‘‘tyranny’’ in the Madisonian system is a mean- external checks are required. And these external ingful term. By assuming it to be meaningful, it checks must be constitutionally prescribed. has been possible to show that Hypothesis 1 Chapter 4 214

leads to false conclusions. Now, however, we have the power to decide this question. Hence must ask whether the concept of ‘‘tyranny’’ im- this definition of tyranny seems to have no plicit in the Madisonian system, and basic to the operational meaning in the context of political usual rationale of the American constitutional decision-making.33 And, of course, it follows framework, has any operational meaning. . . . further that, if tyranny has no operational It is self-evident that the definition of tyr- meaning, then majority tyranny has no opera- anny would be entirely empty unless natural tional meaning. . . . rights could somehow be defined. It can be shown, I think, that we must specify a process by which specific natural rights can be defined XI in the context of some political society. To spec- ify this process creates some dilemmas for the If we turn to Madison’s explicit concept of fac- Madisonian. tion, we find that it su¤ers from the same di‰- If a natural right were defined, rather ab- culties as the implicit concept of tyranny. It surdly, to mean the right of every individual to would hardly be worth while to examine Madi- do what he wishes to do, then every form of son’s explicit concept of faction, however, if it government must be tyrannical; for every gov- were not for the fact that some such thought is ernment restrains at least some individuals from implicit in many other attempts to defend the doing what they wish to do. . . . idea of constitutionally prescribed checks on It follows that tyranny must be defined to ‘‘majorities.’’34 ... mean that severe penalties are inflicted only on The di‰culty with this definition of a faction some kinds of behavior. How are these kinds of is similar to the di‰culty encountered with ‘‘tyr- behavior, which it is tyrannical to restrain, to be anny.’’ How can one use this concept? . . . specified in practice? . . . The typical political situation is one in which individuals in a group or a society disagree as to XII the desirability of penalizing or rewarding cer- tain kinds of behavior. Governmental processes It is not part of my purpose to examine every are then employed to adjudicate the dispute. But detailed aspect of the Madisonian viewpoint. Yet when individuals disagree, what rule is to be one more major point is worth considering. employed to determine whether the punishing of Protection against factions and therefore some specified act would or would not be tyran- against tyranny, it will be recalled, requires two nical? One possibility is to permit the majority conditions: to decide. . . . Yet since this operating rule is precisely what Madison meant to prevent, and 33. It might be said that each individual would decide moreover would make the concept of majority himself, upon consulting his own value system, whether tyranny meaningless, we must reject it. The or not a given act was tyrannical. But this is merely a prescription for individual behavior and provides no only remaining possibility, then, is that some rule for a collective decision. specified group in the community, not defined as 34. The quotation marks reflect my belief that in the the majority, but not necessarily always in op- usual sense intended, majorities rarely, if ever, rule in position to it, would be empowered to decide. any country or social organization at any time. Thus But if Hypothesis 1 is correct, then any group the fear of majority rule, as well as the advocacy of it, in the community with such a power would use is founded upon a misconception of the probabilities it to tyrannize over other individuals in the permitted by political reality. . . . community. Hence, in practice, no one could Democracy and Constitutionalism 215

Hypothesis 8: If a faction consists of less than society, they are likely to be politically ine¤ec- a majority, it can be controlled by the operation tive; and herein lies the basic protection against of ‘‘the republican principle’’ of voting in the their exploitation of minorities. This conclusion legislative body, i.e., the majority can vote is of course scarcely compatible with the pre- down the minority. occupation with majority tyranny that is the hallmark of the Madisonian style of thought. Hypothesis 9: The development of majority faction can be limited if the electorate is numerous, extended, and diverse in interests. XIV Because, as we have seen, the terms ‘‘factions’’ The absence of specific meaning for terms like and ‘‘tyranny’’ have been given no specific ‘‘majority tyranny’’ and ‘‘faction’’ coupled with meaning, as they stand these two hypotheses the central importance of these concepts in the also have no specific meaning, i.e., no con- Madisonian style of thinking has led to a rather ceivable way exists by which we can test their tortuous political theory that is explicable ge- validity. Hence they remain mere untestable netically rather than logically. Genetically the assertions. . . . Madisonian ideology has served as a convenient rationalization for every minority that, out of XIII fear of the possible deprivations of some major- ity, has demanded a political system providing it 37 Hypothesis 9 asserts that the e¤ects of majority with an opportunity to veto such policies. ... faction can be controlled if the electorate is nu- Nevertheless, as political science rather than merous, extended, and diverse in interests. Here as ideology the Madisonian system is clearly in- again, the absence of any definite meaning of the adequate. In retrospect, the logical and empirical word faction is an obstacle to testing the predic- deficiencies of Madison’s own thought seem to tion. Yet if we examine the arguments that have arisen in large part from his inability to Madison himself used to prove the validity of reconcile two di¤erent goals. On the one hand, this hypothesis, it is clear that the hypothesis Madison substantially accepted the idea that all must be read to mean that the e¤ectiveness of the adult citizens of a republic must be assigned any majority whatsoever is severely limited if the equal rights, including the right to determine the electorate is numerous, extended, and diverse general direction of government policy. In this in interests. Whether or not the majority is sense majority rule is ‘‘the republican principle.’’ factional is irrelevant to the operation of the On the other hand, Madison wished to erect a restrictions imposed by the existence of a nu- political system that would guarantee the lib- merous, extended, and diverse electorate. Fur- erties of certain minorities whose advantages thermore, so far as I am aware, no modern of status, power, and wealth would, he thought, Madison has shown that the restraints on the ef- probably not be tolerated indefinitely by a fectiveness of majorities imposed by the facts of a pluralistic society operate only to curtail ‘‘bad’’ 37. Calhoun’s transparent defense of the southern sla- majorities and not ‘‘good’’ majorities; and I vocracy by his doctrine of concurrent majorities seems confess I see no way by which such an ingenious to me prone to all the weaknesses of the Madisonian proposition could be satisfactorily established. system, which in many respects it parallels. But I have not tried to deal specifically with Calhoun’s special Hence the net e¤ect of Hypothesis 9 seems to variant on Madison. Cf. his Disquisition on Govern- be this: because majorities are likely to be un- ment, ed. R. K. Cralle (New York: Peter Smith, 1943), stable and transitory in a large and pluralistic esp. pp. 28–38. Chapter 4 216

constitutionally untrammeled majority. Hence majorities had to be constitutionally inhibited. Madisonianism, historically and presently, is a compromise between these two conflicting goals. I think I have shown that the explicit and im- plicit terms of the compromise do not bear care- ful analysis. Perhaps it is foolish to expect them to. . . . A Bill of Rights for Britain

Ronald Dworkin

When the eminent French historian Franc¸ois to restore the British culture of liberty? Learned Furet came recently to Britain to lecture on the Hand, a great American constitutional judge, occasion of the bicentennial of the French Rev- said that when the spirit of freedom dies in a olution, he said that the signal triumph of de- people, no constitution or Supreme Court can mocracy in our time is the growing acceptance bring it back to life. And it is true that many and enforcement of a crucial idea: that democ- nations with formal constitutional guarantees, racy is not the same thing as majority rule, and including some of the European nations that that in a real democracy liberty and minorities have made the European Convention of Human have legal protection in the form of a written Rights part of their own law, fail fully to honour constitution that even Parliament cannot change their constitutional rights in practice. But though to suit its whim or policy. Under that vision of a written constitution is certainly not a su‰cient democracy, a bill of individual constitutional condition for liberty to thrive again in Britain, it rights is part of fundamental law, and judges, may well be a necessary one. . . . who are not elected and who are therefore re- Of course the idea of a Bill of Rights is re- moved from the pressures of partisan politics, jected by many of the people you might expect are responsible for interpreting and enforcing to reject it: the leading politicians of both of the that Bill of Rights as they are for all other parts two great parties whose power, when in o‰ce, of the legal system. would be curtailed if people enjoyed constitu- The United States was born committed to that tional rights as individuals. Most Tory politi- idea of democracy, and now every member of cians, in spite of the shambles they have made of the European Community but Britain accepts it, liberty in recent years, think that their govern- and so do the great majority of other mature ment is too much rather than too little hedged in democracies, including India, Canada, and al- by judges. They howl whenever judges find the most all the other democratic Commonwealth actions of ministers and o‰cials illegal, as judges nations. Britain stands alone in insisting that have done several times in recent years, and they Parliament must have absolutely unlimited legal call for Parliament to change the law to keep power to do anything it wishes. the judges o¤ their backs. The Labour Party, British constitutional lawyers once bragged too, has so far been adamantly opposed to a that a constitutional Bill of Rights was unneces- constitutional Bill of Rights, in spite of its own sary because in Britain the people can trust the historical concern for individual liberty. For- rulers they elect. But now a great many people— tunately, there are now indications that Labour more than ever before—believe that this is no has changed its mind and will support a Bill of longer true, and that the time has come for Brit- Rights. But most of the pressure has come from ain to join other democracies and put its Parlia- the bottom rather than the top, from people ment under law. Charter 88, an organisation demanding the rights and liberties that in other created to press that argument, has attracted countries belong to them, not to the politicians. impressive support at every level of British soci- How could a Bill of Rights be enacted? One ety. Would a charter of constitutional rights help way would be remarkably simple. As I said ear- lier, Britain is already committed by interna- Excerpted from: Ronald Dworkin, A Bill of Rights for tional treaty to a charter of constitutional rights Britain. London: Chatto & Windus, 1990. Used by called the European Convention. With very little permission of The Random House Group Ltd. procedural fuss Parliament could enact a statute Chapter 4 218

providing that the principles of that convention of people accused of crimes, could be challenged are henceforth part of the law of Britain, en- at once, and not years later when the damage forceable by British judges in British courts. A was done and long past undoing. statute to that e¤ect has been introduced in Par- If the judges used this new authority well, the liament on three occasions in recent years; it was most important and immediate benefit would actually debated, as a private member’s Bill, in be a revitalisation of the liberty and dignity of 1986, though it did not obtain the necessary ma- the people. Government and o‰cials would no jority for closure to permit a vote. . . . longer be so free to keep secrets from the people In theory, then, Britain already has a consti- they are supposed to serve, or to ignore rights the tution of individual rights, enforceable by a court nation has a solemn obligation to respect. Other, in Strasbourg, which Parliament is powerless to more speculative but in the long run equally im- abridge except in a case of emergency. But the portant, benefits might then follow. . . . European Convention is no substitute for a do- If British judges began to create as well as mestic Bill of Rights interpreted and enforced follow constitutional jurisprudence in that way, by British judges trained in British traditions. their decisions would be bound to influence the A private citizen who feels his rights under the Commission and Court in Strasbourg, as well as Convention have been violated must first ex- the courts of the other nations who have signed haust whatever remedies might be thought to be the Convention, and, indeed, of all the other available at home, and then prepare and argue nations across the globe who are now wrestl- a case first before the European Commission ing with the problem of making abstract human and then, if matters go that far, before the Eu- rights concrete. Incorporation would put the ropean Court. The process is fearsomely expen- special skills of British lawyers and judges, and sive (there is, for all practical purposes, no legal the heritage of British legal principle, at the ser- aid available) and takes on average six years, by vice of the civilised world. Britain could become which time, particularly in cases involving cen- once again a leader in defining and protecting sorship, the issue is almost always academic. individual freedom, instead of a sullen defendant Two thirds of European countries, including giving ground to liberty only when ordered to do all the other major ones, have made the Con- so by a foreign court. . . . vention part of their domestic law, so that it can be raised and its benefit claimed in national The European Convention is not a perfect Bill of courts. But Britain has not done so. . . . Rights for Britain. It was a compromise drafted If Parliament made the European Conven- to accommodate a variety of nations with di¤er- tion part of British law, on the other hand, ent legal systems and traditions; it is in many judges could decide on their own whether some ways weaker than the American Bill of Rights; o‰cial action or parliamentary statute violated and it is hedged about with vague limitations the Convention. They could decide that question and powerful escape clauses of di¤erent sorts. in the same way they decide any other issue of The Convention does protect liberty better than law. So the broadcasting ban, and all the other it is now protected by Parliament alone, how- tawdry acts of censorship that violate Britain’s ever, as recent history shows. It protects freedom solemn obligations under the treaty, could be of speech, religion and expression, privacy, and challenged at once and not five or six years later the most fundamental rights of accused crimi- when the government’s aim or stopping public nals, and it grants in an indirect but e¤ective way access to information has long since been rights against discrimination. Since Britain is achieved anyway. O‰cial denials of privacy, or already subject to the Convention as a matter of of the right of legitimate protest, or of the rights both moral obligation and international law, it Democracy and Constitutionalism 219

would plainly be casier to enact that charter into At least in the first instance, therefore, propo- British law, substantially as it is, perhaps with nents should press for the weaker version of clarifying changes and additions from other in- incorporation. If they succeed, then unless Par- ternational covenants Britain has also signed, liament has expressly provided to the contrary than to begin drafting and debating a wholly any citizen will have the right in British courts new Bill of Rights. Even if it were possible to to challenge a law or an o‰cial decision on the adopt an entirely new set of rights, perhaps ground that it is o¤ensive to the Convention’s modelled on the American Constitution, the Eu- principles. Some European nations have estab- ropean Convention would remain law enforce- lished special courts to hear constitutional chal- able in Strasbourg, and the potential conflict lenges. But it would be better, at least in Britain, between the two fundamental charters of rights to allow any division of the High Court to en- would be a source of wasteful confusion. tertain such a challenge. Constitutional issues are So those who love liberty should unite in sup- not so arcane or specialised that ordinary judges, porting the incorporation of the Convention. But assisted by counsel in the normal way, could not how can this be done, and in what form should it master them. . . . be done? . . . [T]he popular argument that there is no way Parliament can impose a constitutional That is the case for incorporating the European Bill of Rights on a later Parliament is at least Convention into domestic British law. It is no dubious. But notice that I have so far been dis- mystery that powerful politicians are reluctant to cussing what might be called a strong form of accept that case. . . . incorporation, which provides that any statute The politicians say that the very idea of a Bill inconsistent with the Convention is null and of Rights restricting the power of Parliament void. Several influential supporters of a Bill of is hostile to the British tradition that Parlia- Rights . . . have proposed that in the first instance ment and Parliament alone should be sovereign. incorporation should take what is technically a That supposed tradition seems less appealing weaker form: the incorporating statute should now, when a very powerful executive and well- provide that an inconsistent statute is null and disciplined political parties mean less e¤ective void unless Parliament has expressly stated that power for backbench MPs than it did before it intends the statute to override the Convention. these developments. The tradition has already In practice this technically weaker version of in- been compromised in recent decades, moreover. corporation would probably provide almost as It was altered by the European Communities much protection as the stronger one. If a gov- Act, for example, under which judges have the ernment conceded that its statute violated the power to override parliamentary decisions in Convention, it would have no defence before order to enforce directly e¤ective Community the Commission or Court in Strasbourg. In any rules. case, quite apart from that practical point, no In any case, quite apart from these consid- respectable government would wish to announce erations, incorporating the European Conven- that it did not care whether its legislation or tion would not diminish Parliament’s present decisions violated the country’s domestic prom- power in any way that could reasonably be ises and international obligations. If a gov- thought objectionable. Parliament is already ernment felt itself able to make such an bound by international law to observe the terms announcement, except in the most extraordinary of that Convention. If the Convention were in- circumstances, the spirit of liberty would be dead corporated in what I have called the strong form, anyway, beyond the power of any constitution to under which a future Parliament would not have revive. the legal power to violate the Convention even if Chapter 4 220

it expressly said it intended to do so, then the o‰cials have been elected in otherwise fair elec- power of Parliament might be somewhat more tions, unless voters have had access to the in- limited than it is now, because British judges formation they need so that their votes can be might develop a special British interpretation of knowledgeable choices rather than only manip- the Convention that in some cases recognised ulated responses to advertising campaigns. Citi- individual constitutional rights the Strasbourg zens of a democracy must be able to participate Court would not. . . . in government not just spasmodically, in elec- The argument for parliamentary supremacy tions from time to time, but constantly through would be irrelevant, moreover, if the Convention informed and free debate about their govern- were incorporated in the weaker form I sug- ment’s performance between elections. Those gested should be the initial goal. For then Par- evident requirements suggest what other nations liament could override the Convention by mere have long ago realised: that Parliament must be majority vote, provided it was willing expressly constrained in certain ways in order that democ- to concede its indi¤erence about doing so. No racy be genuine rather than sham. The argument doubt that condition would, in practice, prevent that a Bill of Rights would be undemocratic is a government from introducing legislation it therefore not just wrong but the opposite of the might otherwise enact. That is the point of truth. . . . incorporation, even in the weak form. But forc- This seems to me a decisive answer to the ar- ing Parliament to make the choice between gument that incorporation would be undemo- obeying its international obligations and admit- cratic. I hope and believe that a di¤erent but ting that it is violating them does not limit Par- equally decisive answer can also be made in liament’s supremacy, but only its capacity for Britain now: that the argument is self-defeating duplicity. Candour is hardly inconsistent with because the great majority of British people sovereignty. . . . themselves rejects the crude statistical view of democracy on which the argument is based. The argument for parliamentary supremacy is Even people who do not think of themselves as often thought to rest on a more important and belonging to any minority have good reasons fundamental argument, however, according to for insisting that a majority’s power to rule which Britain should not have subscribed to the should be limited. Something crucially important European Convention in the first place. This is to them—their religious freedom or profes- the argument: that it is undemocratic for ap- sional independence or liberty of conscience, for pointed judges rather than an elected Parliament example—might one day prove inconvenient to to have the last word about what the law is. the government of the day. Even people who People who take that view will resist incorpora- cannot imagine being isolated in that way might tion, because incorporation enlarges the practical prefer to live in a genuine political community, consequences of what they regard as the mistake in which everyone’s dignity as an equal is pro- of accepting the Convention. They will certainly tected, rather than just in a state they control. . . . resist the idea that domestic judges should have the power to read the Convention more liberally and so provide more protection than Strasbourg requires. Their argument misunderstands what democ- racy is, however. In the first place, it confuses democracy with the power of elected o‰cials. There is no genuine democracy, even though A Right-Based Critique of Constitutional Rights

Jeremy Waldron

Secondly, I shall argue that political philoso- 1 Introduction phers should be more aware than other propo- nents of constitutional reform of the di‰culty, . . . Should we embody our rights in legalistic complexity, and controversy attending the idea formulae and proclaim them in a formal Bill of of basic rights. I shall argue that they have Rights? Or should we leave them to evolve in- reason—grounded in professional humility—to formally in dialogue among citizens, representa- be more than usually hesitant about the enact- tives and o‰cials? How are we to stop rights ment of any canonical list of rights, particularly from being violated? Should we rely on a general if the aim is to put that canon beyond the scope spirit of watchfulness in the community, at- of political debate and revision. tempting to raise what Mill called ‘‘a strong Thirdly, I shall argue that philosophers who barrier of moral conviction’’ to protect our talk about rights should pay much more atten- liberty?4 Or should we also entrust some spe- tion than they do to the processes by which cific branch of government—the courts, for decisions are taken in a community under cir- example—with the task of detecting violations cumstances of disagreement. Theories of rights and with the authority to overrule any other need to be complemented by theories of author- agency that commits them? ity, whose function it is to determine how deci- The advantages of this last approach continue sions are to be taken when the members of a to attract proponents of constitutional reform in community disagree about what decision is right. the United Kingdom. Ronald Dworkin, for ex- Since we are to assume a context of moral dis- ample, has argued that it would forge a decisive agreement, a principle such as ‘‘Let the right link between rights and legality, giving the decision be made’’ cannot form part of an ade- former much greater prominence in public life. quate principle of authority. It follows from this By throwing the authority of the courts be- that, if people disagree about basic rights (and hind the idea of rights, the legal system would they do), an adequate theory of authority can begin to play ‘‘a di¤erent, more valuable role in neither include nor be qualified by a conception society’’. . . . of rights as ‘‘trumps’’ over majoritarian forms of In this paper, I shall question that assumption. decision-making. I want to develop four main lines of argument. Finally, I shall argue that, in a constitutional The first is a negative case: I shall show that regime of the sort envisaged by proponents of there is no necessary inference from a right-based Charter 88, the courts will inevitably become the position in political philosophy to a commit- main forum for the revision and adaptation of ment to a Bill of Rights as a political institution basic rights in the face of changing circumstances along with an American-style practice of judicial and social controversies. (This of course is an review. extrapolation from the experience of constitu- tional politics in the United States.) I shall argue Excerpted from: Jeremy Waldron, ‘‘A Right-Based that a theorist of rights should have grave mis- Critique of Constitutional Rights.’’ Oxford Journal of givings about this prospect. Some of us think Legal Studies 13, no. 1 (1993): 18–51. Reprinted by that people have a right to participate in the permission of Oxford University Press. democratic governance of their community, and 4. John Stuart Mill, On Liberty, ch 1, para 15 (Indian- that this right is quite deeply connected to the apolis: Bobbs-Merrill, 1955), 18. values of autonomy and responsibility that are Chapter 4 222

celebrated in our commitment to other basic lib- called for is to think oneself justified in disabling erties. We think moreover that the right to de- legislators in this respect (and thus, indirectly, mocracy is a right to participate on equal terms in disabling the citizens whom they represent). in social decisions on issues of high principle and It is, I think, worth pondering the attitudes that it is not to be confined to interstitial matters that lie behind the enthusiasm for imposing such of social and economic policy. I shall argue that disabilities. our respect for such democratic rights is called To embody a right in an entrenched con- seriously into question when proposals are made stitutional document is to adopt a certain atti- to shift decisions about the conception and revi- tude towards one’s fellow citizens. That attitude sion of basic rights from the legislature to the is best summed up as a combination of self- courtroom, from the people and their admittedly assurance and mistrust: self-assurance in the imperfect representative institutions to a hand- proponent’s conviction that what she is putting ful of men and women, supposedly of wisdom, forward really is a matter of fundamental right learning, virtue and high principle who, it is and that she has captured it adequately in the thought, alone can be trusted to take seriously particular formulation she is propounding; and the great issues that they raise? . . . mistrust, implicit in her view that any alternative For these reasons, then, the proponent of a conception that might be concocted by elected given right may be hesitant about embodying it legislators next year or the year after is so likely in a constitutionally entrenched Bill of Rights. to be wrong-headed or ill-motivated that her own She may figure that the gain, in terms of an im- formulation is to be elevated immediately be- munity against wrongful legislative abrogation, yond the reach of ordinary legislative revision. is more than o¤set by the loss in our ability to This attitude of mistrust of one’s fellow citi- evolve a free and flexible discourse. zens does not sit particularly well with the aura But the deepest reasons of liberal principle of respect for their autonomy and responsibility have yet to be addressed. When a principle is that is conveyed by the substance of the rights entrenched in a constitutional document, the which are being entrenched in this way. The claim-right (to liberty or provision) that it lays substantive importance of a given right may well down is compounded with an immunity against be based on a view of the individual person as legislative change. Those who possess the right essentially a thinking agent, endowed with an now get the additional advantage of its being ability to deliberate morally and to transcend a made di‰cult or impossible to alter their legal preoccupation with her own particular or sec- position. That can sound attractive; but as W. N. tional interests. For example, an argument for Hohfeld emphasized, we should always look at freedom of speech may depend on a view of both sides of any legal advantage.30 The term people as ‘‘political animals’’ in Aristotle’s sense, correlative to the claim-right is of course the capable of evolving a shared and reliable sense duty incumbent upon o‰cials and others to re- of right and wrong, justice and injustice, in spect and uphold the right. And the term correl- their conversations with one another.31 If this is ative to the constitutional immunity is what why one thinks free speech important, one can- Hohfeld would call a disability: in e¤ect, a dis- not simply turn round and announce that the abling of the legislature from its normal func- products of any deliberative process are to be tions of revision, reform and innovation in the mistrusted. law. To think that a constitutional immunity is If, on the other hand, the desire for entrench- ment is motivated by a predatory view of human 30. Wesley N. Hohfeld, Fundamental Legal Con- ceptions (New Haven: Yale University Press, 1923). 31. See Aristotle, Politics, Bk I, ch 2, 1253al–18 (3). Democracy and Constitutionalism 223

nature and of what people will do to one another majority voting among its members)44 on issues when let loose in the arena of democratic poli- of fundamental rights is just such a procedural tics, it will be di‰cult to explain how or why rule. It too may (and sometimes has) yielded people are to be viewed as essentially bearers of egregiously unjust decisions.45 Anyone whose rights. For in order to develop a theory of rights, theory of authority gives the Supreme Court we need some basis for distinguishing those power to make decisions must—as much as any interests which are characteristic of human dig- democrat—face up to the paradox that the op- nity from those which are relatively unimportant tion she thinks is just may not be the option in a person’s activity and desires. If our only which, according to her theory of authority, image of man is that of a self-seeking animal should be followed. . . . who is not to be trusted with a concern for the interests of others, we lack the conception of dignified moral autonomy on which such dis- 10 Imperfect Democracy criminations of interest might be based. These are not intended as knock-down argu- . . . [T]he enactment of a Bill of Rights need not ments against constitutionalization. All I have involve the entrenchment of one particular view tried to show so far is that there is nothing obvi- of individual rights beyond the reach of chal- ous about combining a respect for rights with a lenge or reform. A Bill of Rights can specify profound mistrust of people in their democratic procedures for amendment; and certainly one and representative capacities. Accordingly there upshot of the argument I have made is that we is nothing perverse in saying: ‘‘The reasons should insist on such opportunities for constitu- which make me think of the human individual as tional revision, for they give a politically em- a bearer of rights are the very reasons that allow powered people the chance to think afresh about me to trust her as the bearer of political respon- their understanding of individual rights.64 How- sibilities. It is precisely because I see each per- ever, even if the e¤orts of rights-proponents fall son as a potential moral agent, endowed with short of absolute entrenchment, there is a temp- dignity and autonomy, that I am willing to en- tation to make the amendment process as di‰- trust the people en masse with the burden of self- cult as possible, a temptation often motivated by government.’’ Once we see this as an intelligible the same self-assured mistrust of one’s fellow set of attitudes, we might be more hesitant in citizens that I have been criticizing throughout expressing our enthusiasm for rights in terms of the disabling of representative institutions. . . . 44. So it is a little misleading to describe the demo- cratic objection to judicial review in the US as ‘‘the counter-majoritarian di‰culty’’—cf Alexander Bickel, 5 Doing Philosophy The Least Dangerous Branch: the Supreme Court at the Bar of Politics (New Haven: Yale University Press, . . . American-style judicial review is often 1962), 16. The US Supreme Court is a majoritarian defended by pointing to the possibility that institution; the problem is the very small number of participants in its majoritarian decision-making. democratic majoritarian procedures may yield unjust or tyrannical outcomes. And so they may. 45. For an uncontroversial example of an egregiously unjust decision, see the ‘‘Dred Scott’’ decision, Scott v But so may any procedure that purports to solve Sandford 60 US (19 How) 393 (1857). the problem of social choice in the face of dis- 64. The opportunity for constitutional amendment is agreements about what counts as injustice or celebrated, in the American context, in Bruce Acker- what counts as tyranny. The rule that the Su- man, ‘‘The Storrs Lectures: Discovering the Constitu- preme Court should make the final decision (by tion,’’ (1984) 93 Yale Law Journal 1013. Chapter 4 224

this paper. At the very least, it is thought appro- enforced, is a proposal to institute a similar situ- priate that any amendment to a Bill of Rights ation: to allow in e¤ect routine constitutional should require a super-majority, and often the revision by the courts and to disallow routine procedural obstacles that are proposed are much constitutional revision by Parliament. I hope it is more formidable than that. easy to see . . . why this arrogation of judicial The point of such super-majoritarian require- authority, this disabling of representative insti- ments is, presumably, to reduce the probability tutions, and above all this quite striking political that any amendment will be successful. To the inequality, should be frowned upon by any right- extent that that is the aim, one needs to ask: how based theory that stresses the importance of is the Bill of Rights to be made responsive to democratic participation on matters of principle changing circumstances and di¤erent opinions in by ordinary men and women. the community over time about the rights we Responses to this critique take three forms. have and the way they should be formulated? First, it is argued that the judicial power of in- Are the formulations of one generation to be cast terpretation and revision is simply unavoidable. in stone, and given precedence over all subse- After all, it is the job of the courts to apply the quent revisions, save for the rare occasion on law. They cannot do that except by trying to which the obstacles to amendment can be sur- understand what the law says, and that involves mounted? Or are there to be, in e¤ect, other and interpreting it. . . . even less democratic procedures for constitu- However, the inescapability of judicial inter- tional revision than these? pretation does not settle the issue of whether The experience of the United States indicates other institutions should not also have the power the importance of the latter possibility. For, of to revise the o‰cial understanding of rights. On course, there it would be quite misleading to any account of the activity of the US Supreme suggest that the formal amendment procedure Court over the past century or so, the inescap- exhausts the possibilities for constitutional revi- able duty to interpret the law has been taken as sion. In addition to the processes specified in the occasion for serious and radical revision. Article V of the US Constitution, changes in the There may not be anything wrong with that, American Bill of Rights have come about most but there is something wrong in conjoining it often through the exercise of judicial power. The with an insistence that the very rights which Supreme Court is not empowered to alter the the judges are interpreting and revising are to be written terms of the Bill of Rights. But the jus- put beyond the reach of democratic revision and tices do undertake the task of altering the way reinterpretation. in which the document is interpreted and ap- In the end, either we believe in the need for plied, and the way in which individual rights are a cumbersome amendment process or we do authoritatively understood—in many cases with not. If we do, then we should be disturbed by drastic and far-reaching e¤ects. . . . the scale of the revisions in which the judges en- Members of the higher judiciary in the United gage (inescapably, on Dworkin’s account). They States have the power to revise the o‰cial un- find themselves routinely having to think afresh derstanding of rights for that society and, when about the rights that people have, and having to they do, their view prevails. The ordinary elec- choose between rival conceptions of those rights, tors and their state and Congressional repre- in just the way that traditional arguments for sentatives do not have that power, at least in any making amendment di‰cult are supposed to sense that counts. A proposal to establish a Bill preclude. It is no answer to this that the amend- of Rights for Britain, judicially interpreted and ment process focuses particularly on changes in Democracy and Constitutionalism 225

constitutional wording, and that the judges are cratic credentials. Judicial review, it may be said, not assuming the power to make verbal alter- is a form of democratic representation, albeit a ations. For one thing, judicial doctrine in the US rather indirect form. In the US, justices are has yielded catch-phrases (such as ‘‘clear and nominated to the Supreme Court by the Presi- present danger,’’ or ‘‘substantive due process,’’ dent and their appointment is ratified by the or ‘‘strict scrutiny’’) which have become as much Senate, and in the United Kingdom appoint- a part of the verbalism of the American consti- ments to the higher judiciary are made on the tutional heritage as anything in the Constitution advice of the Prime Minister, who is of course itself. For another thing, it cannot be that the head of the elected government. To that extent, words matter more—and so need more protec- the authority of a judge is an upshot of the exer- tion from change—than our substantive under- cise of elected representative power, and recent standing of the content of the rights themselves. American experience shows that occasionally If, on the other hand, we think it desirable that something of an electoral issue can be made of a Bill of Rights should be treated as ‘‘a living who a Presidential candidate’s Supreme Court organism . . . capable of growth—of expansion nominees are likely to be. and of adaptation to new conditions,’’67 then we But it is not enough to show, as this argument do have to face the question of authority: who does, a scintilla of democratic respectability in should be empowered to participate in this quo- the constitution of judicial power. For that does tidian organic process? Now, if Dworkin is right, not show that the courts should have prerog- the question is not ‘‘Who?’’ but ‘‘The judges and atives that the people and their directly elected who else?,’’ for the judges’ participation is ines- representatives lack, nor does it establish that capable. But if it is really thought to be necessary when judicial authority clashes with parliamen- for society ‘‘to adapt canons of right to situa- tary authority, the former ought to prevail. The tions not envisaged by those who framed them, sponsors of a piece of legislation struck down by thereby facilitating their evolution and preserv- a court can also point to a democratic pedigree. ing their vitality,’’68 it is di‰cult to see why the They can say, moreover, that if the people dis- ordinary people and their representatives should agree with their legislation, they can hold them be excluded from this process. Or rather—and accountable for it at the next election, throw more disturbingly—it is all too easy to see why: them out of o‰ce, and elect MPs who are those who want an adaptive constitution do not pledged to repeal it, and so on. Nothing like that trust the people to participate in its adaptation. can be said in behalf of the judges. That distrust, it seems to me, is something we In other words, the second response goes should recoil from, on the same right-based wrong by failing to see that the issue is essen- ground as we recoil from any attempt to exclude tially a comparative one. If a majority of judges people from the governance of the society in in the House of Lords, for example, strikes down which they live. legislation passed by majoritarian processes in A second response is to appeal, not to the parliament, then the voting powers of a few inescapability of judicial power, but to its demo- judges are being held to prevail over the voting powers of the people’s representatives. To pro- 67. Justice Brandeis, quoted in William Brennan, vide a democratic justification for the judges’ ‘‘Why Have a Bill of Rights?’’ (1989) 9 OJLS 426. prevailing, one has to show not only that they 68. Brennan, ‘‘Why Have a Bill of Rights?’’ 426. have democratic credentials but that they have a (These are Brennan’s own words now, not those of better democratic claim than that asserted in the Brandeis.) legislative action in question. I don’t know of Chapter 4 226

any jurist who can maintain that (with a straight issue by issue; and as for deliberation, Prime face).69 Minister’s Question-time and party political Consider, moreover, how artificial this line broadcasts on television hardly answer to the of argument is. It is true that judges are high-minded account of participation that we appointed by elected o‰cials. But the courts developed in Section 8. It is all very well to say are not, either in their ethos or image, elective that Parliament has a democratic self-image. institutions, whereas parliament—whatever its What are we to say about the numerous ways in imperfections—obviously is. Both in theory and which the corrupt reality falls short of this ideal? in political practice, the legislature is thought of We must remember, once again, what that as the main embodiment of popular government: argument is seeking to justify—the disempower- it is where responsible representatives of the ment of ordinary citizens, on matters of the people engage in what they would proudly de- highest moral and political importance. No one scribe as the self-government of the society. Now ever thought that the imperfection of existing there are lots of dignified ways of describing the representative institutions was a justification judiciary, but ‘‘locus of representative authority’’ for not enfranchising women, or that in the is unlikely to be one of them. Since my argument United States it could be an argument to con- is in part about the respect and honour we ac- tinue denying political rights to Americans of cord to the people in our constitutional struc- African descent. If someone were to meet those tures, it is important to understand that when participatory demands with an argument like a court strikes down a piece of legislation, a the one we are currently considering, the move branch of the government that neither thinks of would be rejected immediately as an insult. . . . itself, nor is thought of, as a representative insti- The other thing to note about the argument tution is striking down the act of an institution from the imperfections of democracy is that it is that is seen in more or less precisely that way. still not an argument in favour of judicial power. Thirdly and perhaps most insidiously, it is The imperfection of one institution, by demo- argued that the objection to judicial power is a cratic standards, goes no way towards justifying weak one, since both legislative and plebiscitary the imperfection of another. One cannot, for ex- channels are rather imperfect forms of democ- ample, legitimize the power of the monarchy or racy. Now it is certainly true that the processes the unelected second chamber by pointing to the of election, representation, and legislation, as democratic imperfections of the House of Com- they actually exist in the United Kingdom, are mons (egregious though they are); for the Lords quite imperfect by democratic standards. The and the monarchy are even worse from a demo- executive dominates the House of Commons, cratic point of view. To empower those institu- leaving it weak as an independent institution; tions is to compound rather than mitigate the small or new parties are squeezed out by the imperfections of British democracy. The same plurality system; voters have to choose between applies to the courts. Even if we agree that whole packages of policies and cannot vote parliament is not the epitome of democratic decision-making, the question is whether allow- 69. I shall not waste time with the argument that since ing parliamentary decisions to be overridden by judges live in the same community as the rest of us and the courts makes matters better or worse from a read the newspapers, etc, their views about rights are democratic point of view. therefore ‘‘informally’’ in tune with, and representative Ronald Dworkin has argued that ‘‘[i]f we give of, the views prevalent in the community. Even if this is up the idea that there is a canonical form of de- true, the same might be said of any dictator who mocracy, then we must also surrender the idea inhabits the society that she dominates. that judicial review is wrong because it inevitably Democracy and Constitutionalism 227

compromises democracy.’’70 Certainly there is that. But we must not confuse the reason for no canonical form of democracy—no final or carrying out a proposal with the character of the transcendently given set of answers to the ques- proposal itself. If the people wanted to experi- tion of what institutions can best embody the ment with dictatorship, principles of democracy popular aspiration to self-government. But the might give us a reason to allow them to do so. argument against judicial reform does not de- But it would not follow that dictatorship is pend on our access to a democratic canon. It democratic. Everyone agrees that it is possible depends solely on the point that, whatever you for a democracy to vote itself out of existence; say about your favourite democratic procedures, that, for the proponents of constitutional reform, decision-making on matters of high importance is one of their great fears. My worry is that by a small elite that disempowers the people or popular support for the constitutional reforms their elected and accountable representatives is envisaged by Dworkin and other members of going to score lower than decision-making by the Charter 88 amounts to exactly that: voting de- people or their elected and accountable repre- mocracy out of existence, at least so far as a wide sentatives. It may score higher in terms of the range of issues of political principle is concerned. substantive quality of the decision. But it will not There is a debate going on in Britain about score higher in terms of the respect accorded to these issues. Citizens are deliberating about ordinary citizens’ moral and political capacities. whether to limit the powers of parliament and enhance the powers of the judiciary along the lines we have been discussing. One of the things 11 Democratic Self-Restraint they are considering in this debate is whether such moves will make Britain more or less dem- If a Bill of Rights is incorporated into British law ocratic. This article is intended as a contribution it will be because parliament (or perhaps the to that debate: I have o¤ered grounds for think- people in a referendum) will have voted for in- ing that this reform will make Britain less of a corporation. Ronald Dworkin has argued that democracy. What the participants in that debate this fact alone is su‰cient to dispose of the do not need to be told is that constitutional re- democratic objections we have been considering. form will make Britain more democratic if they The objections, in his view, are self-defeating think it does. For they are trying to work out because polls reveal that more than 71 percent what to think on precisely that issue. of people believe that British democracy would Dworkin also suggests that the democratic ar- be improved by the incorporation of a Bill of gument against a Bill of Rights is self-defeating Rights.71 in a British context, ‘‘because a majority of Brit- However, the matter cannot be disposed of ish people themselves rejects the crude statistical so easily. For one thing, the fact that there is view of democracy on which the argument is popular support, even overwhelming popular based.’’72 But although democracy connotes the support, for an alteration in constitutional pro- idea of popular voting, it is not part of the con- cedures does not show that such alteration cept of democracy that its own content be fixed therefore makes things more democratic. Cer- by popular voting. If a majority of the British tainly, my arguments entail that if the people people thought a military dictatorship was dem- want a regime of constitutional rights, then that ocratic (because more in tune with the ‘‘true is what they should have: democracy requires spirit of the people’’ or whatever), that would not show that it was, nor would it provide 70. Dworkin, A Matter of Principle, 70. 71. Dworkin, A Bill of Rights for Britain, 36–37. 72. Ibid., 36. Chapter 4 228

grounds for saying that democratic arguments the same function in relation to democratic against the dictatorship were ‘‘self-defeating.’’ If values as strategies like hiding the cigarettes or Dworkin wants to make a case against ‘‘the handing the car keys to a friend serve in relation crude statistical view’’ as a conception of de- to the smoker’s or the drinker’s autonomy.74 mocracy, he must argue for it: that is, he must The analogy is an interesting one, but it is not show that a system in which millions of votes ultimately persuasive. In the cases of individual cast by ordinary people are actually counted, and pre-commitment, the person is imagined to be actually count for something when decisions are quite certain, in her lucid moments, about the being made against a background of disagree- actions she wants to avoid and the basis of their ment, is a worse conception of the values set out undesirability. The smoker knows that smoking in section 8 than a model in which votes count is damaging her health and she can give a clear only when they accord with a particular theory explanation in terms of the pathology of addic- of what citizens owe one another in the way of tion of why she still craves a smoke notwith- equal concern and respect. standing her possession of that knowledge. The However, Dworkin’s comments do point the drinker knows at the beginning of the evening way to what is perhaps a more sophisticated that her judgment at midnight about her own answer to the democratic objection. We are fa- ability to drive safely will be seriously impaired. miliar in personal ethics with the idea of ‘‘pre- But the case we are dealing with is that of a commitment’’—the idea that an individual may society whose members disagree, even in their have reason to impose on herself certain con- ‘‘lucid’’ moments, about what rights they have, straints so far as her future decision-making is how they are to be conceived, and what weight concerned. Ulysses, for example, decided that he they are to be given in relation to other values. should be bound to the mast in order to resist the They need not appeal to aberrations in ratio- charms of the sirens, and he instructed his crew nality to explain these disagreements; they are, that ‘‘if I beg you to release me, you must tighten as we have seen, su‰ciently explained by the and add to my bonds.’’73 Similarly, a smoker subject-matter itself. A pre-commitment in these trying to quit may hide her own cigarettes, and a circumstances, then, is not the triumph of pre- heavy drinker may give her car keys to a friend emptive rationality that it appears to be in the at the beginning of a party with strict instruc- smoker’s or in the drinker’s case. It is rather the tions not to return them when they are requested artificially sustained ascendancy of one view in at midnight. These forms of pre-commitment the polity over other views whilst the philosoph- strike us as the epitome of self-governance rather ical issue between them remains unresolved. . . . than as a derogation from that ideal. So, simi- Upholding another’s pre-commitment may larly, it may be said, an electorate could decide be regarded as a way of respecting her auton- collectively to bind itself in advance to resist the omy only if a clear line can be drawn be- siren charms of rights-violations in the future. tween the aberrant mental phenomena the Aware, as much as the smoker or the drinker, of pre-commitment was supposed to override, on the temptations of wrong or irrational action the one hand, and genuine uncertainty, changes under pressure, the people of a society might in a of mind, conversions, etc, on the other hand. In lucid moment put themselves under certain con- the drunk driver case, we can draw such a line; stitutional disabilities—disabilities which serve in the theological case, we have much more di‰culty, and that is why respecting the pre- 73. Quoted in Jon Elster, Ulysses and the Sirens: commitment seems like taking sides in an inter- Studies in Rationality and Irrationality (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1984), 36. 74. I am grateful to Eric Rakowski for these analogies. Democracy and Constitutionalism 229

nal dispute between two factions warring on so far as the governance of the community roughly equal terms. was concerned. Most theories of rights commit Clearly there are dangers in any simplistic themselves also to democratic rights: the right analogy between the rational autonomy of indi- to participate in the political process through viduals and the democratic governance of a voting, speech, activism, party association, and community. The idea of a society binding itself candidacy. I have argued that these rights are in against certain legislative acts in the future is danger of being abrogated by the sort of pro- particularly problematic in cases where the posals put forward by members of Charter 88 in members of that society disagree with one an- the United Kingdom. other about the need for such bonds, or if they The matter is one of great importance. People agree abstractly about the need, disagree about fought long and hard for the vote and for dem- their content or character. It is particularly ocratic representation. They wanted the right to problematic where such disagreements can be govern themselves, not just on mundane issues of expected to persist and to develop and change policy, but also on high matters of principle. in unpredictable ways. If, moreover, the best They rejected the Platonic view that the people explanation of these persisting disagreements is are incapable of thinking through issues of jus- that the issues the society is addressing are tice. Consider the struggles there have been, in just very di‰cult issues, then we have no justifi- Britain, Europe and America—first for the abo- cation whatever for regarding the temporary lition of property qualifications, secondly for the ascendancy of one or other party to the dis- extension of the franchise to women, and thirdly, agreement as an instance of full and rational for bringing the legacy of civil rights denials to pre-commitment on the part of the entire soci- an end in the context of American racism. In all ety. In these circumstances, the logic of pre- those struggles, people have paid tribute to the commitment must simply be put aside, and we democratic aspiration to self-governance, with- must leave the members of the society to work out any sense at all that it should confine itself to out their di¤erences and to change their minds in the interstitial quibbles of policy that remain to collective decision-making over time, the best be settled after some lawyerly elite have decided way they can. the main issues of principle. These thoughts, I have argued, are reinforced when we consider how much room there is for 13 Conclusion honest and good faith disagreement among citi- zens on the topic of rights. Things might be dif- It is odd that people expect theorists of rights ferent if principles of right were self-evident or if to support the institutionalization of a Bill of there were a philosophical elite who could be Rights and the introduction of American-style trusted to work out once and for all what rights practices of judicial review. All modern theories we have and how they are to be balanced against of rights claim to respect the capacity of ordinary other considerations. But the consensus of the men and women to govern their own lives on philosophers is that these matters are not settled, terms that respect the equal capacities of others. that they are complex and controversial, and It is on this basis that we argue for things like that certainly in the seminar room the existence freedom of worship, the right to life and liberty, of good faith disagreement is undeniable. Since free speech, freedom of contract, the right to that is so, it seems to me obvious that we should property, freedom of emigration, privacy and view the disagreements about rights that exist reproductive freedoms. It would be curious if among citizens in exactly the same light, unless nothing followed from these underlying ideas there is compelling evidence to the contrary. It is Chapter 4 230

no doubt possible that a citizen or an elected ‘‘the counter-majoritarian di‰culty,’’ we should politician who disagrees with my view of rights is distinguish between a court’s deciding things by motivated purely by self-interest. But it is some- a majority, and lots and lots of ordinary men what uncomfortable to recognize that she prob- and women deciding things by a majority. If ably entertains exactly the same thought about we do this, we will see that the question ‘‘Who me. Since the issue of rights before us remains gets to participate?’’ always has priority over controversial, there seems no better reason to the question ‘‘How do they decide, when they adopt my view of rights as definitive and dismiss disagree?’’ her opposition as self-interested, than to regard Above all, when we think about taking certain me as the selfish opponent and her as the de- issues away from the people and entrusting them fender of principle. to the courts, we should adopt the same individ- Of course such issues have got to be settled. If ualist focus that we use for thinking about any I say P has a right to X and my opponent dis- other issue of rights. Someone concerned about agrees, some process has got to be implemented rights does not see social issues in impersonal to determine whether P is to get X or not. P and terms: she does not talk about ‘‘the problem of people like her cannot be left waiting for our torture’’ or ‘‘the problem of censorship’’ but disagreements to resolve themselves. One of us at about the predicament of each and every indi- least will be dissatisfied by the answer that the vidual who may be tortured or silenced by the process comes up with, and it is possible that the State. Similarly, we should think not about answer may be wrong. But the existence of that ‘‘the people’’ or ‘‘the majority,’’ as some sort of possibility—which is, as we have seen, an im- blurred quantitative mass, but of the individual portant truth about all human authority— citizens, considered one by one, who make up should not be used, as it is so often, exclusively the polity in question. to discredit the democratic process. There is al- If we are going to defend the idea of an ways something bad about the denial of one’s entrenched Bill of Rights put e¤ectively beyond rights. But there is nothing specially bad about revision by anyone other than the judges, we the denial of rights at the hands of a majority of should try and think what we might say to some one’s fellow citizens. public-spirited citizen who wishes to launch a In the end, I think, the matter comes down to campaign or lobby her MP on some issue of this. If a process is democratic and comes up rights about which she feels strongly and on with the correct result, it does no injustice to which she has done her best to arrive at a con- anyone. But if the process is non-democratic, it sidered and impartial view. She is not asking to inherently and necessarily does an injustice, in its be a dictator; she perfectly accepts that her voice operation, to the participatory aspirations of the should have no more power than that of anyone ordinary citizen. And it does this injustice, tyr- else who is prepared to participate in politics. annizes in this way, whether it comes up with the But—like her su¤ragette forebears—she wants correct result or not. a vote; she wants her voice and her activity to One of my aims in all this has been to ‘‘dis- count on matters of high political importance. aggregate’’ our concepts of democracy and ma- In defending a Bill of Rights, we have to jority rule. Instead of talking in grey and abstract imagine ourselves saying to her: ‘‘You may write terms about democracy, we should focus our at- to the newspaper and get up a petition and or- tention on the individuals—the millions of men ganize a pressure group to lobby Parliament. But and women—who claim a right to a say, on even if you succeed, beyond your wildest dreams, equal terms, in the processes by which they are and orchestrate the support of a large number of governed. Instead of talking impersonally about like-minded men and women, and manage to Democracy and Constitutionalism 231

prevail in the legislature, your measure may be challenged and struck down because your view of what rights we have does not accord with the judges’ view. When their votes di¤er from yours, theirs are the votes that will prevail.’’ It is my submission that saying this does not comport with the respect and honour normally accorded to ordinary men and women in the context of a theory of rights. The Political Origins of Judicial Empowerment through Constitutionalization: Lessons from Four Constitutional Revolutions

Ran Hirschl

The constitutionalization of rights has recently about a growing reliance on adjudicative means become a booming industry. Many countries for clarifying and settling crucial public policy and several supranational entities (e.g., the Eu- issues and normative debates (Tate and Val- ropean Union) have engaged in fundamental linder 1995).3 These global trends have been constitutional reform over the past three de- described by scholars as ‘‘one of the most sig- cades.1 Significantly, nearly every recently nificant developments in comparative politics’’ adopted constitution or constitutional revision (Gibson, Caldeira, and Baird 1998, 343) and contains a bill of rights and establishes some form of active judicial review.2 In most countries 2. E.g., Canada adopted a Charter of Rights in 1982. in which a constitutional bill of rights has been Brazil adopted a Bill of Rights in 1988. New Zealand recently enacted, there has been an increasing adopted a Bill of Rights in 1990, and Hong Kong did intrusion of the judiciary into the prerogatives so in 1991. Almost all the new democracies in Eastern of legislatures and executives and a correspond- Europe adopted bills of basic rights as part of their new ing acceleration of the process whereby political constitutions. Israel adopted Basic Laws on human agendas have been judicialized, thus bringing rights in 1992. Peru adopted a Bill of Rights in 1993. Denmark adopted the European Convention on Hu- man Rights in 1993, and Sweden did so in 1995. South Excerpted from: Ran Hirschl, ‘‘The Political Origins of Africa adopted a Bill of Rights as part of its new con- Judicial Empowerment through Constitutionalization: stitution in 1993. Even Britain, the last bastion of the Lessons from Four Constitutional Revolutions.’’ Law Westminster system, has embarked on a comprehen- and Social Inquiry: Journal of the American Bar Foun- sive overhaul of its political institutions. This overhaul dation 25, no. 1 (2000): 91–149. 6 2000 American Bar is most notably marked by the newly elected Labour Foundation. Reprinted by permission. Government’s consideration of a bill of rights to for- 1. A partial list of countries that have undergone fun- mally incorporate the provisions of the European damental constitutional reform since the early 1970s Convention for the Protection of Human Rights and includes new democracies in Eastern Europe (e.g., Fundamental Freedoms into British constitutional law. Hungary 1990, Romania 1991, Bulgaria 1991, Poland On November 9, 1998, the proposed Human Rights 1992, the Czech Republic 1993, Russia 1993, Slovakia Act gained royal assent. This enshrined the act in law 1993); new democracies in Southern Europe (e.g., and marked the first rights legislation to be introduced Greece 1975, Portugal 1976; Spain 1978, Turkey 1982); in the United Kingdom in 300 years. new democracies in Africa (e.g., Mozambique 1990, 3. Substantive judicial review is almost always related Zambia 1991, Uganda 1992, Ghana 1993, Ethiopia to the existence of a justiciable bill of rights. If the 1995, South Africa 1993 and 1996); new independent constitution does not provide rights for individuals countries in Africa (e.g., Zimbabwe 1980, Namibia against the state, judicial review is often confined to 1990, Eritrea 1993); other African countries (e.g., procedural matters. Ordinarily, the probability of in- Egypt 1980); Asian countries and territories (e.g., Sri tervention by the judiciary into highly political, or Lanka 1978, the Philippines 1987; Hong Kong 1991, politicized, issues is rather low in these circumstances. Vietnam 1992, Cambodia 1993); Pacific Islands (e.g., The existence of a constitutional bill of rights in a pol- Papua New-Guinea 1975, Solomon Islands 1978, Cook ity, on the other hand, provides the necessary institu- Islands 1981, Niue 1994, Fiji 1998); Latin American tional conditions for judicial review to expand its countries (e.g., Chile 1980, Nicaragua 1987, Brazil boundaries to encompass substantive political issues 1988, Colombia 1991, Peru 1993, Bolivia 1994); and central to that polity. The rise of a ‘‘politics of rights’’ industrialized democracies (e.g., Sweden 1975, Canada following the constitutionalization of rights further 1982, Israel 1992, New Zealand 1990 and 1993). For facilitates the process whereby political disputes are comprehensive surveys see Maddox (1995); and Blau- judicialized. stein and Flanz (1998). Democracy and Constitutionalism 233

as ‘‘one of the most significant trends in late- Since judiciaries and national high courts pos- twentieth and early-twenty-first-century govern- sess neither military nor financial power and do ment’’ (Tate and Vallinder 1995, 5). not bring much leverage to negotiations with the Despite the fact that judicial power has other branches of government, the question recently been expanded in many countries arises of how we can explain judicial empower- through the constitutional entrenchment of ment in relatively open polities that were not rights and the establishment of judicial review, subject to comprehensive changes in the political very few studies have thoroughly examined the or economic regimes. The removal of policy- political vectors behind the recent global wave of making authority from legislatures and execu- judicial empowerment. . . . tives and its investiture in the courts through the Three broad categories of constitutionaliza- enactment of constitutional catalogues of rights tion have been most common in the past three and the establishment of judicial review seems, decades. In some countries constitutionalization prima facie, to run counter to the interests of was part of a dual transition to democracy and power holders in legislatures and executives. market economy (e.g., countries in the Eastern I suggest that neither the institutional fortifi- Bloc). In other countries, constitutionalization of cation of judiciaries nor the accelerated judicial- rights and the expansion of judicial power were ization of politics that often follows it develop byproducts of a transition to democracy (e.g., in isolation from the central political struggles South Africa, several Latin American countries and interests that structure political systems. Po- in the 1980s, and a number of southern Euro- litical power holders usually attempt to shape pean countries in the late 1970s). In many other the institutional structure within which they op- countries, the constitutionalization of rights has erate so that it best suits their interests. Since neither been accompanied by, nor has resulted institutions such as bills of rights and judiciaries from, fundamental changes in political or eco- do not possess independent enforcement power nomic regime (e.g., Canada 1982, Belgium 1985, but nonetheless limit the flexibility of decision New Zealand 1990, and Israel 1992). Most if not makers, those who establish such institutions all constitutional revolutions of the two latter must generally think it serves their interests to types have taken place in societies deeply divided abide by the limits imposed by them. In other along political, economic, or ethnic lines.5 This words, those who are eager to pay the price of article seeks to o¤er a coherent explanation for judicial empowerment assume that their posi- the seemingly counterintuitive, voluntary dele- tion vis-a-vis other political forces would be im- gation of policymaking authority from legis- proved under a ‘‘juristocracy.’’ latures and executives to judiciaries through Hence, the process of judicial empowerment constitutionalization of rights in internally frag- through the constitutionalization of rights may mented polities. . . . accelerate when the hegemony of ruling elites in majoritarian decision-making arenas is 5. To these three common constitutionalization one threatened by ‘‘peripheral’’ groups. As such might add, of course, the domestic constitutionaliza- threats become severe, hegemonic elites who tion of rights through supranational treaties and its possess disproportionate access to and influence impact upon constitutional reforms in member coun- upon the legal arena may initiate a constitutional tries of such supranational regimes (as in the recent entrenchment of rights in order to transfer power enactment in the United Kingdom of the Human to the courts. This process of conscious judicial Rights Act, 1998, or the incorporation of the ECHR empowerment in relatively open, rule-of-law provisions into domestic law in Denmark in 1993 and polities is likely to occur when the judiciary’s in Sweden in 1995). public reputation for political impartiality and Chapter 4 234

rectitude is relatively high and when the courts decision makers, and because such institutions are likely to rule, by and large, in accordance carry no arms and hold no independent purse with the cultural propensities of the hegemonic strings, it must be in the interest of actors who community. In other words, judicial empower- establish such institutions and protect their au- ment through the constitutional fortification of tonomy to abide by the limits imposed by those rights may provide an e‰cient institutional institutions. When the establishment of judicial way for hegemonic sociopolitical forces to pre- review is initiated by those whose prima facie serve their hegemony and to secure their policy decision-making flexibility it is likely to limit, the preferences even when majoritarian decision- most plausible assumption is that those who ini- making processes are not operating to their tiated the reform, or who consciously refrained advantage. . . . from blocking it despite having the power to do so, estimate that the reform will enhance their relative power vis-a-vis other elements in the II. The Hegemonic Preservation Thesis political system.15 Thus, political actors who es- tablish self-enforcing institutions such as con- My explanation for judicial empowerment as stitutions and judicial review, and the hegemonic based on the struggle for hegemony suggests that elites who actively support or refrain from legal innovators, that is, politicians, representing blocking such reforms, assume that their costs cultural and economic elites, in cooperation under the new institutional structure will prove with the legal elite, determine the timing, extent, less expensive than the limits the new institu- and nature of constitutional reforms. Legal in- tional structure will impose on rival political novations are, in other words, products of the elements.16 interplay between hegemonic elites (and their political representatives) and the legal profes- 15. The now classic argument of North and Weingast sion. Political actors representing hegemonic (1989) illustrates this point. According to them, the social and economic forces usually attempt to self-constraining of a ruler’s arbitrary authority to shape the legal system to suit their interests. To confiscate wealth was the key political factor under- do so e¤ectively in rule-of-law societies, they pinning economic growth and the development of must secure the cooperation of the legal elite to markets in early capitalist Europe. Making credible whom the political elite often have close social commitments through self-enforcing institutional ties. The changes that emerge reflect a combina- mechanisms (such as developing private property rights tion of political and economic preferences and enforceable in parliament and removing the ruler’s control of the judiciary) established the legal security of professional interests. To be sure, demands for expectations and allowed rulers to borrow capital from constitutional change often emanate from vari- lenders who were protected by law from arbitrary sei- ous groups within the body politic, but if zure of their capital. In other words, by constraining hegemonic political and economic elites, their themselves by establishing new institutions that limited, parliamentary representatives, and the legal elite prima facie, their flexibility, rulers were able to main- do not forecast gain from a proposed change, the tain their long-term economic survival. change is likely to be blocked (Horowitz 1994, 16. My argument here finds striking parallels in the 251; Watson 1983). literature regarding the political sources of empower- Moreover, because institutions such as judi- ment of other semi-autonomous institutions similar in cial review (and other semi-autonomous institu- nature to the judicial review of bills of rights, such as tions such as central banks, transnational trade central banks and supranational tribunals. For exam- organizations, international monetary funds, and ple, in her study of the political sources of central bank authority in developing countries, Sylvia Maxfield supranational tribunals) limit the flexibility of (1994, 1997) argues that the interests and capacities of Democracy and Constitutionalism 235

When their hegemony is increasingly chal- tionate access to and influence upon the legal lenged in majoritarian decision-making arenas, environment, may promote their interests by powerful elites and their political representatives transferring political disputes from majoritarian may deliberately initiate and support a constitu- decision-making arenas, in which particularistic tionalization of rights in order to transfer power interests are often attributed to individual par- to supreme courts, where they assume, based ticipants, to the professional judiciary, whose primarily on the courts’ record of adjudication actions seem to be circumscribed by objective and on the justices’ ideological preferences, that rules. These transfers take advantage of the ex- their policy preferences will be less contested. In pertise, rectitude, and political impartiality often other words, increasing judicial intrusion into the attributed to courts. prerogatives of the legislature and the executive The second way that political power holders following the enactment of constitutional bills of may profit from an increasing judicialization rights may provide an e‰cient institutional so- of politics is that politicians may encourage a lution for influential sociopolitical groups who transfer of power to the judiciary in order to di- seek to preserve their hegemony vis-a-vis margi- vert responsibility to the court. This institutional nalized minority groups and who, given an ero- transfer reduces the possible costs of their own sion in their popular support, may find strategic involvement in potential public blunders as well drawbacks in adhering to majoritarian decision- as the risk that their policy preferences will be making processes. challenged in majoritarian policymaking arenas. The judicialization of politics through the From the politicians’ point of view, the courts constitutionalization of rights and the empower- may be an e¤ective means of reducing the risk ment of courts may serve the interests of political to themselves and to the institutional apparatus power holders in at least four principal ways. within which they operate. Delegating policy- First, hegemonic elites, as well as political and making to courts may become even more attrac- economic power holders who possess dispropor- tive for political power holders when disputes arise that most of them would rather not address early central banking institutions in such countries are publicly, either because they present ‘‘no-win’’ shaped by the financial interests of those in a position dilemmas, such as the dispute about abortion to delegate authority to central banks: government policy in the United States (Graber 1993) or politicians and private banks. Another example is the because politicians regard public disputes in ‘‘intergovernmentalist’’ thesis, which suggests that majoritarian policymaking fora as likely to put member states are the central institution builders of the their own policy preferences at risk. Under such European Community and that they provide auton- conditions, empowering national high courts omy to the European Court of Justice to serve their may serve the interests of the political status quo own purposes. According to this approach, member states choose to create (and selectively abide by the by transferring public responsibility for policy- limits imposed by) supranational institutions, because making and by insulating policymaking from these institutions help them surmount problems raised popular political pressures. by the need for collective action and overcome domes- Third, as specific groups (primarily economic tic political problems. The political power version of elites) that possess disproportionate access to the this thesis suggests that national governments from legal environment discover the potential useful- the EU member states have not been passive and un- ness of the courts to maximize their objectives, willing victims of European legal integration. They they become more enthusiastic about expanding consciously delegated power to the European Court of the legal understanding of human rights to in- Justice, and where the court has been pro-active, the clude interests that may appear to some to be member governments have supported this. See Garrett et al. (1998); Garrett (1992). only remotely connected to any constitutional Chapter 4 236

foundation in a formal bill of rights.17 Influential seek to preserve or improve the Court’s institu- coalitions of domestic neoliberal economic forces tional position vis-a-vis other major national (e.g., powerful industrialists and economic con- decision-making bodies. The striving of the legal glomerates given added impetus by global eco- elite and the judiciary to enhance their power nomic trends) may view constitutionalization of is especially likely to be an important factor rights (especially property, mobility, and occu- in instituting a judicial review in a polity pational rights) as a means to promote economic whose legal establishment and political person- deregulation and to fight what its members often nel are drawn from the same social groups. understand to be harmful ‘‘large government’’ Moreover, the constitutionalization of rights policies of the encroaching state. may support the interests of a supreme court The delegation of power to the courts may seeking to increase its symbolic power by foster- also serve both the interests of a professional ing its alignment with the growing community of legal elite seeking to enhance its symbolic power liberal democratic nations engaged in rights- and the interests of a supreme court seeking to based discourse. enhance its political influence and international Having shown that there are distinct groups profile. National high courts may primarily be whose ability to gain or maintain power and in- seekers of legal policy, but they are also sophis- fluence for themselves is contingent upon judicial ticated and strategic actors who may realize empowerment through the constitutionalization when the changing preferences of other influen- of rights, it is clear that my interest-based he- tial political actors as well as changes in the gemonic struggle explanation does not depend institutional context allow them to strengthen upon the existence of any systemic social need. their institutional position by widening and Nor does this movement assume any necessary deepening their involvement in crucial policy- evolution in a progressive direction. Such move- making arenas. As recent studies have shown ment is not deterministic but is actor oriented (Epstein and Knight 1998; Epstein and Walker and, unlike extant microfoundational theories of 1995), landmark decisions of the U.S. Supreme judicial independence, it does not depend upon Court, for example, have not merely been apo- the competitiveness of the party system. litical jurisprudence or a reflection of its justices’ ideological preferences but also a reflection of their strategic behavior as rational actors who III. The ‘‘Constitutional Revolution’’ in Israel as an Illustrative Case 17. E.g., the extension of some constitutional human rights protections (e.g., freedom of expression, prop- The 1992 constitutional revolution in Israel erty rights, search and seizure, due process rights, oc- presents a nearly ideal illustration of my expla- cupational rights, and mobility rights) to business nation of judicial empowerment. The hands that corporations, which often draw upon those rights in guided the constitutionalization of rights and the challenging various governmental regulatory measures establishment of judicial review in Israel are en- (e.g., claims for protection of commercial speech under tirely visible. They were driven by purely politi- freedom of expression constitutional provisions, claims cal interests not by their subordination to some against taxation in general and income tax in particular invisible evolutionist or structural forces or by based on constitutional provisions protecting property the devotion of politicians to some elevated vi- rights, claims against state monitoring and licensing of various professions or against regulatory environmen- sion of human rights or national unity. tal laws based on freedom of occupation constitutional The 1992 constitutional entrenchment of provisions, claims against marketing quotas based on rights and the establishment of judicial review freedom of occupation and freedom of movement in Israel were initiated and supported by politi- constitutional provisions). cians representing Israel’s secular bourgeoisie, Democracy and Constitutionalism 237

whose political hegemony in the majoritarian during the same period; after the enactment of policymaking arena had become increasingly the new Basic Laws in 1992, however, the bal- threatened. The political representatives of this ance of powers between the branches changed, group found the delegation of policymaking enabling the Supreme Court to begin scrutinizing authority to the court an e‰cient way to over- legislative and administrative acts. come the growing popular backlash against its The seemingly counterintuitive voluntary del- ideological hegemony and, perhaps more im- egation of authority from the Knesset to the ju- portantly, an e‰cient way to avoid the poten- diciary through the entrenchment of rights and tially negative consequences of its continuously the establishment of judicial review decreased declining control over the majoritarian decision- the significance of majoritarian politics in deter- making arena. mining the public policy agenda and gradually The intentional empowerment of the judiciary transferred the locus of political struggle to a by the secular bourgeoisie in Israel was also seemingly apolitical arena, where the ideology supported by neoliberal economic forces in Is- of the ‘‘enlightened public’’—the ruling elite raeli society (mainly powerful industrialists and of Israel and its Ashkenazi, secular bourgeois economic conglomerates) who have used basic constituency—has traditionally enjoyed a clear law litigation since 1992 to promote their own dominance. This alliance between the Supreme material interests (Hirschl 1998; Gross 1998; Court, the neoliberal economic elite, and the Marmor 1997). These forces joined the repre- secular bourgeoisie initiated the constitutional sentatives of the (mainly) Ashkenazi secular revolution and the transition to ‘‘juristocracy,’’ high-income group to create an influential coali- not as a means for protecting human rights in tion that initiated and advocated the delegation Israel or as a solution to a systemic ungovern- of policymaking authority to the judiciary.18 ability crisis but simply as a way to protect its While the secular bourgeoisie was motivated by hegemony and to promote the policies favored serious popular challenges to its political and by its members. cultural hegemony and by its parliamentary rep- resentatives’ growing political dependence upon representatives of marginalized groups in the Is- IV. Factors Facilitating the Delegation of raeli society, the economic elite supported the Power to Courts delegation of power to courts as a means to fight what its members understood to be the regulated In general, two factors may facilitate conscious market, large government, and policies of the judicial empowerment and reduce the short-term encroaching state (Hirschl 1999). . . . risk of those who voluntarily hand policymaking Although the judicialization of politics in Is- authority over to the judiciary. The first condi- rael began in the mid-1980s, it accelerated sig- tion is a su‰cient level of certainty among those nificantly in the aftermath of the constitutional initiating the transition to juristocracy that the revolution of 1992. Until 1992, the Knesset judiciary in general and the supreme court in retained formal legislative powers that only a particular are likely to produce decisions that, by few parliaments in democratic countries (e.g., the and large, will better serve their interests and United Kingdom and New Zealand) still held reflect their ideological preferences. In this re- gard, a growing body of literature tends to refute 18. Also among the forces that publicly supported the proposition that supreme courts are simply Israel’s constitutional revolution were the country’s guardians of the rule of law without any other major economic organizations, such as the Chambers complementary or contradictory political inter- of Commerce and Manufacturing, and leading eco- ests. According to this body of literature, su- nomic figures. preme courts are inclined to rule in accordance Chapter 4 238

with national metanarratives, prevailing ideo- high courts, an important caveat should be logical and cultural propensities, and the inter- entered. Political power holders tend to be ests of ruling elites (Smith 1997; Knight and myopic, seeking to advance their particularistic Epstein 1996; Epstein and Walker 1995; Mishler short-term interests even at the expense of po- and Sheehan 1993; Koh 1988; Tushnet 1988; tentially unfavorable long-term consequences to Dahl 1957). There is quite decisive evidence the institutional apparatus within which they showing that the U.S. Supreme Court, for ex- operate. Moreover, political power holders tend ample, has been inclined to adapt itself to to underestimate the unfavorable long-term con- hegemonic ideological and cultural propen- sequences of the policies they advocate, espe- sities.34 As Robert Dahl observes, ‘‘it is unreal- cially when their immediate gain from adopting istic to suppose that a Court whose members are these policies is significant. Politics, however, is recruited in the fashion of the Supreme Court an ongoing, multidimensional, and reflective en- justices would long hold to norms of justice that vironment that may yield unintended conse- are substantially at odds with the rest of the po- quences even for carefully designed institutions litical elite’’ (Dahl 1957, 291). The Court may be and policies. At least two such possible unin- ‘‘the forum of principle’’ in American life, as tended long-term consequences of the judicializa- Ronald Dworkin argues (1990), but the princi- tion of politics through the constitutionalization ples that justices articulate, Dahl and others of rights and the establishment of judicial review point out, are likely to be those favored by come to mind. members of the existing lawmaking majority First, while the delegation of policymaking (Graber 1993, 36). The adjudication of the Is- authority to courts increases the courts’ formal raeli Supreme Court is, to say the least, no ex- capacity for active participation in the political ception to this pattern. . . . arena in the short term, the abrupt change in the A second condition that reduces the short-term balance of power between the judicial branch risk for those who voluntarily hand power over and other branches of government may have a to courts is the existence of widespread public negative long-term e¤ect on the popular legiti- trust in the political impartiality of the judiciary. macy accorded to the courts’ decisions. Courts The appearance of political dependence would have historically enjoyed professional autonomy collapse the distinction between law and politics and a large measure of protection from political on which the fundamental legitimacy of separa- interference; however, as they exercise their tion of powers system depends (Gibson, Cal- newly awarded authority, they may come to be deira, and Baird 1998; Mishler and Sheehan seen as active political bodies trying to forward 1993). . . . their own political agendas, rather than neutral arbiters. The delegation of power to courts may therefore pose a long-term threat to the legiti- V. Some Possible Unintended Consequences of macy, impartiality, and independence of the Intentional Judicial Empowerment judiciary. The negative impact of the judicialization of Having discussed two factors that may encour- politics in Israel on its Supreme court’s legiti- age conscious judicial empowerment by reducing macy is not merely theoretical. Over the past five the short-term risk of those who voluntarily years, there has been an increasing erosion of the hand over policymaking authority to national public image of the Israeli Supreme Court as an autonomous and politically impartial arbiter as 34. The literature on this issue is too vast to cite. Two the political representatives of minority groups recent examples are Smith (1997) and Kairys (1998). have come to realize that political arrangements Democracy and Constitutionalism 239

and public policies agreed upon in majoritarian In summary, the empowerment of courts in decision-making arenas are likely to be thor- Israel through the constitutional revolution of oughly reviewed by an often hostile Supreme 1992 marked an abrupt change in the balance of Court. As a result, the court and its judges are power between the judiciary, the legislature, and increasingly viewed by a considerable portion of the executive. While the legislative and executive the Israeli public as pushing forward their own branches of government enjoyed clear domi- political agenda, one identified primarily with nance as Israel’s most important policymaking the secular-liberal segment of the Israeli society arenas until the late-1980s, in Israel’s post- (Avnon 1996, Hofnung 1996b). . . . constitutional revolution era there is hardly a A second possible unintended long-term con- public policy question that does not sooner or sequence of judicial empowerment through the later turn into a judicial question (to paraphrase establishment of judicial review that myopic and de Tockville’s often-cited observation regarding threatened elites are likely to underestimate is the the American political system). At first glance, irreversibility of the constitutionalization process this shift may seem to run counter to the interests in rule-of-law democracies. As the history of of the legislature and the executive. In practice, constitutionalism teaches us, constitutions are however, a coalition of Knesset members repre- di‰cult to amend or reform after their enact- senting a relatively coherent social class com- ment, so that an entrenched constitution seems posed of Israel’s political, cultural, and economic to acquire a ‘‘life of its own.’’ The delegation of elites initiated and promoted the entrenchment power to courts through constitutionalization of rights and the establishment of judicial review may prove to be an irreversible process. While in Israel in 1992. The primary motivation for this increasing judicial intrusion into the prerogatives initiative, as I have shown, was a strong interest of the legislature and the executive through the in preserving the political and cultural hegemony constitutionalization of rights and the fortifica- of the ruling elite and its secular bourgeois con- tion of judicial review may provide a short-term stituency. Indeed, the constitutional revolution institutional solution for influential elites—who, of 1992 generated an extensive judicialization of given an erosion in their popular support, may politics in Israel and enhanced values and poli- find strategic drawbacks in adhering to major- cies favored by those who initiated the reform at itarian decision-making processes—it may also the expense of ideological and policy preferences establish long-term limitations on the institu- of peripheral groups. Relying, on the one hand, tional room for maneuvering that political power on the Israeli Supreme Court’s reputation for holders possess. Hence, intentional judicial em- rectitude and political impartiality and, on the powerment through constitutionalization may other hand, on the court’s inclination to rule in create an undesirable institutional setting for the accordance with the values of the ‘‘enlightened ruling elites and their constituencies in the long public,’’ the forces behind Israel’s constitutional term. Minority groups may learn to draw upon revolution were able to transfer sensitive political the new constitutional framework to advance and cultural issues to the legal arena and reduce their policy preferences by presenting them as some of the growing costs they were forced to rights claims. But perhaps more important, it pay when complying with the rules of the game may bring about an embedded institutional ob- of proportional political representation. While stacle to the reduction of the court’s significance the delegation of policymaking authority to the as a major national policymaking body, which judiciary bought short-term political relief for may pose problems if the political incentive Israel’s ruling elite and its bourgeois constitu- structure that encouraged the delegation of ency, the unprecedented judicialization of poli- power to the judiciary changes. tics also brought about a gradual politicization Chapter 4 240

of the law and hence unintentionally planted the introduction of the Charter has been nothing less seeds of a long-term erosion of the judiciary’s than a revolution on the scale of the introduction legitimacy, as well of the ruling elite’s future of the metric system, the great medical discov- institutional room for political maneuvering. eries of Louis Pasteur, and the invention of pen- icillin and the laser’’ (Lamer 1992, A11). . . . As in Israel, the delegation of authority to the VI. The Hegemonic Preservation Thesis in Canadian Supreme Court has also depended on Other Politics the court’s inclination to rule, by and large, in accordance with hegemonic ideological and cul- My explanation for the conscious judicial em- tural propensities. On the basis of a customary powerment in Israel may shed light on the po- constitutional convention, the judges of the Ca- litical rationale behind judicial empowerment nadian Supreme Court are nominated to the through constitutionalization in other polities as bench according to a ‘‘provincially representa- well. In the following pages I briefly demonstrate tive’’ key, whereby three justices represent On- the contribution of the ‘‘hegemonic struggle’’ tario, three come from Quebec, two from the thesis to the understanding of constitutional pol- western provinces (one is usually from British itics in Canada, New Zealand, and South Africa. Columbia), and one from the Maritime prov- inces. The selection and nomination process it- Canada self, however, is controlled exclusively by the federal government and by the prime minister. The Canadian Constitution Act of 1982 includes The judges selected through this explicitly po- a bill-of-rights-type document titled the Charter litical nomination process are not likely to hold of Rights and Freedoms. The enactment of the policy preferences substantially at odds with Constitution Act marked the o‰cial patriation those held by the rest of the political elite. of the Canadian constitution from the authority Indeed, in its federalism jurisprudence over the of the British Crown after a 115-year-long pro- past decades, the Supreme Court of Canada cess, which started with the enactment of the tended, by and large, to adopt values and poli- Constitution Act in 1867. The adoption of the cies favored by the national government at the Charter of Rights and Freedoms, which con- expense of undermining the policy autonomy of stitutes the first 34 sections of the Constitution the provinces. Moreover, as recent analyses of Act, also marked a dramatic change in the de the interpretations of the charter by the Cana- jure status of rights and liberties in Canada and dian Supreme Court point out, the chief benefi- provided the necessary institutional framework ciaries of charter politics and litigation have been for an extensive judicialization of politics in hegemonic ideas of formal equality, ‘‘negative’’ Canada over the past 15 years (Manfredi 1997; liberty, and social atomism rather than ‘‘periph- Bakan 1997; Mandel 1994; Bogart 1994). Since eral’’ interests and ideas (Hirschl 2000; Bakan the enactment of the charter in 1982, the Cana- 1997; Beatty 1997; Hutchinson 1995; Bogart dian Supreme Court has become one of the most 1994; Mandel 1994; Scott and Macklem 1992). important decision-making fora with regard to In sum, despite the dissimilarities between the the contentious issues of Canadian politics—the Canadian and Israeli sociopolitical scenes and rights of indigenous people, language politics, legacies of constitutional politics, there are strik- gender equality, and the political and cultural ing parallels in the political rationales that status of Quebec. In 1992, 10 years after the supported judicial empowerment through con- charter came into force, Chief Justice Lamer of stitutionalization in the two countries. the Canadian Supreme Court declared that ‘‘the Democracy and Constitutionalism 241

New Zealand lishing an e¤ective guarantee for the protection of New Zealand residents’ individual rights and Only 15 years ago, New Zealand’s political liberties (Richardson 1995; Rishworth 1995, system was described by leading political sci- 1996; Joseph 1996). Perhaps this is why Sir Ivor entists as ‘‘a virtually perfect example of the Richardson of the Court of Appeal of New Zea- Westminster model of democracy’’ and as ‘‘the land has recently declared that ‘‘[f ]uture histor- only example of the British majoritarian democ- ians may recognize the Bill of Rights as one of racy system left’’ (Lijphart 1984, 19). The enact- the most important statutes ever enacted in New ment of the New Zealand Bill of Rights Act in Zealand’’ (Richardson 1995, 75). 1990 marked an abrupt change in the balance of Following the enactment of the NZBOR, New power between, on the one hand, the judiciary Zealand’s judiciary in general, and the court of and, on the other, the legislature and the execu- appeal in particular, have gradually become im- tive (which were important policymaking arenas portant political actors dealing with the salient until the late-1980s) and symbolized the demise political issues on New Zealand’s public agenda of the ‘‘last Westminster system’’ (Lijphart (e.g., Maori rights and land claims, immigration 1987). The driving force behind the 1990 con- policy, and the extensive privatization of public stitutionalization of rights in New Zealand was a services). This appears to match the expectation coalition of the disparate sections of a threatened of the act’s author (Geo¤rey Palmer) that the elite seeking to preserve its power and economic Bill of Rights, though nonentrenched, would actors who were pushing for neoliberal economic gradually acquire su‰cient legal and political reforms. . . . authority to allow the courts to exercise at least Although the Bill of Rights does not formally some of the powers of scrutiny and control that empower the courts to nullify legislation incon- they would have had under a system of full-scale sistent with its provisions, the courts are required judicial review (Joseph 1998). to interpret ambiguous laws in a manner consis- In sum, the enactment of the NZBOR, along tent with the act, and there are clear signs that with other new laws such as the Human Rights the New Zealand Court of Appeal may simply Act of 1993 and the Privacy Act of 1993,68 was be giving it a de facto entrenched status.67 intended to elevate the traditional set of classic Moreover, it has acquired a de facto constitu- civil liberties to the status of prime constitutional tional status as a politically, if not legally, en- rights and to empower New Zealand’s judiciary trenched document and has therefore become by delegating policymaking authority from Par- an important catalyst for the judicialization of liament to the Court of Appeal.69 Not surpris- politics in New Zealand. Thus, the Bill of rights ingly then, the judicial elite and the oligarchy of has been recognized by scholars as finally estab- 68. The Human Rights Act 1993 prohibits discrimina- 67. In a recent verdict, the court observed that lack of tion on the basis of sex, marital status, religious belief, entrenchment and constitutional status ‘‘makes no dif- ethical belief, color, race, ethnic or national origin, ference to the strength of the Bill of Rights where it is disability, age, political opinion, employment status or to be applied.’’ See Simpson v. Attorney General (1994) family status. The Privacy Act 1993 aims to protect 3 NZLR 667, 706. This and other recent decisions of individuals by regulating the disclosure of information the Court of Appeal indicate that the Bill of Rights, about them. For a detailed discussion of the new legal though unentrenched, may gradually gain su‰cient le- regime protecting rights and liberties in New Zealand, gal and political authority to allow the courts to prac- see the essays in Rishworth (1995). tically exercise most of the powers of scrutiny and 69. For a comprehensive discussion of the bill’s oper- control they would have had under a system of full- ational provisions and a survey of the adjudication re- scale judicial review. lated to the bill, see Joseph (1996). Chapter 4 242

wealth and political power, seeking to preserve year, South Africa excluded over 80% of its their hegemony and to increase their impact population from participation in the democratic on policymaking outcomes, quickly endorsed political game, while parliamentary sovereignty the constitutional change, while opposition to was strictly adhered to. Calls for entrenched the enactment of the NZBOR came mainly rights and for the establishment of active judicial from leftist opponents of privatization and from review were strongly and consistently opposed Maori activists who perceived the enactment as a by the ruling elites of South Africa throughout threat to the status of the Treaty of Waitangi and the twentieth century. Throughout the early- to the success of future Maori land claims.70 1980s, for example, the National Party leaders insisted that a bill of rights should not form part South Africa of any future constitutional order in South Af- rica, arguing that an emphasis on ‘‘individual Yet another confirmation of the hegemonic interests’’ would be inconsistent with the political preservation thesis is the struggle of South Afri- and religious tradition of Afrikaanerdom which ca’s white ruling elite during the late-1980s preferred to emphasize ‘‘the State’’ over ‘‘indi- and early-1990s to ensure the inclusion of an vidual interests.’’ The strong anti-judicial-review entrenched bill of rights and active constitutional position of the ruling elites echoed President court in the postapartheid political pact in South Kruger’s famous declaration that the power of Africa.71 Prior to the enactment of the 1993 the courts to test legislation was ‘‘a principle interim Bill of Rights (replaced by the final Bill invented by the Devil!’’ (Cockrell 1997, 518). of Rights in 1996), there was perhaps no other But when it became obvious in the late-1980s country in the postwar world in which the gap that the apartheid regime could not be sustained between popular will and constitutional ar- by repression, the incentive structure of the white rangements was quite so wide. Up until that minority rapidly changed, and a sudden conver- sion to the supposed virtues of a bill of rights 70. The Treaty of Waitangi (1840, amended 1975) has occurred. Not surprisingly, the idea of institut- been an important symbolic source for New Zealand’s ing a bill of rights came from its old enemies— constitutional law. The beginning of constitutional the National Party Government and other polit- government is commonly said to be the signing of the ical representatives of the white minority, who Treaty of Waitangi in 1840. In that year, New Zealand suddenly ‘‘rediscovered’’ judicial review. Con- became a British colony and the Parliament in West- scious judicial empowerment through constitu- minster could make laws that applied in New Zealand. tionalization followed. . . . Thus, the Treaty of Waitangi is often claimed to be a ‘‘founding document,’’ a ‘‘fundamental charter,’’ which brought about the foundation of the state. The Maori 71. The literature dealing with the constitutional perception, in particular, is that the treaty is a ‘‘basic aspects of the abolition of apartheid in South Africa is document’’ since it recognizes the rights of the indige- too vast to cite. For a broad survey of the road to nous people of New Zealand (and thus its alleged general su¤rage in South Africa see ‘‘South Africa— breach by the colonizers is the legal basis for Maori Recent History,’’ in Africa South of the Sahara (1999, land claims). For many Maori, the entrenchment of 974). For two general accounts of the struggle over the the Treaty of Waitangi would have demeaned the new constitution in South Africa see Gloppen (1997), document and exposed it to change through the Worden (1995), and Sisk (1995). On the political ori- bill’s amending procedure (a 75% majority vote of gins and likely consequences of South Africa’s ‘‘nego- the members of the House of Representatives or a tiated transition’’ to democracy see Jung and Shapiro referendum). (1995). Democracy and Constitutionalism 243

empowerment of the judiciary by threatened but Conclusion still dominant political powers was strongly supported by influential coalitions of domestic As my analysis of the 1992 constitutional revo- neoliberal economic forces (mainly powerful lution in Israel and my brief discussion of other industrialists and economic conglomerates given constitutional reforms suggest, the constitutional added impetus by global economic trends) who entrenchment of rights and the establishment of viewed the constitutionalization of rights as a judicial review do not develop in isolation from means to promote economic deregulation, as the central political struggles and economic in- well as by national high courts seeking to en- terests that structure political systems. To best hance their political influence and international serve their own interests, hegemonic political, profile. economic, and judicial elites attempt to shape The causal mechanisms behind the trend to- the institutional structure within which they op- ward constitutionalization and judicialization erate. Constitutional reform is one such arena in divided polities have not been adequately in which these power struggles occur. Because delineated by the major theories of constitu- entrenched rights and judicial review (like other tional transformation. As I have shown in this semi-autonomous, professional policymaking article, the ‘‘consociational,’’ evolutionist, sys- institutions such as central banks, electoral temic need-based (or the ‘‘ungovernability’’), committees, transnational trade organizations, ‘‘new institutionalist,’’ and electoral markets supranational financial bodies and judicial tri- models cannot explain, for example, the recent bunals) are self-enforcing institutions that limit, history of constitutional entrenchment of rights by and large, the flexibility of political decision and judicial review in Israel, Canada, New Zea- makers, the actors who voluntarily establish such land, and South Africa (to mention only the institutions must have an interest in abiding by four cases I have examined in this paper). My their limits. Moreover, because bills of rights and brief analysis of constitutional politics in the judiciaries lack the a priori independent power to above polities reveals that the wave of con- enforce their mandates, their authority depends stitutionalization in these countries can be more mainly on the degree to which elites find judicial productively understood, on the basis of an empowerment beneficial to their own political, interest-based hegemonic struggle approach, as a economic and cultural hegemony. conscious strategy undertaken by threatened po- The governing elites in divided, rule-of-law litical and economic elites seeking to preserve polities face a constant struggle to preserve their their hegemony through the insulation of policy- hegemony. Such elites are likely to advocate a making from the democratic menace of popular delegation of power to the judiciary (a) when political pressures. Moreover, what I have called their hegemony is increasingly challenged in the ‘‘hegemonic preservation’’ thesis serves as a majoritarian decision-making arenas by periph- reminder that seemingly humanitarian constitu- eral minority groups; (b) when the judiciary in tional reforms often mask an essentially self- that polity enjoys a relatively high reputation for serving agenda. The constitutionalization of rectitude and political impartiality; and (c) when rights, in other words, is often not so much the the courts in that polity are inclined, by and cause or a reflection of a progressive revolution large, to rule in accordance with hegemonic in a given polity, as it is a means by which pre- ideological and cultural propensities. Moreover, existing and ongoing sociopolitical struggles in in many countries (e.g., Israel, Canada, New that polity are carried out. Zealand, and South Africa) the intentional Chapter 4 244

Graber, Mark. 1993. The Nonmajoritarian Di‰culty: References Legislative Deference to the Judiciary. Studies in American Political Development 7: 35–73. Avnon, Dan. 1996. The Enlightened Public: Jewish Gross, Aeyal. 1998. The Politics of Rights in Israeli and Democratic or Liberal and Democratic (in He- Constitutional Law. Israel Studies 3: 80–119. brew). Mishpat U’Mimshal 3: 113–149. Hirschl, Ran. 1998. Israel’s ‘‘Constitutional Revolu- Baaklini, Abdo, and Helen Desfosses. 1997. Designs tion’’: The Legal Interpretation of Entrenched Civil for Democratic Stability: Studies in Viable Constitu- Liberties in an Emerging Neo-Liberal Economic tionalism. Armonk, N.Y.: M. E. Sharpe. Order. American Journal of Comparative Law 46: Bakan, Joel. 1997. Just Words: Constitutional Rights 427–452. and Social Wrongs. Toronto: University of Toronto ———. 1999. The Great Economic-Juridical Trans- Press. formation: The Legal Arena and the Transformation Beatty, David. 1997. The Canadian Charter of Rights: of Israel’s Economic Order. In Shafir and Peled 1999. Lessons and Laments. Modern Law Review 60: 481– ———. 2000. ‘‘Negative’’ Rights vs. ‘‘Positive’’ Enti- 498. tlements: A Comparative Study of Judicial Interpreta- Blaustein, Albert, and G. H. Flanz. eds. 1998. Con- tions of Rights in an Emerging Neo-Liberal Economic stitutions of the Countries of the World. Dobbs Ferry, Order. Human Rights Quarterly 22: 1060–1098. N.Y.: Oceana Publications. ———. 1996b. The Unintended Consequences of Un- Bogart, William A. 1994. Courts and Country: The planned Constitutional Reform: Constitutional Politics Limits of Litigation and the Social and Political Life of in Israel. American Journal of Comparative Law 44: Canada. New York: Oxford University Press. 585–604. Cockrell, Alfred. 1997. The South African Bill of Horowitz, Donald. 1994. The Qur’an and the Com- Rights and the ‘‘Duck/Rabbit.’’ Modern Law Review mon Law: Islamic Law Reform and the Theory of Le- 60: 513–537. gal Change. American Journal of Comparative Law 42: Dahl, Robert. 1957. Decision-Making in a Democracy: 233–293. The Supreme Court as a National Policy-Maker. Hutchinson, Allan. 1995. Waiting for Coraf: A Critique Journal of Public Law 6: 279–295. of Law and Rights. Toronto: University of Toronto Epstein, Lee, and Jack Knight. 1998. The Choices Jus- Press. tices Make. Washington, D.C.: CQ Press. Joseph, Philip, ed. 1995. Essays on the Constitution. Epstein, Lee, and Gary Walker. 1995. The Role of Wellington, New Zealand: Brooker’s. the Supreme Court in American Society: Playing the ———. 1996. The New Zealand Bill of Rights Act Reconstructing Game. In Contemplating Courts, ed. 1990. Public Law Review 7: 76–92. Lee Epstein. Washington: D.C.: CQ Press. ———. 1998. Constitutional Review Now. New Zea- Garrett, Geo¤rey. 1992. International Cooperation land Law Review [1998]: 85–128. and Institutional Choice: The European Community’s Jung, Courtney, and Ian Shapiro. 1995. South Africa’s Internal Market. International Organization 46: 533– Negotiated Transition: Democracy, Opposition, and 560. the New Constitutional Order. Politics and Society 23: Garrett, Geo¤rey, R. Daniel Keleman, and Heiner 269–308. Schulz. 1998. The European Court of Justice, National Kairys, David. Ed. 1998. The Politics of Law. New Governments, and Legal Integration in the European York: Basic Books. Union. International Organization 52: 149–176. Knight, Jack, and Lee Epstein. 1996. On the Struggle Gibson, James L., Gregory A. Caldeira, and Vanessa for Judicial Supremacy. Law and Society Review 30: Baird. 1998. On the Legitimacy of National High 87–120. Courts. American Political Science Review 92: 343– Koh, Harold H. 1988. Why the President (Almost) 358. Always Wins in Foreign A¤airs. Yale Law Journal 97: Gloppen, Siri. 1997. South Africa: The Battle over the 1255–1342. Constitution. Aldershot, United Kingdom: Ashgate. Democracy and Constitutionalism 245

Lamer, Antonio. 1992. How the Charter Changes Jus- Tate, C. Neal, and Torbjorn Vallinder. 1995. The tice. Globe and Mail (Toronto), 17 April 1992, A11. Global Expansion of Judicial Power. New York: New Lijphart, Arendt. 1984. Democracies: Patterns of York University Press. Majoritarian and Consensus Government in Twenty-One Tushnet, Mark. 1988. Red, White, and Blue: A Critical Countries. New Haven, Conn.: Yale University Press. Analysis of Constitutional Law. Cambridge: Harvard ———. 1987. The Demise of the Last Westminster University Press. System? Electoral Studies 6: 2–26. Watson, Alan. 1983. Legal Change: Sources of Law Maddox, Robert. 1995. Constitutions of the World. and Legal Culture. University of Pennsylvania Law Washington D.C.: Congressional Quarterly. Review 131: 1121–1187. Mandel, Michael. 1994. The Charter of Rights and Worden, Nigel. 1995. The Making of Modern South the Legalization of Politics in Canada. Toronto: Africa. Oxford, Eng.: Blackwell. Thompson. Marmor, Andrei. 1997. Judicial Review in Israel (in Hebrew). Mishpat U’Mimshal 4: 133–160. Maxfield, Sylvia. 1994. Financial Incentives and Cen- tral Bank Authority in Industrializing Nations. World Politics 46: 556–588. ———. 1997. Gatekeepers of Growth. Princeton, N.J.: Princeton University Press. Mishler, William, and Robert Sheehan. 1993. The Su- preme Court as Countermajoritarian Institution? The Impact of Public Opinion on Supreme Court Deci- sions. American Political Science Review 87: 87–101. North, Douglas, and Barry Weingast. 1989. Constitu- tions and Commitment: The Evolution of Institutions Governing Public Choice in Seventeenth-Century En- gland. Journal of Economic History 49: 803–832. Richardson, Ivor. 1995. ‘‘Rights Jurisprudence— Justice for All?’’ In Joseph 1995. Rishworth, Paul. 1995. The Birth and Rebirth of the Bill of Rights.’’ In Rights and Freedoms: The New Zealand Bill of Rights Act and the Human Rights Act 1993, ed. Grant Huscroft and Paul Rishworth. Well- ington, New Zealand: Brooker’s. ———. 1996. Human Rights and the Bill of Rights. New Zealand Law Review [1996]: 298–324. Scott, Craig, and Patrick Macklem. 1992. Constitu- tional Ropes of Sand of Judicial Guarantees? Social Rights in a New South African Constitution. Univer- sity of Pennsylvania Law Review 141: 1–141. Shafir, Gershon, and Yoav Peled. 1999. The New Is- rael. Boulder, Colo.: Westview Press. Sisk, T. D. 1995. Democratization in South Africa. Princeton, N.J.: Princeton University Press. Smith, Rogers. 1997. Civic Ideals: Conflicting Visions of Citizenship in U.S. History. New Haven, Conn.: Yale University Press. Decision Making in a Democracy: The Supreme Court as a National Policymaker

Robert Dahl

To consider the Supreme Court of the United tain limits, both possibilities are independent of States strictly as a legal institution is to underes- the number of policy alternatives at issue, and timate its significance in the American political since the argument is not significantly a¤ected by system. For it is also a political institution, an the number of alternatives, it is convenient to institution, that is to say, for arriving at decisions assume that each policy dispute represents only on controversial questions of national policy. As two alternatives.3 a political institution, the Court is highly un- If everyone prefers one of two alternatives, usual, not least because Americans are not quite then no significant problem arises. But a case willing to accept the fact that it is a political in- will hardly come before the Supreme Court un- stitution and not quite capable of denying it; so less at least one person prefers an alternative that that frequently we take both positions at once. is opposed by another person. Strictly speaking, This is confusing to foreigners, amusing to logi- then, no matter how the Court acts in determin- cians, and rewarding to ordinary Americans who ing the legality or constitutionality of one alter- thus manage to retain the best of both worlds. . . . native or the other, the outcome of the Court’s

2. Provided that the total membership of the society is II an even number, it is technically possible for a dispute to occur that divides the membership into two equal In determining and appraising the role of the parts, neither of which can be said to be either a ma- Court, two di¤erent and conflicting criteria are jority or minority of the total membership. But even in sometimes employed. These are the majority cri- the instances where the number of members is even terion and the ceriterion of Right or Justice. (which should occur on the average only half the time), Every policy dispute can be tested, at least in the probability of an exactly even split, in any group of principle, by the majority criterion, because more than a few thousand people, is so small that it may be ignored. (again: in principle) the dispute can be analyzed according to the numbers of people for and 3. Suppose the number of citizens, or members eligible to participate in collective decisions, is n. Let each against the various alternatives at issue, and member indicate his ‘‘most preferred alternative.’’ therefore according to the proportions of the Then it is obvious that the maximum number of most citizens or eligible members who are for and preferred alternatives is n. It is equally obvious that if against the alternatives. Logically speaking, ex- the number of preferred alternatives is more than or cept for a trivial case, every conflict within a equal to n=2, then no majority is possible. But for all given society must be a dispute between a ma- practical purposes those formal limitations can be jority of those eligible to participate and a mi- ignored, for we are dealing with a large society where nority or minorities; or else it must be a dispute the number of alternatives at issue before the Supreme between or among minorities only.2 Within cer- Court is invariably quite small. If the number of alter- natives is greater than two, it is theoretically possible for preferences to be distributed so that no outcome is Excerpted from: Robert Dahl, ‘‘Decision Making in consistent with the majority criterion even where all a Democracy: The Supreme Court as a National Poli- members can rank all the alternatives and where there cymaker.’’ In Toward Democracy: A Journey, Reflec- is perfect information as to their preferences, but this tions 1940–1997. Berkeley: Institute of Governmental di‰culty does not bear on the subsequent discussion, Studies Press, 1997. Reprinted with permission of In- and it is disregarded. For an examination of this stitute of Governmental Studies Press, University of problem, consult Arrow, Social Choice and Individual California Berkeley. Values (1951). Democracy and Constitutionalism 247

decision must either (1) accord with the prefer- Table 4.1 ences of a minority of citizens and run counter Type of congressional action after Supreme Court to the preferences of a majority; (2) accord with decisions holding legislation unconstitutional within the preferences of a majority and run counter four years after enactment (including new deal legislation) to the preferences of a minority; or (3) accord with the preferences of one minority and run Congressional Major Minor counter to the preferences of another minority, action policy policy Total the rest being indi¤erent. Reverses Court’s In a democratic system with a more or less policy 17 2 19 representative legislature, it is unnecessary to None 0 12 12 maintain a special court to secure the second Other 6* 1 7 class of outcomes. A case might be made out that the Court protects the rights of national Total 23 15 38 majorities against local interests in federal ques- *[This table] includes the NRA legislation a¤ected by tions, but so far as I am aware, the role of the the Schechter Poultry case. Court as a policymaker is not usually defended in this fashion; in what follows, therefore, I pro- pose to pass over the ticklish question of feder- tion it has modified a good many more. It might alism and deal only with ‘‘national’’ majorities be argued, then, that in all or in a very large and minorities. The third kind of outcome, al- number of these cases the Court was, in fact, though relevant according to other criteria, is defending the rights of some minority against a hardly relevant to the majority criterion, and ‘‘tyrannical’’ majority. There are, however, some may also be passed over for the moment. exceedingly serious di‰culties with this interpre- One influential view of the Court, however, is tation of the Court’s activities. . . . that it stands in some special way as a protection The entire record of the duel between the of minorities against tyranny by majorities. In Court and the lawmaking majority, in cases the course of its 167 years, in 78 cases, the Court where the Court has held legislation unconstitu- has struck down 86 di¤erent provisions of fed- tional within four years after enactment, is sum- eral law as unconstitutional,4 and by interpreta- marized in table 4.1. Thus the application of the majority criterion 4. Actually, the matter is somewhat ambiguous. There seems to show the following: First, if the Court appear to have been 78 cases in which the Court has did in fact uphold minorities against national held provisions of federal law unconstitutional. Sixty- majorities, as both its supporters and critics four di¤erent acts in the technical sense have been often seem to believe, it would be an extremely construed, and 86 di¤erent provisions in law have been anomalous institution from a democratic point in some respects invalidated. I rely here on the figures of view. Second, the elaborate ‘‘democratic’’ and the table given in Library of Congress Legisla- rationalizations of the Court’s defenders and the tive Reference Service, Provisions of Federal Law hostility of its ‘‘democratic’’ critics are largely Held Unconstitutional By the Supreme Court of the United States 95, 141–47 (1936), to which I have added United States v. Lovett, 328 U.S. 303 (1946), Legislative Reference Service, The Constitution of the and United States ex rel. Toth v. Quarles, 350 U.S. 11 United States of America, Analysis and Interpretation (1955). There are some minor discrepancies in totals (Corwin, ed. 1953). The di¤erence is a result of clas- (not attributable to the di¤erences in publication dates) sification. The latter document lists 73 acts held un- between this volume and Acts of Congress Held Un- constitutional (to which Toth v. Quarles, supra, should constitutional in Whole or in Part by the Supreme be added), but di¤erent sections of the same act are Court of the United States, in Library of Congress, sometimes counted separately. Chapter 4 248

irrelevant, for lawmaking majorities generally cases referred to a moment ago, where the policy have had their way. Third, although the Court consequences of the Court’s decisions were seems never to have succeeded in holding out overcome only after long battles, will not appeal indefinitely, in a very small number of important to many contemporary minds as evidence for the cases it has delayed the application of policy up proposition under examination. A natural right to as much as 25 years. to employ child labor in mills and mines? To be How can we appraise decisions of the third free of income taxes by the federal government? kind just mentioned? Earlier I referred to the To employ longshoremen and harbor workers criterion of Right or Justice as a norm sometimes without the protection of workmen’s compensa- invoked to describe the role of the Court. In ac- tion? The Court itself did not rely upon such cordance with this norm, it might be argued that arguments in these cases, and it would be no the most important policy function of the Court credit to their opinions to reconstruct them along is to protect rights that are in some sense basic or such lines. fundamental. Thus (the argument might run) in So far, however, our evidence has been drawn a country where basic rights are, on the whole, from cases in which the Court has held legisla- respected, one should not expect more than a tion unconstitutional within four years after small number of cases where the Court has had enactment. What of the other 40 cases? Do we to plant itself firmly against a lawmaking major- have evidence in these that the Court has pro- ity. But majorities may, on rare occasions, be- tected fundamental or natural rights and liberties come ‘‘tyrannical’’; and when they do, the Court against the dead hand of some past tyranny by intervenes; and although the constitutional issue the lawmakers? The evidence is not impressive. may, strictly speaking, be technically open, the In the entire history of the Court there is not one Constitution assumes an underlying fundamental case arising under the First Amendment in which body of rights and liberties that the Court guar- the Court has held federal legislation unconsti- antees by its decisions. tutional. If we turn from these fundamental lib- Here again, however, even without examining erties of religion, speech, press and assembly, we the actual cases, it would appear, on political do find a handful of cases—something less than grounds, somewhat unrealistic to suppose that a 10—arising under Amendments Four to Seven Court whose members are recruited in the fash- in which the Court has declared acts uncon- ion of Supreme Court justices would long hold stitutional that might properly be regarded as to norms of Right or Justice substantially at involving rather basic liberties.25 An inspection odds with the rest of the political elite. More- of these cases leaves the impression that, in all of over, in an earlier day it was perhaps easier to them, the lawmakers and the Court were not believe that certain rights are so natural and self- very far apart; moreover, it is doubtful that the evident that their fundamental validity is as much a matter of definite knowledge, at least to 25. The candidates for this category would appear to all reasonable creatures, as the color of a ripe be Boyd v. United States, 116 U.S. 616 (1886), Rass- apple. To say that this view is unlikely to find mussen v. United States, 197 U.S. 516 (1905); Wong many articulate defenders today is, of course, Wing v. United States, 163 U.S. 228 (1896); United not to disprove it; it is rather to suggest that we States v. Moreland, 258 U.S. 433 (1922); Kirby v. do not need to elaborate the case against it in United States, 174 U.S. 47 (1899); United States this essay. v. Cohen Grocery Co., 255 U.S. 81 (1921); Weeds, Inc. v. United States, 255 U.S. 109 (1921); Justices of the In any event the best rebuttal to the view of Supreme Court v. United States ex rel Murray, 9 Wall. the Court suggested above will be found in the (U.S.) 274 (1870); United States ex rel. Toth v. Quarles, record of the Court’s decisions. Surely the six 350 U.S. 11 (1955). Democracy and Constitutionalism 249

fundamental conditions of liberty in this country VI have been altered by more than a hair’s breadth as a result of these decisions. However, let us Thus the role of the Court as a policymaking give the Court its due; it is little enough. institution is not simple; and it is an error to Over against these decisions we must put the suppose that its functions can be either de- 15 or so cases in which the Court used the pro- scribed or appraised by means of simple concepts tections of the Fifth, Thirteenth, Fourteenth, and drawn from democratic or moral theory. It is Fifteenth Amendments to preserve the rights and possible, nonetheless, to derive a few general liberties of a relatively privileged group at the conclusions about the Court’s role as a policy- expense of the rights and liberties of a submerged making institution. group: chiefly slaveholders at the expense of National politics in the United States, as in 26 slaves, white people at the expense of colored other stable democracies, is dominated by rela- 27 people, and property holders at the expense of tively cohesive alliances that endure for long 28 wage earners and other groups. These cases, periods of time. One recalls the Je¤ersonian alli- unlike the relatively innocuous ones of the pre- ance, the Jacksonian, the extraordinarily long- ceding set, all involved liberties of genuinely lived Republican dominance of the post-Civil fundamental importance, where an opposite War years, and the New Deal alliance shaped by policy would have meant thoroughly basic shifts Franklin Roosevelt. Each is marked by a break in the distribution of rights, liberties, and op- with past policies, a period of intense struggle, portunities in the United States—where, more- followed by consolidation, and finally decay and over, the policies sustained by the Court’s action disintegration of the alliance. have since been repudiated in every civilized Except for short-lived transitional periods nation of the western world, including our when the old alliance is disintegrating and the own. Yet, if our earlier argument is correct, it is new one is struggling to take control of political futile—precisely because the basic distribution of institutions, the Supreme Court is inevitably a privilege was at issue—to suppose that the Court part of the dominant national alliance. As an could have possibly acted much di¤erently in element in the political leadership of the domi- these areas of policy from the way in which it did nant alliance, the Court of course supports the in fact act. major policies of the alliance. By itself, the Court is almost powerless to a¤ect the course of na- 26. Dred Scott v. Sandford, 19 How. (U.S.) 393 tional policy. In the absence of substantial agree- (1857). ment within the alliance, an attempt by the Court 27. United States v. Reese, 92 U.S. 214 (1876); United to make national policy is likely to lead to disas- States v. Harris, 106 U.S. 629 (1883); United States v. ter, as the Dred Scott decision and the early New Stanley (Civil Rights Cases), 109 U.S. 3 (1883); Bald- Deal cases demonstrate. Conceivably, the cases win v. Franks, 120 U.S. 678 (1887); James v. Bowman, of the last three decades involving the freedom of 190 U.S. 127 (1903); Hodges v. United States, 203 U.S. Negroes, culminating in the now famous deci- 1 (1906); Butts v. Merchants & Miners Transportation Co., 230 U.S. 126 (1913). sion on school integration, are exceptions to this generalization; I shall have more to say about 28. Monongahela Navigation Co. v. United States, 148 U.S. 312 (1893); Adair v. United States, 208 U.S. them in a moment. 161 (1908); Adkins v. Children’s Hospital, 261 U.S. The Supreme Court is not, however, simply an 525 (1923); Nichols v. Coolidge, 27 U.S. 531 (1927); agent of the alliance. It is an essential part of the Untermyer v. Anderson, 276 U.S. 440 (1928); Heiner v. political leadership and possesses some bases of Donnan, 285 U.S. 312 (1932); Louisville Joint Stock power of its own, the most important of which Land Bank v. Radford, 295 U.S. 555 (1935). Chapter 4 250

is the unique legitimacy attributed to its inter- better be called minorities rule, where one aggre- pretations of the Constitution. This legitimacy gation of minorities achieves policies opposed by the Court jeopardizes if it flagrantly opposes another aggregation. the major policies of the dominant alliance; such The main objective of presidential leadership a course of action, as we have seen, is one in is to build a stable and dominant aggregation of which the Court will not normally be tempted to minorities with a high probability of winning engage. the presidency and one or both houses of Con- It follows that within the somewhat narrow gress. The main task of the Court is to confer limits set by the basic policy goals of the domi- legitimacy on the fundamental policies of the nant alliance, the Court can make national pol- successful coalition. There are times when the icy. Its discretion, then, is not unlike that of a coalition is unstable with respect to certain key powerful committee chairman in Congress who policies; at very great risk to its legitimacy cannot, generally speaking, nullify the basic pol- powers, the Court can intervene in such cases icies substantially agreed on by the rest of the and may even succeed in establishing policy. dominant leadership, but who can, within these Probably in such cases it can succeed only if its limits, often determine important questions of action conforms to and reinforces a widespread timing, e¤ectiveness, and subordinate policy. set of explicit or implicit norms held by the po- Thus the Court is least e¤ective against a current litical leadership; norms that are not strong lawmaking majority—and evidently least in- enough or are not distributed in such a way as to clined to act. It is most e¤ective when it sets the insure the existence of an e¤ective lawmaking bounds of policy for o‰cials, agencies, state majority but are, nonetheless, su‰ciently power- governments, or even regions, a task that has ful to prevent any successful attack on the legiti- come to occupy a very large part of the Court’s macy powers of the Court. This is probably the business.29 explanation for the relatively successful work of Few of the Court’s policy decisions can be in- the Court in enlarging the freedom of Negroes to terpreted sensibly in terms of a ‘‘majority’’ versus vote during the past three decades and in its fa- a ‘‘minority.’’ In this respect the Court is no dif- mous school integration decisions.30 ferent from the rest of the political leadership. Yet the Court is more than this. Considered as Generally speaking, policy at the national level is a political system, democracy is a set of basic the outcome of conflict, bargaining, and agree- procedures for arriving at decisions. The opera- ment among minorities; the process is neither tion of these procedures presupposes the exis- minority rule nor majority rule but what might tence of certain rights, obligations, liberties and restraints; in short, certain patterns of behavior. 29. ‘‘Constitutional law and cases with constitutional The existence of these patterns of behavior in undertones are of course still very important, with al- turn presupposes widespread agreement (partic- most one-fourth of the cases in which written opinions ularly among the politically active and influential were filed [in the two most recent terms] involving such segments of the population) on the validity and questions. Review of administrative action . . . con- stitutes the largest category of the Court’s work, com- 30. Rice v. Elmore, 165 F.2d 387 (C.A. 4th, 1947), prising one-third of the total cases decided on the cert. denied 333 U.S. 875 (1948); United States v. merits. The remaining . . . categories of litigation . . . all Classic, 313 U.S. 299 (1941); Smith v. Allwright, 321 involve largely public law questions’’ Frankfurter, U.S. 649 (1944); Grovey v. Townsend, 295 U.S. 45 [‘‘The Supreme Court in the Mirror of Justice.’’ Uni- (1935); Brown v. Board of Education, 347 U.S. 483 versity of Pennsylvania Law Review 105: 781–793, (1954); Bolling v. Sharpe, 347 U.S. 497 (1954). 1957], note 1, at 793. Democracy and Constitutionalism 251

propriety of the behavior. Although its record is by no means lacking in serious blemishes, at its best the Court operates to confer legitimacy, not simply on the particular and parochial policies of the dominant political alliance, but upon the basic patterns of behavior required for the op- eration of a democracy. Democratic Justice

Ian Shapiro

appointed judiciaries or administrative author- Two Dimensions of Democratic Justice ities. . . . Notice, for now, that it is the exceptions that stand in need of justification. In this con- Democrats are committed to rule by the people. nection the argument for democratic justice They insist that no aristocrat, monarch, philoso- exhibits an elective a‰nity with the approaches pher, bureaucrat, expert, or religious leader has to constitutional adjudication that have been the right, in virtue of such status, to force people defended in recent years by Ruth Bader Gins- to accept a particular conception of their proper burg and Robert Burt, and it will be useful to common life. People should decide for them- end this statement of the general argument with selves, via appropriate procedures of collective some discussion of their views. decision, what their collective business should be. Burt conceives of a constitutional democracy They may reasonably be required to consult and as inescapably committed to two principles— take account of one another, and of others af- majority rule and equal self-determination—that fected by their actions, but beyond this no one have the potential to conflict with one another. If may legitimately tell them what to do. The peo- majoritarian processes are employed to promote ple are sovereign; in all matters of collective life domination of some by others, the contradiction they rule over themselves. latent in democratic politics becomes manifest. Although this is less often commented on in the In such circumstances democracy goes to war academic literature, democracy is as much about with itself, and an institutional mechanism is opposition to the arbitrary exercise of power as it needed to resolve the conflict. This is supplied, is about collective self-government. . . . on Burt’s account, by judicial review, understood In a world of ideal political institutions a de- as ‘‘a coercive instrument extrinsic to the dis- rivative view of the place of opposition in dem- putants’’ in a political struggle. Burt sees judicial ocratic politics might be sustainable. But in the review as a ‘‘logical response to an internal con- actual world, where social orders come to be tradiction between majority rule and equal self- what they are in morally arbitrary ways, and determination. It is not a deviation from that where all procedures of government turn out on theory.’’59 close inspection to be flawed, opposition must enjoy a more independent and exalted status in a persuasive account of just democratic politics. . . . 59. Notice that this claim about necessity is agnostic The aspiration to avoid imposed solutions with respect to whether the imperatives on which people must act are ‘‘natural’’ features of the human suggests that the presumption should generally condition or ‘‘socially constructed.’’ Whether the be in favor of doing things through representa- imperatives on which people must act are alterable— tive institutions rather than courts or other and if so, by whom and at what cost to whom—are agencies, because legislatures are more demo- important issues that play a role in the following dis- cratically accountable. Even when action from cussion. But it is a common misconception to believe above is warranted in accordance with the logic that questions about the alterability of the human of subsidiarity, it is generally better for this condition depend on views about social construction. action to be by elected legislatures rather than by The degree to which things are alterable may not vary with the extent to which they are socially constructed at all. Many features of the natural world, ranging Excerpted from: Ian Shapiro, Democratic Justice. from the temperature of our bath water to the genetic 6 New Haven: Yale University Press, 1999. Yale Uni- structure of our beings, can be altered by conscious versity Press, 1999. Reprinted by permission. human design. As the advent of genetic engineering Democracy and Constitutionalism 253

If the court’s legitimate role in a democracy is problem back to southern state legislatures, re- rooted in this logic of preventing domination quiring them to fashion acceptable remedies through democratic process, then it follows for themselves.61 These remedies came before the Burt that its activities should be limited to deal- Court as a result of subsequent litigation, were ing with the consequences of the democratic evaluated when they did, and were often found contradiction. And because preventing domina- to be wanting.62 But the Court avoided de- tion is the goal, it also follows that courts signing the remedy itself, and thus avoided should generally avoid imposing solutions of the charge that it was usurping the legislative their own when democracy has wrought domi- function. nation. Rather, they should declare the domina- Ginsburg, too, has made the case that when tion that has emerged from the democratic courts try to step beyond a reactive role, they process unacceptable and insist that the parties undermine their legitimacy in a democracy. Al- try anew to find an accommodation. Thus in though she thinks that it is sometimes necessary contrast to what many have seen as the alto- for the court to step ‘‘ahead’’ of the political gether too timid approach taken by the U.S. process to achieve reforms that the Constitution Supreme Court in the school desegregation requires, if it gets too far ahead, it can produce a cases of the 1950s and after, on Burt’s view the backlash and provoke charges that it is over- Court took the right stand. In Brown v. Board of reaching its appropriate place in a democratic Education the justices declared the doctrine of constitutional order.63 She and Burt both think ‘‘separate but equal’’ to be an unconstitutional violation of the Equal Protection Clause, but lapsed currency and depleted capital reserves, and a they did not describe schooling conditions that political capacity to tax that is not remotely equal to would be acceptable.60 Rather, they turned the the demands it confronts. In such conditions it might be appropriate for the state to o¤er corporations a mix indicates, those features of human life that are alterable of incentives and penalties to induce them to build and run local hospitals and schools for their workers and may themselves change, so that what has to be ac- cepted as given in one era may become subject to hu- families. Although, for reasons elaborated later in this man modification in another. Socially constructed chapter, this is a less than ideal approach to vindicating basic interests of a population, when the situation is so phenomena, by contrast, often defy all e¤orts at con- scious human control. Markets are human construc- bad, and no feasible alternative is on the horizon, tions, yet we may be unable to regulate them so as to loading even these basic interests onto the employment operate at full employment without inflation. Ethnic relationship may be defensible. hatred might concededly be learned behavior, yet we 61. By focusing on the imperatives that people are may have no idea how to prevent its being reproduced constrained to satisfy, I do not mean to suggest that in the next generation. It is a mistake to leap from the people always value them more highly than other idea of social construction to that of alterability; at activities. People might resent the constraining e¤ects best, the two are contingently related. of many basic interests (on themselves or on others); 60. By the same token, there may be circumstances in they might find them irksome or mundane. One could, which the state lacks the relevant mix of financial and indeed, imagine a person reasonably concluding that a institutional resources to provide many components of life in which one can do no more than act on such imperatives is not worth living. a social wage needed to vindicate basic interests, but it could induce corporations to provide some of them. I 62. This is not to deny that how to cope with expensive think particularly here of countries like contemporary addictions should figure prominently in a discussion of South Africa, which has almost 40 percent unemploy- the collective health care provision. ment in many regions, chronically inadequate basic 63. See Lester C. Thurow, The Future of Capitalism: education and medical care for the majority, a col- How Today’s Economic Forces Shape Tomorrow’s World (Morrow, 1996), pp. 26–29. Chapter 4 254

that the sort of approach adopted by Justice would significantly increase access to abortion Blackmun in Roe v. Wade exemplifies this dan- for anyone.’’ Nonetheless, he points out that ger.64 In contrast to the Brown approach, in ‘‘the abortion issue was openly, avidly, con- Roe the Court did a good deal more than strike troverted in a substantial number of public fo- down a Texas abortion statute. The majority rums, and unlike the regimen extant as recently opinion laid out a detailed test to determine the as 1967, it was no longer clear who was winning conditions under which any abortion statute the battle.’’66 Following the Brown model, the could be expected to pass muster. In e¤ect, Jus- Court might have struck down the Texas abor- tice Blackmun authored a federal abortion stat- tion statute in Roe and remanded the matter for ute of his own. As Ginsburg put it, the Court further action at the state level, thereby setting ‘‘invited no dialogue with legislators. Instead, it limits on what legislatures might do in the mat- seemed entirely to remove the ball from the ter of regulating abortion without involving the legislators’ court’’ by wiping out virtually every Court directly in designing that regulation. On form of abortion regulation then in existence.65 the Ginsburg-Burt view, this would have left On the Ginsburg-Burt view, the sweeping space for democratic resolution of the conflict, holding in Roe diminished the Court’s demo- ensuring the survival of the right to abortion cratic legitimacy at the same time as it polarized while at the same time preserving the legitimacy opinion about abortion and put paid to various of the Court’s role in a democracy.67 schemes to liberalize abortion laws that were Although the tensions that arise within demo- under way in di¤erent states. Between 1967 and cratic justice di¤er from those that motivate Burt 1973 statutes were passed in nineteen states lib- and Ginsburg, in three important respects their eralizing the permissible grounds for abortion. view of the appropriate role for courts in a dem- Many feminists had been dissatisfied with the ocratic order fits comfortably within the general pace and extent of this reform. This is why they argument developed here. First, they articulate mounted the campaign that resulted in Roe. Burt an appropriate institutional response to the in- concedes that in 1973 it was ‘‘not clear whether junction that rather than impose democracy on the recently enacted state laws signified the be- collective activities, the goal should be to try to ginning of a national trend toward abolishing structure those activities so that people will find all abortion restrictions or even whether in the ways to democratize things for themselves. By so-called liberalized states, the new enactments placing courts in a nay-saying stance of ruling out practices as unacceptable when they violate 64. On the e¤ects of global trade on wages and em- the strictures of democratic justice, courts can ployment, see Adrian Wood, North-South Trade, force legislatures and the conflicting parties they Employment, and Inequality: Changing Fortunes in a represent to seek creative democratic solutions to Skill-Driven World (Clarendon, 1994). For a review of literature that points to factors other than trade, prin- 66. Candidates commonly discussed by economists in- cipally technology, see Gary Burtless, ‘‘International clude maximizing sales, capital, and managers’ and trade and the rise of earnings inequality,’’ Journal of own compensation subject to a profitability constraint, Economic Literature , vol. 33 (June 1995), pp. 800–816. or maximizing the probability that profits will remain 65. ‘‘In fact there is democracy in the typical capitalist above a given threshold. For an overview, see David firm; it is just that investors of capital do the voting Kreps, A Course in Economic Theory (Princeton Uni- rather than workers. Converting to worker ownership versity Press, 1990), pp. 724–741. dis means not only enfranchising the workers but also - 67. Robin Archer, Economic Democracy: The Poli- enfranchising the firm’s investors.’’ Henry Hansman, tics of Feasible Socialism (Clarendon Press, 1995), The Ownership of Enterprise (Harvard University pp. 47–48. Press, 1996), p. 43. Democracy and Constitutionalism 255

their conflicts that can pass constitutional mus- in place that may not be reversed for decades or ter. Second, the Ginsburg-Burt view is attractive even generations. Although it may thus be wise because it is reactive but directed; it exemplifies from the standpoint of democratic justice to em- the creative pragmatism that motivates demo- brace an activist role for a constitutional court, it cratic justice. It involves accepting that there is is equally wise to limit courts to a circumscribed an important—if circumscribed—role for courts and negationist activism. in a democracy, yet it does not make the un- manageable and undemocratic administrative demands on courts that accompany more proac- The Path to Application tive views of adjudication. On this view a court might reasonably hold that a given policy should My aim here has been to state the general case be rejected without stating (indeed, perhaps for a democratic conception of social justice. without having decided) what policy would This I have sought to do by building on the pass muster. ‘‘This is unacceptable for reasons popular view, in which considerations of de- a; b; c ...; find a better way’’ is seen as an mocracy and justice are intimately linked, rather appropriate stance for a constitutional court. than conventional academic views of them as Finally, by recognizing the relatively greater fundamentally distinct and mutually antagonis- legitimacy of legislatures and treating courts tic. The account that I o¤er rests on the twin as institutional mechanisms for coping with leg- commitments to government and opposition in islative failure, the Ginsburg-Burt view takes democratic theory, suggesting that there should account of the fact that no decision-making always be opportunities for those a¤ected by the mechanism is flawless. Yet it does so in a way operation of a collective practice both to partici- that is rooted in the idea that democratic proce- pate in its governance and to oppose its results dures should be made to operate as well as pos- when they are so inclined. These two injunctions sible, and when they fail, remedies should be no should reasonably be expected to have di¤erent more intrusive on the democratic process than is implications in di¤erent cultures, and, within necessary to repair them. the same culture, to evolve over time and play Some will object to this as too minimal a role themselves out di¤erently in di¤erent circum- for reviewing courts, but democrats have to stances. They are best thought of as conditioning concern themselves not only with courts that as- constraints, designed to democratize social rela- pire to advance the cause of democratic justice, tions as they are reproduced, rather than as as they might reasonably be thought to have blueprints for social justice. . . . done in Brown and Roe, but also with courts that do not, as was the case in Dred Scott, the Civil Rights Cases, and Lochner v. New York.68 Insu- lated from any further review, and lacking, at least in the American context, in democratic ac- countability, courts can put decisions of this kind

68. For the same reason, whether the employment re- lationship is in the public or private sector is of no particular concern from the standpoint of democratic justice (although the strategic possibilities for advanc- ing democratic justice may be di¤erent in public- and private-sector employment).

5 PRESIDENTIALISM VERSUS PARLIAMENTARISM

The Perils of Presidentialism Juan Linz

Presidentialism, Multipartism, and Democracy: The Di‰cult Combination Scott Mainwaring

Presidents and Assemblies Matthew Soberg Shugart and John Carey

Minority Governments, Deadlock Situations, and the Survival of Presidential Democracies Jose´ Antonio Cheibub

Minority Governments in Parliamentary Democracies: The Rationality of Nonwinning Cabinet Solutions Kaare Strom

Institutional Design, Party Systems, and Governability: Di¤erentiating the Presidential Regimes of Latin America Joe Foweraker

Presidential Power, Legislative Organization, and Party Behavior in Brazil Argelina Cheibub Figueiredo and Fernando Limongi The Perils of Presidentialism

Juan Linz

. . . [T]he superior historical performance of par- the symbolic head of state and can be removed liamentary democracies is no accident. A care- between elections only by the drastic step of ful comparison of parliamentarism as such with impeachment. In practice, as the history of the presidentialism as such leads to the conclusion United States shows, presidential systems may be that, on balance, the former is more conducive to more or less dependent on the cooperation of the stable democracy than the latter. This conclusion legislature; the balance between executive and applies especially to nations with deep politi- legislative power in such systems can thus vary cal cleavages and numerous political parties; for considerably. . . . such countries, parliamentarism generally o¤ers Two things about presidential government a better hope of preserving democracy. stand out. The first is the president’s strong claim to democratic, even plebiscitarian, legitimacy; the second is his fixed term in o‰ce. . . . Parliamentary vs. Presidential Systems But what is most striking is that in a presi- dential system, the legislators, especially when A parliamentary regime in the strict sense is they represent cohesive, disciplined parties that one in which the only democratically legitimate o¤er clear ideological and political alternatives, institution is parliament; in such a regime, the can also claim democratic legitimacy. This claim government’s authority is completely dependent is thrown into high relief when a majority of the upon parliamentary confidence. Although the legislature represents a political option opposed growing personalization of party leadership in to the one the president represents. Under such some parliamentary regimes has made prime circumstances, who has the stronger claim to ministers seem more and more like presidents, it speak on behalf of the people: the president or remains true that barring dissolution of parlia- the legislative majority that opposes his policies? ment and a call for new elections, premiers can- Since both derive their power from the votes of not appeal directly to the people over the heads the people in a free competition among well- of their representatives. Parliamentary systems defined alternatives, a conflict is always possible may include presidents who are elected by direct and at times may crupt dramatically. There is no popular vote, but they usually lack the ability democratic principle on the basis of which it can to compete seriously for power with the prime be resolved, and the mechanisms the constitution minister. might provide are likely to prove too compli- In presidential systems an executive with cated and aridly legalistic to be of much force in considerable constitutional powers—generally the eyes of the electorate. It is therefore no acci- including full control of the composition of the dent that in some such situations in the past, the cabinet and administration—is directly elected armed forces were often tempted to intervene by the people for a fixed term and is indepen- as a mediating power. One might argue that dent of parliamentary votes of confidence. He is the United States has successfully rendered such not only the holder of executive power but also conflicts ‘‘normal’’ and thus defused them. To explain how American political institutions and Excerpted from: Juan Linz, ‘‘The Perils of Presiden- practices have achieved this result would exceed tialism.’’ Journal of Democracy 1 (1990): 51–69. 6 The the scope of this essay, but it is worth noting Johns Hopkins University Press and National Endow- that the uniquely di¤use character of American ment for Democracy. Reprinted by permission of The political parties—which, ironically, exasperates Johns Hopkins University Press. Presidentialism versus Parliamentarism 259

many American political scientists and leads presidentialism might reply that this rigidity is an them to call for responsible, ideologically dis- advantage, for it guards against the uncertainty ciplined parties—has something to do with it. and instability so characteristic of parliamen- Unfortunately, the American case seems to be an tary politics. Under parliamentary government, exception; the development of modern political after all, myriad actors—parties, their leaders, parties, particularly in socially and ideologically even rank-and-file legislators—may at any time polarized countries, generally exacerbates, rather between elections adopt basic changes, cause than moderates, conflicts between the legislative realignments, and, above all, make or break and the executive. prime ministers. But while the need for authority The second outstanding feature of presidential and predictability would seem to favor presi- systems—the president’s relatively fixed term in dentialism, there are unexpected developments— o‰ce—is also not without drawbacks. It breaks ranging from the death of the incumbent to the political process into discontinuous, rigidly serious errors in judgment committed under the demarcated periods, leaving no room for the pressure of unruly circumstances—that make continuous readjustments that events may de- presidential rule less predictable and often mand. The duration of the president’s mandate weaker than that of a prime minister. The latter becomes a crucial factor in the calculations of all can always seek to shore up his legitimacy and political actors, a fact which (as we shall see) is authority, either through a vote of confidence or fraught with important consequences. . . . It is a the dissolution of parliament and the ensuing paradox of presidential government that while new elections. Moreover, a prime minister can be it leads to the personalization of power, its legal changed without necessarily creating a regime mechanisms may also lead, in the event of a crisis. sudden midterm succession, to the rise of some- Considerations of this sort loom especially one whom the ordinary electoral process would large during periods of regime transition and never have made the chief of state. consolidation, when the rigidities of a presiden- tial constitution must seem inauspicious indeed compared to the prospect of adaptability that Paradoxes of Presidentialism parliamentarism o¤ers.

Presidential constitutions paradoxically incor- porate contradictory principles and assumptions. Zero-Sum Elections On the one hand, such systems set out to create a strong, stable executive with enough plebi- . . . Presidentialism is ineluctably problematic scitarian legitimation to stand fast against the because it operates according to the rule of array of particular interests represented in the ‘‘winner-take-all’’—an arrangement that tends legislature. . . . On the other hand, presidential to make democratic politics a zero-sum game, constitutions also reflect profound suspicion of with all the potential for conflict such games the personalization of power: memories and portend. Although parliamentary elections can fears of kings and caudillos do not dissipate produce an absolute majority for a single party, easily. . . . they more often give representation to a number Perhaps the best way to summarize the basic of parties. Power-sharing and coalition-forming di¤erences between presidential and parliamen- are fairly common, and incumbents are accord- tary systems is to say that while parliamentarism ingly attentive to the demands and interests of imparts flexibility to the political process, presi- even the smaller parties. These parties in turn dentialism makes it rather rigid. Proponents of retain expectations of sharing in power and, Chapter 5 260

therefore, of having a stake in the system as a necessarily award the o‰ce to the candidate with whole. By contrast, the conviction that he pos- the most votes. More common are run-o¤ pro- sesses independent authority and a popular visions that set up a confrontation between mandate is likely to imbue a president with a the two major candidates, with possibilities sense of power and mission, even if the plurality for polarization that have already been men- that elected him is a slender one. Given such tioned. One of the possible consequences of two- assumptions about his standing and role, he will candidate races in multiparty systems is that find the inevitable opposition to his policies far broad coalitions are likely to be formed (whether more irksome and demoralizing than would a in run-o¤s or in preelection maneuvering) in prime minister, who knows himself to be but the which extremist parties gain undue influence. spokesman for a temporary governing coalition If significant numbers of voters identify strongly rather than the voice of the nation or the tribune with such parties, one or more of them can of the people. . . . plausibly claim to represent the decisive electoral The danger that zero-sum presidential elec- bloc in a close contest and may make demands tions pose is compounded by the rigidity of the accordingly. Unless a strong candidate of the president’s fixed term in o‰ce. Winners and center rallies widespread support against the losers are sharply defined for the entire period of extremes, a presidential election can fragment the presidential mandate. There is no hope for and polarize the electorate. shifts in alliances, expansion of the government’s In countries where the preponderance of base of support through national-unity or emer- voters is centrist, agrees on the exclusion of gency grand coalitions, new elections in response extremists, and expects both rightist and leftist to major new events, and so on. Instead, the candidates to di¤er only within a larger, moder- losers must wait at least four or five years with- ate consensus, the divisiveness latent in presi- out any access to executive power and patron- dential competition is not a serious problem. age. The zero-sum game in presidential regimes With an overwhelmingly moderate electorate, raises the stakes of presidential elections and in- anyone who makes alliances or takes positions evitably exacerbates their attendant tension and that seem to incline him to the extremes is un- polarization. likely to win, as both Barry Goldwater and On the other hand, presidential elections do George McGovern discovered to their chagrin. o¤er the indisputable advantage of allowing the But societies beset by grave social and economic people to choose their chief executive openly, problems, divided about recent authoritarian directly, and for a predictable span rather than regimes that once enjoyed significant popular leaving that decision to the backstage maneu- support, and in which well-disciplined extremist vering of the politicians. But this advantage can parties have considerable electoral appeal, do only be present if a clear mandate results. If not fit the model presented by the United States. there is no required minimum plurality and sev- In a polarized society with a volatile electorate, eral candidates compete in a single round, the no serious candidate in a single-round election margin between the victor and the runner-up can a¤ord to ignore parties with which he would may be too thin to support any claim that a otherwise never collaborate. decisive plebiscite has taken place. To preclude A two-round election can avoid some of these this, electoral laws sometimes place a lower limit problems, for the preliminary round shows the on the size of the winning plurality or create extremist parties the limits of their strength and some mechanism for choosing among the candi- allows the two major candidates to reckon just dates if none attains the minimum number of which alliances they must make to win. This votes needed to win; such procedures need not reduces the degree of uncertainty and promotes Presidentialism versus Parliamentarism 261

more rational decisions on the part of both great powers associated with the presidency voters and candidates. In e¤ect, the presidential but also the limits imposed on it—particularly system may thus reproduce something like the those requiring cooperation with the legislative negotiations that ‘‘form a government’’ in par- branch, a requirement that becomes especially liamentary regimes. But the potential for polar- salient when that branch is dominated by oppo- ization remains, as does the di‰culty of isolating nents of the president’s party. Above all, how- extremist factions that a significant portion of ever, there are the time constraints that a fixed the voters and elites intensely dislike. term or number of possible terms imposes on the incumbent. The o‰ce of president is by nature two-dimensional and, in a sense, ambiguous: on The Spanish Example the one hand, the president is the head of state and the representative of the entire nation; on . . . Spanish politics since Franco has clearly felt the other hand, he stands for a clearly partisan the moderating influence of parliamentarism; political option. If he stands at the head of a without it, the transition to popular government multiparty coalition, he may even represent an and the consolidation of democratic rule would option within an option as he deals with other probably have taken a far di¤erent—and much members of the winning electoral alliance. rougher—course. The president may find it di‰cult to combine Let me now add a moderating note of my his role as the head of what Bagehot called the own. I am not suggesting that the polarization ‘‘deferential’’ or symbolic aspect of the polity . . . which often springs from presidential elections with his role as an e¤ective chief executive and is an inevitable concomitant of presidential gov- partisan leader fighting to promote his party ernment. If the public consensus hovers reliably and its program. . . . A presidential system, as around the middle of the political spectrum and opposed to a constitutional monarchy or a re- if the limited weight of the fringe parties is in public with both a premier and a head of state, evidence, no candidate will have any incentive to does not allow such a neat di¤erentiation of coalesce with the extremists. They may run for roles. o‰ce, but they will do so in isolation and largely Perhaps the most important consequences as a rhetorical exercise. Under these conditions of the direct relationship that exists between a of moderation and preexisting consensus, presi- president and the electorate are the sense the dential campaigns are unlikely to prove danger- president may have of being the only elected ously divisive. The problem is that in countries representative of the whole people and the caught up in the arduous experience of estab- accompanying risk that he will tend to conflate lishing and consolidating democracy, such happy his supporters with ‘‘the people’’ as a whole. The circumstances are seldom present. They certainly plebiscitarian component implicit in the presi- do not exist when there is a polarized multiparty dent’s authority is likely to make the obstacles system including extremist parties. and opposition he encounters seem particularly annoying. In his frustration he may be tempted to define his policies as reflections of the popular The Style of Presidential Politics will and those of his opponents as the selfish designs of narrow interests. This identification of . . . Some of presidentialism’s most notable leader with people fosters a certain populism that e¤ects on the style of politics result from the may be a source of strength. It may also, how- characteristics of the presidential o‰ce itself. ever, bring on a refusal to acknowledge the limits Among these characteristics are not only the of the mandate that even a majority—to say Chapter 5 262

nothing of a mere plurality—can claim as out of public life altogether. A premier’s minis- democratic justification for the enactment of its ters, by contrast, are not his creatures but nor- agenda. The doleful potential for displays of mally his parliamentary colleagues; they may go cold indi¤erence, disrespect, or even downright from the cabinet back to their seats in parliament hostility toward the opposition is not to be and question the prime minister in party cau- scanted. . . . cuses or during the ordinary course of parlia- Unlike the rather Olympian president, the mentary business just as freely as other members prime minister is normally a member of parlia- can. A president, moreover, can shield his cabi- ment who, even as he sits on the government net members from criticism much more e¤ec- bench, remains part of the larger body. . . . Espe- tively than can a prime minister, whose cabinet cially uncertain in presidential regimes is the members are regularly hauled before parliament place of opposition leaders, who may not even to answer queries or even, in extreme cases, to hold public o‰ce and in any case have nothing face censure. like the quasi-o‰cial status that the leaders of One need not delve into all the complexities of the opposition enjoy in Britain, for example. the relations between the executive and the leg- The absence in presidential regimes of a mon- islature in various presidential regimes to see that arch or a ‘‘president of the republic’’ who can act all such systems are based on dual democratic symbolically as a moderating power deprives the legitimacy: no democratic principle exists to system of flexibility and of a means of restraining resolve disputes between the executive and the power. A generally neutral figure can provide legislature about which of the two actually rep- moral ballast in a crisis or act as a moderator resents the will of the people. . . . between the premier and his opponents—who Even more ominously, in the absence of may include not only his parliamentary foes but any principled method of distinguishing the true military leaders as well. A parliamentary regime bearer of democratic legitimacy, the president has a speaker or presiding member of parlia- may use ideological formulations to discredit his ment who can exert some restraining influence foes; institutional rivalry may thus assume the over the parliamentary antagonists, including the character of potentially explosive social and po- prime minister himself, who is after all a member litical strife. Institutional tensions that in some of the chamber over which the speaker presides. societies can be peacefully settled through nego- tiation or legal means may in other, less happy lands seek their resolution in the streets. The Problem of Dual Legitimacy

. . . Ministers in parliamentary systems are situ- The Issue of Stability ated quite di¤erently from cabinet o‰cers in presidential regimes. Especially in cases of coali- Among the oft-cited advantages of presiden- tion or minority governments, prime ministers tialism is its provision for the stability of the ex- are much closer to being on an equal footing ecutive. This feature is said to furnish a welcome with their fellow ministers than presidents will contrast to the tenuousness of many parliamen- ever be with their cabinet appointees. . . . tary governments, with their frequent cabinet A presidential cabinet is less likely than its crises and changes of prime minister, especially parliamentary counterpart to contain strong and in the multiparty democracies of Western Eu- independent-minded members. The o‰cers of a rope. Certainly the spectacle of political insta- president’s cabinet hold their posts purely at the bility presented by the Third and Fourth French su¤erance of their chief; if dismissed, they are Republics and, more recently, by Italy and Por- Presidentialism versus Parliamentarism 263

tugal has contributed to the low esteem in which o‰ce. In the latter case, there is a temptation many scholars—especially in Latin America— to conceal the president’s infirmity until the end hold parliamentarism and their consequent pref- of his term. In event of the president’s death, erence for presidential government. But such resignation, impeachment, or incapacity, the invidious comparisons overlook the large degree presidential constitution very often assures an of stability that actually characterizes parlia- automatic and immediate succession with no in- mentary governments. The superficial volatility terregnum or power vacuum. But the institution they sometimes exhibit obscures the continuity of vice-presidential succession, which has worked of parties in power, the enduring character of so well in the United States, may not function so coalitions, and the way that party leaders and smoothly elsewhere. . . . key ministers have of weathering cabinet crises without relinquishing their posts. In addition, the instability of presidential cabinets has been The Time Factor ignored by students of governmental stability. It is also insu‰ciently noted that parliamentary Democracy is by definition a government pro systems, precisely by virtue of their surface in- tempore, a regime in which the electorate at stability, often avoid deeper crises. A prime regular intervals can hold its governors account- minister who becomes embroiled in scandal or able and impose a change. The limited time that loses the allegiance of his party or majority co- is allowed to elapse between elections is prob- alition and whose continuance in o‰ce might ably the greatest guarantee against overweening provoke grave turmoil can be much more easily power and the last hope for those in the minor- removed than a corrupt or highly unpopular ity. Its drawback, however, is that it constrains president. Unless partisan alignments make the a government’s ability to make good on the formation of a democratically legitimate cabinet promises it made in order to get elected. If these impossible, parliament should eventually be able promises were far-reaching, including major to select a new prime minister who can form a programs of social change, the majority may feel new government. In some more serious cases, cheated of their realization by the limited term new elections may be called, although they often in o‰ce imposed on their chosen leader. On the do not resolve the problem and can even, as in other hand, the power of a president is at once the case of Weimar Germany in the 1930s, com- so concentrated and so extensive that it seems pound it. unsafe not to check it by limiting the number of The government crises and ministerial changes times any one president can be reelected. Such of parliamentary regimes are of course excluded provisions can be frustrating, especially if the by the fixed term a president enjoys, but this incumbent is highly ambitious; attempts to great stability is bought at the price of similarly change the rule in the name of continuity have great rigidity. Flexibility in the face of constantly often appeared attractive. changing situations is not presidentialism’s Even if a president entertains no inordinate strong suit. Replacing a president who has lost ambitions, his awareness of the time limits facing the confidence of his party or the people is an him and the program to which his name is tied extremely di‰cult proposition. . . . What in a cannot help but a¤ect his political style. . . . parliamentary system would be a government The fixed term in o‰ce and the limit on crisis can become a full-blown regime crisis in a reelection are institutions of unquestionable presidential system. value in presidential constitutions, but they mean The same rigidity is apparent when an in- that the political system must produce a capable cumbent dies or su¤ers incapacitation while in and popular leader every four years or so, and Chapter 5 264

also that whatever ‘‘political capital’’ the out- may alternate as premiers; each knows that the going president may have accumulated cannot other may be called upon to replace him at any endure beyond the end of his term. time and that confrontations can be costly to All political leaders must worry about the both, so they share power. A similar logic applies ambitions of second-rank leaders, sometimes be- to relations between leaders of competing parties cause of their jockeying for position in the order or parliamentary coalitions. of succession and sometimes because of their The time constraints associated with presi- intrigues. The fixed and definite date of succes- dentialism, combined with the zero-sum charac- sion that a presidential constitution sets can only ter of presidential elections, are likely to render exacerbate the incumbent’s concerns on this such contests more dramatic and divisive than score. Add to this the desire for continuity, and it parliamentary elections. The political realign- requires no leap of logic to predict that the pres- ments that in a parliamentary system may take ident will choose as his lieutenant and successor- place between elections and within the halls of apparent someone who is more likely to prove a the legislature must occur publicly during elec- yes-man than a leader in his own right. tion campaigns in presidential systems, where The inevitable succession also creates a dis- they are a necessary part of the process of build- tinctive kind of tension between the ex-president ing a winning coalition. . . . A presidential regime and his successor. The new man may feel driven leaves much less room for tacit consensus- to assert his independence and distinguish him- building, coalition-shifting, and the making of self from his predecessor, even though both compromises which, though prudent, are hard to might belong to the same party. The old presi- defend in public. . . . dent, for his part, having known the unique honor and sense of power that come with the o‰ce, will always find it hard to reconcile him- Parliamentarism and Political Stability self to being out of power for good, with no prospect of returning even if the new incumbent This analysis of presidentialism’s unpromising fails miserably. Parties and coalitions may pub- implications for democracy is not meant to licly split because of such antagonisms and frus- imply that no presidential democracy can be trations. They can also lead to intrigues, as when stable; on the contrary, the world’s most stable a still-prominent former president works behind democracy—the United States of America— the scenes to influence the next succession or to has a presidential constitution. Nevertheless, one undercut the incumbent’s policies or leadership cannot help tentatively concluding that in many of the party. other societies the odds that presidentialism will Of course similar problems can also emerge in help preserve democracy are far less favorable. parliamentary systems when a prominent leader While it is true that parliamentarism pro- finds himself out of o‰ce but eager to return. vides a more flexible and adaptable institutional But parliamentary regimes can more easily miti- context for the establishment and consolidation gate such di‰culties for a number of reasons. of democracy, it does not follow that just any The acute need to preserve party unity, the def- sort of parliamentary regime will do. Indeed, to erence accorded prominent party figures, and the complete the analysis one would need to reflect new premier’s keen awareness that he needs the upon the best type of parliamentary constitution help of his predecessor even if the latter does and its specific institutional features. Among not sit on the government bench or the same side these would be a prime-ministerial o‰ce com- of the house—all these contribute to the main- bining power with responsibility, which would tenance of concord. Leaders of the same party in turn require strong, well-disciplined political Presidentialism versus Parliamentarism 265

parties. Such features—there are of course many others we lack the space to discuss—would help foster responsible decision making and sta- ble governments and would encourage genuine party competition without causing undue polit- ical fragmentation. In addition, every country has unique aspects that one must take into account—traditions of federalism, ethnic or cul- tural heterogeneity, and so on. Finally, it almost goes without saying that our analysis establishes only probabilities and tendencies, not determin- isms. No one can guarantee that parliamentary systems will never experience grave crisis or even breakdown. In the final analysis, all regimes, however wisely designed, must depend for their preserva- tion upon the support of society at large—its major forces, groups, and institutions. They rely, therefore, on a public consensus which recog- nizes as legitimate authority only that power which is acquired through lawful and democratic means. They depend also on the ability of their leaders to govern, to inspire trust, to respect the limits of their power, and to reach an adequate degree of consensus. Although these qualities are most needed in a presidential system, it is precisely there that they are most di‰cult to achieve. Heavy reliance on the personal qualities of a political leader—on the virtue of a states- man, if you will—is a risky course, for one never knows if such a man can be found to fill the presidential o‰ce. But while no presidential constitution can guarantee a Washington, a Jua´rez, or a Lincoln, no parliamentary regime can guarantee an Adenauer or a Churchill either. Given such unavoidable uncertainty, the aim of this essay has been merely to help recover a de- bate on the role of alternative democratic insti- tutions in building stable democratic polities. Presidentialism, Multipartism, and Democracy: The Di‰cult Combination

Scott Mainwaring

Choices of political institutions matter. Institu- does not produce a clear winner, but as the fun- tions create incentives and disincentives for damental process, the system is usually parlia- political actors, shape actors’ identities, estab- mentary5 and never presidential. Postelection lish the context in which policy-making occurs, negotiations that determine which parties will and can help or hinder in the construction govern and which will head the government are of democratic regimes. And among all of the crucial in many parliamentary regimes, so they choices regarding institutions, none is more im- indirectly determine who will be prime minister. portant than the system of government: presi- Such postelection negotiations are not part of the dential, semipresidential, parliamentary, or some selection process of chief executives in presiden- hybrid. . . . tial systems. Rather than addressing general problems or In presidential systems, the president must be strengths of presidential systems, as Linz did, the head of government. In semipresidential sys- or specific case studies, as several other analysts tems (e.g., Finland, France), a popularly-elected have done, this article focuses on a sizable sub- president is head of state but is not always the category of presidential systems: those in multi- head of government. In Austria, Iceland, and party democracies. I argue that the combination Ireland, a president is elected by direct popular of presidentialism and multipartism makes stable vote but has only minor powers and, therefore, is democracy di‰cult to sustain. Since many presi- not the head of government. In all three coun- dential democracies have multiparty systems, the tries, the system of government is parliamentary, argument has broad implications for scholarship and for the political debate about institutional 5. Switzerland is an exception. The executive (which is choices in new democracies. . . . collegial) is selected by the legislature, but the system is A presidential democracy has two distinguish- not parliamentary because the executive has a fixed ing features.4 First, the head of government is term of o‰ce. In Bolivia, as was also the case in Chile essentially popularly elected; this includes the before 1973, when no presidential candidate wins an U.S., where the electoral college has little auton- absolute majority of the popular vote, congress elects omy with respect to the popular vote. Legislative the president. But there is a key di¤erence between these two cases. In Chile, the congress always selected elections and postelection negotiations do not the front-runner in popular votes; it did not broker the determine executive power. Wherever the head election but rather confirmed the popular winner, so it of government is selected by the legislature, not can be considered presidential. If, however, congress as a second alternative where the popular vote plays the dominant role in selecting the president, as is the case in Bolivia, then the system is not presidential. Excerpted from: Scott Mainwaring, ‘‘Presidentialism, In Bolivia, the congress gave the presidency to candi- Multipartism, and Democracy: The Di‰cult Com- dates who did not capture the most votes in 1979, 1985, bination.’’ Comparative Political Studies 26(2) (July and 1989. Legislative negotiations became the primary 1993): 198–228. 6 1993 Sage Publications, Inc. Re- mechanism for selecting the president. Consequently, printed by permission of Sage Publications, Inc. the system is not strictly presidential, but rather alter- nating; it is presidential when one candidate obtains an 4. For related discussions of how presidentialism should be defined, see Linz (1994), Lijphart (1984, pp. absolute majority in the popular vote, but it is a hybrid 68–74), Riggs (1988), and Shugart and Carey (1992, when, as has been occurring consistently, this is not the p. 18–27). case. Because the president’s term of o‰ce is fixed, the system is not parliamentary. Presidentialism versus Parliamentarism 267

notwithstanding the existence of popular elec- (a) democracies that, as of 1992, had enjoyed at tions for president.6 least 25 years of uninterrupted democracy . . . ; The second distinguishing feature of presi- (b) governments that at some point enjoyed at dential democracies is that the president is least 25 years of uninterrupted democracy, but elected for a fixed time period. Most presidential that broke down after 1945 . . . ; (c) democratic democracies allow for impeachment, but this governments that experienced breakdowns be- practice is rare and does not substantially a¤ect tween 1945 and 1992 without making the 25-year our definition because of its extraordinary char- minimum . . . ; and (d) extant democracies that acter. The president cannot be forced to resign have not yet met the 25 year minimum. This because of a no-confidence vote by the legisla- latter category is excluded from the present ture. In contrast, in a parliamentary system, the analysis because these cases cannot yet be con- head of government is selected by the legislature sidered stable democracies. Only 7 of 31 (22.6%) and subsequently depends upon the ongoing presidential democracies have endured for at confidence of the legislature for remaining in of- least 25 consecutive years, compared with 25 of fice; thus the time period of the chief executive’s 44 parliamentary systems (56.8%), 2 of 4 hybrids mandate is alterable. (50.0%), and 2 of 3 semipresidential systems In synthesis, following Lijphart (1984, pp. 68– (66.7%). 74), I define presidentialism according to two The lack of stable presidential democracies dimensions: whether the chief executive is elected could be unrelated to presidentialism, but there by the legislature and whether the term of o‰ce are reasons to believe it probably is related. is fixed. . . . Blondel and Sua´rez (1981), Lijphart (in press), Linz (in press), Riggs (1988), and Sua´rez (1982), have argued that presidentialism is less likely Presidentialism and Stable Democracy to promote stable democracy. I do not share all of their criticisms,8 and most of the critics have Stable (or continuous) democracy is defined here overlooked some strengths of presidential sys- strictly on the basis of democratic longevity, tems (Shugart & Carey, 1992; Ceaser, 1986). more specifically, at least 25 years of uninter- Nevertheless, I agree that presidentialism is rupted democracy. . . . Presidential systems have not fared well. 8. Linz (1994) and Lijphart (1994) add a fourth li- Out of 31 countries that have had continuous ability: the supposedly majoritarian bent of presi- democracy since at least 1967, only four—the dentialism. I disagree with this part of their argument. debatable case of Colombia, plus Costa Rica, The most majoritarian democracies are the West- the U.S., and Venezuela—have presidential sys- minster style parliamentary systems with highly dis- tems. Twenty-four stable democracies have par- ciplined parties, in which the winning party controls liamentary systems, two have semipresidential everything for a protracted period of time, possibly systems, and one has a hybrid. . . . despite winning well under 50% of the votes. Presi- The post-1945 democracies can be divided into dentialism is predicated upon a separation of powers, so that an opposition party or coalition can control the four categories, of which three are relevant here: legislature (or one house thereof ), thereby exercising some control over presidential initiatives even if it does 6. Duverger (1980) argued that Austria, Iceland, and not control the presidency. I agree with Linz and Lij- Ireland have semipresidential governments, but the phart, however, that parliamentarism is more condu- presidents have only symbolic power in all three cases. cive to coalition building. For a critical examination What matters is whether these o‰ces are largely sym- of Linz’s seminal piece, see Mainwaring and Shugart bolic or, conversely, whether the o‰ce holders wield (1997). considerable power. Chapter 5 268

generally less favorable for democracy and that where in most countries, several other factors presidentialism has some distinct liabilities, have contributed to democratic instability; in three of which are highlighted in the following this sense, there is a possibility of overdeter- discussion. mination. Moreover, there is no absolutely clear Perhaps the greatest comparative liability of correlation between the system of government presidential systems is their di‰culty in handling and policy e¤ectiveness. One presidential de- major crises. Presidential systems o¤er less flexi- mocracy (the United States) stands out as bility in crisis situations because attempts to de- successful by most historical/comparative stan- pose the president easily shake the whole system. dards, and Costa Rica and Venezuela have There are no neat means of replacing a president strong democratic institutions with presidential who is enormously unpopular in the society at systems. Many parliamentary systems have pro- large and has lost most of his/her support in the duced e¤ective government, but some have not, legislature. . . . with the Third and Fourth French Republics In many cases, a coup appears to be the only often being cited as examples. Finally, the nature means of getting rid of an incompetent or un- of the party system and specific institutional popular president. . . . prerogatives of the executive and legislature A second liability of presidentialism, a greater can either promote or undermine the viability of likelihood of executive/legislative deadlock, presidential or parliamentary democracy. There stems primarily from the separate election of the are di¤erent kinds of presidentialism and par- two branches of government and is exacerbated liamentarism, and the di¤erences between one by the fixed term of o‰ce. Presidential systems variant and another can be crucial (Shugart & are more prone to immobilism than parliamen- Carey, 1992); di¤erences in the nature of the tary systems for two primary reasons. They are parties and party system also crucially a¤ect how more apt to have executives whose program is well presidential and parliamentary governments consistently blocked by the legislature, and they function. are less capable of dealing with this problem when it arises. The president may be incapable of pursuing a coherent course of action because of Presidentialism, Multipartism, and Stable congressional opposition, but no other actor can Democracy resolve the problem playing within democratic rules of the game. . . . Among stable presidential democracies, the A third problem of presidentialism stems from virtual absence of multiparty systems is striking. the direct popular election of presidents, which This observation, however, does not explain why in itself seems desirable. The downside of direct multiparty systems are less propitious to stable popular elections is that political outsiders with presidential democracy than two-party systems. little experience in handling congress can get Without some logical explanation, it remains elected. . . . possible that this is an accident or a spurious Although I agree with the critics of presi- correlation. But there are reasons to believe that dentialism on these key points, none of this the combination of presidentialism and multi- implies that democracy cannot be sustained by party systems makes it more di‰cult to achieve presidentialism, that presidentialism is the main stable democracy. explanation for the vicissitudes of democracy in Two-party systems, in and of themselves, are certain countries, or that parliamentary govern- not necessarily a desideratum. They constrict the ment would always work better. Most presiden- breadth of opinion represented, and they hinder tial democracies have been in Latin America, the building of coalition governments, making Presidentialism versus Parliamentarism 269

it di‰cult to establish consociational forms of lack stable legislative support, so pushing policy democracy (Lijphart 1994). As Sartori (1976, pp. measures through is apt to be more di‰cult. 191–192) observed, two-party systems become Immobilism and sharp conflict between the less functional and less viable as the spread of executive and the legislature, with potentially opinion becomes greater. Nevertheless, in presi- deleterious consequences for democratic stabil- dential systems a two-party format seems more ity and/or e¤ective governance, often result. favorable to stable democracy. The question is Protracted conflicts between the legislature and why multipartism and presidentialism make a congress can lead to a decision-making paralysis di‰cult combination, why a two-party system (Santos, 1986). In fledgling democracies, such ameliorates the problems of presidentialism, and paralysis can have pernicious results. If, in addi- why parliamentarism mitigates the di‰culties of tion to being highly fragmented, the party system multipartism. is also polarized, the di‰culties of governing will The answer to these questions, I submit, is be compounded. threefold. In presidential systems, multipartism The likelihood of immobilism is lower in two- increases the likelihood of executive/legislative party presidential and in parliamentary systems. deadlock and immobilism. It also increases the Having a two-party system increases the like- likelihood of ideological polarization. Finally, lihood that the president will enjoy majority with multipartism, presidents need to build backing in congress, and hence decreases the interparty coalitions to get measures through the probability of presidential/legislative impasse. legislature, but interparty coalition building in Two-party systems are not necessarily better presidential systems is more di‰cult and less equipped to handle the problems created by a stable than in parliamentary systems. . . . lack of legislative support, but they are better at avoiding this problem. . . . Not only are multiparty presidential systems Presidentialism, Multipartism, and Immobilism more apt to generate deadlocks, with the fixed electoral timetable and the separation of powers, Multiparty presidentialism is more likely to pro- presidential systems have no institutionalized duce immobilizing executive/legislative deadlock means of resolving such deadlocks (Linz 1994). than either parliamentary systems or two-party Because of the fixed electoral timetable, even if presidentialism, and presidential systems are less congress opposes a president’s programs, it has fitted to handle executive/legislative deadlock no way of dismissing the president except for than parliamentary systems. Because of the sep- impeachment. Impeachment, however, is gener- aration of powers, presidential systems lack ally reserved for criminal proceedings, and legis- means of ensuring that the president will enjoy lators may have no grounds for criminally trying the support of a majority in congress. Presidents a president. Consequently, the opposition may are elected independently of congress, and the believe that the only means of deposing an inef- winner need not come from a majority party, if fective president is supporting a coup. The par- one exists. In some presidential systems, candi- liamentary mechanism of a no-confidence vote is dates from small parties make successful runs for not available. . . . the presidency. . . . Two-party presidential systems also face insti- The tendency toward executive/legislative tutional rigidity when executive/legislative dead- deadlock and immobilism is particularly acute lock occurs but, as noted earlier, presidents are in multiparty presidential democracies, especially more likely to have stable support in congress. In with highly fragmented party systems. Under contrast to presidential systems, parliamentary these circumstances, the president is likely to Chapter 5 270

systems have an institutionalized mechanism for Presidentialism, Multipartism, and Party overcoming deadlocks when they arise. A vote of Coalitions no-confidence can topple the government, lead- ing to new elections that may change the balance . . . Now I look at why presidentialism makes it of power and help resolve the crisis. This provi- di‰cult for multipartism to function well, focus- sion allows for replacing, with less institutional ing on problems of coalition building in presi- strain, unpopular or inept executives. Frequent dential systems. In multiparty systems, interparty recourse to dismissing governments can breed coalition building is essential for attaining a leg- instability, but this problem can be mitigated by islative majority. While the need for such coali- measures such as the West German or Spanish tion building exists in both presidential and constructive vote of no-confidence. Conversely, parliamentary multiparty systems, three factors if a prime minister is frustrated because of the make building stable interparty legislative coali- di‰culty of e¤ecting policy in the face of oppo- tions more di‰cult in presidential democracies sition control of the legislature, in most parlia- than in parliamentary systems. mentary systems, he/she can call new elections First, party support for the government tends in an e¤ort to achieve a majority. In either case, to be more secure in parliamentary systems be- there are means of changing the government cause of the way executive power is formed and without threatening the regime. dissolved. In a coalition parliamentary govern- ment, the parties forming the government choose Presidentialism, Multipartism, and Ideological the cabinet and the prime minister. Executive Polarization power is formed through post-election agree- ments among parties and is divided among Two or two-and-one-half party systems are also several parties. The parties themselves are corre- more likely to be compatible with presidential sponsible for governing and are committed to democracy because ideological polarization is supporting government policy. . . . unlikely. Competition tends to be centripetal In presidential systems the president (not the because to win a majority, the parties must parties) has the responsibility of putting together win votes from the center of the political spec- a cabinet. The president may make prior deals trum (Downs, 1957). . . . In most two-party and with the parties that support him or her, but two-and-one-half party systems, parties with these deals are not as binding as they are in a a centrist, moderate orientation dominate the parliamentary system. Presidents are freer to electoral market. Such characteristics generally dismiss ministers and to rearrange the cabinet favor moderation and compromise, character- than prime ministers in a coalition government istics that in turn enhance the likelihood of stable are. . . . democracy. . . . Whereas in parliamentary systems, party co- Intense ideological divisions increase the alitions generally take place after the election stakes of the political game, serve as an incentive and are binding, in presidential systems, they to polarization and, consequently, are less fa- often take place before the election and are not vorable to stable democracy. Such ideological binding past election day. . . . divisions are unlikely in the context of a two- Second, in presidential systems, the com- party system. This is one of the reasons why mitment of individual legislators to support an two-party democracies have been less prone to agreement negotiated by the party leadership breakdown. is often less secure. The extension of a cabinet Presidentialism versus Parliamentarism 271

portfolio does not necessarily imply party sup- Valenzuela (Eds.), Presidential or parliamentary de- port for the president, as it does in a parliamen- mocracy: Does it make a di¤erence? Baltimore: Johns tary system. . . . In contrast, in parliamentary Hopkins University Press. systems, individual legislators are more or less Mainwaring, S., & Shugart, M. (1997). Juan Linz, bound to support the government unless their presidentialism, and democracy: A critical appraisal. In party decides to drop out of the governmental A. Valenzuela (Ed.), Politics, society, and democracy: alliance. MPs risk bringing down a government Latin America. New York: Praeger. and losing their seats in new elections if they fail Riggs, F. (1988). The survival of presidentialism in International to support the government (Epstein, 1964, 1967). America: Para-constitutional practices. Political Science Review, 9, 247–278. Finally, incentives for parties to break coali- tions are stronger in presidential systems than Santos, W. G. dos. (1986). Sessenta e quatro: Anatomia da crise. Sao Paulo: Vertice. in many parliamentary systems. In multiparty Parties and party systems: A frame- presidential systems, as new presidential elec- Sartori, G. (1976). work for analysis. New York: Cambridge University tions appear on the horizon, party leaders gen- Press. erally feel a need to distance themselves from the Shugart, M., & Carey, J. (1992). Presidents and assem- president in o‰ce. By remaining a silent partner blies: Constitutional design and electoral dynamics. New in a governing coalition, party leaders fear they York: Cambridge University Press. will lose their own identity, share the blame for Suarez, W. (1982). El poder ejecutivo en America government mistakes, and not reap the benefits Latina: Su capacidad operativa bajo regimenes presi- of its accomplishments. . . . dencialistas de gobierno. Revista de Estudios Politicos, 29, 109–144.

References

Blondel, J., & Suarez, W. (1981). Las limitaciones institucionales del sistema presidencialista. Criterio, No. 1853–1854, 57–70. Ceaser, J. C. (1986). In defense of separation of powers. In R. Goldwin & A. Kaufman (Eds.), Separa- tion of powers—Does it still work? (pp. 168–193). Washington, DC: American Enterprise Institute. Downs, A. (1957). An economic theory of democracy. New York: Harper. Epstein, L. (1964). A comparative study of Canadian parties. American Political Science Review, 58, 46–59. Epstein, L. (1967). Political parties in western democ- racies. New York: Praeger. Lijphart, A. (1984). Democracies. New Haven, CT: Yale University Press. Lijphart, A. (1994). Presidentialism and majoritarian democracy: Theoretical observations. In J. J. Linz & A. Valenzuela (Eds.), Presidential or parliamentary de- mocracy: Does it make a di¤erence? Baltimore: Johns Hopkins University Press. Linz, J. J. (1994). Democracy: Presidential or parlia- mentary. Does it make a di¤erence? In J. J. Linz & A. Presidents and Assemblies

Matthew Soberg Shugart and John Carey

of several aspects in which systems with elected Assessing the Powers of the Presidency presidencies vary. The first set of aspects entail legislative powers constitutionally granted to In this chapter we undertake a process of assess- the president. These aspects are the veto, the ing just how powerful a president is in constitu- partial veto, presidential authority to legislate by tional terms. We identify two basic dimensions decree, exclusive right to initiate certain legisla- of presidential power: one concerning power tive proposals, budgetary initiative, and power over legislation, the other encompassing non- to propose referenda. Aspects of presidential legislative powers, including authority over the power apart from the legislative domain include cabinet and calling of early elections for con- cabinet formation, cabinet dismissal, lack of gress. Additionally, because the latter powers are assembly censure, and dissolution of the assem- directly related to the question of separation of bly. The scores on each aspect of each dimension powers, we provide a comparison of presidential can then be summed to arrive at an overall indi- powers over the composition of cabinets to sep- cator of presidential powers on the respective aration of executive from assembly. There are dimension. . . . two main, related lessons we shall be able to draw from this exercise. First, systems that score Powers: Legislative versus Nonlegislative high on presidential powers, and in particular those that are extreme on presidential legislative Figure 5.1 graphs the strength of the presidents powers, are often those systems that have exhib- across all the cases in two dimensions. Thus the ited the greatest trouble with sustaining stable very strongest presidents in both dimensions democracy. Second, systems that give the presi- would be found in the upper right region, while dent considerable powers over the composition presidents with no power in either dimension of the cabinet but also are low on separation of would be at the origin (0; 0). Most of the sys- survival of assembly and executive powers like- tems commonly understood to be presidential wise tend to be among the ‘‘troubled’’ cases. are located on the vertical line running at 12 There are thus left two basic clusters that, we on the dimension of nonlegislative power. These argue, are ‘‘safer’’ for the success of democracy: systems are thus all identical in the extent of au- (1) those with high separation of survival of thority they give to the president over the gov- powers but low presidential legislative powers; ernment and the assembly: All have exclusive and (2) those with low separation of survival authority over the cabinet and none may dissolve but also low presidential authority over the the congress. These systems di¤er only on the cabinet. . . . dimension of presidential legislative powers, but there is a very wide range of variation on this Powers of the Presidency: Legislative Powers dimension. . . . We have divided the space of figure 5.1 into To assess presidential powers, it is possible to six regions, numbered counterclockwise from devise a simple interval scoring method on each the upper right. Region I consists of the very powerful presidents. Presidencies in Region I Excerpted from: Matthew Soberg Shugart and John have great powers in both dimensions. Region Carey, Presidents and Assemblies. Cambridge: Cam- II comprises presidents with great legislative bridge University Press, 1992. 6 Cambridge University powers, but whose powers outside the legislative Press, 1992. Reprinted with the permission of Cam- bridge University Press. process are somewhat weaker. Region III is Table 5.1 Powers of popularly elected presidents Legislative Powers Package Veto/Override Partial Veto/Override 4 Veto with no override 4 No override 3 Veto with override requiring majority greater than 2/3 3 Override by extraordinary majority (of quorum) 2 Override by absolute majority of whole 2 Veto with override requiring 2/3 membership 1 Veto with override requiring absolute majority of 1 Override by simple majority of quorum assembly or extraordinary majority less than 2/3 0 No partial veto 0 No veto; or veto requires only simple majority override Exclusive Introduction of Legislation (Reserved Decree Policy Areas) 4 Reserved powers, no rescission 4 No amendment by assembly 2 President has temporary decree authority with few 2 Restricted amendment by assembly restrictions 1 Unrestricted amendment by assembly 1 Authority to enact decrees limited 0 No exclusive powers 0 No decree powers; or only as delegated by assembly Proposal of Referenda Budgetary Powers 4 Unrestricted 4 President prepares budget; no amendment permitted 2 Restricted 3 Assembly may reduce but not increase amount of 0 No presidential authority to propose referenda budgetary items 2 President sets upper limit on total spending, within which assembly may amend 1 Assembly may increase expenditures only if it designates new revenues 0 Unrestricted authority of assembly to prepare or amend budget

Nonlegislative Powers Cabinet Formation Cabinet Dismissal 4 President names cabinet without need for confirmation 4 President dismisses cabinet ministers at will or investiture 2 Restricted powers of dismissal 3 President names cabinet ministers subject to 1 President may dismiss only upon acceptance by confirmation or investiture by assembly assembly of alternative minister or cabinet 1 President names premier, subject to investiture, who 0 Cabinet or ministers may be censured and then names other ministers removed by assembly 0 President cannot name ministers except upon Dissolution of Assembly recommendation of assembly 4 Unrestricted Censure 3 Restricted by frequency or point within term 4 Assembly may not censure and remove cabinet or 2 Requires new presidential election ministers 1 Restricted: only as response to censures 2 Assembly may censure, but president may respond by dissolving assembly 0 No provision 1 ‘‘Constructive’’ vote of no confidence (assembly majority must present alternative cabinet) 0 Unrestricted censure Chapter 5 274

Figure 5.1 Powers of popularly elected presidents (democratic regimes that have broken down indicated by circles). Presidentialism versus Parliamentarism 275

empty, reflecting the lack of any logical reason to tains the presidential systems with relatively give great legislative powers to a president whose weak presidential legislative powers. Of the nine power over the composition of governments cases, two (Argentina and Nigeria) have su¤ered is even weaker than those in Region II. Region breakdowns at some time. Cuba’s ambiguous IV, in the lower left of figure 5.1, contains our system . . . is also found here. We also observe weakest presidents in both dimensions. Almost that the longest-lived presidential systems—all all of the premier-presidential regimes are scoring 11 or 12 on the dimension of nonlegisla- located here. Region V also includes premier- tive power—may be found at the low end of the presidential systems, as well as other systems scale of presidential legislative powers. These with moderately powerful presidents. Finally, cases include: Region VI includes only presidential systems with relatively weak legislative powers but great Costa Rica United States powers over government formation. Dominican Republic Venezuela If we consider the performance of the regimes These are the four of the five longest-lived presi- in figure 5.1, we find reason to believe that the dential democracies in the world (the other is more powerful presidencies are also the more Colombia, where presidential powers recently problematic. . . . were reduced in both dimensions). If there really Although the sample is too small to make is a link, then there are reasons to be optimistic any claims of statistical significance, six of the about several fledgling presidential democracies ten breakdowns have occurred in the region we that rank low on presidential legislative powers. have suspected would be most problematic: very Regimes such as those of Argentina and El Sal- strong presidencies (Region I). Fully half of vador, for example, have weathered severe crises these cases have su¤ered breakdowns at some that have not been allowed to become clashes point. We thus have reason to be concerned between the two elected branches of government (absent constitutional revision) about the future over constitutional powers, in part because the viability of democracy in three countries. In the assembly is clearly the dominant branch. . . . 1980s, Brazil and the Philippines have adopted constitutions with powers at least as strong as Conclusions: Presidential Powers in the earlier, failed constitutions. Chile has adopted a new constitution that, while weaken- Our examination of the dimensions of presiden- ing legislative powers compared to the earlier tial power suggests the regimes with great presi- period, expands nonlegislative powers. dential legislative powers are problematic, as are Regions II and V of figure 5.1, which contain those in which authority over cabinets is shared the ‘‘confused’’ cases of shared presidential- between assembly and president. These issues parliamentary authority over cabinets, also in- need to be addressed in turn. On matters of leg- clude several cases of dubious democratic islation, we suggest that relatively strong assem- performance, although only one breakdown. . . . blies should be associated with more stable and We are left with two regions. One, Region IV e¤ective government relative to strong presi- contains three premier-presidential systems and dencies because assemblies serve as arenas for no breakdowns.2 The other, Region VI, con- the perpetual fine-tuning of conflicts. An assem- bly represents the diversity of a polity far better 2. This lack of breakdowns among the premier- than an executive dependent on the president’s presidential systems provides support for Lijphart whims is likely to do. Because of the diverse and Rogowski’s (1991) suggestion that such regimes may be especially well equipped to manage political forces represented in an assembly, such a body cleavages. Chapter 5 276

has the potential for encompassing divergent to the most majoritarian component (the presi- viewpoints and striking compromises on them. dency) of a regime meant to be consensual, or The dual democratic legitimacies decried by granting shared authority over the composition critics of presidentialism—the claim that no of the cabinet, is a potentially dangerous ar- democratic principle exists to resolve conflicts rangement. Finally, we saw in this chapter that over who better can claim to represent the ‘‘will’’ actual regimes, as well as a promising proposal of the electorate—are minimized to the extent for a directly elected ‘‘prime minister,’’ entail that an assembly is accorded a more powerful varying combinations on two dimensions—sep- role in legislation than is the president. Thus aration of survival of executive and assembly, presidentialism with a strong congress indeed and presidential power over cabinets. In the next does a¤ord a democratic principle for the regu- chapters we shall see how presidential powers lation of interbranch conflicts; that principle is interact with the means of electing the assembly that the assembly prevails, subject to a need for and president. compromise with the president. The relatively weaker presidents (those of Costa Rica and the United States, for example) cannot use decree legislative authority to break a ‘‘logjam’’ in con- gress, as many presidents can do with perfect legality. Thus, a fundamental conclusion is that the criticisms of presidential regimes should not be put forward as if all presidencies were created equal; rather, these criticisms apply with greatest force to strong presidents. On the matter of authority over cabinets, again the shared control that we said typifies the president-parliamentary type goes right to the heart of the concern of many with dual demo- cratic legitimacies. If there is no ‘‘democratic principle’’ that defines who fills cabinet posts, one of the most basic elements to any democ- racy, then conflicts of a very basic nature are likely. Are the ministers the president’s ministers, or are they the assembly’s? In some regimes the answer is both. In either a premier-presidential regime or a presidential regime, on the other hand, the primacy of one branch over the other is clear. Both types make for a cabinet subject (whether exclusively or primarily) to one branch or the other even when the branches are con- trolled by di¤erent political tendencies. This does not prevent conflict, but it is not as clearly guar- anteed to generate conflict as is the president- parliamentary type. Democratic institutions are supposed to be conflict regulators, not conflict generators. Either giving great legislative powers Minority Governments, Deadlock Situations, and the Survival of Presidential Democracies

Jose´ Antonio Cheibub

Between 1946 and 1996, there have been 133 to the wealth of countries in which they are transitions to and from democracy in the world. observed; to their economic performance; or to Fifty-nine of these, or 45%, took place in the 23 conditions under which they emerged, in partic- countries of Latin America, while the remaining ular the military legacy of the previous authori- 74 were spread among the other 166 countries tarian regime.3 located in other areas of the world.1 The instability of presidential democracies has This high level of political instability used to been commonly accounted for by the principle be explained in terms of structural variables— of separation between executive and legislative the degree of dependency, the level of inequality, authorities. A conventional wisdom has emerged poverty, and so on—that supposedly created that, first, sees the occurrence of minority gov- conditions that were adverse to the survival ernments, and the deadlock between executives of democratic regimes. More recent explana- and legislatures that it supposedly causes, as the tions have moved away from this focus on predominant condition of presidential regimes. economic and social conditions, concentrating Second, because these regimes lack a constitu- instead on institutional arrangements. Stimu- tional principle that can be invoked to resolve lated by the formulations first advanced by Linz conflicts between executives and legislatures, (1994),2 the breakdown of democratic regimes such as the vote of no confidence of parliamen- and the alleged ‘‘crisis of governability’’ of new tary regimes, minority presidents and deadlock democracies—and not only in Latin America— would provide incentives for actors to search for have been attributed to presidentialism, which, extraconstitutional means of resolving their dif- in combination with permissive electoral systems ferences, thus making presidential regimes prone and weakly institutionalized political parties, is to instability and eventual death. It is thus the supposed to produce presidents whose parties separation of executive and legislative powers do not control a majority of seats in congress, inherent to presidential regimes that is usually deadlocks, institutional paralysis, and ultimately invoked to account for the fact that they die the breakdown of democratic institutions. more frequently than parliamentary regimes.4 Indeed, existing evidence shows that parlia- mentary democracies tend to last longer than 3. See Alvarez (1997) and Przeworski et al. (2000) presidential democracies and that the di¤erence for a comprehensive comparison of performance, in survival rates of these two regimes is not due political and economic, under parliamentarism and presidentialism. Excerpted from: Jose´ Antonio Cheibub, ‘‘Minority 4. The original formulation of this view was, of course, Governments, Deadlock Situations, and the Survival Linz (1978), elaborated in Linz (1994, p. 7): of Presidential Democracies.’’ Comparative Political Since [the president and the congress] derive their Studies 35(3) (April 2002): 384–312. 6 2002 Sage power from the vote of the people in a free competition Publications. Reprinted by permission of Sage among well-defined alternatives, a conflict is always Publications. latent and sometimes likely to crupt dramatically; there 1. These numbers come from Przeworski, Alvarez, is no democratic principle to resolve it, and the mech- Cheibub, and Limongi (2000) and the author’s update. anisms that might exist in the constitution are generally complex, highly technical, legalistic, and, therefore, of 2. An early argument was o¤ered in Linz (1978, pp. 71–74). See also Linz (1990a, 1990b) for further devel- doubtful democratic legitimacy for the electorate. It is opments. therefore no accident that in some of those situations the military intervenes as ‘‘poder moderador.’’ Chapter 5 278

In this article, I examine the conditions that opposition. Legislation is passed by votes of at generate minority presidents, minority govern- least M members of congress and, in the case of ments, and deadlock conditions in presidential bicameral systems, bills have to be approved in regimes; and I evaluate their impact on the sur- both houses. Under these conditions, it is possi- vival of these regimes. . . . ble to distinguish the situation in which the gov- ernment controls a majority of seats in congress, and hence in which congress passes bills pre- Minority Governments and Deadlock Situations ferred by the president, from the situation in which the government does not control a ma- Minority governments are those in which the jority of seats in congress. When the latter is the governing coalition does not control a majority case, congress approves bills that are not the of seats in the legislature or, in a bicameral sys- ones preferred by the president. In these situa- tem, those in which it does not control a major- tions, if constitutionally allowed, the president ity of seats in at least one of the chambers. Here vetoes the bill. Presidential vetoes can be over- I am primarily interested in minority govern- ridden by at least V members of Congress, ments and not, as in much of the existing lit- V b M. Thus, 0 < M a V < 100 (see figure erature, in minority presidents. The latter are 5.2). frequent under presidential regimes, but they are This setup defines three possible situations in not what really matters for the operation of these terms of executive-legislative relations. One situ- regimes.7 In much the same way as prime min- ation is defined by P < 100 V and O b V.In isters in parliamentary systems, presidents who find themselves in a minority situation may enter 8. The probability that at any given point in time a into coalition to obtain the support of a majority minority president (i.e., a president whose party con- in congress. They do so by distributing cabinet trols less than 50% of the seats in at least one legislative positions to parties that pledge their support to house) will head a majority government is .24. How- the government in congress.8 Government, thus, ever, little is known about coalition formation in pres- is here defined by all the parties that hold cabinet idential regimes. Part of the reason has to do with the positions, and the government legislative support fact that the dominant view of presidentialism implies by the sum of seats held by all the parties that that coalition governments are unlikely in these are in the government. . . . regimes and, when they exist, that they are precarious if not absolutely meaningless. In my opinion (Cheibub Deadlock situations are more complex to & Limongi, 2000) this view is not correct. A few define and observe. Consider the following situ- analysts (e.g., Mainwaring & Shugart, 1997) have ation. P is the share of seats held by the govern- attempted to assess the partisan composition of presi- ment and O is the share of seats held by the dential governments by measuring the legislative seats held by the parties that participated in the president’s This view has become widespread and can be found electoral coalition. They, however, recognize the limi- in Ackerman (2000, p. 645), Gonza´lez and Gillespie tation of this measure to indicate the size of the coali- (1994, p. 172), Hartlyn (1994, p. 221), Huang (1997, tion of parties that support the president in congress, pp. 138–139), Jones (1995a, pp. 34, 38), Linz and Ste- ultimately concluding that the share of seats held by pan (1996, p. 181), Mainwaring and Scully (1995), the party of the president is a better measure of the Nin˜o (1996, pp. 168–169), Stepan and Skach (1993), president’s legislative support (Mainwaring & Shugart, and Valenzuela (1994, p. 136), among others. 1997, p. 403). To my knowledge, only very recently 7. See Cheibub (2002) for an analysis that looks spe- have some analysts focused their attention on govern- cifically at minority presidents and considers the im- ing coalitions in presidential regimes. See, for example, Dehesa (1997), Amorin Neto (1998), and Altman-Olin pact of deadlock on government accountability with respect to economic outcomes. (1999). Presidentialism versus Parliamentarism 279

Figure 5.2 Conditions for deadlock between the president and congress when presidents have veto power and a majority of votes is required for legislative override. Note: P ¼ share of seats held by the government coalition; M ¼ share of members of congress necessary to approve legislation; V ¼ share of members of congress necessary to override presidential veto. these cases, congress passes bills preferred by the sary to override the presidential veto, whether opposition and these bills are likely to become the system is unicameral or bicameral, and law: even if the president vetoes the bill, the op- whether in bicameral systems veto override is by position has the votes to override the presidential a vote in each chamber separately or in a joint veto. In these cases, we can say that the opposi- session of both chambers. . . . tion dominates. Another situation is defined by P > M, when congress passes bills preferred by the president, the president signs the bills, and Survival of Presidential Regimes they become law. In these cases, the president dominates. It is only when 100 V a P < M With the definitions of minority governments and M a O < V that deadlock can occur: in and deadlock situations in mind, it is now pos- these cases, congress passes bills preferred by the sible to investigate the conditions under which opposition, the president vetoes these bills, and these situations are likely to occur in presidential the opposition does not have enough votes to regimes, the way in which they relate to each override the presidential veto. There is a stale- other, and the impact they are likely to have on mate between congress and the president, to the survival of presidential regimes. There are which there is no automatic solution since exec- five main points to be noted. utive and legislative have independent basis The first point is that minority presidents are of authority. This is the situation that should indeed frequent in presidential regimes. . . . make presidential regimes the most vulnerable, . . . [O]verall, about 40% of the years of presi- because both the president and the opposition dentialism were experienced with minority gov- would have an incentive to seek extraconstitu- ernments, higher . . . in bicameral (42.54%) than tional solutions to the stalemate. in unicameral (36.46%) systems. These numbers Empirically, thus, deadlock situations depend are higher than what has been observed in (Eu- on the combination of institutional and political ropean) parliamentary systems, but not dramati- factors. On one hand, they depend on the distri- cally higher. As reported by Strom (1990, p. 8), bution of seats in congress or, more specifically, studies of parliamentary governments in Europe, on the share of seats held by the government. including his own, have found that the frequency On the other hand, they depend on institutional of minority governments ranges from 30% to provisions regarding the presidential veto. These 37%. provisions are whether the president has veto Second, the occurrence of minority presidents power, the type of congressional majority neces- is associated with the number of political parties, Chapter 5 280

with the type of electoral system, and with the governments will control a majority of seats in electoral cycle, as suggested by Mainwaring congress, it is not the case that they a¤ect the (1993), Jones (1995a), Shugart (1995), and chances of survival of presidential regimes. others. As the descriptive patterns in table 5.2 Table 5.3 presents the probabilities that presi- indicate, minority presidents are more frequent dential regimes will break down as a function of when congressional elections are held under electoral and partisan variables. It can be seen proportional representation systems, in multi- that neither the type of electoral system nor the party systems (although it does not increase relative timing of presidential and legislative monotonically as the e¤ective number of parties elections has any impact on the survival of pres- increases), and when presidential and legislative idential regimes. . . . elections do not coincide. The occurrence of mi- The story with the number of political parties nority governments is also associated with these is somewhat more complex. It is not, contrary factors, although some of the e¤ect is diluted by to Mainwaring (1993) and Jones (1995a), multi- the fact that minority presidents sometimes build partism per se that a¤ects the survival of pres- a majority through coalitions. . . . idential regimes. In presidential democracies, Third, deadlock situations are far from being higher risks are associated with situations of very the predominant condition of presidentialism. low pluralism, or situations conducive to mod- Overall, deadlock occurs in about one third of erate pluralism, which, as Sartori (1976) sug- the cases (33.52%), and it is only weakly related gested, are the ones in which there are between to the conditions that are considered to be at two and five relevant political parties. Presiden- the root of the instability of presidential regimes: tial democracies with an e¤ective number of the e¤ective number of parties, whether con- parties larger than five, the cases that tend to be gressional elections are proportional or not, or conducive to ‘‘polarized pluralism’’ in Sartori’s whether legislative and presidential elections are typology, have an expected life considerably concurrent. . . . higher than the presidential democracies in Fourth, we cannot infer anything about the which the e¤ective number of parties is fewer survival of presidential democracies from elec- than five: 91 years against 25. . . . toral and partisan variables. The evidence that Finally, but certainly not any less important, is sometimes (e.g., Mainwaring, 1993; Jones, contrary to all expectations, minority presidents, 1995a) o¤ered in support of the proposition that minority governments, and deadlocks have no minority presidents and deadlock situations are negative e¤ect on the survival of presidential detrimental to presidentialism is usually indirect: regimes. If arguments about the perils of presi- it is about the conditions that are more likely to dentialism are correct, presidential democracies produce a minority president, because minority should face higher risks of dying when the presi- presidents are assumed to produce deadlock and dency and the congress are controlled by di¤er- deadlock is assumed to have a negative e¤ect ent parties and when the conditions for deadlock on the survival of the regime. Thus, the type of between the president and the congress are pres- electoral system, the number of political parties, ent. Yet as the bottom rows in table 5.3 demon- and the electoral cycle are all found to influence strate this is not true. Presidential regimes are the likelihood that presidents will control legis- slightly more likely to die when presidential lative majorities. From that, it is then inferred parties do not hold a majority of seats in con- that these factors also a¤ect the survival of pres- gress. However, whatever di¤erence there is, it idential regimes. However, whereas it is indeed disappears entirely when we allow for the fact true, as has been seen, that these conditions that minority presidents sometimes form coali- a¤ect the likelihood that presidents and their tion governments and, hence, increase the share Presidentialism versus Parliamentarism 281

Table 5.2 Frequency of minority presidents, minority governments, and deadlock situations in presidential regimes by type of legislature, e¤ective number of political parties, electoral system, and timing of elections Minority Minority Deadlock presidents governments situations % n % n % n All 53.35 731 40.22 726 33.52 710 Type of legislature Unicameral 45.85 277 36.46 277 29.67 273 Bicameral 59.93 454 42.54 449 35.96 437 Electoral system Majority-plurality 43.84 146 39.04 146 36.99 146 Pure proportional 54.15 554 39.42 553 32.96 540 Pure proportional þ mixed 55.73 585 40.52 580 32.62 564 E¤ective number of parties (ENP) ENP a 2 38.67 150 35.33 150 27.33 150 2 < ENP a 3 38.08 281 33.45 281 31.49 280 3 < ENP a 4 88.46 130 59.69 129 49.22 128 4 < ENP a 5 63.38 71 28.17 71 28.17 71 ENP > 5 62.65 83 50.60 83 32.10 81 ENP excluding the United States and Switzerland ENP a 2 31.13 106 26.42 106 15.09 106 2 < ENP a 3 37.96 274 33.21 274 31.13 273 3 < ENP a 4 88.46 130 59.69 129 49.22 128 4 < ENP a 5 90.00 50 40.00 50 40.00 50 ENP > 5 98.11 53 79.24 53 50.98 51 Timing of legislative and presidential elections Nonconcurrent 59.68 124 45.16 124 40.32 124 Alternate 73.91 138 66.92 133 47.11 121 Nonconcurrent þ alternate 67.18 262 56.42 257 43.67 245 Concurrent 45.63 469 31.34 469 28.17 465 Note: Minority presidents are the cases in which the party of the president does not control more than 50% of the seats in the legislature in a unicameral system or in at least one of the chambers in a bicameral system. Minority governments are defined similarly for the party of the president plus the parties that hold cabinet positions. Chapter 5 282

Table 5.3 Breakdown probabilities of presidential regimes by partisan, electoral, and political conditions Number of Number of Breakdown transitions cases probability E¤ective number of parties (ENP) ENP a 2 7 153 .0458 2 < ENP a 3 6 287 .0209 3 < ENP a 4 10 140 .0714 4 < ENP a 5 3 72 .0417 ENP > 5 1 90 .0111 Electoral system Majority-plurality 8 166 .0482 Proportional 22 582 .0378 Proportional þ mixed 23 618 .0372 Timing of legislative and presidential elections Nonconcurrent 5 157 .0318 Alternate 8 146 .0548 Nonconcurrent þ alternate 13 303 .0429 Concurrent 18 481 .0374 Political conditions Minority presidents 18 390 .0462 Majority presidents 10 341 .0293 Minority governments 17 434 .0392 Majority governments 11 292 .0377 Deadlock situations 9 238 .0378 No deadlock situations 15 472 .0318

of seats they can count on to govern. The di¤er- number of parties do a¤ect, as expected, the leg- ence between deadlock and no-deadlock situa- islative strength of presidents and the likelihood tions, although in favor of the former, is rather of minority presidents. These cases are more small: Whereas 1 in every 31 presidential demo- frequent in proportional representation systems, cracies dies when there is no deadlock, 1 in every when presidential and legislative elections do 26 dies when there is deadlock. This di¤erence not coincide, and when the number of parties is does not seem to warrant the level of concern large. These factors also a¤ect the occurrence of with deadlock that is often expressed in the minority governments, although not as strongly. comparative literature on presidentialism. . . . This relationship, however, does not warrant any To summarize, some of the commonly postu- conclusion about the survival chances of presi- lated e¤ects of electoral and partisan factors on dential democracies; neither the type of electoral presidentialism can be observed empirically: the system nor the timing of presidential and legis- electoral system, the timing of elections, and the lative elections has any impact on the survival of Presidentialism versus Parliamentarism 283

presidential regimes. The number of parties, in Jones, Mark P. (1995a). Electoral laws and the survival turn, matters for the survival of presidentialism, of presidential democracies. Notre Dame, IN: Notre but not in the way and probably not for the rea- Dame University Press. sons commonly postulated. What matters is Mainwaring, Scott. (1993). Presidentialism, multi- not multipartism per se but whether pluralism is partism, and democracy: The di‰cult combination. moderate; moderate pluralism, in turn, a¤ects Comparative Political Studies, 26, 198–228. survival of presidentialism not because of its Mainwaring, Scott, & Shugart, Matthew Soberg. e¤ect on the president’s legislative support (1997). Conclusion: Presidentialism and the party sys- but most likely because of the distribution of tem. In Scott Mainwaring & Matthew Soberg Shugart (Eds.), Presidentialism and democracy in Latin America strength among the three largest parties. Most (pp. 394–439). Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University important, none of these factors a¤ect the likeli- Press. hood of deadlock, which does not have a nega- Sartori, Giovanni. (1976). Parties and party systems: tive e¤ect on the survival of presidential regimes. A framework for analysis. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge It seems, thus, that there must be other mecha- University Press. nisms operating in presidential regimes that Shugart, Matthew Soberg. (1995). The electoral allow them to survive under conditions that pre- cycle and institutional sources of divided presidential sumably would make them perish. . . . government. American Political Science Review, 89, 327–343. Strom, Kaare. (1990). Minority government and major- References ity rule. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press.

Altman-Olin, David. (1999). The politics of coalition formation and survival in multiparty presidential democracies: The case of Uruguay (1989–1999). Unpublished manuscript, Department of Government, University of Notre Dame, IN. Amorin Neto, Octavio. (1998). Of presidents, parties and ministers: Cabinet formation and legislative decision-making under separation of powers. Unpub- lished doctoral dissertation, Department of Political Science, University of California, San Diego. Cheibub, Jose´ Antonio. (2002). Presidentialism and democratic performance. In Andrew Reynolds (Ed.), Constitutional design: Institutional design, conflict man- agement, and democracy in the late twentieth century. Oxford, UK: Oxford University Press. Cheibub, Jose´ Antonio, & Limongi, Fernando. (2000, August). Where is the di¤erence? Parliamentary and presidential democracies reconsidered. Paper presented at the XVIIIth World Congress of Political Science, International Political Science Association, Que´bec City, Canada. Dehesa, Grace Ivana. (1997). Goviernos de coalicio´nen el sistema presidencial: Ame´rica del Sur [Coalition governments in presidential systems: South America]. Unpublished doctoral dissertation, European Univer- sity Institute, Florence, Italy. Minority Governments in Parliamentary Democracies: The Rationality of Nonwinning Cabinet Solutions

Kaare Strom

The objective of this study is to investigate the yet their total tenure of more than 125 cabinet formation of minority governments in parlia- years remains very substantial. The durability mentary democracies. Minority governments (or advantage of majority cabinets is largely cabinets) are governments formed by parties that accounted for by majority party governments. together control less than half of the seats in the In minority situations, minority governments national legislature or, operationally, the lower represent 37.7% of total tenure. Thus, minority house of bicameral legislatures. . . . governments constitute a substantial propor- tion of all governments in minority situations, whether this proportion is measured in terms The Incidence of Minority Governments of the number of governments formed or their share of time in o‰ce. . . . In order to subject minority governments to closer scrutiny, I have collected data on all recent governments in countries with a significant rec- Explaining Minority Governments ord of minority cabinets. . . . The overall frequency of minority govern- Although the literature on minority governments ments is 114 out of 323 governments during this is meager, it is possible to identify a conventional period, or 35.3%, which corresponds to close view of the conditions under which such govern- to eight minority cabinets per country, or more ments form. Minority cabinets, it is commonly than two per decade per country. This record can held, tend to form in unstable and conflictual only be described as very substantial, whether political systems, whose party systems are highly in absolute or relative terms. . . . Majority party fractionalized. These cabinets are suboptimal governments will almost invariably form when- solutions, which are only resorted to when all ever possible, that is, in any majority situation. else fails. Though causal relationships are rarely In minority situations, when no majority party specified, minority governments are commonly exists, majority coalitions and minority cabinets associated with social and political malaise. . . . are the natural options. In these situations, mi- nority solutions have been chosen 43.0% of the time. . . . Minority Governments and Instability The high number of minority governments could be a misleading indicator of their com- One of the propositions within the conventional monness, if these governments tended to be of explanation is that minority governments are very short duration. Measured in cabinet years, symptoms of political instability of crisis (Frie- minoritarian solutions account for a somewhat senhahn, 1971; von Beyme, 1970). According smaller proportion of all governments (29.1%), to this view, the less stable a political system is, the more common minority governments should Excerpted from: Kaare Strom, ‘‘Minority Govern- be. . . . The argument that minority governments ments in Parliamentary Democracies: The Rationality reflect severe systemic crises could hardly be of Nonwinning Cabinet Solutions.’’ Comparative Po- defended in view of the high incidence of such litical Studies 17(2) (July 1984): 199–227. 6 1984 Sage cabinets across a wide range of democracies. . . . Publications, Inc. Reprinted by permission of Sage Publications, Inc. Presidentialism versus Parliamentarism 285

Table 5.4 Distribution of cabinet types by country Non- Country Majority Minority partisan Total Pct Min Mean PB Belgium 25 4 0 29 14 62.0 Canada 7 8 0 15 53 53.1 Denmark 3 20 0 23 87 40.1 Finland 19 11 7 37 30 54.6 France 18 12 0 30 40 51.0 Iceland 13 4 0 17 24 51.5 Ireland 10 5 0 15 33 50.5 Israel 23 2 0 25 8 62.0 Italy 26 19 0 45 42 51.8 Netherlands 15 3 0 18 17 61.6 Norway 8 10 0 18 56 47.4 Portugal 7 1 4 12 8 64.5 Spain 1 3 0 4 75 50.0 Sweden 9 10 0 19 53 47.2 United Kingdom 14 2 0 16 13 52.7 Total 198 114 11 323 35.3 53.2

Sources: Mackie and Rose (1982), Keesing’s Contemporary Archives, Cook and Paxton (1975), Facts on File. Note: Pct Min ¼ Minority Governments as Percentage of all Governments; Mean PB ¼ Mean Parliamentary Basis.

Minority Governments and Fractionalization Minority Governments and Polarization

Conventionally, minority governments have also Political polarization may complement or com- been associated with high degrees of political pete with fractionalization as an explanation fragmentation and party system fractionalization of minority government formation. Legislatures (Budge and Herman, 1978). The more fraction- that are polarized should experience a high inci- alization the parliamentary party system, it is dence of minority governments, particularly un- argued, the more di‰cult the formation of a der conditions of fractionalization and instability winning coalition becomes, and the greater the (Dodd, 1976; Powell, 1982). . . . likelihood of an undersized solution. . . . Table Table 5.5 reveals that polarization is related to 5.5 demonstrates that the average fractionaliza- cabinet type in a pattern almost identical to that tion under which substantive minority govern- of fractionalization. Majority party governments ments form is lower than that of majority form in radically less polarized systems than coalitions. Although the di¤erence in fraction- any other cabinet type. Nonpartisan administra- alization scores is by no means dramatic, it is tions are found in the most polarized, as well as in the opposite direction of what has been the most fractionalized, systems. But there is hypothesized. . . . no tendency for minority governments to form Chapter 5 286

Table 5.5 Fractionalization and polarization by cabinet type (mean values) Fractionalization Cabinet type (Rae’s F) Polarization (N) Majority Party .575 .011 (42) Majority Coalition .755 .183 (156) Minority Formal .754 .205 (13) Minority Substantive .726 .145 (101) Non-Partisan .765 .213 (11) All Governments .723 .151 (323) Sources: Mackie and Rose (1982), Powell (1982), Keesing’s Archives. Note: Polarization ¼ Electoral support for extremist parties as proportion of parliamentary seats. in more polarized environments than majority their behavior must be understood in temporal coalitions. On the contrary, substantive minor- terms. . . . Thus, decisions about cabinet forma- ity governments are associated with markedly tion will often take the form of a trade-o¤ be- lower levels of polarization than majority co- tween power and electoral prospects. . . . alitions. . . . My fundamental assumption is that minority How do these considerations help us make governments can be understood as results of ra- sense out of minority governments? I assume tional choices made by political parties, or more that minority governments form when the bene- specifically, by the parliamentary leaders of these fits of being in o‰ce are outweighed by the costs organizations. . . . for a majority segment of the party system. I have further argued that a principal benefit of (1) Political parties are organizations that governing consists in the policy influence di¤er- contest political elections and seek governmental ential between government and opposition. The o‰ce (Sartori, 1976). . . . For analytical purposes, greater the opportunities for the parliamentary I also assume that o‰ce and electoral advantage opposition to influence legislative policymaking, in part are valued instrumentally, and that the the lower the benefits of governing. The costs of underlying motivation is to influence policy- governing refer to anticipated electoral losses. making in the national assembly. . . . Government incumbency tends to result in sub- sequent electoral losses, and coalition govern- (2) The crucial point is that if policy influence ments tend to lose more than others (Powell, is a principal objective of political parties, then 1981; Strom, 1983). Moreover, coalitions typi- government participation is not a necessary con- cally involve policy compromises as well as pro- dition for payo¤. . . . jected electoral misfortunes. With these costs in (3) The third modification of conventional mind, potential governmental parties may forego coalition theory consists in the recognition that the immediate gratification of holding o‰ce. majority status is not always the e¤ective deci- Broad coalitions should be eschewed in particu- sion point.... lar. Future o‰ce holding will figure prominently (4) Finally, political parties are not exclu- in party calculations of political prospects. A sively concerned with immediate objectives, but decision to remain in opposition temporarily implies no lack of interest in governing in the Presidentialism versus Parliamentarism 287

long run, but rather a willingness to wait for critical role of legislative committees, I have more favorable circumstances. Thus, considera- constructed an index of the potential for opposi- tions of electoral prospects will focus not only on tional influence on the basis of the following how competitive future elections are likely to be, dichotomized indicators: but also on their e¤ect on opportunities for sub- sequent government participation. In fact, the (1) The number of standing committees. Com- impact or decisiveness of elections for cabinet mittee specialization is a precondition for ef- formation will be a principal factor in party cal- fective decision making. And specialization is culations. . . . The more decisive elections are, the di‰cult to attain without di¤erentiation of the more likely they are to deter parties from gov- committee structure. In other words, a certain ernment participation. . . . minimum number of standing committees is In sum, the conditions most favorable for mi- necessary for deliberation to be e¤ective and the nority government formation are where policy opposition influential. I have considered more can be influenced even from opposition status than ten standing committees necessary for high (low benefits of governing), and where future oppositional influence. The next two indicators elections are likely to be competitive and decisive are also measures of specialization, and the ra- for government formation (high costs of govern- tionale behind them parallels the one above. ing). Thus, the explanatory variables are: (2) Whether the standing committees have fixed areas of specialization. (1) The potential influence of the parliamentary (3) Whether such areas of specialization corre- opposition, and spond to ministerial departments. (2) The decisiveness of the electoral site for gov- (4) Whether there are any restrictions on the ernment formation. number of committee assignments per legislator. With increases in electoral decisiveness and If such restrictions exist, the legislators are more oppositional influence, I predict that the parlia- likely to be specialists in the areas in which they mentary bases of governments will diminish, and serve. Moreover, restrictions make it more dif- minority governments should, under these cir- ficult for the governing parties to manipulate cumstances, be more common. . . . committee assignments to their advantage. Thus, restrictions on committee assignments should enhance oppositional influence. Oppositional Influence (5) Whether the committee chairs are propor- tionately distributed among the parties in the The benefits of governing depend on the oppor- legislature. The alternative is normally that the tunities for legislative influence open to opposi- government controls all chairs, which, of course, tion parties. These opportunities are in turn is less desirable from the point of view of the determined by internal parliamentary structure opposition. and procedures, as well as by the role of the legislature in the larger political system. A strong For the last four indicators a positive value is and decentralized committee structure o¤ers interpreted as a high score on the variable. The much better prospects for oppositional influence aggregate score for each country corresponds to than the more centralized and less deliberative the number of positive values; thus the range is mode of decision making traditionally found, from 0 to 5. It should be emphasized that we are such as in the British House of Commons (Lees concerned with structural constraints on opposi- and Shaw, 1979; Mezey, 1979). In view of the tional influence, and not with the actual power Chapter 5 288

Table 5.6 Influence of opposition by country No/Com Special Corresp Membshp Chair Aggregate Country (1) (2) (3) (4) (5) value

Belgium þþþþ4 Canada þþþ3 Denmark þþþ3 Finland þþþ3 France þþþþ4 Iceland þþþþ4 Ireland þ1 Israel þþ2 Italy þþþþ4 Netherlands þþ2 Norway þþþþþ5 Portugal þþþþ4 Spain þþþ3 Sweden þþþþ4 United Kingdom þ1 Sources: Herman (1976) and others; see Strom (1984: 123) for details. enjoyed by the parties out of o‰ce. This distinc- components. These components and their indi- tion is important for the direction of the causal cators are as follows: relationship. While influential oppositions may facilitate the formation of minority governments, (1) The identifiability of government options. it is also arguable that minority governments Unless the voters are presented with clear, pre- enhance the influence of the opposition. It is electoral governmental choices, there can hardly much less plausible that cabinet minoritarianism be decisive elections. For each decade, countries would alter the committee structure of the na- have been scored impressionistically as low (0), tional assembly, as measured here. Historically, medium (.5), or high (1) in preelectoral govern- there have been strong continuities in the char- ment identifiability. acteristics of the legislatures under investigation. (2) Electoral volatility. In order for elections to Table 5.6 presents the data on oppositional in- be decisive, there must be significant variation in fluence by country. the proportion of parliamentary seats captured by the various parties from election to election. As a measure of this type of competitiveness, The Decisiveness of Elections I have chosen electoral volatility (for seats) between successive elections (Pedersen, 1979). The second variable is the decisiveness of elec- Each government has been given the mean score tions for government formation, which has for the country and decade in which it was been designed to tap the costs of governing. This formed. variable consists of four theoretically derived Presidentialism versus Parliamentarism 289

Table 5.7 Electoral decisiveness by country (mean values) Country Identifiability Volatility Responsiveness Proximity Belgium .10 .09 .60 .45 Canada 1.00 .19 .73 .87 Denmark .76 .12 .64 .70 Finland .00 .08 .53 .34 France .00 .18 .47 .14 Iceland .59 .08 .52 .63 Ireland .87 .08 .85 .80 Israel .14 .13 .44 .40 Italy .12 .09 .48 .22 Netherlands .00 .08 .46 .67 Norway .83 .10 .70 .56 Portugal .50 .11 .46 .33 Spain .50 .29 1.00 .75 Sweden 1.00 .06 .52 .63 United Kingdom 1.00 .07 1.00 .72 All countries .39 .11 .58 .48

(3) Electoral responsiveness. A third require- following a general election, again measured on ment for electoral decisiveness is that govern- a decade-to-decade basis for each country. ments be formed by parties that have gained rather than lost seats at the latest election. I have Electoral decisiveness is a systemic rather than scored every government formation according to governmental property. Accordingly, our mea- the proportion of electoral gainers among its sures have been computed at the systemic level. constituent parties7. Electoral responsiveness has All four component variables are bounded by then been computed as the mean responsiveness the values 0 and 1. Each government has then score for a given country and decade. been assigned the appropriate score for its coun- try and decade of formation. Table 5.7 presents a (4) Proximity. Finally, electoral decisiveness summary of mean electoral decisiveness scores requires that governments be formed in close by country. proximity to general elections. Proximity scores simply correspond to the proportion of all gov- ernment formations taking place immediately Testing the Rationalist Explanation

7. Parties that exhibit no change in their proportion of The hypotheses predict that as electoral deci- seats in the most recent election have been excluded siveness and oppositional influence increase, the from the computations of electoral responsiveness, parliamentary basis of the governments formed except when they form single-party governments. Any should tend to diminish, and the likelihood of party gaining an absolute parliamentary majority has minority government formation increase. I have been counted as a winner. Chapter 5 290

Table 5.8 Parliamentary basis and numerical status by conditions of government formation Parliamentary basis Numerical status Regression Logit Correlation Variable Pearson’s R Coe¤ Std Err Beta Coe¤ Std Err

Influence of opposition .10 2.68** .93 .17 .39** .16 Electoral salience .30 5.28** 1.05 .30 .95** .18 Volatility .14 39.77** 14.16 .16 7.56** 2.46 Responsiveness .22 10.08** 4.30 .14 1.79** .71

Note: Adjusted R Square (Std Regression): .147; Correct Prediction Rate (Logit): 72.8%; N ¼ 265. **Significant at .01 level in one-tailed tests. tested these hypotheses by regressing the parlia- together with the measures of volatility, respon- mentary basis of each government (including siveness, and oppositional influence. The depen- external support) on the explanatory variables. dent variable (parliamentary basis) is a Only minority situations with partisan outcomes continuous one, with hypothetical bounds of 0 have been included, which is to say that majority and 100. However, the qualitative di¤erence be- party and nonpartisan governments have been tween 49% and 51% parliamentary support is excluded. These restrictions are essential, since it much more significant for an explanation of would be meaningless to attempt to predict mi- minority governments than the range from, for nority government formation in situations where example, 55% to 75%. Hence, I have also run a a majority party exists or where party politics logistic regression, where the governmental out- has been suspended. come (numerical status) is treated as a dichot- Factor analysis of the four indicators of elec- omy and scored 1 for majority coalitions and toral decisiveness reveals that governmental formal minority governments and 0 for substan- identifiability and electoral proximity load tive minority governments. Table 5.8 presents strongly on the same factor, whereas competi- the results for the equation with four indepen- tiveness and responsiveness do not. Evidently, dent variables. electoral decisiveness is a multidimensional phe- The dependent variables have been con- nomenon, but the identifiability and proximity structed in such a way that we should expect to measures seem to capture the same dimension. find consistently negative signs and significant The latter two indicators have therefore been relationships in table 5.8. And in fact the ex- combined into a single measure of electoral sa- planatory variables are related to minority gov- lience, since they both appear to tap the extent to ernment formation in the expected direction and which elections serve as focal events in the game at high levels of significance. There is also a high of government formation8. Electoral salience level of consistency between the standard regres- has then been entered in the regression equation sion and the logit analysis. The hypothesized relationships show up whether the governmental 8. The measure of electoral salience has been con- outcome is measured as a dichotomy (majority structed by standardizing the identifiability and prox- versus minority) or as a continuous measure imity measures, and then, for each government, adding of parliamentary support. And the order of sig- up the two standardized scores and dividing the sum by nificance of the various predictors is virtually two. Presidentialism versus Parliamentarism 291

unchanged. The predicted di¤erence in parlia- with the same two dependent variables (parlia- mentary basis between the highest and lowest mentary basis and numerical status) and a more observed values on the independent variables is extensive set of predictors, representing compet- 10.7% for oppositional influence, 16.4% for elec- ing explanations. Most of the additional vari- toral salience, 20.1% for volatility, and 10.1% for ables have already been discussed in the analysis responsiveness. Clearly, electoral decisiveness is of the conventional explanations. The indepen- by far a stronger predictor of minority govern- dent variables now include: electoral salience, ment formation than oppositional influence. volatility, responsiveness, oppositional influence, Among the three dimensions of electoral deci- fractionalization, polarization, crisis duration, siveness, volatility accounts for the greatest dif- the number of formation attempts, constitutional ferential impact between its extreme values. investiture requirements, and the concentration However, in the normal range of variation, elec- of the opposition. The latter variable is a mea- toral salience has a considerably larger e¤ect sure of the proportion of the total opposition on parliamentary basis. But even volatility and contained in the major oppositional bloc along a responsiveness are highly significant predictors left-right dimension (Dahl, 1966). Governments of minority government formation, each with faced with unilateral oppositions (as in two-party about as much explanatory power as opposi- systems) have an opposition concentration score tional influence. The relatively smaller impact of of 1. If, on the other hand, the opposition is oppositional influence is entirely to be expected evenly divided between right and left, the score for two reasons. Presumably the anticipation of is 0.5. This measure presupposes a meaningful upcoming elections may in itself be su‰cient to ordering of all relevant political parties on a left- induce parties to abstain from power, whereas a right dimension. In the actual rankings on which consideration of the opportunities for opposi- the variable has been constructed, every e¤ort tional influence in isolation would never produce has been made to maximize consistency with the same result. In other words, it is always bet- existing authoritative rankings. The theoretical ter to be in government than in opposition, if the interest in this measure stems from the concep- future is disregarded. Second, the explanatory tion of minority governments as governments power of the measure of oppositional influence of the political center, with bilateral opposi- may be a¤ected by the fact that it is a somewhat tions. From their strategic location, they could crude ordinal-level variable. arguably divide and rule the opposition on the The model with these four independent vari- extremes. ables provides a respectable measure of overall The models also include a dummy variable fit. The standard regression model explains indicating whether there exists a constitutional about 15% of the total variation in parliamen- provision for obligatory parliamentary investi- tary basis. With governmental outcome dicho- ture at the time of government formation. The tomized, the logit model is capable of correctly reasoning here is that minority government for- predicting 72.5% of the cases. This represents a mation is less likely if an incoming administra- reduction in error of approximately 18% over tion needs to secure a vote of confidence in its estimates based on the modal category. first encounter with the national assembly. Table 5.9 presents the models. The dependent variables are the same as Confronting the Competing Explanations previously. Simple correlation coe‰cients with the continuous measure of parliamentary basis As a final step in the analysis of minority gov- have been reported for illustration and in order ernment formation, I have estimated models to relate the findings to the previous bivariate Chapter 5 292

Table 5.9 Parliamentary basis and numerical status by conditions of government formation (expanded set) Parliamentary basis Numerical status Regression Logit Correlation Variable Pearson’s R Coe¤ Std Err Beta Coe¤ Std Err

Influence of opposition .09 1.70* .95 .11 .40* .19 Electoral salience .29 10.20** 1.43 .59 1.34** .24 Volatility .16 31.94* 13.92 .13 8.01** 2.79 Responsiveness .22 11.22** 4.19 .16 2.15** .80 Polarization .01 .42** .11 .33 NS Fractionalization .09 NS NS NS NS Crisis duration .16 NS NS NS .02** .01 Formation attempts .02 .99* .57 .10 .31** .12 Opposition concentration .01 12.24* 6.69 .12 2.88* 1.34 Investiture .09 NS NS NS NS Note: Reported coe‰cients are those from the reestimated equations excluding variables not significant at the .05 level. Significance levels reported for one-tailed tests. Adjusted R Square (Std Regression): .216; Correct Prediction Rate (Logit): 82.6%. *Significant at .05 level. **Significant at .01 level. NS ¼ Not significant at .05 level. analysis of these relationships. Since many of the volatility and oppositional influence diminish relationships in the model are clearly insignifi- somewhat when control variables are intro- cant, a backward elimination procedure has been duced. However, both relationships retain their employed. Only predictors with a significant im- significance, though oppositional influence only pact at the .05 level have been included in the barely so, in the standard regression. final equations. Polarization turns out to be the second The introduction of these various control vari- strongest predictor in the standard regression, ables does not detract from the explanatory but falls to insignificance in the logit analysis. power of my rational choice explanation. In fact, This is an interesting finding and one of the few the beta weights of both electoral salience and cases of radically di¤erent results between the responsiveness have increased from the previous standard and logistic regressions. We may recall analysis, and all hypothesized relationships re- that the bivariate relationship between polariza- main significant. Electoral salience is far and tion and parliamentary basis is positive (though away the most powerful predictor of minority hardly significant) and thus contrary to conven- government formation in the logistic as well as tional expectations. In the regression model high the standard regression. Its observed range is levels of polarization are in fact related to nar- approximately 3.1, which corresponds to a pre- row parliamentary support when control vari- dicted di¤erence of well over 30 percentage ables are introduced. The conventional view is points in parliamentary basis. The impacts of thus supported, but the results also dovetail Presidentialism versus Parliamentarism 293

nicely with other theoretical interpretations. pendent variables. The logit model shows the High levels of polarization imply that there are more significant improvement, as the reduction large segments of the party system for which in error climbs to 34%. Residual analysis reveals government participation is always unattractive that the models yield the most accurate results in the short term. Polarization also means that for the Anglo-American democracies (Great the policy distance between parties is high and Britain, Ireland, and Canada) and the Scandi- compromises accordingly costly. But the logit navian nations, whereas Portugal and Iceland analysis indicates that these constraints do not exhibit the worst fit. It is perfectly reasonable produce minority governments. One interpreta- that Portuguese governments are much less likely tion of this puzzle is that polarization reduces to be minoritarian than the models would pre- the likelihood of oversized coalitions, but that it dict. Postrevolutionary Portugal probably fits my simultaneously induces the relevant parties to theoretical assumptions least well of all 15 polit- seek solutions that do not fall below the majority ies. The regime has been too unstable for party threshold. The size principle, then, may be par- leaders to forego voluntarily the benefits and ticularly applicable under conditions of high security of holding o‰ce. Also, in a nascent de- polarization. Perhaps minority governments are mocracy, risk-averse inclinations may lead poli- perceived to be especially ine¤ective or asso- ticians to eschew government solutions perceived ciated with serious systemic risks under such cir- as potentially destabilizing. On the other hand, cumstances. Such perceptions probably do exist, the countries that exhibit the best fit seem to and they could well give responsible parliamen- meet the theoretical assumptions of stability and tary leaders added incentives to seek stable and oppositional security particularly well. In other ‘‘winning’’ solutions. Whether minority govern- words, the rationalist explanation fits best where ments are in fact less stable or e¤ective than its assumptions are most plausible. majority coalitions under these and other cir- In sum, this multivariate analysis o¤ers cumstances is a di¤erent question (Strom, 1983). substantial support for the rational choice ex- It is also plausible that high polarization in- planation of minority government formation. creases the value of being in o‰ce and the risks However, it indicates that electoral decisiveness and disadvantages of opposition status. is more important than oppositional influence as Note that the number of formation attempts an explanatory factor. Hence, future electoral and the concentration of the opposition turn out success may be a more important consideration to be significantly related in the expected direc- than immediate access to policy making when tions in the multivariate analysis, despite the fact governments are formed in multiparty systems. that their zero-order correlations are virtually If this is correct, then it would have profound nil. On the other hand, investiture requirements implications for coalition theory, which has and party system fractionalization show no sig- tended to ignore future electoral considerations. nificant relationship to the incidence of minority governments. The unexpected tendency for mi- nority governments to emerge from particularly Conclusions short cabinet crises is confirmed, but only in the logit analysis. In other words, minority gov- In this analysis, I have surveyed the universe ernments follow short crises, but radically un- of minority governments and investigated the dersized cabinets probably do not result from conditions under which they form. The analysis exceptionally brief negotiation processes. of minority government formation has examined The overall fit of the models is moderately macro-structural characteristics of political sys- improved with the more extensive set of inde- tems as well as the immediate processes that Chapter 5 294

precede the formation of parliamentary govern- the recent evolution toward lessened centraliza- ments. Throughout this analysis, I have sought tion of government control in the House of to test two competing explanations of minor- Commons could be a critical facilitating factor ity government formation. The conventional (Schwarz, 1980). theory views minority cabinets as options of last Beyond factual clarification, my results should resort under conditions of severe political stress. have interesting implications for our under- Accordingly, minority government formation standing of the logic of government formation in should be associated with political instability, di¤erent types of party systems. Traditionally, fractionalization, and long and di‰cult forma- minority governments have been portrayed as tion processes. My results o¤er little support defective coalition governments. The present for these propositions. In fact, in some cases analysis suggests that at least substantive minor- the exact opposite appears to be the case. As ity governments may share more characteristics an alternative to this conventional view, I have with majority party governments than with ma- o¤ered a theory that explains minority govern- jority coalitions. It may not be unreasonable to ments as rational cabinet solutions under con- see the typical substantive minority government ditions of competition rather than conflict. The as an imperfect majority party government. These data have given considerable support to this governments form as alternatives to majority explanation. coalitions in minority situations, but their The conventional view may not be unreason- mode of formation resembles that of alternative- able as a historically bounded proposition. It is majority two-party systems. Canada may be the not di‰cult to see how critical events in major country that best illustrates this practice. Formal countries between the world wars could give minority governments, though few in number, rise to negative perceptions of minority govern- appear much more akin to the conventional im- ments. Unquestionably, the fear and loathing age of minority governments. of minority governments are results of the I also hope that this study will contribute historical lessons of the interwar period and par- toward an enrichment of the literature on gov- ticularly of the experiences of the Weimar Re- ernment coalitions. Coalition theories have tra- public. These lessons were reinforced by the fate ditionally fared rather poorly as explanations of the Third and, subsequently, the Fourth Re- of minority government formation. This analysis public in France. However, these images do not suggests the possibility of incorporating minor- conform to the realities of contemporary minor- itarian solutions as something more than aber- ity government formation. rations within a rational choice paradigm. I Minority governments are still frequently as- have focused on three modifications that could sociated with the turbulence of Southern Euro- help coalition theory make better sense of the pean politics. This analysis has found them to high frequency of undersized cabinets. The first be more common in the very di¤erent context point is that majority status need not be the ef- of the Scandinavian countries. It may be just as fective decision point in government formation; interesting to note that the countries most influ- a ‘‘winning’’ coalition may be neither a func- enced by the Westminster model of democracy tional requirement nor a fundamental objective seem to turn to minority governments rather of the actors in that game. Second, even opposi- than majority coalitions when their two-party tion status may hold certain benefits for parties systems fragment. My theory would predict a interested in policy influence. And finally, coali- high likelihood of minority governments in tion theories must take into account the time Great Britain if the current trend toward party perspectives of the actors and the role of pro- system fragmentation continues. In that case, spective elections as democratic constraints on Presidentialism versus Parliamentarism 295

political parties. It is this responsiveness to the anticipated reactions of the electorate that makes democracy special.

References

Budge, I. and V. Herman (1978) ‘‘Coalitions and gov- ernment formation: an empirically relevant theory.’’ British J. of Pol. Sci. 8: 459–477. Dahl, R. A. [ed.] (1966) Political Oppositions in West- ern Democracies. New Haven: Yale University Press. Dodd, L. C. (1976) Coalitions in Parliamentary Gov- ernment. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press. Friesenhahn, E. (1971) ‘‘Parlament and Regierung in modernen Staat,’’ pp. 307–319 in K. Kluxen (ed.) Parlamentarismus. Cologne: Kiepenheuer & Witsch. Lees, J. D. and M. Shaw [eds.] (1979) Committees in Legislatures: A Comparative Analysis. Durham, NC: Duke University Press. Mezey, M. L. (1979) Comparative Legislatures. Dur- ham, NC: Duke University Press. Pedersen, M. N. (1979) ‘‘The dynamics of European party systems: changing patterns of electoral volatil- ity.’’ European J. of Pol. Research 7: 1–26. Powell, G. B., Jr. (1982) Contemporary Democracies. Cambridge: Harvard University Press. ——— (1981) ‘‘Party systems as systems of represen- tation and accountability.’’ Presented at the annual meeting of the American Political Science Association, New York. Schwarz, J. E. (1980) ‘‘Exploring a new role in policy making: the British House of Commons in the 1970s.’’ Amer. Pol. Sci. Rev. 74: 23–37. Strom, K. (1983) ‘‘Party goals and government perfor- mance in parliamentary democracies.’’ Presented at the annual meeting of the American Political Science Association, Chicago. Von Beyme, K. (1970) Die Parlamentarischen Regier- ungssysteme in Europa. Munich: R. Piper. Institutional Design, Party Systems, and Governability: Di¤erentiating the Presidential Regimes of Latin America

Joe Foweraker

Commonalities in Latin American Political 13. Shugart and Carey allege that ‘‘where the selection Systems of the executive involves the formation of coalitions among parties within the assembly, we cannot call the In the broad compass of democratic political regime presidential, even if there is an initial round of systems, the countries of Latin America com- voting for the executive’’ (Shugart and Carey, Presi- prise a distinctive sub-set, defined by a combina- dents and Assemblies, p. 77). In the Bolivian case, since the president is selected by assembly bargaining, and tion of presidentialism and assemblies elected on 11 since popular plurality winners tend to fare poorly in the basis of proportional representation (PR). the process, Shugart and Carey see the system as a Moreover, the sub-set mainly conforms to a hybrid they call ‘‘assembly-independent.’’ Although the model of pure presidentialism, with popularly Chilean system from 1925 to 1973 followed the same elected chief executives, the terms of both execu- formal rules, in practice the assembly vote simply rati- tive and assembly fixed and not contingent on fied the popular choice, and so the system remained mutual confidence, the government named and presidential (and elections for the executive and the directed by the executive, and with at least some assembly were separated by both date and ballot constitutionally granted law-making authority structure in Chile, in ways they are not contemporarily vested in the president.12 But, as with most cat- in Bolivia). But Shugart and Carey’s main doubt about the present Chilean system is the alleged power of the egorizations of political systems, there are pos- president to dissolve the Chamber of Deputies once in sible exceptions, including Bolivia, Peru and any one term (although not in the last year of the 13 Chile, and even Ecuador, Uruguay and Gua- term), with no negative consequences for the executive. temala.14 But this makes no di¤erence to the If this was correct, it would represent a big shift in power towards a ‘‘super-presidential’’ system. In fact, Excerpted from: Joe Foweraker, ‘‘Institutional Design, this provision of the 1980 Constitution was abolished Party Systems, and Governability: Di¤erentiating the under the 1989 Constitution. Although several consti- Presidential Regimes of Latin America.’’ British Jour- tutions of the sub-set allow legislative censure of min- nal of Political Science 28(4) (Oct. 1998): 651–676. isters, doubts about Peru’s categorization stem from its 6 1998 Cambridge University Press. Reprinted with peculiarly potent form of censure, which makes minis- the permission of Cambridge University Press. ters directly dependent on congress for their survival. The first Belaunde Terry administration (1963–68) was 11. Arend Lijphart, ‘‘Constitutional Choices for New obliged to employ 178 ministers in just five years. But Democracies’’ in Larry Diamond and M. F. Plattner, Linz argues that the system remains presidential, since eds, The Global Resurgence of Democracy (Balti- the president remains in o‰ce for the fixed term, and more and London: Johns Hopkins University Press, can continue to appoint ministers, but cannot threaten 1993), pp. 146–58, at p. 150; and Arend Lijphart, the assembly with dissolution. See Linz, ‘‘Presidential Electoral Systems and Party and Party Systems: or Parliamentary Democracy,’’ p. 61. A Study of Twenty-Seven Democracies, 1945–1990 (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1994). Lijphart 14. Under the 1978 Constitution in Ecuador, ministers divides this compass into four main categories, can be censured ‘‘for infractions committed in the exe- which are presidential-plurality (United States, Philip- cution of their o‰cial functions,’’ which appears to pines), parliamentary-plurality (the United Kingdom, imply the possibility of legal proceedings. In Uruguay, the old Commonwealth, India and Malaysia), PR- although the Constitution permits the assembly to parliamentary (Western Europe), and PR-presidential censure and remove ministers, this can lead to its own (Latin America). dissolution, unless the censure motion is won by two- thirds of the vote. The assembly’s power in this respect 12. Shugart and Carey, Presidents and Assemblies, tends therefore to be one of principle not practice. p. 19. Presidentialism versus Parliamentarism 297

critics of PR-presidentialism, who see all these nant and assemblies as weak and subservient, countries as beset by the same fundamental with the oft-cited exceptions of Chile, Costa problems, leading to political instability and Rica and Uruguay.21 The danger to the present poor economic performance. Consequently, ‘‘the democracies in the continent is seen either in the Latin American model remains a particularly authoritarian residues which give extensive leg- unattractive option.’’ . . . islative and emergency powers to the president,22 In some degree these problems are endemic or in the tendency for weak parties in the as- to all presidential systems, since these systems sembly to delegate powers to the presidency in embody two separate agents of the electorate, order to overcome stalemate and immobilism.23 and lack of policy agreement between executive In fact, most legislation in most Latin American and assembly can always ‘‘cause stress in the countries is initiated by the executive, which also regime.’’16 Such stress tends towards gridlock (to tends to have both total and line-item vetoes; use the language of the United States), or the and presidents tend to have both decree and kind of stalemate that subverts the legislative extensive emergency powers, including that of process.17 Hence, these systems are not really the state-of-siege.24 But this need not imply that ‘‘majoritarian,’’ as suggested by Linz and Lij- assemblies are weak in consequence, or ‘‘emas- phart,18 but, much to the contrary, often su¤er culated,’’ still less that they willingly delegate the ‘‘double minority’’19 of a president elected by their power to the executive.25 On the contrary, a plurality without majority support in the as- the available evidence suggests that assemblies sembly. In these circumstances the assembly can are powerful agents, which retain a strong ability always block executive initiatives, even if it to check the executive (in countries as di¤erent cannot directly control the president, while the president remains incapable of forcing a majority 21. Scott Mainwaring, ‘‘Presidentialism in Latin in the assembly through threat of dissolution.20 America,’’ Latin American Research Review, 25 (1990), The received wisdom on Latin American po- 157–179. litical systems tends to see presidents as domi- 22. Shugart and Carey, Presidents and Assemblies, pp. 36–38. In Guatemala the assembly has the power to dismiss 23. Geddes, ‘‘Initiation of New Democratic Institu- ministers against the will of the president, if it can tions in Eastern Europe and Latin America.’’ muster a two-thirds majority. 24. Mainwaring, ‘‘Presidentialism, Multipartism, and 16. Shugart and Carey, Presidents and Assemblies,p.2. Democracy.’’ 17. Stalemate was such in Brazil from 1961 to 1964, 25. According to Geddes, the new legislatures of East- and in Chile from 1970 to 1973, that ‘‘not a single piece ern Europe are equally jealous of their powers, and of ordinary legislation is passed.’’ See Przeworski, Sus- despite the presence of strong presidencies which were tainable Democracy, p. 46. established prior to or concurrently with the legislature, 18. See Linz, ‘‘Presidential or Parliamentary Democ- in all cases the legislators have tried to curtail the racy,’’ and Arend Lijphart, ‘‘Democracies: Forms, powers of the presidency (Geddes, ‘‘Initiation of New Performance, and Constitutional Engineering,’’ Euro- Democratic Institutions in Eastern Europe and Latin pean Journal of Political Research, 25 (1994), 1–17. America,’’ p. 29). Such observations are relevant to the notorious reluctance of recent democracies to 19. Valenzuela, ‘‘Latin America: Presidentialism in adopt parliamentary forms, since presidentialism better Crisis,’’ p. 7. answers the ‘‘legislators’ desire to remain free of the 20. See Scott Mainwaring, ‘‘Presidentialism, Multi- party shackles that parliamentarianism would bring partism, and Democracy: The Di‰cult Combination,’’ down on them’’ (Shugart, ‘‘The Inverse Relationship Comparative Political Studies, 26 (1993), 198–228, between Party Strength and Executive Strength’’). and Valenzuela, ‘‘Latin America: Presidentialism in Crisis.’’ Chapter 5 298

as Brazil, Ecuador, Uruguay and Venezuela).26 Variations in Latin American Political Systems Thus, the executive often has immense di‰- culty in putting through an agenda, and often But it is argued that it is not presidentialism per lacks e¤ective means for levering a recalcitrant se but ‘‘the combination of presidentialism and a assembly. fractionalized multiparty system’’ which is ‘‘es- It is plausible that it is this executive inca- pecially inimical to stable democracy.’’30 ... pacity which tempts presidents either to seek new Evidently, just as presidentialism is not a ho- powers through constitutional reforms or to rule mogeneous regime type,40 so PR-presidentialism largely by decree. In this way executive-assembly is not a homogeneous category. There is consid- stalemate can lead to decretismo, and, by exten- erable variation in the degrees of multipartism, sion, to the phenomenon of ‘‘delegative democ- party discipline, and the stability of party sys- racy.’’27 Decretismo was typical of Colombia tems and government coalitions. At the same during the National Front years and later, with time, these variables will strongly a¤ect gov- the country being under state-of-siege for 75 ernability by their direct and often conjoint in- per cent of the time from 1958 to 1989. ‘‘Dele- fluence on the key variable of the degree of gative democracy’’ has been used to characterize presidential support in the assembly.41 Most regimes as di¤erent as that of Menem in Argen- observers agree that for a PR-presidential system tina and (early) Fujimori in Peru. Alternatively, to govern e¤ectively ‘‘what is really needed is a executive legislative deadlock can lead to mili- working majority’’ in the assembly,42 or, at the tary coups (Brazil 1964, Peru 1968, Chile 1973) very least, ‘‘a reasonably large congressional or autogolpes28 (Uruguay 1973, Peru 1992, and delegation from the president’s party.’’43 With- an attempted autogolpe in Guatemala 1993), out a straight majority or near majority, the and the breakdown of democracy.29 president needs to build either a stable coalition majority, or shifting coalition majorities on sin- 26. Mark P. Jones, Electoral Laws and the Survival of gle issues and initiatives; and a near majority Presidential Democracies (Notre Dame, Ind.: Univer- will certainly facilitate such coalition formation. sity of Notre Dame Press, 1995). In this view, if PR-presidential systems break 27. Guillermo O’Donnell, ‘‘Delegative Democracy?’’ down it is not because of political polarization or Working Paper 172, Helen Kellogg Institute, Univer- ‘‘polarized pluralism,’’44 but because of the lack sity of Notre Dame, South Bend, Ind. (1992). of a working majority. Indeed, Chile is the only 28. Autogolpe refers to action by an elected president to curtail or dismantle democratic government, usually with the open collaboration or covert collusion of the 30. Mainwaring, ‘‘Presidentialism in Latin America,’’ military. p. 168. 29. Yet this cannot be interpreted to mean that presi- 40. Shugart and Carey, Presidents and Assemblies. dential regimes are necessarily more prone to break- 41. Jones, Electoral Laws and the Survival of Presi- down than parliamentary ones. Whether it is concluded dential Democracies, chap. 1. that they are so or not tends to depend on the time- 42. Mainwaring, ‘‘Presidentialism, Multipartism, and frame and geographical scope of the inquiry. By fo- Democracy,’’ p. 224, f. 18. cusing uniquely on ‘‘Third World’’ cases, Shugart and 43. Scott Mainwaring and Timothy R. Scully, eds., Carey are able to conclude that ‘‘just over half (52.2 Building Democratic Institutions: Party Systems in percent) of the presidential regimes . . . have broken Latin America (Stanford, Calif.: Stanford University down, while a higher percentage (59.1) of the parlia- Press, 1995), p. 33. mentary regimes have.’’ Presidentialism is over- whelmingly a Third World phenomenon, and in this 44. Giovanni Sartori, Parties and Party Systems: A context it has fared at least as well and arguably better Framework for Analysis (Cambridge: Cambridge Uni- than parliamentarianism. versity Press, 1976). Presidentialism versus Parliamentarism 299

case of a presidential democracy surviving for tary tends to refer to coalition formation as ex- over a generation without such a majority. . . . ceptional and confined to cases of extreme party . . . [I]t is safe to conclude that the democratic fractionalization, or di‰cult and beset by party systems of Latin America can be divided be- indiscipline and factionalism. tween those which run plurality-concurrent ex- A recent study distinguishes 123 separate ecutive elections, have low levels of multipartism administrations in nine countries over thirty- and habitually generate presidential majorities or six years, and finds sixty-nine cases of coalition near-majorities in their assemblies, and those government.69 Of the sixty-six majority govern- which do not. ments in the sample, forty-four secured their majority through coalition formation.70 Yet the major comparative study of presidential govern- Coalition Formation and Presidential Majorities ment in Latin America, which is equally recent, in no way reflects this prevalence when address- In large degree this conclusion does encompass ing the question of governability.71 On the one the present state of our knowledge regarding hand, the authors seem simply to miss this prev- institutional design and governability in the Lat- alence by focusing exclusively on pre-electoral in American democracies. But it is only ‘‘safe’’ coalitions (of which they find strangely few), so long as the prevalence of coalition formation and coalition government is ignored, as it tends 69. Grace Ivana Dehesa, ‘‘Gobiernos de Coalicion to be in the literature. In fact, even on a restric- en el Sistema Presidencial: America del Sur’’ (doctoral tive definition,65 coalition governments have re- dissertation, European University Institute, Florence, curred in Bolivia, Brazil, Chile, Ecuador and 1997). Peru, and even in the mainly two-party systems 70. The cases are Argentina, Brazil, Bolivia, Chile, of Colombia and Uruguay, while the only Colombia, Ecuador, Peru, Uruguay and Venezuela cases of uniformly single-party government have over the years 1958–94. Since Dehesa’s analytical cri- been Argentina, Costa Rica and Venezuela (after teria for distinguishing separate administrations and 1968). But, despite a number of good case for characterizing the coalition governments cannot studies of the process of coalition formation in be closely scrutinized here, these proportions should be Colombia,66 Brazil67 and Chile,68 no systematic taken as rough measures of tendency, nothing more. Argentina never has coalition government; Brazil al- and comparative study of the phenomenon has ways has coalition government; Chile and Ecuador yet been published. Most more casual commen- mainly have coalition government; while Bolivia, Peru, Uruguay and Venezuela have roughly the same num- 65. On this definition, government coalitions require ber of single-party and coalition governments. both party participation in the presidential cabinet and 71. See Mainwaring and Shugart, Presidentialism and party co-operation in the assembly. Democracy in Latin America. They construct a table 66. Johnathon Hartlyn, The Politics of Coalition Rule from twenty-two Latin American ‘‘cases’’ (a case com- in Colombia (New York: Cambridge University Press, prising a country and a period, with some countries 1988). including more than one period, and with the overall 67. Lucia Hippolito, PSD: De Raposas a Reformistas: period di¤ering from country to country), which shows o PSD e a Experiencia Democratica Brasileira (Rio the mean share of assembly seats for both the presi- de Janeiro: Paz e Terra, 1985) and Sergio Henrique dent’s party and the president’s coalition (Table 11.1, Abranches, ‘‘Presidencialismo de Coalizao: o Dilema p. 400). They included the cases of the ‘‘country’’ chap- Institucional Brasileiro,’’ Dados, 31 (1988), 5–34. ters in their book (Argentina, Brazil, Bolivia, Chile, Colombia, Costa Rica, Mexico, Venezuela), ‘‘plus 68. Arturo Valenzuela, The Breakdown of Democratic Regimes: Chile (Baltimore, Md.: Johns Hopkins Uni- most other Latin America cases with some recent ex- versity Press, 1978). perience of democratic elections’’ (p. 402). Chapter 5 300

rather than on all governing coalitions. On the Secondly, they argue that coalitions anyway do other, they purport to find analytical grounds not work because parties are so indisciplined for refusing to take coalitions of any kind into that the support of individual deputies can account.72 But Dehesa’s data suggest that such never be secure. The latter stricture applies a a restrictive approach will fail to capture the fortiori to open-list PR systems like that of Bra- real conditions of governability. Of the fifty-nine zil, where electoral success depends on the indi- elected presidents in her sample, eighteen were vidual candidate’s ability to attract votes, so elected by coalition, while seventeen went on to encouraging personalism and pork-barrel poli- form post-electoral coalitions;73 and of the thirty tics, and a consequent lack of party loyalty. presidents who were initially minority presidents Since, in this view, coalitions are ine¤ective, the in the assembly, ten formed post-electoral coali- familiar argument about the imperfections of tions to overcome their minority status. Interest- multiparty presidentialism still apply. Frag- ingly . . . it is . . . the 45 per cent threshold of mented party systems tend to minimize the as- presidential representation in the assembly that sembly representation of the presidential party, appears to provide the incentive for coalition so impairing governability. formation. Nine of the ten presidents forming But party discipline may be a¤ected not only post-electoral coalitions to overcome their mi- by control of candidate selection and the list nority status initially enjoyed less than 45 per- system, but by assembly rules and procedures,77 cent support in the assembly, which appears to and, in particular, by party leaders’ control over confirm that this is the critical threshold below key procedural resources. Mainwaring and Shu- which it is di‰cult or impossible to mobilize ad gart allege, correctly, that there is insu‰cient hoc support for policy initiatives.74 But if interparty coalitions are highly fragile 74. The structure of incentives for pre-electoral coali- in presidential systems, as is often asserted,75 tions must necessarily be rather di¤erent. First, these they can be prevalent without being significant. coalitions are more frequent in multiparty systems Mainwaring and Shugart rea‰rm this fragility (Chile, Brazil) than in two-party systems (Argentina, for two main reasons. First, they argue that Venezuela 1972–94), with the big exception of Colom- coalitions are basically pre-electoral and so can- bia, and the higher the number of e¤ective parties, the not be binding after the election, going so far as stronger the tendency to coalition formation. It might also be expected that electoral rules will provide incen- to conclude that ‘‘executive power is not formed 76 tives or disincentives to coalition formation, but of the through post-electoral agreement,’’ which is eighteen pre-electoral coalitions in Dehesa’s sample, constitutionally correct, but fails to recognize the seven competed under plurality rules, six under major- importance of post-electoral coalition-formation. ity with second-round run-o¤, and five under majority with congressional selection from the two or three most 72. For instance, they exclude coalitions from their voted candidates. See Dehesa, Gobiernos de Coalicion assessment of the likelihood of the president enjoying en el Sistema Presidencial. a ‘‘veto-sustaining’’ share of assembly seats for the 75. See Arend Lijphart, Democracies: Patterns of dubious reason that they are only interested ‘‘in the Majoritarian and Consensus Government in Twenty-One second-worst situation imaginable in terms of partisan Countries (New Haven, Conn.: Yale University Press, support: when only the president’s own party remains 1984); and Mainwaring, ‘‘Presidentialism, Multi- supportive’’ (Mainwaring and Shugart, Presidentialism partism, and Democracy.’’ and Democracy in Latin America, p. 411). 76. Mainwaring and Shugart, Presidentialism and De- 73. Four of the seventeen were initially elected by co- mocracy in Latin America, p. 397. alition, and went on to expand it. Seven of the seventeen 77. Gary W. Cox and Mathew D. McCubbins, Legis- went on to form post-electoral coalitions even though lative Leviathan: Party Government in the House they initially enjoyed a majority or near majority. (Berkeley: University of California Press, 1993). Presidentialism versus Parliamentarism 301

information to draw general, comparative con- it is the fact of coalition that tends to reinforce clusions about the impact of these rules on party internal party cohesion and legislative discipline, discipline across the continent.78 But there is especially of the smaller parties. Thus, far from good information on and analysis of Brazil, being characterized by ‘‘loose and shifting coali- which Mainwaring, in his own case study, sees as tions,’’ as alleged by Mainwaring, the Brazilian a ‘‘worst case’’ of indisciplined, catch-all parties, assembly is clearly divided into three ideologi- with a robust federalism further fracturing party cally distinct coalitions of left, centre and right. coherence.79 In his view, a fragmented party Consequently, party discipline in the assembly system with highly indisciplined parties leads to is not so very di¤erent from that of a system of coalitional fragility and cabinet instability, and closed lists like Venezuela’s, and the rate of suc- to almost insuperable barriers to e¤ective legis- cess of executive legislation is similar to that lation, especially reform initiatives of any kind. found in parliamentary regimes. But recent research comprehensively dismantles Analysis of the Brazilian case cannot substi- this construction of the legislative process in tute for a fuller comparative analysis, but it sug- Brazil, by demonstrating the high degree of party gests that Mainwaring and Shugart’s failure to discipline and legislative predictability achieved pay proper attention to coalition formation may by party leaderships in the assembly’s College of distort their account of executive-legislative rela- Leaders.80 By bending the procedural rules to tionships in Latin America. In this account, their own purposes, the party leaders are able executive e¤ectiveness is a function of the com- to control legislative rhythms and outcomes, so bination of the president’s legislative powers of ‘‘party fragmentation and the fact that the presi- decree, veto and so forth, and his so-called par- dent cannot count on a solid majority does tisan powers, which are mainly conferred by not prevent the executive’s initiatives being party support in the assembly. A lack of partisan approved.’’81 support, or no guarantee of an assembly major- This relatively high degree of party discipline ity, can be compensated by strong legislative underpins the formation of firm and stable co- powers, as in the case of Brazil, where the presi- alitions which are bound by ideology.82 Indeed, dent’s powers in this regard are only inferior to those of Yeltsin’s Russia,83 while small formal 78. Mainwaring and Shugart, Presidentialism and De- mocracy in Latin America, p. 421, fn. 26. 81. Figueiredo and Limongi, ‘‘Mudanca Constituc- 79. Scott Mainwaring, ‘‘Multipartism, Robust Feder- ional, Desempenho do Legislativo e Consolidacao alism, and Presidentialism in Brazil,’’ in Mainwaring Institucional,’’ p. 198. Further research by Santos and Shugart, Presidentialism and Democracy in Latin reinforces these findings, and shows that the procedural America, pp. 55–109. prominence of the assembly’s ‘‘special committees’’ 80. Limongi and Figueiredo demonstrate that even the bolsters the control of the legislative process by the least disciplined party can always expect at least 85 leaderships of the principal parties, and so facilitates per cent of its members to vote with their leaders, and the executive agenda. See Fabiano G. M. Santos, calculate that 89 per cent of all voting outcomes in the ‘‘Democracy and Legislative Dynamics in Brazil’’ assembly conform to the predictions of party leaders. (paper presented to conference on Power Structure, See Fernando Limongi and Argelina C. Figueiredo, Interest Intermediation and Policy-making: Prospects ‘‘Partidos Politicos na Camara dos Deputados: 1989– for Reforming the State in Brazil, Institute of Latin 1994,’’ Dados, 38 (1995), 497–523; and Argelina American Studies, London, 1997). C. Figueiredo and Fernando Limongi, ‘‘Mudanca 82. Limongi and Figueiredo, ‘‘Partidos Politicos na Constitucional, Desempenho do Legislativo e Con- Camara dos Deputados.’’ solidacao Institucional,’’ Revista Brasileira de Ciencias 83. Shugart and Carey, Presidents and Assemblies, Socials, 29 (October 1995), 175–200. p. 141. Chapter 5 302

powers may be buttressed by a large and dis- ment succeeded in implementing a di‰cult eco- ciplined assembly majority, as was traditionally nomic stabilization package, while the Cardoso the case in Mexico. But, as we have seen, execu- government in Brazil (from January 1995) put tive e¤ectiveness in Brazil is only partly owing to through a series of radical reform measures, presidential powers, and depends more closely including a constitutional reform to allow re- on stable and disciplined coalitions in the as- election of the president himself. But where the sembly; while executive dominance in Mexico failure to form coalitions has created minority owed most to the huge accumulation of infor- governments (top right quadrant), instability has mal, metaconstitutional, powers in the presi- ensued: the suppression of democracy by auto- dency, which worked to dissolve any separation golpe in Peru; the impeachment of the president of powers. and severe social unrest in Venezuela (despite the Mainwaring and Shugart seek to explain why much vaunted discipline of its political parties); some presidential systems work better than their mass social protest and the forced resignation traditional emphasis on fragmented party sys- of the president in Ecuador. If nothing else, it tems and party indiscipline can possibly predict appears that the presence or absence of majority by recourse to the idea of presidential powers. or near majority presidential coalitions should be But their rigid and dichotomous model misses included in the comparative analysis of presi- the informal interplay of the two types of powers dential democratic regimes. . . . in general, and its primary expression in the The present state of comparative analysis does process of coalition formation in particular. demonstrate, beyond reasonable doubt, that the Consequently, they tend to overemphasize the institutional variation across these regimes has importance of presidential powers for govern- significant implications for governability, under- ability, although confessing—at least in the case stood as government stability, legislative capac- of Colombia—that eventually ‘‘presidents must ity and the avoidance of gridlock. Furthermore, return to the legislature for the long-term insti- the five key variables in this respect all have to tutionalization of reforms enacted by decree’’;84 do, more or less directly, with electoral rules and and, equally, tend to overemphasize party indis- the party system. Thus, these regimes will be cipline and its deleterious e¤ects on partisan more or less governable according to variations powers. In sum, it is at least as plausible that it in executive electoral rules, the e¤ective number is the prevalence of coalition formation (pre- of parties, the presidential party presence in and post-electoral) that mitigates gridlock and the assembly, the degree of polarization and the enhances governability; and there is some evi- conditions of coalition formation. This can be dence for this in the case-by-case distribution of illustrated in a synoptic and simplified fashion, presidential coalitions in recent years. . . . by dichotomizing these variables and distribut- Prima facie, where coalition formation has ing the nine South American countries which re- created a presidential majority, or near majority cur in all of the studies reviewed here—namely (bottom left quadrant), governability has been Argentina, Bolivia, Brazil, Chile, Colombia, enhanced. For example, the Bolivian govern- Ecuador, Peru, Uruguay and Venezuela. . . . On the basis of these distributions it can be 84. Mainwaring and Shugart, Presidentialism and De- suggested that the initial key to governability is mocracy in Latin America, p. 52. Nor can they ade- a presidential party presence in the assembly quately explain how governability is to be enhanced by which exceeds the critical threshold of 45 per- the kind of overweening presidential powers that facil- cent. This is determined in large degree by the itate ‘‘delegative democracy’’ and often precipitate re- e¤ective number of parties in the system, which gime break-down. itself is closely conditioned by the profile of Presidentialism versus Parliamentarism 303

executive electoral rules. But it also appears that a high degree of polarization may promote mul- tipartism (although the direction of causality cannot be clear), and therefore damage govern- ability both by reducing the presidential presence in the assembly and by making it more di‰cult to overcome minority representation through coalition-building. Finally, favourable conditions for coalition formation can clearly compensate for the di‰culties of multipartism and polariza- tion. If this still highly hypothetical line of argu- ment is correct, then it is possible to distinguish South America’s most governable countries (Argentina, Chile, Colombia, Uruguay) from its least governable countries (Ecuador, Peru and contemporary Venezuela), with the current gov- ernability of Bolivia and Brazil remaining closely contingent on (very di¤erent) processes of coali- tion formation. Presidential Power, Legislative Organization, and Party Behavior in Brazil

Argelina Cheibub Figueiredo and Fernando Limongi

Presidential regimes are considered to be prone highest levels ever found in the world. In addi- to produce institutional deadlocks. In the gener- tion, the open list system prevents party leaders ally shared view, influenced by the work of Juan from exerting control over candidacies and, Linz, presidentialism lacks a built-in mechanism consequently, over party members’ voting deci- to induce cooperation between the executive and sions within the congress.2 With this institutional legislative branches of the government.1 Repre- framework, it is usually inferred that parties sentatives and the president have di¤erent con- will not be disciplined and that presidents will stituencies, and their mandates are independent face systematic resistance to their legislative and fixed. Hence the chances that the legislative proposals.3 and the executive powers will have the same This inference is not true. . . . agenda are small. Because the failure of the government does not a¤ect the legislators’ polit- ical survival, representatives have few incentives Executive Agenda and Party Behavior in the to support the government. Minoritarian presi- Legislature dents, in particular, will necessarily face con- gressional opposition. Evidence shows that recent Brazilian presidents Political parties are the only conceivable basis have had a high degree of success in enacting for executive-legislative cooperation. Ideally, the their legislative agendas. Post-1988 Brazilian same disciplined party would control the presi- presidents have had most of their legislative ini- dency and a majority in the legislature. It follows tiatives approved by the congress. This conclu- that ‘‘institutional engineering’’ should focus on sion is at odds with the conventional wisdom electoral formulas that reduce party fragmenta- about the Brazilian political system and presi- tion and increase party discipline. dential systems in general. Even scholars willing Brazil is viewed as an extreme example of the to acknowledge this evidence would nevertheless threats to governability represented by multi- argue that presidents obtained approval for their party presidential systems. Constrained by the agenda at a high cost by assembling majorities separation of powers, Brazilian presidents must through bargaining individually with representa- obtain political support in a congress in which tives on a case by case basis. This argument is party fragmentation has reached one of the not supported by the evidence. Analysis of roll call votes in the chamber of deputies shows that Excerpted from: Argelina Cheibub Figueiredo and parties are disciplined and that political sup- Fernando Limongi, ‘‘Presidential Power, Legislative port for the presidential agenda comes mainly Organization, and Party Behavior in Brazil.’’ Compar- from the parties participating in the government ative Politics 32 (2000): 151–170. Reprinted by per- coalition. mission of the authors and Comparative Politics. 1. Juan Linz, ‘‘Presidential or Parliamentary Democ- 2. Barry Ames, ‘‘Electoral Rules, Constituency Pres- racy: Does It Make a Di¤erence?,’’ in Juan Linz and sures, and Pork Barrel: Bases of Voting in the Brazilian Arturo Valenzuela, eds., The Failure of Presidential Congress,’’ Journal of Politics, 57 (May 1995), 324– Democracy: Comparative Perspectives (Baltimore: The 343; Barry Ames, ‘‘Electoral Strategy under Open-List Johns Hopkins University Press, 1994), pp. 3–87; Scott Proportional Representation.’’ American Journal of Mainwaring, ‘‘Presidentialism, Multipartism, and De- Political Science, 39 (May 1995), 406–433. mocracy: The Di‰cult Combination,’’ Comparative 3. Bolivar Lamounier, ‘‘Brazil at Impasse,’’ Journal of Political Studies, 26 (1993), 198–222. Democracy, 5 (July 1994), 72–87. Presidentialism versus Parliamentarism 305

. . . Presidents introduced 86 percent of the However, the opposite is true. The failure of the bills enacted, and the overall rate of approval of first two plans was not necessarily due to con- executive bills, 78 percent, is high. Rejection of gressional opposition. Stabilization plans can fail executive bills is rare: only twenty-four out of the for other reasons than congressional opposition. 1,881 bills introduced. In contrast, legislators’ One may still object that the proposals sent proposals have much higher rejection rates, and to the legislature may not have represented the the number of bills approved by both houses and executive’s real agenda, since presidents, antici- then vetoed by the president is significant. In pating the di‰culties they would face in con- addition, congress approves the bills introduced gress, might not have submitted it. This type of by the executive much faster than it does its own behavior is indeed possible, and presidents have proposals. . . . certainly acted at times in this way, but such be- These data may not tell the whole story. Leg- havior is part of the normal working of any islators can amend the bills submitted by the democratic system. executive. Representatives present many amend- We are not arguing that the executive imposes ments, and the data do not distinguish the extent its will on the congress. The congress is not an to which the original proposal has been changed. obstacle simply because it transforms a bill pro- But, as we show below, the representatives’ posed by the president or because the president amendment capacity is limited by the executive anticipates its legislative preferences. Under a and party leaders’ control over the agenda and democratic government one should expect the by the executive’s veto. Analysis of specific pol- congress to influence policy. The real question icy areas reveals that congress plays a minor concerns the basis of the bargaining between the ‘‘transformative role.’’17 president and the congress. The executive’s A related objection can be raised with regard success in winning approval of its legislative to the importance of approved bills. In the end, proposals in the chamber of deputies was not the approved bills may not be the really impor- obtained through bargaining with individual tant ones. One can ask, further, whether there deputies. Roll call data in the Brazilian lower is an association between importance and failure house, the Caˆmara dos Deputados, show that to be passed, that is, whether the noncontro- party members tended to vote according to their versial measures were passed and the controver- leaders directives; parties were meaningful col- sial ones failed. Despite the obvious problem in lective actors. Brazilian presidents also relied on distinguishing controversial from noncontro- party coalitions to win approval of their agen- versial measures, it is indisputable that bills of das. They obtained political support more or less great importance were approved. The three sta- the same way as prime ministers, by building bilization plans presented under di¤erent admin- government coalitions through the distribution istrations—the Summer Plan, the Collor Plan, of ministries to political parties and thereby and the Real Plan—were enacted by provisional securing the votes they needed in congress. . . . decrees, and they were approved by the legisla- . . . Table 5.10 reports the average proportion ture with minor changes.18 If the more impor- of disciplined votes, that is, those votes cast in tant measures were rejected, one should observe accordance with party leaders’ announced direc- high rates of rejection of the provisional decrees. tives, for the seven biggest parties (PT, PDT, PSDB, PMDB, PTB, PFL, and PPB).20 For all 17. See Argelina Figueiredo and Fernando Limongi, ‘‘Instituic¸o˜es Polı´ticas e Interac¸a˜o Executivo-Legisla- 20. During this period the PDS changed its name tivo: A Agenda de Estabilizac¸a˜o e Reformas’’ (Work- twice, to PPR and to PPB. The behavior of the mem- ing Paper, Cebrap/Ipea, February 1998). bers of the micro parties is not less predictable. See 18. Ibid., p. 17. Limongi and Figueiredo, ‘‘Partidos Polı´ticos,’’ p. 520. Chapter 5 306

Table 5.10 the original 575 roll call votes 434 meet at least Average proportion of disciplined votes by political one of these criteria, and 165 of them were votes party, 1989–1998 on amendments to the constitution that required Party % discipline N* a three-fifths quorum for approval. The general pattern, high party discipline, is not altered PT 98.4 533 when the sample is restricted to the presidential PDT 92.1 505 agenda. PSDB 90.7 538 Presidents won the great majority of roll call PMDB 85.0 538 votes. The government won 241 of the 269 roll PTB 87.9 506 call votes that required a simple majority, and PFL 93.1 531 143 of the 165 that required a three-fifths major- PPB 87.4 509 ity. Victories were achieved through disciplined votes, and defeats due to lack of discipline were *Variations are due to roll calls in which the leader rare. . . . does not announce the party position. Presidents may obtain partisan support on a case by case basis or by building stable coali- parties the mean is greater than the median: that tions. Most students of presidential systems, fol- is, the distributions are concentrated on the up- lowing Linz’s original formulation, rule out the per tail. The PMDB presents the lowest mean second alternative. Since presidents derive their discipline, while the PT is the most disciplined. popular mandate directly from the people, they But three other parties, the PFL, the PDT, and prefer to impose their will on congress rather the PSDB, also have a mean discipline above 90 than attempt to form party coalitions within percent. The average floor discipline in the lower congress. . . . house is 90 percent; that is, for any roll call vote We assumed that Brazilian presidents formed nine in ten representatives voted according to party coalition governments through the distri- party leaders’ recommendations. To vote with bution of portfolios and assessed the support the party is the norm. In more than 90 percent of given by the parties in the cabinet on the floor the registered cases the proportion of the dis- to the presidential agenda. There are four pos- ciplined vote was superior to 80 percent. In only sible situations. First, leaders of all parties hold- twelve of 575 cases did the proportion of repre- ing ministerial portfolios vote in accordance sentatives voting according to party position fall with the government leader. Second, no coalition below 70 percent of the floor.21 ... party opposes the government, but at least one To analyze the fate of the presidential agenda leaves the vote on the issue open. Third, at least in the congress, it is necessary to know the pres- one party opposes the government. Finally, all idential position on issues. Roll call votes are parties within the coalition may oppose the taken on the presidential agenda if the bills were president. introduced by the president or if the government Overall, the parties composing the cabinet leader stated the government’s position on the voted in accordance with the government leader. issue before the voting. In these cases the presi- All party leaders indicated votes supporting the dent had an interest in the result of the votes and president in 77 percent of the cases. In addition, made his position on the issues known. Out of at least one party left the vote on the issue open in 11 percent of the cases. Thus, the president could count on the support of cabinet parties in 21. The distribution is strongly skewed. Hence con- trolling for presence or the expected margin of victory 88 percent of the cases. In 11 percent of the cases does not alter the overall picture. Ibid., p. 523. the president met with the opposition of at least Presidentialism versus Parliamentarism 307

one party of its congressional political basis. In granted to the executive by the 1988 constitution only four cases did all parties forming the coali- include the expansion of exclusive initiative, the tion oppose the government. Therefore, cabinet right to demand urgency procedures in bringing parties in general supported the government. bills up for a vote, and, most important, the Defections occurred but were rare. . . . power to issue provisional decrees.33 ... Parallel to the executive’s extensive legislative power, the legislative organization is highly cen- Institutional Power, Governability, and Party tralized. The speaker and party leaders exercise Support tight control over the legislative agenda. They are responsible for the setting of the legislative . . . Why does the Brazilian executive exercise calendar. Moreover, party leaders have proce- such great dominance on legislative outcomes in dural rights that allow them to represent back- a multiparty system with separation of powers? benchers (bancadas) and thus to control the Given electoral incentives and the lack of party floor. For instance, the standing orders of the control over candidacies, why is the voting pat- lower house state that a roll call can be held tern in the lower house structured by parties? whenever one is requested by a petition signed by How does the executive obtain political support 6 percent of the house members. To request a in a system with separation of powers? separate vote on an amendment, the petition has The 1988 constitution did not change either to be signed by 10 percent. A request for the the form of government or the electoral and consideration of a bill under urgency procedures party legislation.30 However, it greatly extended requires the signatures of one-third of the house the legislative powers of the president. In fact, it members or an absolute majority if the bill is maintained all the constitutional changes intro- to be voted on in twenty-four hours. In all duced by the military regarding the role of the these cases—requesting a roll call, considering executive in the legislative process. These insti- an amendment, and requesting urgency—the tutional choices have had profound e¤ects on the party leader’s signature automatically represents Brazilian political system and on the executive- the will of all members of his party. Hence legislative relationship. . . . leaders decide procedures concerning roll calls, The current level of executive dominance over amendments, and urgency. legislation resembles that found in parliamentary Consideration under urgency limits back- regimes.32 Therefore, we are observing, not an benchers’ capacity to participate in the law- executive that simply circumvents the legislature, making process. As noted above, most bills are but rather one that controls the legislative pro- approved by this route. Under urgency proce- cess. Executive dominance is due primarily to the dures the bill is discharged from the committee, range and extension of legislative powers held by whether the latter has reported on the proposal the president, which alter the nature of execu- or not, and then referred directly to the floor. tive-legislative relations. The legislative powers According to house rules and practices, both the

30. The plebiscite held in 1993 maintained this form of 33. The 1988 constitution also granted the president government. No attempt to change electoral legislation the initiative in introducing constitutional amend- has succeeded. ments, which was absent from the 1946 constitution. It 32. See George Tsebelis, ‘‘Decision Making in Politi- also kept changes to speed up the consideration of leg- cal System: Veto Players in Presidentialism, Parlia- islation subject to the joint deliberation of both houses mentarism, Multicameralism, Multipartisms,’’ British through the national congress, which has specific in- Journal of Political Science, 25 (July 1995), 304. ternal rules but no permanent organizational structure. Chapter 5 308

request for and the approval of urgency proce- fragile and weak executive, blackmailed by op- dures depend on party leaders. Moreover, the portunistic legislators who obtain new appoint- right to amend a bill considered under urgency ments and positions for each vote, does not hold. is restricted. To be considered, an amendment The executive, with the resources it controls, is in needs to fulfill one of the following prerequisites: a very advantageous position. Most cabinets are to be presented by the standing committee; to be formed by the formal agreement of parties, and subscribed to by 20 percent of house members party leaders become the main brokers in the (about one hundred representatives); or to be bargaining between the executive and the legis- subscribed to by party leaders representing this lators. Presidents do not need to bargain case same percentage of the representatives. In prac- by case. They are in a position to demand sup- tice, only amendments supported by party lead- port for their entire legislative agenda. Once the ers are considered. Thus, the rules favor party government is formed and benefits are dis- leaders, especially leaders of the larger parties. tributed among the members of the coalition, the They restrict the action of the leaders of very president, with the help of party leaders, may small parties. threaten representatives and punish those who The extensive legislative powers held by the do not follow the party line.35 ... president and the distribution of legislative rights within the legislature in favor of party leaders explain the patterns observed in the previous Conclusions section. Constitutional rules and the house’s standing orders provide the executive and party Representatives’ behavior can not be inferred leaders with the means to neutralize legislators’ exclusively from electoral laws. Incentives to individualistic behavior. Members of congress cultivate the personal vote stemming from the may have electoral incentives to pursue their electoral arena may be neutralized in the legis- own particularistic interests, but they do not lature through the internal distribution of leg- have the capacity to influence legislation to islative rights. The ability of members of the achieve them. Institutional arrangements con- congress to influence policymaking may be spire against their capacity to realize them. small. Besides access to the ballot, there are Why should the leaders of the parties that be- other means by which leaders can punish recal- long to the presidential coalition cooperate with citrant rank-and-file members. the executive? Why should they use their agenda Legislative failure is not the inevitable fate of powers to help the executive? Participation in minoritarian presidents. There are no good rea- the government provides parties with access to sons to rule out the possibility of coalition gov- resources that individual legislators need for ernment under presidentialism. The combination their political survival: policy influence and pat- of presidentialism and a multiparty system is ronage. Leaders bargain with the executive; they not necessarily a threat to governmental perfor- exchange political support (votes) for access to mance. The emphasis on electoral formulas that policy influence and patronage. The executive reduce the number of parties is not warranted. provides party leaders with the means to punish Presidents may form governments the way prime backbenchers. The backbenchers who do not ministers do by obtaining support from a coali- follow the party line may have their share of tion of parties. patronage denied. Thus, a rather di¤erent image of the relation- 35. Legislators have no guarantee that their approved ship among the president, party leaders, and amendments to the budget will be implemented. individual legislators emerges. The image of a Presidentialism versus Parliamentarism 309

It is widely recognized that executive control by the government. In sum, the characteristics over the legislative agenda is a central feature of the decision-making process—the legislative of the parliamentary system. It has been shown powers of the president and the legislative that the executive’s predominance over legisla- organization—may be more important determi- tive output, party discipline, and the working of nants of governability than the form of govern- coalitions depend upon the legislative powers ment, the characteristics of party system, or the concentrated in the prime minister’s hands.38 electoral laws. However, the legislative powers of the president have been interpreted to have di¤erent e¤ects. They have been thought of as a means to cir- cumvent an institution assumed to be antagonis- tic. In contrast, we have argued that legislative powers may provide presidents with the means to entice a part of the legislature’s members into a cooperative strategy. In the end, the legisla- tive powers of the executive may have the same e¤ects on both systems. This observation allows us to dispute Tsebelis’ conclusion about the basic di¤erence between parliamentary and presidential systems. Accord- ing to him, control over the agenda distinguishes these two systems. ‘‘In parliamentary systems the executive (government) controls the agenda, and the legislature (parliament) accepts or rejects proposals, while in presidential systems the leg- islature makes the proposals and the executive (the president) signs or vetoes them.’’39 In Brazil the president controls the legislative agenda. The president proposes, and the legislature accepts or rejects what he has proposed. In fact, the first alternative—acceptance—prevails, because cen- tralized control over the agenda has profound e¤ects on party discipline. The capacity of back- benchers to participate in the policymaking process is curtailed. Centralization denies back- benchers access to the resources they need to in- fluence legislation. The bills and the amendments they introduce do not reach the floor. They can only vote yes or no on an agenda defined

38. Gary Cox, The E‰cient Secret (New York: Cambridge University Press, 1987); John Huber, Rationalizating Parliament (New York: Cambridge University Press, 1996). 39. Tsebelis, p. 325.

6 REPRESENTATION

Representative Government John Stuart Mill

On Elections Marquis de Condorcet

Liberalism against Populism William H. Riker

Saving Democracy from Political Science Gerry Mackie

Unlikelihood of Condorcet’s Paradox in a Large Society A. S. Tangian

Congruence between Citizens and Policymakers in Two Visions of Liberal Democracy John D. Huber and G. Bingham Powell, Jr.

The Political Consequences of Electoral Laws Douglas W. Rae

South Africa’s Negotiated Transition: Democracy, Opposition, and the New Constitutional Order Courtney Jung and Ian Shapiro

The Representation of Women Anne Phillips Representative Government

John Stuart Mill

the sovereignty, or supreme controlling power That the Ideally Best Form of Government Is in the last resort, is vested in the entire aggregate Representative Government of the community; every citizen not only having a voice in the exercise of that ultimate sover- It has long (perhaps throughout the entire dura- eignty, but being, at least occasionally, called on tion of British freedom) been a common saying, to take an actual part in the government, by the that if a good despot could be ensured, despotic personal discharge of some public function, local monarchy would be the best form of govern- or general. . . . ment. I look upon this as a radical and most The ideally best form of government, it is pernicious misconception of what good govern- scarcely necessary to say, does not mean one ment is; which, until it can be got rid of, will fa- which is practicable or eligible in all states of tally vitiate all our speculations on government. civilisation, but the one which, in the circum- The supposition is, that absolute power, in the stances in which it is practicable and eligible, is hands of an eminent individual, would ensure a attended with the greatest amount of beneficial virtuous and intelligent performance of all the consequences, immediate and prospective. A duties of government. . . . completely popular government is the only polity A good despotism means a government in which can make out any claim to this character. which, so far as depends on the despot, there is It is pre-eminent in both the departments be- no positive oppression by o‰cers of state, but in tween which the excellence of a political consti- which all the collective interests of the people are tution is divided. It is both more favourable to managed for them, all the thinking that has re- present good government, and promotes a better lation to collective interests done for them, and and higher form of national character, than any in which their minds are formed by, and con- other polity whatsoever. senting to, this abdication of their own energies. Its superiority in reference to present well- Leaving things to the Government, like leaving being rests upon two principles, of as universal them to Providence, is synonymous with caring truth and applicability as any general proposi- nothing about them, and accepting their results, tions which can be laid down respecting human when disagreeable, as visitations of Nature. . . . a¤airs. The first is, that the rights and interests of Such are not merely the natural tendencies, every or any person are only secure from being but the inherent necessities of despotic govern- disregarded when the person interested is himself ment; from which there is no outlet, unless in able, and habitually disposed, to stand up for so far as the despotism consents not to be des- them. The second is, that the general prosperity potism; in so far as the supposed good despot attains a greater height, and is more widely dif- abstains from exercising his power, and, though fused, in proportion to the amount and variety holding it in reserve, allows the general business of the personal energies enlisted in promoting it. of government to go on as if the people really Putting these two propositions into a shape governed themselves. . . . more special to their present application; hu- There is no di‰culty in showing that the ide- man beings are only secure from evil at the ally best form of government is that in which hands of others in proportion as they have the power of being, and are, self-protecting; and they Excerpted from: John Stuart Mill, Representative Gov- only achieve a high degree of success in their ernment. New York: E. P. Dutton, 1972. struggle with Nature in proportion as they are Representation 313

self-dependent, relying on what they themselves when the person acted on either is, or is looking can do, either separately or in concert, rather forward to becoming, a citizen as fully privileged than on what others do for them. . . . as any other. What is still more important than It is an adherent condition of human a¤airs even this matter of feeling is the practical disci- that no intention, however sincere, of protecting pline which the character obtains from the oc- the interests of others can make it safe or salu- casional demand made upon the citizens to tary to tie up their own hands. Still more obvi- exercise, for a time and in their turn, some social ously true is it, that by their own hands only can function. It is not su‰ciently considered how any positive and durable improvement of their little there is in most men’s ordinary life to give circumstances in life be worked out. Through any largeness either to their conceptions or to the joint influence of these two principles, all their sentiments. Their work is a routine; not a free communities have both been more exempt labour of love, but of self-interest in the most from social injustice and crime, and have at- elementary form, the satisfaction of daily wants; tained more brilliant prosperity, than any others, neither the thing done, nor the process of doing or than they themselves after they lost their it, introduces the mind to thoughts or feelings freedom. . . . extending beyond individuals; if instructive It must be acknowledged that the benefits of books are within their reach, there is no stimulus freedom, so far as they have hitherto been to read them; and in most cases the individual enjoyed, were obtained by the extension of its has no access to any person of cultivation much privileges to a part only of the community; and superior to his own. Giving him something to do that a government in which they are extended for the public, supplies, in a measure, all these impartially to all is a desideratum still unreal- deficiencies. If circumstances allow the amount ised. But though every approach to this has an of public duty assigned him to be considerable, it independent value, and in many cases more than makes him an educated man. . . . an approach could not, in the existing state of . . . Still more salutary is the moral part of the general improvement, be made, the participation instruction a¤orded by the participation of the of all in these benefits is the ideally perfect con- private citizen, if even rarely, in public functions. ception of free government. In proportion as He is called upon, while so engaged, to weigh any, no matter who, are excluded from it, the interests not his own; to be guided, in case of interests of the excluded are left without the conflicting claims, by another rule than his pri- guarantee accorded to the rest, and they them- vate partialities; to apply, at every turn, princi- selves have less scope and encouragement than ples and maxims which have for their reason of they might otherwise have to that exertion of existence the common good: and he usually finds their energies for the good of themselves and of associated with him in the same work minds the community, to which the general prosperity more familiarised than his own with these ideas is always proportioned. and operations, whose study it will be to supply Thus stands the case as regards present well- reasons to his understanding, and stimulation to being; the good management of the a¤airs of the his feeling for the general interest. He is made to existing generation. If we now pass to the influ- feel himself one of the public, and whatever is for ence of the form of government upon character, their benefit to be for his benefit. . . . we shall find the superiority of popular govern- From these accumulated considerations it is ment over every other to be, if possible, still evident that the only government which can fully more decided and indisputable. . . . satisfy all the exigencies of the social state is . . . The maximum of the invigorating e¤ect of one in which the whole people participate; that freedom upon the character is only obtained any participation, even in the smallest public Chapter 6 314

function, is useful; that the participation should everywhere be as great as the general degree of improvement of the community will allow; and that nothing less can be ultimately desirable than the admission of all to a share in the sovereign power of the state. But since all cannot, in a community exceeding a single small town, par- ticipate personally in any but some very minor portions of the public business, it follows that the ideal type of a perfect government must be representative. On Elections

Marquis de Condorcet

In a free society based on equality, accurate may sometimes be inconsistent, even when the popular choices are necessary not only for public individual judgements of each voter involve no prosperity and the safety of the state, but also to contradiction. This can easily be shown through ensure the preservation of the basic principles examples and can be explained by the simple fact upon which that society is grounded. . . . that the majority in favour of each of these ac- cepted propositions is not made up of the same individuals. We must therefore reject the propo- The Theory of Elections sition with the smallest majority and retain the other two. Thus, whenever we are able to obtain For a man who chooses alone and who wants to only a fairly large probability, we must reject a adhere to a strict procedure, an election is the proposition which is probable in itself if it ex- result of a series of judgements comparing all the cludes another which is more probable. candidates two by two. The candidates to whom An election result incorporating a proposi- he restricts his choice are, in this case, the men he tion which runs contrary to one of the majority considers worthy of the place. judgements may still be very probable. In fact, Similarly, an election vote is the result of those this only occurs in situations where it is certain judgements which obtain a majority. In each that the majority has been mistaken at least judgement, an individual weighs up the reasons once. The probability of the result being accurate for preference between two candidates. In an is then equal to the probability that the majority election, each person’s votes for or against a has made only one mistake regarding a certain candidate represent these reasons, and are proposition. counted rather than weighed up. When a man There is no need to point out that the con- compares two individuals and prefers the second tradiction which can occur between majority to the first, and then, on comparing the second judgements when there are three candidates must with a third, prefers the latter, it would be self- be even more likely when there are a greater contradictory if he did not also prefer the third number of candidates; or that, in such cases, to the first. If, however, on making a direct several of these judgements may contradict one comparison of the first and the third, he found another, meaning that the majority must neces- reasons for preferring the first, he would then sarily have made more than one mistake. The have to examine this judgement, balance the consequences of this are the same. reasons behind it with those behind his other The list of candidates who are put forward for judgements (which cannot exist alongside this election must be determined if all the members new one) and sacrifice the one he considers least of an assembly are to give a complete vote by probable. comparing the same candidates two by two, or In an election between three candidates, the to list them in order of merit, which comes to three judgements which obtain majority support the same thing. That is, everyone must know when the candidates are compared two by two the names of the candidates between whom the voters will be choosing. Excerpted from: Marquis de Condorcet, ‘‘On Elec- However, it is not necessary for everyone to tions.’’ In Condorcet: Foundations of Social Choice and compare all the candidates or to form a complete Political Theory. Brookfield, Vermont: Edward Elgar list. A voter may for various reasons regard a Publishing, 1994. Reprinted by permission. certain number of candidates as equal to one Chapter 6 316

another, either after considering their attributes In theory, therefore an election procedure or because he does not know the candidates should be as follows: after having determined the and is therefore unable, or unwilling, to judge list of acceptable candidates, each voter should them. . . . express his complete will, whether of preference This condition in no way restricts the voters’ or indi¤erence. freedom, since it simply requires everyone to de- A table of majority judgements between the cide which candidates he wishes to choose be- candidates taken two by two would then be tween. The list of all those put forward in this formed and the result—the order of merit in way would then present each voter with the which they are placed by the majority—ex- names of all the candidates between whom the tracted from it. If these judgements could not other voters wanted the election to be conducted, all exist together, then those with the smallest and he would then have complete freedom to majority would be rejected. decide how he could share in this judgement: This is exactly the same procedure as that fol- which candidates he wanted to rank in order of lowed by any individual who wants to make a merit and which he wanted to reject entirely by considered choice by using a general, regular placing them after all the others. method which applies to all situations. Any election method in which the votes given Since there is only one way of obtaining a true are incomplete will produce results which con- decision, the procedures used by a deliberative tradict the will which the majority would have assembly should generally be as close as possible had if complete votes had been collected. to those used when an individual examines a The results of these incomplete votes will of question for himself. course have some degree of probability of being This principle can have other important ap- correct, but it would be similar to that of a plications. In this case, it allows us to develop an proposition which has been only half examined. election method which is reasonably natural and In fact, we should support a probable proposi- as perfect as the nature of things permits. tion only when we have discovered the impossi- Any substitute method put forward should be bility of incorporating new information, and as compared to this one in terms of the time re- long as this impossibility lasts. quired by an election, the degree of enlighten- However, we would be just as far from fulfill- ment of those to whom it is entrusted, the ing our aim if we forced each voter to express, problems of outlawing the influence of intrigue, not the complete vote which he actually forms, and the need both to preserve true equality be- but a complete vote in an absolute sense; that is, tween the voters and to interest them in fulfill- if we forced him to establish an order of prefer- ing this function with scrupulous care and ence between all the candidates, including those enthusiasm. . . . he does not know. Clearly, he would then rank the latter at random and his vote could result in the election of a candidate who would not oth- erwise have had su‰cient support. In the first case, we are neglecting judgements which should have been assessed, and in the second, we are assessing judgements which have not been given. In the first case, we are acting as if we had ran- domly excluded a certain number of voters, and in the second as if we were randomly giving some of them double the number of votes. Liberalism against Populism

William H. Riker

1. There are n persons, n b 2, and n is finite. 5.A. Arrow’s Theorem Di‰culties comparable to the paradox of voting can arise in individuals who use several stan- . . . Kenneth Arrow published Social Choice and dards of judgment for choice. Our concern is, Individual Values in 1951. Although his theo- however, social choice, so we can ignore the rem initially provoked some controversy among Robinson Crusoe case. economists, its profound political significance was not immediately recognized by political 2. There are three or more alternatives—that is, scientists.1 In the late 1960s, however, a wide for the set X ¼ (x1; ...; xm), m b3. Since tran- variety of philosophers, economists, and politi- sitivity or other conditions for logical choice are cal scientists began to appreciate how pro- meaningless for fewer than three alternatives and foundly unsettling the theorem was and how since, indeed, simple majority decision produces deeply it called into question some convention- a logical result on two alternatives, the conflict ally accepted notions—not only about voting, between fairness and logicality can only arise the subject of this work, but also about the when m b3. ontological validity of the concept of social wel- 3. Individuals are able to order the alternatives fare, a subject that, fortunately, we can leave to transitively: If xRi y and yRi z, then xRi z.Ifit metaphysicians. is not assumed that individuals are able to be The essence of Arrow’s theorem is that no logical, then surely it is pointless to expect a method of amalgamating individual judgments group to produce logical results. can simultaneously satisfy some reasonable con- ditions of fairness on the method and a condition The conditions of fairness are: of logicality on the result. In a sense this theorem 1. Universal admissibility of individual orderings is a generalization of the paradox of voting (see (Condition U). This is the requirement that section 1.H), for the theorem is the proposition the set, D, includes all possible profiles, D,of that something like the paradox is possible in individual orders, Di. If each Di is some per- any fair system of amalgamating values. Thus mutation of possible orderings of X by prefer- the theorem is called the General Possibility ence and indi¤erence, then this requirement is Theorem. that individuals can choose any of the possible To make the full meaning of Arrow’s theorem clear, I will outline the situation and the con- proof here. For Arrow’s proof, as revised by Julian ditions of fairness and of logicality that cannot 2 Blau, see Kenneth Arrow, Social Choice and Individual simultaneously be satisfied. The situation for Values, 2nd ed. (New Haven: Yale University Press, amalgamation is: 1963), pp. 96–100. A refined form of Arrow’s proof is to be found in Amartya K. Sen, Collective Choice and Reprinted by permission of Waveland Press, Inc. from Social Welfare (San Francisco: Holden-Day, 1970), William H. Riker, Liberalism against Populism. Pros- chap. 3. See also Peter C. Fishburn, The Theory of pect Heights, Ill.: Waveland Press, 1982 (reissued Social Choice (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1988). All rights reserved. 1973), p. 206. Bengt Hansson, ‘‘The Existence of 1. William H. Riker, ‘‘Voting and the Summation of Group Preference Functions,’’ Public Choice, Vol. 28 Preferences,’’ American Political Science Review, Vol. (Winter 1976), pp. 89–98, contains a topological proof. 55 (December 1961), pp. 900–911. An informal sketch of Arrow’s proof is contained in William H. Riker and Peter C. Ordeshook, An Intro- 2. Since many proofs are easily available to those who duction to Positive Political Theory (Englewood Cli¤s, wish to follow up the subject, I will not reiterate the N.J.: Prentice-Hall, 1973), pp. 92–94. Chapter 6 318

permutations. For example, if X ¼ (x; y; z), the 4. Unanimity or Pareto optimality (Condition individual may choose any of the following 13 P). This is the requirement that, if everyone orderings: prefers x to y, then the social choice function, F, does not choose y. . . . This is the form in which 1. xyz 7. x (yz) 10. (xy) z 13. (xyz) monotonicity and citizens’ sovereignty enter all 2. yzx 8. y (zx) 11. (yz) x proofs of Arrow’s theorem. There are only two 3. zxy 9. z (xy) 12. (zx) y ways that a result contrary to unanimity could 4. xzy occur. One is that the system of amalgamation is 5. zyx not monotonic. Suppose in D0 everybody but i 0 6. yxz (5-1) prefers x to y and yPi x. Then in D, i changes to xPi y so everybody has x preferred to y; but, if The justification for this requirement is straight- F is not monotonic, it may be that x does not forward. If social outcomes are to be based belong to F({x; y}; D). The other way a violation exclusively on individual judgments—as seems of unanimity could occur is for F to impose y implicit in any interpretation of democratic even though everybody prefers x to y. Thus the methods—then to restrict individual persons’ juncture of monotonicity and citizens’ sover- judgments in any way means that the social out- eignty implies Pareto optimality. come is based as much on the restriction as it Many writers have interpreted the unanimity is on individual judgments. Any rule or com- condition as purely technical—as, for example, mand that prohibits a person from choosing in the discussion of the Schwartz method of some preference order is morally unacceptable completing the Condorcet rule. . . . But Pareto (or at least unfair) from the point of view of optimality takes on more force when it is rec- democracy. ognized as the carrier of monotonicity and 2. Monotonicity. According to this condition, nonimposition, both of which have deep and if a person raises the valuation of a winning al- obvious qualities of fairness. ternative, it cannot become a loser; or, if a per- 5. Independence from irrelevant alternatives son lowers the valuation of a losing alternative, (Condition I). According to this requirement it cannot become a winner. . . . Given the demo- . . . , a method of amalgamation, F, picks the cratic intention that outcomes be based in some same alternative as the social choice every time F way on participation, it would be the utmost in is applied to the same profile, D. Although some perversity if the method of choice were to count writers have regarded this condition simply as a individual judgments negatively, although, as I requirement of technical e‰ciency, it actually have shown, some real-world methods actually has as much moral content as the other fairness do so. conditions. . . . From the democratic point of 3. Citizens’ sovereignty or nonimposition. De- view, one wants to base the outcome on the fine a social choice as imposed if some alter- voters’ judgments, but doing so is clearly impos- native, x, is a winner for any set, D, of individual sible if the method of amalgamation gives dif- preferences. If x is always chosen, then what ferent results from identical profiles. This might individuals want does not have anything to do occur, for example, if choices among alternatives with social choice. It might, for example, happen were made by some chance device. Then it is the that x was everyone’s least-liked alternative, yet device, not voters’ judgments in D, that deter- an imposed choice of x would still select x.In mines outcomes. Even if one constructs the de- such a situation, voters’ judgments have nothing vice so that the chance of selecting an alternative to do with the outcome and democratic partici- is proportional in some way to the number of pation is meaningless. people desiring it (if, for example, two-thirds of Representation 319

the voters prefer x to y, then the device selects x Arrow’s theorem, then, is that every possible 2 with p ¼ 3), still the expectation is that, of sev- method of amalgamation or choice that satisfies eral chance selections, the device will choose x the fairness conditions fails to ensure a social on p selections and y on 1 p selections from ordering. And if society cannot, with fair meth- the same profile, in clear violation of Condition ods, be certain to order its outcome, then it is I. In ancient Greece, election by lot was a useful not clear that we can know what the outcomes method for anonymity; today it would be simply of a fair method mean. This conclusion appears a way to by-pass voters’ preferences. Another to be devastating, for it consigns democratic kind of arbitrariness prohibited by the indepen- outcomes—and hence the democratic method— dence condition is utilitarian voting. Based on to the world of arbitrary nonsense, at least some interpersonal comparisons of distances on scales of the time. of unknown length, utilitarian voting gives advantages to persons with finer perception and broader horizons. Furthermore, independence 5.B. The Practical Relevance of Arrow’s prohibits the arbitrariness of the Borda count. . . . Theorem: The Frequency of Cycles 6. Nondictatorship (Condition D). This is the . . . One meaning of Arrow’s theorem is that, requirement that there be no person, i, such that, under any system of voting or amalgamation, whenever xP y, the social choice is x, regardless i instances of intransitive or cyclical outcomes of the opinions of other persons. Since the whole can occur. . . . Since, by definition, no one of the idea of democracy is to avoid such situations, the alternatives in a cycle can beat all the others, moral significance of this condition is obvious. there is no Condorcet winner among cycled Finally, the condition of logicality is that the alternatives. All cycled alternatives tie with re- social choice is a weak order, by which is meant spect to their position in a social arrangement in that the set, X, is connected and its members can the sense that xyzx, yzxy, and zxyzhave be socially ordered by the relation, R, which is equal claims to being the social arrangement. the transitive social analogue of preference and Borda voting similarly produces a direct tie indi¤erence combined. (This relation, as in xR among cycled alternatives. Hence a social ar- y, means that x is chosen over or at least tied rangement is indeterminate when a cycle exists. with y.) In contrast to the previous discussion, in When the arrangement is indeterminate, the which the method of amalgamation or choice, F, actual choice is arbitrarily made. The selection is simply selected an element from X, it is now not determined by the preference of the voters. assumed that F selects repeatedly from pairs in X Rather it is determined by the power of some to produce, by means of successive selections, a chooser to dominate the choice or to manipu- social order analogous to the individual orders, late the process to his or her advantage. Every Di. And it is the failure to produce such an order cycle thus represents the failure of the voting that constitutes a violation of the condition of process. . . . logicality.2 Since an individual weak order or the relation 5.G. The Absence of Meaning Ri is often spoken of as individual rationality, social transitivity, or R, is sometimes spoken of as collective rationality—Arrow himself so de- The main thrust of Arrow’s theorem and all the scribed it. And failure to produce social tran- associated literature is that there is an unresolv- sitivity can also be regarded as a kind of social able tension between logicality and fairness. To irrationality. guarantee an ordering or a consistent path, in- Chapter 6 320

dependent choice requires that there be some sort of concentration of power (dictators, oligar- chies, or collegia of vetoers) in sharp conflict with democratic ideals. Even the weakest sort of consistency (bþ or PI ) involves a conflict with unanimity, which is also an elementary condition of fairness. These conflicts have been investigated in great detail, especially in the last decade; but no ade- quate resolution of the tension has been dis- covered, and it appears quite unlikely that any will be. The unavoidable inference is, therefore, that, so long as a society preserves democratic institutions, its members can expect that some of their social choices will be unordered or incon- sistent. And when this is true, no meaningful choice can be made. If y is in fact chosen—given the mechanism of choice and the profile of indi- vidual valuations—then to say that x is best or right or more desired is probably false. But it would also be equally false to say that y is best or right or most desired. And in that sense, the choice lacks meaning. . . . Saving Democracy from Political Science

Gerry Mackie

Although democratization is the main trend in favor A over B, Huebert and Deuteronomy the world today, the main intellectual trend in favor B over C, and Deuteronomy and Louis American political science is the view that de- favor C over A. The collective choice cycles over mocracy is chaotic, arbitrary, meaningless, and A > B > C > A. It seems that there is no collec- impossible. This trend originated with economist tive choice. Moreover, if only Huebert controlled Kenneth Arrow’s (1963) impossibility theorem, the order of voting, he could manipulate the which was applied to politics by the late Wil- outcome to his first-ranked A, by declaring first a liam Riker, political scientist at the University majority vote between B and C, and then the of Rochester. Riker’s famed Liberalism against winner of that against A. Arrow’s possibility Populism (1982) claims that elections serve only theorem can be understood as a generalization of to randomly remove o‰cials. Define populism this Condorcet paradox of voting. Cycles are (ignore its pejorative usages) as the doctrine that logically possible, but are they empirically prob- political outcomes are or should be related in able? Data on real individual preference rank- some way to the collective opinion or will of the ings show that they are distributed in a manner free and equal citizenry. Riker, and his followers such that cycles are rare, and theoretical consid- in the so-called Rochester School of political erations predict this finding. Unfairly manipu- thought, are, in this special sense, antipopulists. lated outcomes are possible only if cycles are a Because di¤erent voting systems may yield problem, and only if some political actors are di¤erent outcomes from the same profile of indi- unfairly granted powers not granted to others. vidual voters’ preferences, says Riker, ‘‘populist That a mathematical model shows that those democracy’’ is inaccurate. The claim is made by with greater formal power may have greater in- way of examples that establish the logical possi- fluence over the outcome should come as no bility of such divergence. It turns out, however, surprise. Contrary to Riker, it does not establish that with real-world distributions of individual that there is a problem in principle with democ- preference orders—individual orderings that are racy, which requires equal formal powers. at least mildly correlated with one another rather It is Riker’s dramatic empirical illustrations than unrelated and random—the reasonable of political disequilibrium, more than his theo- voting rules do tend to converge on the same retical arguments, that are responsible for the outcomes. Next, Riker continues, given a fixed wide popularity of his antipopulist views. I have voting system, then democracy is meaningless: closely examined all of the well-developed em- the outcome of voting is manipulable, and it pirical claims of cycling and democratic irratio- is not possible to distinguish manipulated nality published by Riker and his followers, and from unmanipulated outcomes because of the I claim to show that each is mistaken, either unknowability of private intentions underlying conceptually or empirically (Mackie, forthcom- public actions. Riker’s claim that democracy is ing). These case studies include a cycle alleged irremediably manipulable is based on the as- in Congressional agricultural appropriations, sumption that cycles are ubiquitous on impor- agenda control in a flying club, a cycle arising tant issues. from Powell’s desegregation amendment in the Suppose that the Duckburg Troop of the 1956 Congress, a cycle in votes in the Senate Junior Woodchucks are deciding by majority over proposing the 17th amendment to the U.S. voting how to spend their treasury over three Constitution, a cycle in consideration of the alternatives, as in table 6.1. Huebert and Louis Wilmot Proviso in 1846, a cycle over candidates Chapter 6 322

Table 6.1 ence, not what their second-, third-, and fourth- Condorcet paradox of voting ranked preferences were. In order to conduct his Huebert Deuteronomy Louis analysis, Riker must infer voters’ full rankings from historical considerations. He provides esti- 1st A B C mates of voters’ full rankings over 15 likely of 2nd B C A the 24 rankings possible for strong preferences 3rd C A B over four candidates. His estimations then per- mit the calculation of hypothetical outcomes by alternative voting rules. The results of his exer- for the 1860 presidential election, introduction of cise seem to confirm Riker’s thesis that democ- the slavery issue in order to arbitrarily manipu- racy is arbitrary and meaningless. Di¤erent late political outcomes, a cycle in consideration voting rules lead to di¤erent outcomes, and by of the method for selecting the U.S. president pairwise majority voting there is a cycle. Here at the Constitutional Convention, Lincoln’s al- are Riker’s results: leged ‘‘heresthetic’’ manipulation of the Lincoln- Plurality: Lincoln > Douglas > Breckinridge > Douglas debates, Magnuson’s alleged heresthetic Bell manipulation of the nerve-gas issue, and further cases not from Riker’s hand. If these illustrations Pairwise Majority: (Douglas > Lincoln > fail, then so does the antipopulist creed. Bell > Douglas) > Breckinridge It’s not possible in the space at hand to justify Borda Count: Douglas > Bell > Lincoln > my claimed findings. I present an abridged sam- Breckinridge ple, however, having to do with Riker’s most Approval Voting (two votes): Bell > startling claim, that there was a cycle in the Lincoln > Douglas > Breckinridge presidential election of 1860, and that choice Approval Voting (three votes): Douglas > among the candidates in that election was, in Bell > Lincoln > Breckinridge principle, arbitrary and meaningless. Riker’s overarching hypothesis is that the slavery di- Riker concludes that with five methods of voting mension of concern in antebellum American Douglas wins twice, Bell once, Lincoln once, and politics was suppressed by the Democratic Party they are in a cycle and hence tie once. ‘‘Clearly, manipulative elite with the Missouri Compro- if my guesses are even roughly right, there was mise of 1820. The competing Whig and Repub- complete disequilibrium in 1860’’ (1982, 229). lican manipulative elite sought to revive that Riker’s first two rankings have to do with all dimension by contriving a cycle, and succeeded those voters whom we know ranked Lincoln spectacularly with the election of Lincoln in first. The two rankings contain 40 percent of the 1860, the story goes. voting population of the entire country, so if There were four major candidates in the there is a major error among them then we need American presidential election of 1860. They go no further. Reconstructing Riker’s data, he were Lincoln of the recently formed Republican has it that about 1,794,000 voters in the free Party, Douglas of the northern Democrats, Bell north voted for Lincoln, and he is correct from a new third party, the Constitutional enough on that. His further claim is that of Unionists, and Breckinridge of the renegade those, one-fourth or about 450,000 ranked southern Democrats. Lincoln received a plurality Douglas second, and three-fourths or about of 40 percent of the popular vote, and Riker 1,346,000 ranked Bell second. I claim that it is suspects a cycle. From election data we have the reverse, that most Lincoln voters ranked only voters’ expression of first-ranked prefer- Douglas second, and few ranked Bell second. Representation 323

The major controversy in the country was the the Constitutional Unionists aspired to attract extent to which slavery would be allowed in the northern former Whigs, but they largely failed, vast territories, the so-called ‘‘free soil’’ question. because, although more moderate than Breck- Lincoln was most free-soil, then Douglas, then inridge, they did not appeal to northern senti- Bell, then Breckinridge (who was most pro- ments on free soil. The southern orientation of slavery). If the slavery dimension was of greatest the Constitutional Unionists was no secret to concern to voters, then one would expect that northern voters: the party received four percent Douglas would be the second choice of most of their vote. Lincoln voters, not Bell. Riker does not justify A look at a map of the county-level winners in his estimates, but presumably his inference that the 1860 presidential elections (McPherson 1993, Bell was the second choice of most Lincoln 128) shows that latitude is attitude. The upper voters was based on the thought that the Con- north voted for Lincoln (more free soil), the stitutional Unionists contained many southern lower north voted for Douglas (less free soil), the members of the defunct Whig Party, and that upper south voted for Bell (less slave soil), and northern former Whigs whose first choice was the lower south voted for Breckinridge (more Lincoln would second-rank Bell from the Whig- slave soil). Why would a voter in the upper north gish Constitutional Unionists rather than Doug- choose Lincoln? High among the reasons must las from their ancient enemy the Democratic be Lincoln’s appeal to northern interests includ- Party. That did not happen, and to understand ing his position on free soil; otherwise one of the why we have to look at what the parties stood other candidates would do. If such a voter were for, with special attention to the Constitutional denied the choice of Lincoln, who would his Unionists. second choice be? Why not Douglas, who is the The parties’ platforms reflect the positions I next most adjacent on issues of northern interest? suggest, with the exception of the Constitutional And if Douglas were not available where next Unionists. Their brief platform is a platitudinous would the typical upper northern voter turn? appeal to Constitution, Union, and Enforcement He would turn to Bell, the candidate of the of the Laws. Because of this, and their poor upper south, of course, not to Breckinridge the showing in the election, some commentators ne- candidate of the lower south. Similar reasoning glect to locate them ideologically. A close read- would predict the ranking by the typical voter in ing of their platform shows, however, that their the lower north, the upper south, and the lower pledge of continued union is conditioned on south. the reestablishment of states’ rights and equal- If voter preferences were ideologically oriented ity between the sections as found in the origi- to the free soil question, then we would expect nal constitutional compromise. It is the original upper northern voters to rank L > D > Bl > Br. constitutional compact that commands their Aggregate data are suspect because of the mis- loyalty, not present-day misinterpretations or named ‘‘ecological fallacy.’’ Nevertheless, such usurpations by the north. Outside the platform, data are instructive, especially if they support a the Constitutional Unionists believed that Con- position otherwise supported by independent gress must protect the property rights of slave- considerations. Aggregates at the state level owners in the territories, the southern position show that in the upper north Lincoln was first on free soil. They denounced the Breckinridge everywhere and Douglas generally finished sec- Democrats for threatening secession; but did not ond. The ideological approach would predict deny the right to secede should compromise with that Bell would finish third in the northern states, the north fail. The southern former Whigs who but he finishes third in three and fourth in eight were the largest faction in the organization of states. This is the candidate that Riker would Chapter 6 324

have us believe is ranked second by northern contrived on major issues such as the future of Lincoln voters. In the upper north, 55 percent of slavery? In the upper and lower north, Lincoln voters favored Lincoln, 35 percent Douglas, won 53% of the vote, Douglas 36%, and Bell 4%. eight percent Breckinridge, and two percent Bell, Riker has 25% of Lincoln voters ranking Doug- L > D > Br > Bl. Aggregates at the state level las second, and 75% ranking Bell second. The for the lower north, the upper south, and the median historians’ estimate is 60% Douglas sec- lower south support the view that slavery was ond, and 40% Bell second. Suppose that at least the primary dimension of concern. 37% ranked Douglas second, and at most 63% After my first analysis of the issue, Tabarrok ranked Bell second. What happens then to the and Spector (1999) published an intriguing and arbitrarily di¤erent outcomes and the meaning- more technically sophisticated analysis of the less cycle? They disappear! Here are the new 1860 election. Among other things, they queried outcomes: historians of the Civil War as to their views on the rankings, and 15 responded. For voters who Pairwise Majority: Douglas > Lincoln > ranked Lincoln first, the historians’ median Bell > Breckinridge opinion was that 60% ranked Douglas second Borda Count: Douglas > Lincoln > Bell > and 40% ranked Bell second. Tabarrok and Breckinridge Spector constructed a median historian’s pro- Approval Voting (two votes): Douglas > file, and compared it to Riker’s. The plane of Lincoln > Bell > Breckinridge possible outcomes in Tabarrok and Spector’s Approval Voting (three votes): Douglas > positional-vote space, using Riker’s profile, is Bell > Lincoln > Breckinridge large, and permits a large variety of rankings by way of varying the weights of a positional voting Moreover, with plurality runo¤, Lincoln and rule—from plurality to Borda count to anti- Douglas would go to the runo¤ and Douglas plurality and everything in between. The posi- would win (a runo¤ between first-round losers tional vote plane using the median historian’s Bell and Breckinridge has Bell as the winner, profile is small, and ‘‘Douglas wins . . . under any yielding the overall ranking D > L > Bl > Bk). positional voting system which gives significant All five of these voting methods select Douglas weight to second- or second- and third-ranked as the winner. Except for approval voting with preferences’’ (278); but Lincoln wins by plurality three votes, the rules identify the same ranking: count, which gives no weight to any preferences D > L > Bl > Bk. except for the first-ranked. Pairwise majority A centrist such as Douglas should have won voting is cyclic with Riker’s profile, but with the the 1860 election. That one didn’t is due to the median historian’s profile Douglas beats Bell antidemocratic design of the electoral college, by 15.1%, Bell beats Lincoln by 0.033% (three- and due to the spoiler strategy of the Breck- hundredths of one percent), and Lincoln beats inridge faction, which perversely sought a Lin- Breckinridge by 25.4%. coln victory in order to justify secession. The The platforms, aggregate voting data, and the election of Lincoln was not due to a hidden flaw opinion survey of historians support the hypoth- in the ideal of democracy. esis that Douglas and not Bell was second- The Arrow theorem disclosed the logical pos- ranked among most Lincoln voters. What does sibility of a majority cycle, of perpetual political this revision do to Riker’s demonstration that instability. But we observe stability rather than democracy is arbitrary because di¤erent voting instability in democratic politics. Riker origi- methods result in di¤erent outcomes and that nally responded that cycles are common but democracy is meaningless because cycles will be rarely detected. Simulations show and empirical Representation 325

studies corroborate, however, that cycling is an Riker, William H. 1982. Liberalism Against Populism: empirical improbability. Riker later conceded A Confrontation between the Theory of Democracy and that uncontrived cycles are quite rare, but that the Theory of Social Choice. Prospect Heights: Wave- on major issues actors will contrive cycles by in- land Press. troduction of new alternatives. In order to be Tabarrok, Alexander and Lee Spector. 1999. ‘‘Would persuaded to abandon the concept of the public the Borda Count Have Avoided the Civil War?’’ Jour- nal of Theoretical Politics 11: 261–288. good and the idea of democracy as in some sense the expression of the people’s will, most people would require that it be robustly demonstrated that the manipulation of political outcomes is frequent, harmful, and irremediable. Riker’s po- sition is that it is either theoretically impossible or empirically di‰cult to detect such manipula- tion. He is able, however, to produce spectacular anecdotes that purport to show harmful manip- ulation on major issues, including a demonstra- tion that the biggest event in American history was the consequence of a contrived cycle. I have worked through each of his examples only to find that each is mistaken. Theoretical consid- erations about the distribution of preference orders suggest that cycles are most unlikely; em- pirical studies show that cycles are of no practi- cal importance; finally, every developed and published example of a political cycle has now been challenged. Thus, I argue that after fifty years of scholarship, from the first publication of Arrow’s theorem, no one has satisfactorily dem- onstrated the existence of a normatively trou- bling cycle in the real world. The antipopulist interpretations of social choice results inspired by Riker, widely endorsed in the discipline of political science, are unsup- ported by evidence and must be abandoned.

References

Arrow, Kenneth J. 1963/1951. Social Choice and Indi- vidual Values, second edition. New Haven: Yale Uni- versity Press. Mackie, Gerry. Forthcoming. Democracy Defended. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. McPherson, James M. 1993. Ordeal by Fire, vol. 1, The Coming of War. New York: McGraw-Hill. Unlikelihood of Condorcet’s Paradox in a Large Society

A. S. Tangian

On the other hand, the intransitivity of prefer- 1 Introduction ence discovered by Condorcet is generally inher- ent in all ordinal models. Thus having a rigorous 1.1 Social Choice with Respect to Cardinal and methodological basis, the ordinal approach lacks Ordinal Utility the universal solvability inherent in the cardinal approach. In a general formulation, the unsolv- As early as in the last quarter of the 18th cen- ability of the ordinal approach to social choice tury, Borda, Condorcet, and Laplace mathe- has been proved by Arrow (1951). matically investigated election by vote (see Black However, contrary to Condorcet’s predictions, 1958; Young 1988; McLean and Urken 1994). the intransitivity of social preference is seldom Borda described cases when voting implies observed in real voting. Moreover, all demo- intuitively unacceptable results. Condorcet dis- cratic systems are based on di¤erent forms of covered the intransitivity of majoritarian prefer- voting, ignoring the unsolvability of the ordinal ence, the fact known as Condorcet’s paradox. approach. So we have an apparent inconsistency Both authors developed new methods to over- between theory and practice. come this problem with voting, which posed In this paper, we analyze the cause of this further problems. Laplace provided some math- inconsistency. It turns out that Condorcet’s pre- ematical arguments to back up Borda’s model. dictions are true for a quite particular combina- These studies, having questioned the faithfulness torial case, when an ‘average voter’ votes for or of election systems, have had numerous succes- against certain candidates with equal probabil- sors and thus have given birth to a new scientific ity. The related analytical studies have been done branch, the social choice theory. by DeMeyer and Plott (1970), May (1971), Borda and Condorcet founded two di¤erent Merril and Tideman (1991), Niemi and Weisberg standpoints, which continue to be the two prin- (1968), Garman and Kamien (1968), Gehrlein cipal approaches to the problem. Borda’s count and Fishburn (1976), and Gehrlein (1983). The is based on summing ranks of candidates in in- results of computer simulation have been re- dividual schedules, which are cardinal utilities. ported by Campbell and Tullock (1965), Klahr Laplace considered a model with real utilities as (1966), Jones et al. (1995), and Van Deemen a logical development of Borda’s model. Con- (1996). dorcet’s count uses pairwise votes, which are or- The assumption of equal probability of voting dinal data. . . . for or against candidates means that these can- The ordinal approach, including a majority didates have equal merits, a circumstance which rule, is usually considered to be ‘more objective’ is possible theoretically, but can hardly ever oc- and better substantiated than the cardinal one. cur. Much more frequently, candidates have dif- ferent merits, reflected by the vote asymmetry. Editor’s note: Tangian develops some lengthy and We show that in such a case the probability of technical proofs to support his findings, which are not intransitive social preference vanishes as the included here. For our purposes, it su‰ces to provide number of voters increases. From this we con- an explication of his methods and a summary of his results. clude that it is very unlikely to obtain Con- dorcet’s paradox in a real vote. . . . Excerpted from: A. S. Tangian, ‘‘Unlikelihood of Condorcet’s Paradox in a Large Society.’’ Social . . . We prove with a probability model that Choice and Welfare 17 (2000): 337–365. Reprinted by group decisions based on a pairwise majority permission. Representation 327

vote or on summing individual cardinal utilities ment exploited by Condorcet and some other (in the form of either reals, or integers, or ranks) scholars. tend to be the same as the number of individ- Our approach can be explained with a refer- uals increases. The only exception is the case ence to Black’s (1958) model with single-peaked when the vote ratio for pairs of alternatives is preferences. He proved the transitivity of a ma- 50%:50%. Since such an equilibrium is rather jority preference, having assumed an alignment unlikely, we conclude that in most practical sit- of candidates such that each elector has a single- uations pairwise vote count and utility count are peaked preference with respect to this alignment. almost equivalent. In our model, such an alignment is the latent Let us explain the main idea at an intuitive social merit scale. In a large model, the devia- level, in terms of tournaments. Imagine a chess tions from this scale in individual preferences can competition with three participants A, B, and C. be considered as ‘‘errors’’ which become negligi- Due to chance, a weaker player can gain a vic- ble as the number of individuals increases. tory over a stronger one, and the preference Note that, unlike Black, we do not restrict order on the set of players can have cycles like the domain of preference profiles (combinations A B C A. However, in multiple rounds, a of individual preferences). We consider all pro- stronger player wins more often, getting a higher files under some probabilistic assumptions (in- total score of victories over weaker players. After dependence of voters, inequality of the mean a certain number of rounds, the preference order preference probability from 0.5, that is no on the set of participants based on paired games equilibrium of votes). Then we show that the will correspond to their real strength rating. probability of the profiles which result in an (Recall that each chess professional is assigned a intransitive social preference vanishes as the rating calculated with respect to his results in number of voters increases. We conclude that to several tournaments.) avoid Condorcet’s paradox in a large society, A pairwise vote for candidates A, B, C in a there is no need to introduce any domain re- small group of voters is like a single tournament striction, since the domain ‘restricts itself’ almost round with a risk of misrepresentation of real for sure in the probabilistic sense under rather merits of the participants. This can result in in- weak assumptions. That is, the profiles resulting transitive cycles in the preference order. A vote in an intransitive social preference constitute an in a large society, due to the error-vanishing ef- event with vanishing probability. . . . fect, is similar to a multiple-round tournament In intermediate reasoning we make use of in- where the merits of participants are revealed dividual cardinal utilities. We assume that they more accurately. If social merits of candidates do exist and have some probability distribution, are adequately reflected by the vote in an elec- but do not require their expressibility. This as- tion, then the (latent) merit scale linearizes sumption is not crucial, since the question of ex- the resulting preference, as the rating scale lin- istence of probability measures is trivial for finite earizes the order of players in a multiple-round models, which is our case (the number of indi- tournament. viduals is finite, and individual utilities can be The idea of the underlying ‘‘objective’’ prefer- restricted to some finite grid). ence being distorted in individual preferences Since the limit theorems of the paper are valid goes back to Condorcet who has assumed prob- for arbitrary distributions, the results hold even abilistic deviations from some ‘‘correct’’ vote. if these distributions are not known. Here we From this standpoint, the intransitivity of the follow the same line of reasoning as (Tanguiane majoritarian preference is no longer a paradox 1991, 1994) while revising Arrow’s paradox: We but rather an error to be corrected—the argu- prove a property for every measure and then Chapter 6 328

conclude that knowing the measure is not neces- model is a model with a few participants with the sary to be sure that this property holds. weight coe‰cients, corresponding to the size of . . . [W]e consider a model with two alter- coalitions. natives. We prove that the decision obtained by Independence may be regarded as the most voting and that obtained by summing individual consistent realization of the idea of probability. cardinal utilities become the same as the number Therefore, our results relate with reservations to of individuals increases. The two decisions con- a nonindependent probabilistic model, as dem- tradict each other with a significant probability onstrating some kind of a general trend. only if the probability of vote for one candidate Besides, our results illustrate the opinion that against another is equal to 0.5. This case corre- cardinal measurements are not very important in sponds to precisely equal social merits of the processing ordinal data. In fact, we show that candidates which is a rare coincidence. voting leads to the same results as summing car- Then, we extend this result from a pair of dinal utilities, implying that most essential infor- alternatives to several alternatives. This gives the mation is already inherent in ordinal preferences. main statement of the paper: The social prefer- Finally, it follows that the inaccuracy of cer- ences based on ordinal or cardinal counts tend to tain election procedures should not play a deci- become the same as the number of individuals sive role in case of a large society. In particular, increases. As a corollary, in a model with a large a majority vote will reveal the same preference number of voters, the transitivity of the Borda as more sophisticated and ‘‘precise’’ methods of preference is inherent in the preference based on election that are based on cardinal utilities. pairwise vote. For instance, consider the presidential elec- . . . [W]e provide numerical evidence of the tion in Russia for Jelzin against Sjuganow on coincidence of results from voting and from June 16, 1996. In spite of a small vote asymme- summing individual utilities. The speed of con- try (34% and 32% of votes, respectively) we can vergence of the two methods of social decision expect that the social response was not indi¤er- making depends on several parameters. We clas- ent (since the political programs of the candi- sify distributions of individual cardinal utilities dates di¤ered significantly). From our standpoint with respect to these parameters and interpret we can be quite sure that even a hypothetical these classes with regard to the way of social voting system which takes into account the de- behavior. . . . gree of individual preferences would give the . . . [I]n most practical cases (not simulta- same election result. neously vote symmetry and indi¤erent social In conclusion we summarize the main state- response) decisions based on voting and on ments of the paper. summing individual utilities provide close re- sults. For a large society, reservations should be 1. Our model is not based on any domain re- made only for the case of symmetric vote in an striction on the individual preference profiles indi¤erent society. implying the transitivity of a majority prefer- It should be emphasized that Condorcet’s ence. We consider all profiles but show under paradox remains relevant for small groups. Since rather weak assumptions that the probability of our model assumes the probabilistic indepen- an intransitive collective preference is vanishing dence of individuals, a large society means a as the number of individuals increases (Con- large number of independent individuals. A few dorcet has considered equiprobable collective large coalitions with members sharing the same preferences which, as one can see, is not relevant preference do not meet this condition. Such a to real social choice). Representation 329

2. For this purpose we assume the following DeMeyer F, Plott Ch (1970) The Probability of a . Independence of individuals (following Con- Cyclic Majority. Econometrica 38: 345–354. dorcet, Laplace), Garman M, Kamien M (1965) The Paradox of Voting: Probability Calculations. Behavioral Science 10: 306– . Independence of ordinal and cardinal parts 317. in individual preferences (following Borda, Gehrlein WV (1983) Condorcet’s Paradox. Theory and Laplace), Decision 15: 161–197. . Asymmetry of pairwise votes (Tangian). Gehrlein WV, Fishburn PC (1976) The Probability of 3. In a large society, a di¤erent choice with re- the Paradox of Voting: A Computable Solution. Jour- nal of Economic Theory spect to voting or summing individual utilities is 13: 14–25. statistically not significant. The solvability of a Jones B, Radcli¤ B, Taber Ch, Timpone R (1995) large ordinal model of social choice (transitivity Condorcet Winners and the Paradox of Voting: Prob- ability Calculations for Weak Preference Orders. of a majoritarian preference) follows from the American Political Science Review 89: 113–144. existence of the dual cardinal model, not requir- Klahr D (1966) A Computer Simulation of the Para- ing its explicit knowledge. dox of Voting. American Political Science Review 60: 4. In a small group, a di¤erent choice with re- 384–390. spect to voting and summing individual utilities May RM (1971) Some Mathematical Remarks on the is statistically significant. Testing the di¤erence Paradox of Voting. Behavioral Science 16: 143–151. requires additional information about the distri- McLean I, Urken AD (eds.) (1994) Classics of Social bution of preference probabilities. Choice. University of Michigan Press, Ann Arbor. 5. A di¤erent choice with respect to voting and Merril, Tideman (1991) The Relative E‰ciency of Ap- summing individual utilities in caused by the proval and Condorcet Voting Procedures. Rationality following: and Society 3: 65–77. Niemi RG, Weisberg H (1968) A Mathematical Solu- . a high deviation coe‰cient s=m (since s < 1, tion for the Probability of the Paradox of Voting. Be- the expectation m must be small, that is, individ- havioral Science 13: 317–323. uals are indi¤erent); Tanguiane AS (1991) Aggregation and Representation . almost symmetrical votes ( p is close to 1/2). of Preferences. Introduction to Mathematical Theory of 6. One should not worry about the imperfection Democracy. Springer, Berlin Heidelberg New York. of election systems based on voting: Tanguiane AS (1994) Arrow’s Paradox and Mathe- . matical Theory of Democracy. Social Choice and Wel- The risk that an intransitive preference fare 11(1): 1–82. emerges is negligible. Young HP (1988) Condorcet’s theory of voting. . Election based on voting is almost as accurate American Political Science Review 82: 1231–1244. as complex systems with cardinal utilities. . . .

References

Arrow KJ (1951) Social choice and individual values. Wiley, New York. Campbell CD, Tullock G (1965) A Measure of the Importance of Cyclical Majorities. Economic Journal 75: 853–856. Congruence between Citizens and Policymakers in Two Visions of Liberal Democracy

John D. Huber and G. Bingham Powell, Jr.

Liberal democracy claims to establish connec- attempt to give explicit theoretical form to the tions between citizens and policymakers. The re- Majority Control and Proportionate Influence peated processes of electoral competition and visions, to link them empirically to specific types legislative bargaining are supposed to ensure that of modern democracies, and to measure their policymakers do what citizens want them to do. successes and failures at creating congruence. We There are, however, at least two quite di¤erent want to know in particular how such theoreti- visions of the democratic processes that can cre- cally critical features as responsible incumbent ate congruence between citizen preferences and governments at the time of the election, identifi- public policies. able future governments in electoral competition, In what we call the Majority Control vision, proportional representation in electoral out- democratic elections are designed to create comes, and the formation of majority govern- strong, single-party majority governments that ments after the election are related to levels of are essentially unconstrained by other parties in congruence. the policy-making process. Policymakers are Congruence, of course, is not the only demo- likely to do what citizens want them to do be- cratic virtue: some of the processes treated here cause the party that controls the government has as intervening may be highly valued in their won majority support in the election. Its an- own right.1 Voters oriented to control may nounced policy comments, previous record, or wish to see government formations that change both were preferred to the partisan alternative by in response to even small vote shifts. Voters a majority of the citizens. In the other vision, may prefer to have very distinctive choices. which we call the Proportionate Influence vision, Voters may prefer that policy-making be highly elections are designed to produce legislatures e‰cient. Permanent minorities may prefer pro- that reflect the preferences of all citizens. After portionate representation and consultative legis- the election legislative bargaining between lative bargaining, especially if other processes parties is necessary for policymaking, and the directly impose the preferences of the majority. influences of the various parties in post-election We therefore do not propose that congruence bargaining processes determine the extent to between citizen preferences and public policy which policymakers do what citizens want them should be the only grounds for choosing or sup- to do. porting one vision over the other. We do think, In this paper, we o¤er a simple way to con- however, that congruence between the prefer- ceptualize the degree of congruence between ences of citizens and the actions of policymakers citizens and their governments, comparing citi- constitutes a major claim and goal of liberal de- zen self-placements on the left-right scale with mocracy. Thus, Dahl’s ‘‘reasonable justification the placement of the governing political parties for democracy’’ posits that ‘‘a majority of citi- on the same scale by expert observers. We then zens can induce the government to do what they most want it to do and to avoid doing what they Excerpted from: John D. Huber and G. Bingham Powell, Jr., ‘‘Congruence between Citizens and Policy- 1. Some of these other virtues are more fully described makers in Two Visions of Liberal Democracy.’’ World and elaborated in G. Bingham Powell, Jr., ‘‘Elections Politics, 46 (3) (Apr., 1994), 291–326. 6 1994 The as Instruments of Democracy’’ (Manuscript, Univer- Johns Hopkins University Press. Reprinted with the sity of Rochester, 1993). permission of The Johns Hopkins University Press. Representation 331

most want it not to do.’’2 This is not a unique preferred by the citizens. If these defining char- position but rather articulates more clearly than acteristics of majority control are achieved, then most a common assumption of those who theo- whether there is a close correspondence between rize about liberal democracy. Hence, although voters and policymakers will depend on another congruence is only a part of our general inter- feature of the election: the presence of a party or est in democratic processes, it is an important candidate located at or very near the median part. . . . voter. If neither identifiable alternative govern- ment is close to the median voter, then by our definition, the majoritarian democratic process Alternative Visions of Democracy and will not result in a government that is committed Congruence to ‘‘what the voters want.’’ Responsible incum- bents in o‰ce at the time of the election should In each of the two visions of democracy exam- be helpful: single-party majority governments ined here, there is a clear path by which both that bear clear responsibility for their actions will electoral and legislative processes can create be pressed to anticipate the citizen majority as congruence between the citizen median and the they look to the election; voters will find it easier behavior of governments and policymakers. But to evaluate the credibility of promises and to the path in each vision is di¤erent and so are the choose the party whose true position is closest to areas where one may expect problems. their preferences. The Majority Control vision assumes that po- Scholars have o¤ered a variety of specific litical power will be concentrated in the hands of models to explain how Majority Control systems identifiable governments chosen by the electorate can deliver policies that the citizens want. In the and responsible to it. Elections involve competi- well-known two-party competition model pro- tion between incumbent governments and chal- posed by Anthony Downs, the desire to win lengers. Voters evaluate the past performance elections drives both parties toward the position and future promises of each and choose the con- of the median voter. With a single dimension of tender whose policies they expect will be closest party competition, a party that fails to converge to their preferences. That contender wins elec- nearly to the median can always be defeated by a toral and legislative majorities and comes to of- party that does move to the median. The strate- fice committed to a set of policies favored by a gic incentives for the parties and the rational citizen majority. When in o‰ce, the new gov- choices of voters act together to provide victories ernment carries out those policies under the eye for the party that is closest to the median.18 If of the electorate, which can evict it in the next the theory of center-driven party competition election if it fails to keep its promises. were empirically true, it would provide a power- The key stage in the Majority Control vision is ful underpinning for the claim of the Majority clearly electoral competition: party alternatives, voter choices, and the aggregation of the two. 18. Downs, An Economic Theory of Democracy (New Elections must provide voters with identifiable York: Harper and Row, 1957); see also Heinz Eulau alternative governments; they must also produce and Kenneth Prewitt, Labyrinths of Democracy: Adap- clear control over policy-making for the party tations, Linkages, Representation and Policies in Urban Politics (New York: Bobbs-Merril, 1973); Joseph 2. Robert A. Dahl, Democracy and Its Critics (New Schlesinger, Ambition and Politics: Political Careers in Haven, Conn.: Yale University Press, 1989), 95. In a the United States (Chicago: Rand McNally, 1966); and similar vein, see Hanna Pitkin, The Concept of Repre- Joseph Schumpeter, Capitalism, Socialism and Democ- sentation (Berkeley: University of California Press, racy (New York: Harper and Row, 1942). 1967), 234. Chapter 6 332

Control vision to create congruence. However, to representation and bargaining. This vision is there is much controversy about the correspon- less clearly articulated in its multiple stages. At dence between Downs’s theory and the empirical the electoral level the large literature on pro- facts of party competition. portional representation stresses the fairness of Since only the winning party needs to be near having all voters’ voices count in getting o‰cials the citizen median to create congruence, the into o‰ce.22 At the policy-making level, various Majority Control vision need not depend on analysts of accommodative or consociational Downs’s strategic parties. It can also encompass democracy, most influentially Arend Lijphart, ‘‘mandate’’ versions of democracy19 or other argue that minorities in deeply divided systems models in which incumbents face challengers will want ‘‘grand coalition’’ arrangements that who over time o¤er a large array of possible al- guarantee them a voice in policy-making.23 In ternatives.20 We cannot here explicate the vary- his model of ‘‘consensus democracy,’’ Lijphart ing assumptions of these models, but we merely note that various specific models in the broad 21. For theoretical results, see, e.g., Alberto Alesina, Majority Control vision can lead to the predic- ‘‘Credibility and Policy Convergence in a Two-Party tion that the winner of the election should usually System with Rational Voters,’’ American Economic be at or near the median voter. All of these Review 78 (September 1988); Peter J. Coughlin, ‘‘Can- models then tend to assume that the election didate Uncertainty and Electoral Equilibria,’’ in James winner will subsequently dominate the policy- M. Enelow and Melvin J. Hinich, eds., Advances in the making process and implement the promised Spatial Theory of Voting (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1990); Melvin J. Hinich, ‘‘Equilib- policies. rium in Spatial Voting: The Median Voter Result Is an If some combination of these models proves Artifact,’’ Journal of Economic Theory 16 (December empirically accurate, then the other (presumed) 1977); Donald A. Wittman, ‘‘Candidates with Policy virtues of majoritarianism will be buttressed by Preferences: A Dynamic Model,’’ Journal of Economic good congruence between the preferences of the Theory 14 (February 1977); and idem, ‘‘Spatial Strat- electorate and the commitments of the policy- egies When Candidates Have Policy Preferences,’’ in makers. The potential problem, of course, is that Enelow and Hinich. For empirical results, see, e.g., various empirical studies, and also some theo- David Robertson, A Theory of Party Competition retical work, show failure of competition to pro- (London: Wiley, 1976); Ian Budge and Dennis Fairlie, duce consistently a party at the median.21 Voting and Party Competition (London: Wiley, 1983); and Bernard Grofman, Robert Gri¤en, and Amihai The Proportionate Influence vision gets to a Glazer, ‘‘Identical Geography, Di¤erent Party: A Nat- similar prediction of congruence in a very di¤er- ural Experiment on the Magnitude of Party Di¤erences ent way. The models and research associated in the U.S. Senate, 1960–84,’’ in R. J. Johnston, F. M. with this vision are not directly oriented to Shelley, and P. J. Taylor, eds. Developments in Elec- majorities or to control, but rather are oriented toral Geography (London: Routledge, 1990). 22. See Douglas Rae, The Political Consequences of 19. See Anthony Birch, Representation (London: Electoral Laws (New Haven: Yale University Press, Macmillan, 1972); and Austin Ranney, The Doctrine of 1967). Responsible Party Government (Urbana: University of 23. Lijphart, Democracy in Plural Societies (New Illinois Press, 1962). Haven: Yale University Press, 1977); see also G. Lem- 20. See Kollman, Miller, and Page (fn. 5); and Richard bruch, ‘‘A Non-Competitive Pattern of Conflict Man- D. McKelvey and Peter C. Ordeshook, ‘‘Elections with agement in Liberal Democracies,’’ in Kenneth McRae, Limited Information: A Fulfilled Expectations Model ed., Consociational Democracy (Toronto: McClelland Using Contemporaneous Poll and Endorsement Data and Stewart, 1974); and Ju¨rg Steiner, ‘‘The Principles as Sources,’’ Journal of Economic Theory 36 (June of Majority and Proportionality,’’ British Journal of 1985). Political Science 1 (January 1971). Representation 333

draws attention to various institutional devices formation,26 that is, all coalitions should include less inclusive than a grand coalition that induce the median party, although any coalition may majorities to bargain with minorities.24 Most of incorporate other parties that fall to one side or this work assumes that multiparty elections and the other (or both). proportional representation are highly desirable Existing research does not, however, provide prerequisites for such negotiation. a clear prediction about whether the median To convert the Proportionate Influence vision party will dominate policy-making, even in the into a more clearly identified model of elections one-dimensional situation. Laver and Schofield connecting citizens and policymakers, we must and de Swann argue that the policy position of spell out the assumptions at each of the two the median legislator will prevail, but Austen- important stages in the process of government Smith and Banks, in a model that integrates formation. At the election stage, the vision as- electoral competition and government forma- sumes multiple parties o¤ering a variety of al- tion, find that in equilibrium, final policy out- ternatives, so that all groups of citizens can find comes never correspond to the preferences of the compatible parties. The parties do not—must median legislator.27 More generally, in situa- not—converge to the center unless virtually all tions where a single party or coalition of parties the voters are located very close to it.25 At the forms a government and must maintain tight time of the election, then, the choices of voters party discipline—which empirically is the case in and the working of proportionate election laws almost all parliamentary systems—the govern- result in a legislature with parties representing all ment might be expected to make policies that these groups in their proportionate strength. A correspond to its own internal median, not to the critical implication of this fact is that the posi- legislative median. tion of the median legislator (or median party, if Thus, we have here a potential for connec- parties are in fact the relevant units) should be tions—through inclusion of the median party in very close to that of the median voter. the coalition—without very close congruence. The second stage of the Proportionate Influ- As in the concerns about the failure of party ence vision concerns coalition bargaining. Since competition to produce at least one party at the an election often creates a legislature with no median in the majoritarian vision, the processes single-party majority, various coalitions could that connect legislative bargaining to govern- form among the many parties represented. Nat- ment policy may also lead to consistent policies urally, the more diverse the electorate and, con- o¤ the median. sequently, the legislature, the more possible in Up to this point, we have considered only the abstract to build a coalition that strays from the congruence between governments and citi- the position of the median citizen. But as in zen preferences. That is, we have assumed that electoral competition, coalition theory predicts that in one-dimensional situations the median 26. For an excellent review of the coalition formation party will play a dominant role in government literature, see Michael Laver and Norman Schofield, Multiparty Government: The Politics of Coalition in 24. Arend Lijphart, Democracies: Patterns of Ma- Europe (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1990), joritarian and Consensus Government in Twenty-one chap. 5. Countries (New Haven: Yale University Press, 1984); 27. Ibid., 111; Abram de Swaan, Coalition Theory and see also Dahl (fn. 2), chap. 11. Cabinet Government (Amsterdam: Elsevier, 1973); and 25. In Lijphart’s empirical analysis of ‘‘consensus’’ David Austen-Smith and Je¤rey Banks, ‘‘Elections, systems, the number of e¤ective parties virtually de- Coalitions, and Legislative Outcomes,’’ American Po- fines one of his dimensions (fn. 24), 214. litical Science Review 82 (June 1988). Chapter 6 334

Table 6.2 Visions of democracy and processes that create congruence between voters and policymakers Process stages Majority control vision Proportionate influence vision Electoral competition identifiable alternative governments, one a wide range of party choice; absence of responsible incumbent, one or both close explicit coalition commitments to the median voter Election outcomes party close to median voter wins majority proportionate legislative representation of all parties and voters Government formation election winner forms majority government bargaining: government coalition includes the median legislator Policy-making between government dominates all policy-making coalitions may change but still include elections median; negotiation with opposition parties may help balance government parties right or left of median party Congruence prediction government is the policymaker and is close government includes median legislator, to the median voter but average weight of all policymakers will be closer to the median voter

the representation process ends with the forma- government includes the median party but ex- tion of a government coalition. In practice all tends from it to the right or left. Hence, in con- governments will probably be somewhat influ- trast to what we would expect in ideal Majority enced by the issues raised by other parties in the Control systems, giving opposition parties sig- legislature. . . . nificant weight in policymaking may improve Under the Majority Control vision of congru- congruence between what citizens want and what ence (especially in the ‘‘mandate’’ formulations), policies result in Proportionate Influence sys- one would expect that the greater the opposition tems; but it also may not, depending on the spe- influence in policy-making, the less the congru- cific positions of the government and the other ence between policymaker and citizens. In this parties. . . . vision, the selection of a governing party close to the citizen median should already have re- sulted in good congruence between final policies Characteristics of Liberal Democratic Control and the citizen majority. If all other parties have Systems: Theory and Practice not converged to the median position, however, giving weight to the opposition after a govern- The two visions of democracy are founded in ment forms can only move the policymakers experience and custom as well as in theory. away from the median. Moreover, such influence [Table 6.2] suggests that we can identify features will make it more di‰cult for voters to make of electoral competition, electoral outcomes, and clear retrospective judgments about government legislative bargaining that will enable us to cate- responsibility—a fact that decreases the incen- gorize empirically the di¤erent systems accord- tives for parties to converge to the median in the ing to the extent to which they follow one vision first place. or the other. Table 6.3 presents the data neces- In the Proportionate Influence vision, giving sary to accomplish this task; the data are used some weight to the opposition may pull policy- to categorize the systems in twelve industrial makers back toward the median citizen if the democracies for the period 1968–87. Subse- Representation 335 Yes Yes No No Yes Yes No Yes M.C. & P.I. (6) No No Yes Yes Opposition Committee Influence Column 6 is are from Thomas T. 98 97 80 85 98 83 87 95 96 79 96 91 P.I. (5) 0 0 67 83 43 50 75 17 14 100 100 100 M.C. (4) Single Party or PEC Wins Majority Proportionality , 3d ed. (Washington, D.C.: CQ Press, 1991), 509–10. 2.7 5.4 2.2 3.3 2.6 2.0 3.6 2.6 3.5 5.1 6.1 2.5 P.I. (3) E¤ective No. of Parties 1–4 are averages from the period 1968–87. Data for column 5 and Powell and Whitten (fn. 33). .67 .125 .33 .33 .125 .44 0 0 1.0 0 0 0 (2) M.C. Past Govt. Status a 0 0 38 29 17 33 38 100 100 100 100 100 (1) M.C. Identifiability of Future Govt. The International Almanac of Electoral History Mackie and Richard Rose, a. See text for descriptions of the measures. Data for columns based on the analysis by Strom (fn. 29, 1990), chap. 3; United Kingdom Sweden New Zealand Spain Netherlands Italy West Germany Ireland France Denmark Belgium Australia Country Table 6.3 System characteristics in twelve democratic countries Chapter 6 336

quently, we will use data from 1978 to 1985 in Citizens, Governments, and Ideological order to test congruence.30 Congruence in Majoritarian and Proportionate At the stage of electoral competition, the Ma- Influence Systems jority Control vision stresses that the voters be able to identify future alternative governments We develop two measures, called Government and that responsibility for past policy-making Distance I and Government Distance II, of the by the incumbent government should be clear. congruence between the position of the govern- The Proportionate Influence vision emphasizes a ment and the estimated position of the median large number of parties o¤ering a wide range of voter.38 . . . Government Distance I takes the av- choices. In table 6.3 we see the countries in our erage position of all the parties in the government study followed, in columns 1–3, by features of weighted by the size of the respective parties. . . . their electoral competition.31 ... Since the number of portfolios a party receives may not be a good measure of its influence in the 30. It would be ideal to be able to analyze congruence coalition, we developed an alternative measure, for this entire twenty-year span, but since the Castles Government Distance II. This second measure and Mair expert survey measured party positions in assumes that the left-right position of the gov- 1982, we have used only the 1978–85 period so that we can rely on the assumption that party positions have ernment coalition is dominated by the placement not changed much. There are thirty-eight governments of the median party within it. Hence, Govern- in these twelve countries in this time period. Various ment Distance II is simply the left-right posi- readers have suggested that we extend our time period tion of the median party within the government. and bring in more cases, but we simply cannot locate a Which of these two measures is more appropri- comparable survey of experts at another time period ate depends, of course, on whatever theory we that asks the appropriate left-right question. might have about how policy-making goes on 31. Some readers may be troubled by the absence of within the government. As we shall see, however, electoral laws from the analysis. Clearly the electoral the results for both measures are quite similar.40 law of a given political system shapes many features of electoral competition and government formation that are important to this study, including the e¤ective identifiability is high because of the formation of pre- number of parties, proportionality, identifiability, and election coalitions. As our analysis focuses on election- the election of single-party majorities. Nonetheless, specific characteristics of party competition, we do not for the purposes of this study, it would be di‰cult—if use the election laws directly to classify the various not wrongheaded—to categorize a country as either a political systems. However, analysis of the indirect Majority Control or Proportionate Influence system on impact of election laws on congruence under various the basis of its electoral laws. One problem is the di‰- conditions, through the features here examined, is an culty of developing an appropriate measure of electoral interesting topic for future research. laws because each one has unique features, with im- 38. Since the left-right scales have discrete boundaries portant di¤erences in aggregation rules and in district- between the di¤erent cells, we approximate the loca- ing. (For example, Spain and the Netherlands both tion of the median voter using a technique described in have proportional representation [pr], but the propor- Thomas H. Wonnacott and Ronald J. Wonnacott, In- tionality of electoral outcomes in Spain is much lower troductory Statistics for Business and Economics, 3d ed. than in the Netherlands, as shown in Table 6.3.) More (New York: John Wiley, 1984), 671. important for analysis, the nature of electoral compe- 40. The mean scores by country for Government Dis- tition varies over time within systems having the same tance I (II) are Australia 1.35 (1.35), Belgium .74 (.74), election law. In systems with single-member district Denmark 1.36 (1.46), France 1.96 (2.15), West Ger- pluralities, for example, if there is a minority govern- many 1.55 (1.81), Ireland .47 (.84), Italy .92 (1.24), ment at the time of an election, clarity of responsibility Netherlands .90 (.50), New Zealand .95 (.95), Sweden for past policy-making will be low. In systems with pr, 1.28 (1.17), Great Britain 2.39 (2.39), and Spain 1.94 to take another example, there are often cases in which (1.94). Representation 337

average government in the Majority Control and Comparing Congruence between Citizens and the Mixed system is over 1.5 points from the Governments in the Three Types of Systems median; the average government in the Propor- tional Influence system is about 1 point away. Table 6.5 shows the average distance scores for Even with so few cases, the di¤erence between the three types of systems using our two di¤erent the mean of the Proportionate Influence systems measures of the position of the government. The and the mean of the Majority Control systems is data show that the two measures of distance statistically significant at .05 (one-tailed test). work quite similarly. It is also clear that the In parentheses in table 6.5 we show the per- Majority Control and Mixed systems have centage of voters between the government and governments that are on average substantially the median citizen. This figure depends on both farther from the median voter than are govern- the absolute distance and the distribution of ments in the Proportionate Influence systems: the

Table 6.4 Characteristics for majority control, mixed, and proportionate influence systems 1968–87 (1978–85)a System type

Majority control: Mixed: France, Proportionate influence: Australia, Great Germany, Ireland, Belgium, Denmark, Britain, New Zealand Spain, Sweden Italy, Netherlands Electoral competition Identifiability 100 80 36 (100) (75) (45) Past government status .67 .17 0 (.80) (.06) (0) E¤ective no. of parties 2.2 3.1 5.1 (2.2) (3.0) (5.4) Election outcomes Percentage of elections won 95 66 7 by a single party or a (100) (58) (10) preelection coalition Proportionality 85 92 95 (83) (93) (96) Legislative bargaining Percentage of committee 0 60 80 systems that permit (0) (60) (80) opposition influence Number of elections 29 29 27 (5) (12) (10) a. The top number in each cell is for the period 1968–87. The figure in parentheses is for the period 1978–85 (the period for which we analyze congruence). The top number in the ‘‘Proportionality’’ row is calculated using the figures in Mackie and Rose, The International Almanac of Electoral History, 3d ed. (Washington, D.C.: CQ Press, 1991), 510, which are calculated using only the last election reported in their study. Chapter 6 338

Table 6.5 ence systems might result in governments that Congruence between government and citizen left-right are often farther away from the median voter. orientationsa But the converse is true. The reason for the System type poorer performance of the Majority Control systems is basically that the two main parties in Majority Proportional Britain and Australia are far from the median control Mixed influence (over 2 points) during the period of our study. Government 1.61 1.43 .96 The closer of the two large parties does come to Distance I (28%) (23%) (20%) power, but it is still rather extreme.41 In New Government 1.61 1.55 1.03 Zealand the Majority Control vision seems to Distance II (28%) (25%) (20%) work better; in fact both major parties are fairly N 5 16 17 close to the median (about 1 point). A similar problem is evident in the Mixed a. Government Distance I measures the di¤erence systems, although it is less theoretically surpris- between the weighted mean left-right position of the ing in the multiparty situations. A common pat- government and the left-right position of the median tern here is the formation of formal or informal voter. Government Distance II measures the di¤erence preelection coalitions that pit right against left. between the left-right position of the median party in the government coalition and the left-right position of These coalitions frequently fail to converge, but the median citizen. The numbers in parentheses give the one that gets a majority forms a govern- the percentage of voters between the government and ment without bargaining with the opposition. In the median citizen. Positions of the parties are taken France, especially, both major alternative gov- from Castles and Mair (fn. 10). ernments are very far from the median voter. In 1978 the winning conservative coalition was 2.75 from the median—the farthest in our sample. In voters on the left-right scale. If the voters were Germany, Spain, and Sweden, too, the alter- more dispersed in the Majority Control systems, natives are rather far apart, each around 1.5 for example, a larger distance might a¤ect the points from the median. Only in Ireland are both same number of voters as does a smaller distance of the two alternatives quite close to the median. in the Proportionate Influence systems. How- ever, we see the same pattern as in the absolute A Regression Analysis distances. The Majority Control systems find, on average, 28 percent of the electorate between the While the results in table 6.5 are interesting, it is government and the median, whereas the figures troubling that we have only five cases of pure are 23–25 percent in Mixed systems and 20 per- Majority Control elections. A regression analysis cent in the Proportionate Influence systems. can help us go beyond the typology to illuminate The advantage of the Proportionate Influence the contribution of various properties of political systems in o¤ering greater congruence between systems to the degree of congruence. . . . governments and voters is somewhat theoreti- cally unexpected. We expected that governments 41. In Britain the closest parties to the median voter in the Majority Control systems would be close were the Liberals in 1979 and the Alliance in 1983, but to the median as the direct result of party com- neither of these parties won as much as a quarter of the petition and voter choices (under either Down- votes, and both were heavily penalized by the election sian theory or some of the nonstrategic or laws. The Conservatives were somewhat closer to the partially strategic alternatives). We also expected median than was Labour, but both large parties were coalition bargaining in the Proportional Influ- rather far away. Representation 339

Table 6.6 Predicting distance between the median voter and the left-right position of the government (OLS model of Govern- ment Distance I and II) Dependent variable: Dependent variable: Government Distance I Government Distance II Independent Variablesa (1) (2) (3) (4) (5) (6) Identifiability of future government .010 — .009 .009 — .0073 (.003) (.003) (.003) (.0036) Past government status .52 — .54 .58 — .61 (.40) (.38) (.42) (.42) Majority or PEC wins election .17 — .29 .22 — .34 (.30) (.29) (.31) (.32) E¤ective number of parties — .131 .05 — .14 .08 (.070) (.07) (.07) (.08) Proportionality of electoral outcome — .047 .041 — .038 .036 (.021) (.020) (.021) (.021) Opposition influence in committees .27 .44 .07 .46 .28 .12 (.33) (.33) (.37) (.36) (.35) (.40) Intercept .95 5.79 4.83 1.27 5.19 4.78 (.36) (1.80) (1.88) (.38) (1.87) (2.03) N 383838383838 Adjusted R2 .20 .14 .26 .15 .11 .18 Standard error of the regression .65 .68 .63 .69 .71 .68 a. The independent variables are described in the text.

Table 6.6 gives the results of six ols regres- teristics move the government closer to the me- sions where the formation of a new government dian voter. . . . is the unit of analysis and the electoral and leg- . . . [W]hen all the variables are entered into islative characteristics described in table 6.4 are the model, the main variables from the Majority the independent variables.42 ... Control vision have a mixed e¤ect with identifi- The general conclusions from the first two ability of future governments harmful to con- regressions are clear: Majority Control charac- gruence; the variables from the Proportionate teristics have mixed e¤ects, which have the net Influence vision are helpful to congruence.43 The result of moving the government away from the median voter; Proportionate Influence charac- 43. Our findings regarding the Proportionate Influence variables are interesting when compared with empirical 42. Our theoretical discussion does not suggest what studies of budget deficits by political economists; for a the appropriate functional form should be, so we recent review of this literature, see Alberto Alesina and examined a wide variety of functional forms and a Guido Tabellini, ‘‘Positive and Normative Theories of simple linear relationship turned out to be the most Public Debt and Inflation in Historical Perspectives,’’ appropriate for each variable. European Economic Review 36 (April 1992). Roubini Chapter 6 340

regression analysis therefore supports and clari- Table 6.7 fies the simple comparison of system types. De- Congruence between policymakers and citizen left- spite the plausibility of Downsian theory and right orientationsa some of the other formulations of majoritarian System type democracy that predict congruence, when there exist clearly identifiable future governments at Majority Proportionate control Mixed influence election time, the elected governments tend to be far from the median voter. And despite concerns Policymaker 1.17 1.03 .50 about government formation processes, as the Distance I (22%) (18%) (10%) e¤ective number of parties and proportionality Policymaker 1.17 1.15 .59 of electoral outcomes increase, congruence in- Distance II (22%) (20%) (12%) creases. In fact, this congruence is best when parties do not undertake preelection commit- a. For Policymaker Distance I and Policymaker Dis- ments that may lead to the formation of minor- tance II, a party’s weight is determined by whether it is a government party, a support party, or an opposition ity governments. To put the comparison between party. Policymaker Distance I uses the same measure the two types of systems another way, on aver- as Government Distance I to calculate the position of age the failures of electoral competition in the the government. Policymaker Distance II uses the same Majority Control (and Mixed) systems seem measure as Government Distance II to calculate the more serious for congruence than does the failure position of the government. Further details are in the of government formation in the Proportionate text and the appendix. The numbers in parentheses give Influence systems. . . . the percentage of citizens between the Policymakers and the median citizens.

Citizens, Policymakers, and Ideological Congruence in linking policy-making and voters must look beyond the parties that formally share govern- Governments in parliamentary systems are not ment responsibility. . . . totally uninfluenced by the opposition in making policy, and the Majority Control and Propor- Comparing Congruence between Citizens and tionate Influence visions make di¤erent predic- Policymakers in the Three Types of Systems tions about how the role of opposition parties should a¤ect congruence. Consequently, an ex- Table 6.7 compares the distance between policy- ploration of the e¤ectiveness of the two visions makers and the citizen median in the three types of systems...... Most strikingly, congruence improves in all and Sachs, for example, find that systems with a high 48 incidence of coalition and minority governments have three types of systems. Across all thirty-eight relatively large levels of public debt; Roubini and governments, the average distance between the Sachs, ‘‘Political and Economic Determinants of Bud- median voter and the government was about 1.3; get Deficits in the Industrial Democracies,’’ European the average distance between the median voter Economic Review 33 (May 1989). Since the central characteristics of Proportionate Influence systems lead 48. Congruence of policymakers was not greater than to coalition and minority governments, it appears that that of governments in every case, however. It is not a system characteristics which improve congruence be- tautology. In eight of the thirty-eight cases the congru- tween governments and citizens may also be associated ence was less for policymakers on at least one of the with large budget deficits. We are grateful to Bill Keech two measures, although the di¤erences are usually not for pointing this out to us. very large. Representation 341

and the weighted policymakers was about .85. would reveal majoritarian electoral competition This decrease was of approximately the same in which the parties are not so extreme and pro- magnitude for all three types of systems. This portionate influence bargaining is less centrist. does not mean, however, that oppositions are Moreover, we are well aware that the ‘‘commit- closer to the voters than are the governments. ments’’ of governments and their actual policy They are not. Rather, it means that as long as we outcomes are not necessarily the same. This dif- continue to weight the governments more heav- ference would be especially troubling for our re- ily than the oppositions in our estimate of policy- sults if policies diverged further from promises in making, more congruence is created by giving the Proportionate Influence systems than in the the oppositions some weight than by leaving Majoritarian ones. The di‰culty of identifying them out of the process. . . . clear responsibility for policy in the former cre- ates prima facie grounds for concern. Regression Analysis With these caveats said, the results of our analysis seem clear and consistent. In the simple Since the results from table 6.7 are interesting comparison, contrary to our expectations from and somewhat unexpected, it is useful to analyze the theoretical arguments about creating con- further the relationship between the system gruence connections in each approach, the gov- characteristics and the policymaker variables ernments in the Proportionate Influence systems using multivariate regressions. . . . are on average significantly closer to their me- The regression results help interpret and sup- dian voter than are governments in the Majority port the results of the simple comparison of Control and Mixed systems. The regression system types. The policymaker measures show analysis reassures us on this point. If voters are reduced distances in all types of systems. How- presented with two clear alternatives (parties or ever, the Proportionate Influence systems still preelection coalitions), these alternatives—and show a substantial advantage. Identifiability in resulting governments—tend to be rather distant electoral competition remains costly, although from the median voter. If voters are presented the cost is not as great in absolute terms after we with a wide range of choices and electoral out- upweight opposition influence on policy-making. comes are proportional, governments tend to be Poor proportionality in representation remains closer to the median. It is reassuring that the highly costly. Single-party majority incumbents regression results are supportive because they before the election seem to be helpful. Yet mul- allow us to take advantage of the mixture of tiparty systems also remain somewhat helpful, properties in the Mixed systems, rather than as does opposition influence. The net congru- relying solely on the number of pure Majority ence advantage is to the Proportionate Influence Control cases. vision. Our analysis of policymakers, although neces- sarily more speculative because of the weighting problem, is also illuminating because the results Concluding Comments in part run counter to our initial theoretical ex- pectations. Taking some account of opposition We have attempted to being into more precise influence helped congruence with voters in virtu- focus two general visions of the processes that ally all the systems, with surprisingly large e¤ects link citizens and policymakers in contemporary in the Majority Control and Mixed systems. democracies. We should stress that the gener- However, the net advantage remained with the ality of our results is constrained by our research Proportionate Influence systems, which gained design: it may be that a di¤erent slice of time congruence, especially because of the strong Chapter 6 342

weighting of the opposition parties during mi- nority government and because these systems usually permit more opposition influence in committees. The results with respect to Majority Control, and more generally with respect to high identifi- ability, raise an important additional question about policy-making. We examine congruence on a government-by-government basis, and do not have a long enough time span to take aver- ages of the governments over several decades. Hence, although each government in Britain and Australia may be quite distant from the median voter, the average position over time might be much closer to the center. Of course, the long predominance of such governments as the Con- servatives in Britain from 1979 to the present (or the conservative coalition in France from 1958 to 1981) may imply that this oscillation does not redress the balance very quickly (or at all). The appropriate time frame for congruence is an important issue for future research. The rela- tionships between congruence and other features of democratic government frequently proposed as desirable (stability, e‰ciency, responsibility) remain another rich area for exploration. The consideration of these questions reminds us again of the challenging empirical, theoretical, and normative issues associated with the study of congruence. For this reason, we see the current results as a contribution, not a conclusion, to our understanding of the fascinating problem of the electoral connection between citizens and policymakers. . . . The Political Consequences of Electoral Laws

Douglas W. Rae

Variations of Degree The proportionality of seat allocation also varies with the number of seats assigned to elec- The degree to which seat allocations diverge toral districts—district magnitudes. Where many from the condition of perfect proportionality is a seats are allocated in each electoral district, the function of two electoral law variables: (1) elec- outcome is likely to approximate proportion- toral formulae, and (2) district magnitudes. As a ality.14 But where fewer seats are allocated in rule, P.R. formulae and high district magnitudes each district, outcomes are likely to diverge more produce more nearly proportional results, while sharply from proportionality.15 This relation- ‘‘first-past-the-post’’ formulae and low district ship is, however, curvilinear: as district magni- magnitudes produce the greatest disproportion- tudes increase, disproportionality decreases at a ality (i.e. the greatest advantage for large parties decreasing rate.16 Another way to put the same over small ones). Let me consider the two elec- thing is: as district magnitude increases, the pro- toral law variables individually, beginning with portionality of outcome increases at a decreasing the electoral formulae. rate.17 One need not be surprised that the bonus Electoral formulae diverge from proportion- obtained by the strongest party declines as dis- ality along two institutional dimensions. First, trict magnitude rises.18 proportional representation formulae produce Since plurality formulae are always associated smaller deviations from proportionality than with a single-member district, it is hard to dis- ‘‘first-past-the-post’’ formulae, whether the latter tinguish the disproportionality of these formulae are based on pluralities or majorities.9 Second, from that of the single-member district’s low highest averages P.R. formulae diverge farther magnitude. Indeed the distinction has no em- from proportionality than largest remainder P.R. pirical meaning, except in the Australian case, formulae.10 The first di¤erence—between P.R. where a majority formula is associated with a and ‘‘first-past-the-post’’ formulae—is by far the single-member district. greater of the two. Given that the defractionalization pattern, It follows that P.R. formulae are likely to which works in favor of fewer, stronger legisla- minimize (but not to eradicate) the general bias tive parties, is a general fact of electoral life, it of electoral formulae in favor of strong parties. is also evident that specific institutions pro- P.R. formulae give a smaller advantage to the duce variations of degree within the pattern. Po- strong elective parties and exact a smaller price litical ingenuity can render the defractionalizing from weak ones.11 They give a smaller bonus to pattern stronger or weaker through the ma- the strongest single elective party.12 And, natu- nipulation of the institutional variables: electoral rally enough, they are less apt to deny represen- formulae and district magnitudes. tation to elective parties.13 Suppose one wanted to design an electoral law that would maximize the defractionalizing Excerpted from: Douglas W. Rae, The Political Con- sequences of Electoral Laws, revised edition. New 13. Di¤erential Proposition Five. Haven: Yale University Press, 1971. Reprinted by 14. Di¤erential Proposition Ten. permission. 15. Di¤erential Proposition Ten. 9. Di¤erential Proposition Four. 16. Di¤erential Proposition Eleven. 10. Di¤erential Proposition Nine. 17. Di¤erential Proposition Eleven. 11. Di¤erential Proposition One. 18. Di¤erential Proposition Thirteen. 12. Di¤erential Proposition Two. Chapter 6 344

pattern, producing strong advantages for strong tems are influenced by many variables—social, parties, strong penalties for weak ones, and economic, legal, and political. Proximal e¤ect of often ‘‘manufacturing’’ legislative majorities. electoral law upon the legislative representation The findings of this study suggest that the single- of parties is to be counted only one of many member district is the only necessary instrument. determining forces. And it is, secondly, impos- With these very low district magnitudes, the ad- sible to sort out all the contributing factors, or vantage of strong parties will be maximized, no to assign even approximate weights to them. matter what formula is used. Plurality and ma- Worse yet, electoral laws are themselves shaped jority formulae will behave in the same way, by party systems. defractionalizing legislative party systems by In the face of these di‰culties, one can only favoring fewer stronger parties. For that matter, suggest limited connections. I have chosen to even P.R. formulae would have the same e¤ect formulate my commentary in response to the in single-member districts. Because only one question: ‘‘Where electoral laws do in fact make party can win in each district, the strong parties a long-run di¤erence, which specific properties of benefit at the expense of the weak ones, and leg- electoral laws are apt to produce what di¤er- islative party systems are composed of fewer, ences?’’ By choosing to work within the assump- stronger parties.19 tion that electoral laws do exert long-run e¤ects, Suppose, on the other hand, that one were yet without demonstrating this assumption’s va- worried about proportionality, and wished lidity, I have settled for a very limited level of therefore to minimize defractionalization, giving analysis. But to do more would require not one, each party its electoral due—no more and no but twenty or more, developmental studies, each less. Given these objectives, he should insist on devoted to a single country. The limited sugges- a P.R. formula, preferably based on the largest tions o¤ered here may provide some guidelines remainder procedure, linked with high district for research of that kind, and may have at least magnitudes (i.e. many seats per district). It would tentative significance in their own right. probably not be worthwhile to expand the dis- Party systems vary over a continuum, from tricts beyond ten or twenty seats, since the added non-fractionalization in one-party systems to ex- proportionality seems to decline rapidly beyond treme fractionalization in systems where a great that level. But with very low district magnitudes many parties compete on about equal terms. (i.e. less than six seats per district), even the Among the party systems analyzed in this study, largest remainder P.R. formula would produce a the actual range of variation lies between two very substantial defractionalizing e¤ect. less distant points: U.S.-style, two-party compe- tition and Israeli-type multi-partism. Every party system, at any one point in time, may be as- Distal Consequences of Electoral Laws signed a place on this continuum, although (and this is important) individual systems may move Do the short-run e¤ects we have been discussing along these scales, toward or away from the em- have long-run consequences for party systems? pirical extreme of two-party competition. What are they? These questions can be answered How do electoral systems influence the move- only with considerable caution, since party sys- ment of systems on the fractionalization con- tinuum? I wish to suggest that the pattern of 19. This assertion must be modified where parties proximal defractionalization described above is which are weak on a national scale enjoy pockets of the source of whatever influence electoral laws local support, enabling them to profit from the single- have on the fractionalization of party systems. member district in those areas. Representation 345

Where the pattern is strong—large parties are What electoral law provisions intensify the greatly advantaged—the electoral system exerts defractionalizing pattern and therefore seem pressure on the system for two-party competi- likely to exert pressure toward two-party tion. But where the pattern is weak—large competition? The answer is simple: the single- parties are only slightly advantaged—a weaker, member district, or, failing that, small multi- often negligible, pressure is exerted in that direc- member districts. In a single-member district, tion. The defractionalizing pattern is a restraint almost any formula21—the plurality is most on the fractionalization of party systems, and the common—is likely to advantage the strong e¤ective pressure exerted by electoral laws varies parties and, in general, to establish the defrac- with the intensity of the defractionalizing pattern tionalizing pattern. This much is confirmed by itself. Multi-partism is most likely where elec- the analysis of proximal e¤ects. But what about toral laws produce a weak defractionalizing the long-range e¤ects? The findings of the study pattern, and two-party competition most likely show a fairly consistent association between where the electoral laws produce a strong single-member plurality formulae and two-party defractionalizing e¤ect. systems.22 Now, according to my earlier comments, the A causal interpretation of this association falls defractionalizing pattern is complex. It entails at upon several exceptions, the clearest of which are least five related subpatterns: (1) the advantage Canadian and Austrian. Nevertheless, the com- of large parties over small ones in the division of bination of the proximal defracationalizing pat- legislative seats; (2) the awarding of a ‘‘bonus’’ in tern and the distal association with two-party seats to the strongest party; (3) the exclusion of competition suggests that the single-member dis- small parties from the legislative arena; (4) the trict is likely to contribute to the development overall defractionalization of legislative party and sustenance of two-party systems. Other fac- systems; and (5) the fairly frequent creation of tors, such as regional minorities, may reverse this ‘‘manufactured majorities’’ in legislative party condition, as is the case in Canada. But, insofar systems. These are the subpatterns present in as the electoral law exerts a controlling pressure, all electoral systems, but stronger in some than the single-member district is likely to press the others, which constitute the defractionalizing system toward two-party competition. process that seems so important. The question And what arrangements are most likely to thus becomes, ‘‘What electoral law variables press party systems toward multi-partism, be- produce this syndrome?’’ cause they exert a very weak defractionalizing The answer to this question was foretold in the e¤ect? These would be the institutions that examination of proximal e¤ects. Here let me re- optimize the proportionality of outcomes: largest capitulate the e¤ects of these institutions, with remainder P.R. formulae, operating in high attention to the contribution they make to the magnitude electoral districts. Because the out- shaping of party systems over time. Logically, comes are more nearly proportional under the sequence of inferences is: (a) electoral law these provisions, the defractionalizing process is variables to intensity of the defractionalizing weakened. Is there an association between these pattern, and, with less confidence, (b) the inten- arrangements and multi-partism? The study’s sity of the defractionalizing pattern to the long- findings show that there is: run fractionalization of the party system.20 21. The French double ballot may be an exception, 20. A third inference is from the degree to which an although limited evidence suggests that it is not. electoral system is presently fractionalized to the kind 22. Di¤erential Proposition Three and Similarity of electoral laws adopted for future elections. Proposition Seven. Chapter 6 346

1. In general, P.R. formulae are associated with Election Outcomes and Government Stability more fractionalized elective and parliamentary party systems.23 It is generally supposed that election outcomes— 2. Among P.R. formula electoral laws, those allocations of seats among parties—quite di- using the largest-remainder procedure are asso- rectly determine which party or coalition will ciated with greater fractionalization, both elec- control a parliamentary government. So, for ex- tive and parliamentary, than are those using ample, one of our most sophisticated accounts highest-average procedures.24 holds out these conditions for representative de- mocracy: ‘‘A single party (or coalition of parties) 3. High district magnitudes are associated with is chosen by popular election to run the govern- greater fractionalization in both elective and ing apparatus,’’ and ‘‘Any party (or coalition parliamentary systems.25 of parties) receiving the support of a majority of The distal association between these institu- those voting is entitled to take over the powers tions and high fractionalization, even when seen of government until the next election.’’16 It is beside the weakness of the proximal defraction- revealing that these requirements, most obvi- alizing pattern which they produce, does not ously the second, lead to logical contradictions suggest a simple causal relationship. It does, and must therefore be violated by any empirical however, imply that insofar as the electoral law system of parliamentary politics. Since this logi- exerts a controlling pressure, these provisions are cal di‰culty carries our attention toward an apt to press systems toward multi-partism and important empirical question, let me begin by away from two-party competition. examining it briefly. These conclusions suggest that the statesman During a campaign, we have ne parties. Before who must choose between electoral laws con- the electorate decides, one can imagine that e fronts a dilemma. On the one hand, he may opt any of 2n 1 parties or coalitions might com- for highly proportional election outcomes, in mand majorities and form a government. Thus, which case he is likely to encourage the frac- tionalization of party systems over time. Or, on since all of the systems, save Germany and Israel, had the other hand, he may opt to encourage the de- been in operation for many decades before the period velopment and maintenance of two parties, or covered by this study. Historical analyses of the indi- less fractionalized multi-party competition, with vidual systems would be of interest. I must conclude the price being less proportional outcomes. that association, but not sequential data, support my speculations. These alternatives may not be inevitable, but the findings reported here make them seem proba- 16. Anthony Downs, An Economic Theory of Democ- racy (New York: Harper & Row, 1957) pp. 23–24. A ble: if proportionality, then multi-partism; but if related but less clearcut di‰culty arises in Robert two-party competition, then also a dispropor- Dahl’s notion of polyarchy, when it is required that 26 tional outcome. ... alternatives with more votes replace alternatives with fewer. See A Preface to Democratic Theory (Chicago: 23. Di¤erential Proposition Six. University of Chicago Press, 1956), Chap. 3. In both 24. Di¤erential Proposition Nine. cases, the problem arises, I think, because the authors are thinking primarily about two-party systems and 25. Di¤erential Proposition Twelve. only secondarily about multiparty systems. In Dahl’s 26. The time-sequence data for the twenty-year period analysis the requirement is stated as an ideal, but in I have studied do not produce clinching evidence for Downs’s it is treated (incorrectly) as a feature which these speculations: except for West Germany, there is ‘‘in practice’’ distinguishes democracy from other no system which changes drastically in its degree of forms. fractionalization. But that is not altogether surprising, Representation 347

with three electoral parties one can imagine the possible governments include AB, AC, BC, 23 1 ¼ 7 conceivable governments (e.g. A, B, and ABC. This is a more than technical violation C, AB, AC, BC, ABC.) According to ‘‘common of Downs’s requirement, for it leaves an open set sense’’ and Downs’s stipulations, the election of potential governments (and, significantly, a outcome should reduce this set of possibilities to choice of potential alternatives to any govern- one, the party or coalition which commands a ment that forms). majority. But if more than one party wins repre- A useful example is o¤ered by the 1963 elec- sentation, this cannot be literally true. If np tion of the Icelandic parliament (the Althingi). parties win representation, the election outcome The Independence Party obtained 24 seats, the must leave open the possibility of exactly 2np1 Progressives 19, the Communists 8, and the Social distinct majority governments. The e¤ect of an Democrats 7. With four electoral parties, one election outcome is thus to reduce the set of po- might have imagined 24 1 ¼ 15 possible gov- tential majority governments without ‘‘picking’’ ernments, and (since no party was denied repre- a single government. If, for example, three sentation) the outcome simply restricts this to a parties win representation, then exactly 231 ¼ 4 subset of 241 ¼ 8 groupings that command possible governments must remain no matter how majorities and could conceivably form govern- seats are divided among these parties. And this ments. To each of these, there naturally corre- implies that both of Downs’s requirements are sponds a potential set of opposition parties: unrealizable: the election itself cannot pick a party or coalition to govern, and some parties or Possible coalitions holding majorities must inevitably be Possible Government Opposition np1 denied control of government (e.g. 2 ¼ 1). 1. Ind, Prog, Com, SD nil This very formal di‰culty is not without its rel- 2. Ind, Prog, Com SD evance to experience. 3. Ind, Prog, SD Com If a single party wins a majority of its own, the 4. Prog, Com, SD Ind di‰culty is merely technical. Say that A holds a 5. Ind, Com, SD Prog majority over B and C. It is still true that the 6. Ind, SD Prog, Com election permits four possible governments (A, 7. Ind, Prog SD, Com AB, AC, ABC) but there are compelling reasons 8. Ind, Com Prog, SD to presume that one will be chosen (A). In this event, we need only add the stipulation that po- The election itself comes to a very partial ar- tential governments with inessential members bitration of the question ‘‘Who governs?’’ Only (AB, AC, ABC, in our example) may be ignored. seven of the fifteen otherwise conceivable gov- One might suppose that the problem could thus ernments have been eliminated, leaving eight be reduced to a linguistic quibble were it not for possibilities. Each party is a member of at least the fact that about two-thirds of all parliamen- five such possible governments, and no party tary elections fail to produce single-party ma- belongs to all eight. The e¤ective choice must jorities (of 107 elections analyzed in the original therefore rest with party leaders as they are study, only 8 produced natural majorities, 25 influenced by conflicts and compatibilities of produced manufactured majorities, and the re- program, ideology, or personality in the forma- maining 74 produced neither). Thus a more typ- tion of coalitions. It is a choice bounded but left ical case occurs when no single party holds a undecided by the election outcome. As it hap- majority and one is left without an obvious pens, government 6 (Independence–Social Dem- choice of govenment. Thus, if A, B, and C each ocrat) was formed in 1963, but roughly similar have less than half the seats in a parliament, then outcomes have since World War II, also led Chapter 6 348

to the formation of governments 3, 4, and 7.17 so, then there will be a convergence of strong Unless the process of government formation is motives and wide opportunities for changes of understood by the electorate, this surely raises government in such systems. important di‰culties for theories of electoral Unhappily, none of these conjectures can be representation, for it is impossible to see how the mistaken for a theory. And, although coalition citizen could draw useful associations between behavior has been the object of intensive study in his voting decision and the eventual choice of a recent years, research on the specific question of government.18 stability remains inconclusive. We do, however, Parliaments that are fractionalized enough to have a useful exploration of several common- produce these uncertainties19 would seem espe- sense hypotheses in a recent study by Michael cially prone to government instability, for at Taylor and V. M. Herman.20 These authors least two reasons. First, their numerical struc- considered 196 governments in 19 countries tures o¤er wide opportunity for the destruction of (those studied here, minus the U.S. and Switzer- governments. With more than one party-elite in a land, plus Japan) from the end of World War II government, it is possible to reach a vote of no up to 1969. They define ‘‘government stability’’ confidence even without a breach of party disci- in calendar days elapsed without a change of pline. And, as the number of essential partners prime minister or party support.21 Their study is increases, one might expect an actuarial increase an e¤ort to treat variation in stability as a func- in the frequency with which a particular decision tion of the parliamentary party system variables alienates a member party, bringing a new elec- discussed here. The most straightforward of their tion or a change of governments without one. results are these. Moreover, since only one of 2np1 possible gov- ernments has been formed, it seems probable Product-Moment that member parties could, at some point, iden- Correlation with tify alternative partners with whom a more at- Government tractive government could be formed. These Independent Variable Stability reasons are very roughly analogous to the struc- (1) Number of parliamentary –.39 tural relations outlined for partisan insurgency parties (np) earlier, although their interconnections are less (2) Fractionalization of –.448 clear. A second reason points toward the like- parliamentary parties (Fp) lihood that highly fractionalized parliaments (3) Number of parties in –.307 are indices of intense political conflict. If this is government (4) Proportion of seats held –.450 17. Nils Andrain. by anti-system parties 18. See Downs, pp. 142–63 for a discussion of these di‰culties. In Thomas Casstevens, ‘‘An Axiom About These results tend to confirm the intuitive Voting,’’ American Political Science Review, 62 (1968), expectations sketched out above, but they do not 205–07, an attempt is made to show that (on a sim- include the most plausible explanation turned plistic assumption about ‘‘winning’’ and a vitiating as- sumption about the probabilities of parties doing so) the voter should always just vote for his most preferred 20. ‘‘Party Systems and Government Stability,’’ party. American Political Science Review, 65 (1971), 28–37. 19. If parliamentary fractionalization reaches .5, there 21. In this, they follow an earlier study, , may be no single-party solution, and if it reaches .75, ‘‘Party Systems and Patterns of Government in West- there cannot possibly be such a solution. ern Democracies,’’ Canadian Journal of Political Science, 1 (1968), 180–203. Representation 349

up by the Taylor-Herman study. It is inter- esting that their e¤ort to include ideological distances in the notion of fractionalization actu- ally weakened its relationship to instability (to .417.) But the related distinction between anti- system and pro-system parties nevertheless proved highly interesting (variable 4 above.) Their best explanation turns on the joint e¤ect of ‘‘proportion anti-system’’ and the fractionaliza- tion of seats among the remaining parties. Using these two variables in a multiple regression esti- mate they find a fit of R ¼ .496. Ironically, the estimate is improved slightly (R ¼ .506) if right- wing anti-system seats are dropped, leaving only communist seats in the proportion anti-system. The apparent explanation for this account is that, if anti-system parties always refuse to sup- port governments, the proportion of available votes required is increased (being r/2(r a) where r is the parliament’s size and a is the size of the anti-system contingent). The e¤ective de- cision rule for sustaining governments thus grows more restrictive with increases in anti- system representation (or communists) and is less easily met as remaining seats grow more frac- tionalized. This seems, at any rate, the most plausible conjecture. Although this section is less developed ana- lytically than its predecessor, its tendence is similar—to suggest complexity of interconnec- tion. I will not attempt to draw all of these connections together here, but finish with the conjecture that this analysis concerns itself with only a few fragments of the immeasurably more complex pattern by which ruling groups, as they are sustained and replaced over time, leave their marks on publics and the policies by which they are governed. South Africa’s Negotiated Transition: Democracy, Opposition, and the New Constitutional Order

Courtney Jung and Ian Shapiro

In 1965, Robert Dahl remarked that ‘‘of the association as well as the presence of institutions three great milestones in the development of and practices that make it possible for counter- democratic institutions—the right to participate elites to organize and inform themselves so as to in governmental decisions by casting a vote, the be able to contest for power. . . . If the opposition right to be represented, and the right of an is not thus perceived, then the possibility of organized opposition to appeal for votes against turnover is diminished and crises for the govern- the government in elections and in parliament— ment are correspondingly more likely to become the last is, in a highly developed form, so wholly crises for the democratic regime. modern that there are people now living who This suggests a second reason why opposi- were born before it had appeared in most of tion institutions matter: for the legitimacy of the Western Europe.’’7 He might perhaps have democratic political order. Providing the institu- added that opposition is also the milestone that tional space for opposition is essential for ensur- has been least studied by contemporary political ing that discontent and dissatisfaction can be scientists. . . . directed at particular governments rather than at Although the notion of a loyal opposition the democratic regime itself . . . Unless there are finds its origins in monarchical rather than dem- such institutional outlets for dissent within the ocratic politics, democratic systems rely on insti- regime’s institutions, those who are discontented tutionalized oppositions, and it is doubtful that with the status quo may not even distinguish the any regime could long survive as minimally government from the regime, undermining the democratic without them.10 possibility of the ebb and flow of competitive This is true for at least three related reasons. party politics that democracies require. . . . The first is functional, having to do with the Last, institutional arrangements that facili- peaceful turnover of power by governments that tate loyal opposition perform important public- lose elections. . . . If democratic politics is seen interest functions in democracies. They are as requiring at a minimum that there be turnover necessary to ensure the presence of healthy po- of power among elites, then there must be sites litical debate. They encourage competition over for counterelites to form and campaign as po- ideas among elites and counterelites, and this tential alternative governments. Such opposition leads to demands for reason giving and coher- requires the permissive freedoms of speech and ence in public debate. Moreover, opposition institutions empower groups and individuals Excerpted from: Courtney Jung and Ian Shapiro, who have an interest in asking awkward ques- ‘‘South Africa’s Negotiated Transition: Democracy, tions, shining light in dark places, and exposing Opposition, and the New Constitutional Order.’’ Poli- abuses of power. Without an organized political tics and Society 23(3): 269–308. 6 1995 Sage Pub- opposition that has rights to information and lications, Inc. Reprinted by permission of Sage other resources, governing in secret becomes all Publications, Inc. too tempting for the administration of the day. 7. Robert A. Dahl, Political Opposition in Western Governments always have incentives to cam- Democracies (New Haven: Yale University Press, ouflage mistakes or controversial decisions that 1965), p. xiii. might otherwise threaten their popularity and 10. Barrington Moore, Jr., Liberal Prospects under to misuse the perquisites of o‰ce. Unless their Soviet Socialism: A Comparative Historical Perspective members know that they can be called to public (New York: Averell Harriman Institute, 1989), pp. 8, account for their actions, the temptation to act 25. . . . Representation 351

on these incentives will in many cases prove vided along ethnic lines, if democracy can be irresistible. realized at all it will be only if the e¤ects of ma- jority rule are mitigated by institutional devices of this sort. The assumption is that ethnic divi- II. The Opposition/Nonopposition Continuum sions so completely overdetermine other con- flicts, and that they are so intense and enduring Although the principal alternative to democratic (if not primordial), that the only viable institu- systems that institutionalize opposition may be tional recipe is one that is designed to minimize authoritarian systems that repress it, many sys- political competition and keep the groups from tems of government are designed to channel dis- getting at one anothers’ throats. sent and opposition away from national political Consociational systems undermine the func- institutions and otherwise to di¤use it. Such sys- tional, legitimacy-generating, and public-interest tems are usually defended on the grounds that roles of opposition discussed in section I. With disagreements in the society in question are so regard to the first, consociational systems are not potentially explosive that anything else will re- designed to foster alternation of major parties in sult in the war of all against all. Many ortho- power. Instead, they permit the same combina- dox prescriptions for ‘‘divided’’ societies—those tion of elites to entrench themselves at the peaks in which unbridgeable divisions among the of spoils and patronage hierarchies more or less population are thought to preclude pluralist continuously. The democratic benefits that can politics—take this form. Perhaps the best known accrue from ‘‘tossing the rascals out’’ are there- of these is Lijphart’s consociational model of fore unavailable. On the legitimacy front, be- minority vetoes and enforced coalitions, which cause consociational arrangements ensure that might be thought of as occupying a position at every major political player is part of the gov- the far end of a continuum from the opposition ernment, there is little basis for the disa¤ected to model just sketched.13 di¤erentiate the government from the regime. It Consociational models of democracy empha- is hard for an ethos of loyal opposition to de- size participation and representation to the vir- velop when there is no institutional outlet.15 tual exclusion of opposition. Their organizing Those who are not in government are removed principles are proportionality in the electoral from politics altogether, making it more likely system, an institutional structure that forces that they will turn to extra-institutional politics if power sharing and a system of mutual vetoes they can. With regard to the public-interest role among ‘‘a cartel of elites,’’14 and a predisposi- of opposition politics, consociational systems do tion toward robust federalism to insulate ter- not give powerful parliamentary players incen- ritorially based minorities from the power of tives to keep government honest by shining light whoever controls national political institutions. in dark corners. Because consociational systems Advocates of consociational democracy contend require high levels of consensus among governing that particularly when societies are deeply di- 15. This insight is at the core of Horowitz’s critique of 13. See Arend Lijphart, Democracy in Plural Societies consociational systems: that the very circumstances in (New Haven: Yale University Press, 1977), and Power- which they are most needed—when there are powerful Sharing in South Africa (Berkeley: University of Cali- divisions in the society—are the circumstances when fornia Institute of International Studies, 1985). they are also least likely to be e¤ective; see Donald L. 14. Arend Lijphart, ‘‘Consociational Democracy,’’ Horowitz, A Democratic South Africa? Constitutional World Politics 4, no. 2 (January 1969), pp. 213–215, Engineering in a Divided Society (Berkeley: University 222. of California Press, 1991), pp. 142–143. Chapter 6 352

elites, the only way for anyone in the governing tionalization, particularly when constituencies elite to get her way on issues that matter in- are large and thresholds are low,17 uncon- tensely to her is to give other powerful players strained proportional representation makes par- what they want on issues that matter intensely liamentary structure unpredictable. In certain to them. Therefore, mutual vetoes can be ex- circumstances it may produce strong opposition pected to lead to mutual logrolling, rather than coalitions and alternation in government, as is to political confrontations among elites, and to sometimes the case in Israel and The Nether- promote insider clubism. By the same token, lands. In other circumstances, such as Austria logrolling minimizes the likelihood that govern- and Switzerland, the major parties will often ment elites will be called to account by members govern in coalition. Given the unpredictability of of potential alternative governments. In short, unconstrained proportional representation ver- consociational systems, based on the politics of sus the predictability of first-past-the-post plu- elite coalitions, maximize both representation rality systems in generating two-party politics, and participation in government, but at the price one would not choose the former over the latter of almost complete abandonment of a viable if the goal was to produce oppositional rather opposition politics. than consociational parliamentary politics. The position of a regime along the opposition/ Whether a system is presidential or parlia- nonopposition continuum depends on the elec- mentary also a¤ects the prospects for institu- toral system and on the divisions of power within tionalized opposition. Parliamentary systems the legislature and between the legislature and link the fortunes of the executive to those of the the executive. First-past-the-post electoral sys- majority party in parliament, so that institution- tems based on single-member districts are likely alized opposition is apt to be centered in the to produce two-party systems and, as a result, legislature. In presidential systems, significant strong parliamentary oppositions.16 These op- opposition may occur between the executive and positions may or may not have the potential to the legislature, depending on the powers of the become alternative governments (depending on presidency (e.g., whether they include the power their potential grass roots support). Nonetheless, to appoint a cabinet or to conduct some a¤airs they will have an interest in becoming magnets unilaterally) and the interactions between the for antigovernment sentiment, which should give electoral rules for parliament and presidency. them incentives to perform at least some of the An electoral system that produces a govern- conventional functions of loyal oppositions: ment consisting of all the powerful players in the organizing and channeling dissent, disseminating legislature is likely to weaken the presidency, information, and exposing government corrup- reducing the president, in the limiting case, to a tion. Thus although two-party–dominated plu- figurehead. If the president’s party is a minority rality systems have high barriers to entry and are comparatively unrepresentative, they pro- 17. Arend Lijphart, Electoral Systems and Party Sys- duce significant institutionalized opposition. tems (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1994). Rae Things will be less predictable in multiparty suggests that with proportional representation, small systems dependent on coalition governments. and medium-sized constituencies and higher thresholds Given the well-documented propensity of pro- combine to limit fractionalization and give parties portional representation to produce party frac- incentives to form blocs, whether in government or opposition. In e¤ect the constraints make multiparty systems operate more like two-party systems: see 16. Douglas W. Rae, The Political Consequences of Douglas W. Rae ‘‘Using District Magnitude to Regu- Electoral Laws (New Haven: Yale University Press, late Political Party Competition,’’ Journal of Economic 1967). Perspectives 9, no. 1 (winter 1995), pp. 65–75. Representation 353

in the legislature, as is often the case in Brazil for instance, he has to seek support from the major- ity (opposition) party to avoid governmental paralysis. This type of system tends closely to approximate a power-sharing type of arrange- ment. If, however, the constitution confers sub- stantial autonomous power on the president, as it does in the United States, the president may be an institutional figure to be reckoned with even if his party is a minority in the legislature. For presidential systems to be relatively close to the opposition end of the continuum in virtue of their presidentialism, then, either presidents must be institutionally powerful or there must be sig- nificant minority parties in the legislature with which they can ally themselves. As the latter is less predictably so in proportional representa- tion systems, it is less predictably the case in presidential proportional representation sys- tems. Perhaps for this reason, observers have noticed a coincidence of presidential propor- tional representation systems and power-sharing governments.18 ...

18. Scott Mainwaring, ‘‘Presidentialism, Multiparty Systems, and Democracy: The Di‰cult Equation,’’ Comparative Political Studies 26, no. 2 (1993), pp. 198–230; Arend Lijphart, ‘‘Democratization and Con- stitutional Choices in Czechoslovakia, Hungary, and Poland, 1989–1991,’’ Journal of Theoretical Politics 4, no. 2 (1993), p. 209. The Representation of Women

Anne Phillips

In the countries that lay claim to the title of de- as a shock: only forty-three women out of 650 mocracy, women have enjoyed many decades of members of the British parliament? Only twenty- formal equality, sharing with men the right to eight women out of 435 members of the US vote, to stand in elections, to compete for any House of Representatives? What kind of democ- o‰ce (political—not yet religious) in the land. racy is this? Their participation in voting is now much the Liberal democracy makes its neat equations same as men’s. Yet almost regardless of the date between democracy and representation, democ- at which women won their rights (ranging from racy and universal su¤rage, but asks us to con- 1902 in Australia, 1919 in West Germany, 1920 sider as irrelevant the composition of our elected in the USA, 1928 in the UK, to the much assemblies. The resulting pattern has been firmly delayed 1971 in Switzerland), there has been a skewed in the direction of white middle-class marked consistency in the figures for female men, with the under-representation of women participation in national and local politics. With only the starkest (because they are half the pop- the major recent exception of the Nordic coun- ulation) among a range of excluded groups. The tries (to which I shall return), women figure in campaign for women’s right to vote was always national politics at something between 2 and 10 linked to a parallel campaign for women’s right per cent; in Britain and the USA, women have to be elected. Success in the first has not brought found it notoriously hard to break the 5 per much joy in the second. . . . cent barrier. The under-representation of women within Figures for local politics are only marginally conventional politics is nonetheless crucial in more promising. By 1983, women representa- thinking about democracy and gender. The tives had captured 13 per cent of the seats on general critique of liberal democracy leaves a West German local councils; 14 per cent on the teasing vacuum on what could serve as alter- French conseils municipaux; 14.4 per cent on natives, while the questions raised over the two county councils in England and Wales; 11.1 per most common alternatives suggest that neither cent on regional councils in Scotland; and 7.9 can be simply adopted in its place. We can per- per cent on district councils in Northern Ireland haps move on to more substantial ground if we (Lovenduski 1986). By 1985, women made up 14 examine more closely the weaknesses (and pos- per cent of the membership of municipal and sibly strengths) of current liberal democratic township governing boards in the United States, practice. What does the under-representation of but had been elected to mayor in only four of the women add to the understanding of democracy? hundred largest cities (Randall 1987:105). The It shows that there is a problem undoubtedly, percentages are nothing to write home about, but is the problem then in the theory or ap- and women’s relatively higher profile in local plication? Setting aside for the moment what politics only confirms what is frequently ob- may be more fundamental problems with liberal/ served: that the numbers rise where the power of representative democracy, can we anticipate a the o‰ce is less. We all know there are more men trend towards sexual parity? Is there a theo- than women in politics, but the details still come retical problem with the ‘‘representation of women,’’ an incongruity between this and the Excerpted from: Anne Phillips, Engendering Democ- assumptions of liberal democracy? . . . [D]oes racy. Cambridge: Polity Press, 1991. Reprinted by feminism provide us with a novel angle on these permission. issues, a di¤erent way of conceiving either possi- Representation 355

bilities or limits? There are two major aspects of stantial di¤erences between men and women, or this, which I shall discuss in separate sections. between black people and white, then those What are the theoretical issues implied in the elected would undoubtedly be a more random notion of representation? What are the chances sample from those who elect. Consistent under- of electing more women? representation of any social category already establishes that there is a problem. Such a ‘‘Mirror’’ Representation marked variance from the population as a whole Confront people with the damning evidence on could never be an accidental result. Leaving the number of women elected and they tend to aside as mere prejudice the notion that women divide into those who think this matters and are ‘‘naturally’’ indi¤erent to politics, there must those who say it does not. Much of the dis- be something that prevents their involvement. agreement reflects the complacency, not to say The argument from justice then calls on us to dishonesty, of those who enjoy a monopoly of eliminate or moderate whatever obstacles we power, but there are more intriguing issues at find to women’s participation, while the argu- stake. As with many feminist demands, the case ments from women’s di¤erent values or di¤erent for greater parity in politics has been made in interests go one stage further. The sexual dif- three ways (Hernes 1987). Part of it relies on a ferentiation in conditions and experience has notion of basic justice, and fits within a broad produced a specifically woman’s point of view, sweep of arguments that challenges sexual segre- which is either complementary or antagonistic gation wherever it occurs. Just as it is unjust to the man’s. Any system of representation that women should be cooks but not engineers, which consistently excludes the voices of women typists but not directors, so it is unjust that they is not just unfair; it does not begin to count as should be excluded from the central activities in representation. the political realm; indeed, given the overarching All three arguments are at odds with what significance of politics, it is even more unfair that has become the orthodoxy, for while there are women should be kept out of this. But for the a number of competing versions on o¤er, the hundred years and more that access to political idea that representatives should in some way power has been an issue, women’s organizations ‘‘mirror’’ those they represent is probably the have combined the case for justice with at least most contested. . . . one additional point. Sometimes the argument is The dominant practice in most contemporary that women would bring to politics a di¤erent set democracies is a muddled combination of both of values, experiences and expertise: that women accountability and autonomy. Our representa- would enrich our political life, usually in the di- tives are said to represent our views (political rection of a more caring, compassionate society. parties present us with alternative policies, and A more radical version is that men and women we make a choice between them), but only in the are in conflict and that it is nonsense to see vaguest of ways (election manifestos o¤er bland women as represented by men. generalities, and those elected then fill in the The case for justice says nothing about what details themselves). Those elected are seen as women will do if they get into politics, while the carrying some responsibility for their area, but two further arguments imply that the content of are not permitted to take this too far, for they politics will change. All unite in seeing a sexual are ultimately bound by party lines. On any of disproportion between electors and elected as the major social or demographic characteristics evidence that something is wrong. The striking (age, sex, race, class) they do not represent us homogeneity of our existing representatives is at all. Taking the example of British Members proof enough of this, since if there were no sub- of Parliament: lawyers make up the largest Chapter 6 356

single occupational group; women have only just be attributed to accident, while the fact that it pushed beyond five percent of the total; and the serves those who are already advantaged is too proportion of the population that is nonwhite striking for any democrat to ignore. The di‰- is currently ‘‘represented’’ by a mere handful of culties arise in the next stage, for within the MPs, whose election in 1987 marked the first framework of representative democracy, it is substantial breach in the white monopoly. . . . political parties that have provided the vehicle Representative democracy cannot produce a for representation, and in its more substantial perfect reflection of society: the only guarantee sense, the representation of women does not fit. of that would be all the citizens meeting together ‘‘Women’’ are not homogeneous and do not in national assembly. Within the limits of repre- speak with a single voice. . . . sentation, it is hard to see how to get agreement . . . Those who resist an increase in women’s on the categories to be covered. Even where such representation no doubt harbour similar fears, agreement becomes possible, proportionality in- anticipating that the women elected will alter the evitably reduces local autonomy, for it must in- game. I hope there will be changes, but in the volve some form of national party directive over interests of democratic accountability these have the kind of candidates each constituency should to take place in the open, through the decision- choose. But arguments that rely on the impossi- making processes of each party and the publicity bility of one extreme in order to justify its op- of electoral campaigns. We cannot jump too posite are always suspect, and as long as those easily into the notion that there is an interest of who speak for us are drawn from such an women; and short of women’s constituencies or unrepresentative sample, then democracy will women’s elections, there is no clear mechanism remain profoundly flawed. The obstacles that for their representation. deny certain people the chance of election are as undemocratic in their way as the laws that once The relative autonomy of politics excluded them from the right to vote. And Let me now turn the argument the other way. I moving on to the more positive point, di¤erent have said that the case for more women repre- experiences do create di¤erent values, priorities, sentatives rests partly on a notion of equality in interests; while we may all be capable of that participation and partly on a notion of reflection, imaginative leap that takes us beyond our own and that neither in principle nor in practice can situation, history indicates that we do this very this guarantee that women are then represented partially, if at all. Those who regard the current as women. We can anticipate that more women situation with complacency are not too far in elected will shift the context and priorities of spirit from the nineteenth-century apologists of public policy, but cannot say this is necessarily male su¤rage, who claimed that a man spoke so, nor indeed presume that their choices would for himself and ‘‘his’’ woman, and thus that the win general acclaim. The problem may be even woman had no need for a separate voice. Where more acute. If feminists are right in the critiques there are di¤erent interests and di¤erent experi- they have developed of liberal democracy, then ences, it is either naive or dishonest to say that the nature of the public/private divide may make one group can speak for us all. . . . even equal numbers an impossible dream. If the It is easy enough to show that women are constraints on women’s political activity are set under-represented in politics, and not too much by their economic and social position, then the more di‰cult to make the case that women are idea that you could have a parliament made up oppressed. On both counts something should equally of men and women, without also having surely be done. The disproportion between those substantial changes in social relations, is non- elected and those who elect is too astounding to sensical. The absurdity lies not in thinking that Representation 357

women would prove no di¤erent from men, but when they are choosing not one but three or five in imagining that they could ever get into such candidates, it begins to look odd if they are all of positions of power until after the changes were them the same. In particular, where elections are made. A democracy may require the policies on organized through party lists there is consider- equality before the equality of representation— ably more scope for dictating sexual composi- and yet without the second what hope is there of tion. It becomes possible to set a minimum quota the first? . . . for each sex in the winnable positions, or, even Explanations for women’s relative invisibility more ambitiously, to put men and women in al- in politics tend to be multi-causal—which is ternate order on the list and produce parity in probably why I used to find them tedious, for the final results. The evidence from Europe is not they lack the drama of the singular cause. decisive but certainly suggestive. Those countries Women have been socialized into regarding pol- which rely on the single-member, first-past-the- itics as an alien a¤air; women are constrained by post system have found it hardest to advance on their responsibilities as mothers, and indeed their the 5 per cent token representation. Most of those general role as carers for the young, sick and old, with a system of multi-member constituencies all of which make the commitments of full-time and party lists edge towards a 10 per cent repre- politics an almost impossible choice; women are sentation of women. All those that stand out as under-represented in the jobs that most favour spectacularly progressive employ proportional political careers; women are discouraged by the representation with party lists (Norris 1985; attentions of a hostile media; women are actively Lovenduski 1986; Haavio-Mannila et al. 1985). excluded by the male selectorates who guard the General arguments for and against propor- gateways to political life (Randall 1987). Within tional representation establish the di‰culties in the general tendency to give due weight to each saying what is most democratic. The single of these factors, there are still important varia- transferable vote system allows voters to indi- tions in emphasis. Some writers have focused cate a hierarchy of preferences, and protects us more on what stops women coming forward, and against a situation in which party A wins with a others on the male barriers when they none- minority of votes, when parties B and C are be- theless do (Lovenduski and Hills 1981 is an ex- tween them the first and second preferences of ample of the latter). And some writers focus the majority. The implication, however, is that attention on political conditions, while others the party that ends up with most seats could be identify the social and economic obstacles to one that has fewer first preference votes—and change. if people really wanted their first choice, but In the more ‘‘political’’ category are the argu- only marginally preferred their second to their ments about proportional representation, which third, this could be a compromise that leaves the have been most associated in the British context majority unhappy. The multi-member constitu- (they are less of an issue elsewhere) with the ency can iron out some of the inequalities in first- work of Elizabeth Vallance (1979) and more past-the-post systems, but the smaller parties recently Pippa Norris (1985). Single-member within each constituency may still end up with constituencies with a first-past-the-post system no members in parliament even if their support for selecting the winner are said to stack the through the nation turned out quite impressive. cards in favour of the male, for in our sex- The additional or mixed member system tries to divided patriarchal societies, the man is the deal with this by leaving some (usually half ) norm, the woman peculiar. . . . seats selected on the first-past-the-post system, . . . [I]n a multi-member constituency the but distributing the remainder in proportion selectorate might take the risk—and indeed, to the parties’ share of the national vote. The Chapter 6 358

problem here is that if the way we vote in our striking enough. Di¤erences in electoral systems constituencies is still premised on our perception emerged as by far the most significant in rela- of which parties have the most chance in our tion to the election of women, followed at some area (we don’t simply vote for what we most distance by positions on the index of political want, but for what we prefer given what we egalitarianism. The dominant religion proved think others will do) then the figures for national insignificant, as did socio-economic conditions. voting cannot be presumed to reflect genuine Among the notable individual examples, Swit- preference. And, as opponents of any of these zerland is particularly convincing. Women were systems will argue, proportional representation not granted full equal rights till 1971, and the can give undue influence to the small party that society is so traditional in its views that as late as then holds the balance of power. Getting a ‘‘fair’’ 1982 male citizens were still voting in one canton reflection of parties in parliament does not guar- to deny women the vote in local elections. Swiss antee fair reflection in government. women nonetheless weigh in at over 10 per cent In terms of the ‘‘mirror’’ e¤ect of reflecting the in the Nationalrat—under a system of propor- population, however, some form of proportional tional representation (Norris 1985:99). representation wins hands down over first-past- Ten per cent is no great cause for rejoicing, and the-post systems (and when the New Zealand the fact that a particular electoral system can Commission on Electoral Reform recommended marginally enhance women’s participation does the abolition of Maori seats, it was with the not take us very far down the road. Looking be- proviso that the country should switch to a yond the clear evidence that proportional repre- mixed member proportional system, thereby sentation o¤ers more favourable conditions for increasing Maori chances of election). In her women to be elected, what dictates when real study of ‘‘Women’s legislative participation in parity will be won? Is it a matter of women’s Western Europe’’ (1985) Pippa Norris compares political mobilization, both inside and outside of twenty-four liberal democracies, including eigh- party politics, which can make sexual equality a teen in Western Europe, to assess the correlation question of public concern? Does it depend in between the numbers of women elected and in- any way on shifts in economic and social ar- stitutional, cultural and socioeconomic condi- rangements: an equalization in male and female tions. The institutional di¤erences refer to the rates of participation in the labour market? a electoral system: whether the country operates a desegregation in the jobs that men and women party list proportional system or some version of typically do? Is the heart of the matter the con- majoritarianism, including first-past-the-post, al- ditions under which children are cared for and ternative vote and single transferable vote sys- reared, so that as long as this remains the private tems. Cultural di¤erences were defined by the responsibility of invisible women, there is limited strength of Catholicism versus Protestantism (the time for them to invade men’s political sphere? former seen as more traditionalist for women), Coming as I do from a tradition that has viewed and with the help of data contributed by nine political equalities as a reflex, however compli- countries in the European Community in a sur- cated and over-determined, of social and eco- vey on attitudes to sexual equality in politics. nomic equalities, I thought for many years that a Socio-economic di¤erences were roughly identi- social revolution was the only real answer. As fied by the proportions of women in the labour long as women are positioned as the dependants force, their proportions in higher education and of men—a positioning which seems to rest on their proportions in the professions. such an interlocking of social, economic and As in any cross-national survey, the measures cultural forces that it is hard to know where to are a bit rough and ready, but the results proved begin—it had seemed inconceivable to me that Representation 359

men and women could take equal parts in the Taking these countries as a whole, what is political realm. Add on to this the more spe- striking is that, despite significant economic dif- cifically feminist analysis of the relationship ferences with countries in Western Europe, the between public and private, which sees the de- pattern of women’s employment and the pre- termined amnesia over the domestic domain as sumption of women’s primary responsibilities for central to liberal democracy, and the facts re- children are not so many miles away from the quired no further explanation. What else could European norm. . . . one possibly expect? What has shifted me to- . . . The social position of women is still in- wards the more political end of the spectrum— formed by the statistically anachronistic but to the belief, that is, that greater political nonetheless powerful assumption that men oc- equality is possible even pending fundamental cupy the world of work and women the world of social transformation—is the recent experience the home. of the Nordic countries. The contrasts seem puzzling indeed. In 1988 I attended a forum that brought together feminists Women in Nordic Countries from Western and Northern Europe, centring Up till the 1960s there was not much to choose much of its discussion around the impact of between any of the countries in Western or quota systems in increasing the political profile Northern Europe: a somewhat more damning of women. The women from West Germany obstructionism in first-past-the-post systems; a were still digesting the causes and consequences more conservative tendency where the church of the recent conference decision of the German held its sway; generally just the deafening domi- Social Democratic Party (SPD), which just that nance of men. By 1984, however, women had year had committed itself to a minimum of 25 taken 15 per cent of the parliamentary seats in per cent women among its Bundestag members Iceland, 26 per cent in Norway and Denmark, 28 at the next election, progressing to a minimum of per cent in Sweden and 31 per cent in Finland 40 per cent in the course of the next ten years. (Lovenduski 1986:152). In 1985, Norway took Feminists from Britain could hardly begin to the world record. Women made up 34.4 per cent conceive the conditions under which comparable of the Storting (the national assembly), held decisions might be reached in Britain. By con- eight out of eighteen cabinet posts, contributed trast, those from Norway or Sweden had experi- 40.5 per cent of the membership of county coun- enced quota systems for so long that they could cils and contributed 31.1 per cent of the mem- barely remember when they won this battle—or bership of municipal councils. The relatively indeed if it was a battle at all! poor performance of women in Iceland further The pattern, in fact, was as follows. In the confirms the role played by electoral systems, for 1970s a number of Scandinavian parties adopted while Iceland shares with other Nordic countries the principle of at least 40 percent female repre- the practice of proportional representation, the sentation at all levels of elected delegation within small number of constituencies combines with a the party itself. This was adopted by the Swedish large number of parties to mean that few parties Liberal Party and the Swedish Communist Party can anticipate winning more than two seats in in 1972, by the Norwegian Liberal Party in 1974 any one constituency. As in so many countries, and the Norwegian Socialist Left Party in 1975, women are typically nominated to the ‘‘orna- and by the Danish Socialist People’s Party in mental’’ positions on a party’s list, with the first 1977 (Skard and Haavio-Mannila 1985a). In the two places secured to men. Their position is thus 1980s there was a push to extend this to the level more comparable to that in first-past-the-post of female representation in national parliaments. systems (Skard and Haavio-Mannila 1985b). In 1980, parties in both Norway and Sweden Chapter 6 360

proposed legislation that would commit all po- Yet in Sweden, Norway and Finland, it was litical parties to a minimum of 40 per cent women the women’s sections in the social democratic on their electoral lists; failing the success of this parties that began to make the running, and in a bid, various parties introduced the practice uni- chronology that has no parallel in the rest of laterally (Skard and Haavio-Mannila 1985b). In Europe, it is the 1950s that are described as the 1983, for example, the Norwegian Labour Party ‘‘decade of the build-up’’ and the 1960s as the introduced a 40 per cent quota for candidates in ‘‘explosive decade’’ (Eduards et al. 1985:136). . . . local and national elections and, as the largest The remarkable levels of female participation party after the 1985 elections, contributed sig- in these countries can I think be explained by a nificantly to the lead that Norway then assumed. combination of three factors. The first is the en- Among the parties that remain ideologically abling condition of their systems of proportional opposed to the principle of a quota system, there representation, which opens up but does not has also been substantial movement: the Norwe- guarantee more space. The second is the strength gian Conservative Party espouses ‘‘competence’’ of women’s organizations within the traditional in opposition to formal quotas, but women social democratic parties, and the political choices nonetheless make up 30 per cent of its current made by feminists who have attached greater national representation (Skjeie 1988). Again this significance to conventional power. The third is seems to confirm the importance of specifically the di¤erences between liberal and social democ- political factors. Once a few parties have put racy, which hinge around a di¤erent relationship their toes in the water, the exigencies of compe- between public and private spheres; women’s tition require that the others do not lag too far position has been made a more explicit public behind. concern. Each of these begs questions about The initial moves towards increasing women’s what explains them in turn, but they combine to representation pre-dated—or at the latest coin- highlight the importance of politics, and the cided with—the emergence of the contemporary scope for specifically political change. women’s movement; indeed, with the exception of Denmark and to a lesser extent Iceland, the This does not mean the road is now clear. We Nordic countries were rather slow to develop the can draw some reassurance from the e¤ects of characteristically counter-cultural politics of sec- example and competition and anticipate that the ond wave feminism. This itself is rather daunting process will speed up once the first stages are in its implications. Through most of Europe, the won. But repeating the experience of one country women’s movement showed little enthusiasm for in another is not easy, and when Pippa Norris the conventionalities of representative democ- identified the importance of proportional repre- racy, and it was not till quite late in the 1970s sentation she found herself correspondingly de- that feminists began to look to existing political pressed. ‘‘Given the many institutional barriers parties as an important arena for change. Many to political equality, including a resistance to the parties had their own women’s organizations, implementation of electoral reform in major- often dating from the late nineteenth century itarian systems, it seems unlikely that cross- when women members were mobilized to per- national di¤erences in the political position of form various supportive or fund-raising activ- women will diminish in the near future’’ ities. At key periods, these women’s sections had (1985:100). All the trends seem to suggest a con- worked hard to raise feminist issues, but this tinuing growth in female participation in wage early history was lost to most of the activists in employment, higher education and the profes- the new women’s movement; outside of the sions. By early 1989, even the Conservative Nordic countries, connections were rarely made. Government in Britain had woken up to the Representation 361

anticipated shortages of skilled labour and burst the prospect of a gender quota may seem to forth in a series of unlikely pronouncements feminists in Britain or the United States, it is at on the desirability of increasing the proportion least conceivable. No one even talks of a formal of women in higher education, of establishing quota for class. work-place nurseries (not of course financed by Representative democracy may prove itself the state), and encouraging more women to more amenable than I once thought to the elec- work. But if the entry of women into higher ed- tion of women, but it has trouble with their ucation and paid employment has limited impact ‘‘representation.’’ Grounded as it is in a tradi- on their numbers in elected o‰ce (as the example tion that rests on the abstract individual, liberal/ of the United States reveals all too clearly), none representative democracy has to define politics as of these changes can be expected to make much the realm of public rationality in which we con- di¤erence. It is crass materialism to say that test opposing ideas. The least democratic ver- what is ‘‘only’’ political is therefore more open to sions of this will leave the bulk of issues to be change. On the other hand, if it is a matter of settled by those elected, and the electorate as a politics we do at least know where to begin. whole will be permitted to make its occasional With all its limitations, representative democ- foray into the voting booth only to indicate a racy is not necessarily inimical to the election of preference over who these people should be. women, and indeed gender may now prove less More radical versions will try to commit the intransigent than class. I do not hold out great representatives to an explicitly delineated set of hopes for my own country, but find it entirely policies and ideas, so that we will not only be plausible that liberal and, more specifically, so- able to ‘‘punish’’ those who disappoint us by cial democracies will witness a growing propor- not voting for them the next time round, but tion of women in politics, even pending that can more positively influence the decisions they social revolution I once thought a necessary make. Here the emphasis will be on party con- condition. But those elected will be peculiarly gresses, definite commitments, explicit proposals, skewed to a certain kind of woman who, like a heightened profile for ideas. the generations of men who went before her, will The representation of women as women po- be a well-educated professional, and devoted to tentially founders on both the di‰culties of politics full time. Even in the Nordic countries, defining the shared interests of women and the the marked shifts of recent years do not guaran- di‰culties of establishing mechanisms through tee access for all women, any more than previous which these interests are voiced. It has been patterns of elected and corporate representa- noted that women politicians are often reluctant tion guaranteed access for all men. The women to see themselves as representing women. While elected to parliament may be thoroughly ‘‘un- we may regret this refusal of feminist concerns, representative’’ in terms of their class, their in- we cannot jump straight to the opposite camp. come, the number and age of their children, or Feminism should not give unwitting support to whether they previously worked full or parttime. a version of democracy that rests too exclu- The fact that gender quotas are increasingly sively on trust, as if merely by virtue of their sex accepted is no doubt a reflection of this: with women can presume a mandate to speak for us women distributed (however unevenly) across all. The representation of women as women does the range of occupations and professions, they not fit within the framework of representative can be incorporated into our representative democracy, and while this may count as ammu- assemblies without disturbing the conventions nition in the battle for democracy of a di¤erent of competence and leadership, and without dis- kind, it should not be glossed over in discussions rupting the dominance of class. However distant of change. Chapter 6 362

References

Bashevkin, Sylvia (ed.) 1985: Women and Politics in Western Europe. London: Frank Cass. Eduards, Maud, Halsaa, Beatrice and Skjeie, Hege 1985: Equality: how equal? In Haavio-Mannila et al. 1985. Graubard, Stephen R. (ed.) 1986: Norden: The Passion For Equality. Norwegian University Press. Haavio-Mannila, Elina, Dahlerup, Drude, Eduards, Maud et al. 1985: Unfinished Democracy: Women in Nordic Politics. Pergamon. Hernes, Helga Maria 1987: Welfare State and Woman Power: Essays in State Feminism. Norwegian Univer- sity Press. Lovenduski, Joni 1986: Women and European Politics: Contemporary Feminism and Public Policy. Wheatsheaf. Lovenduski, Joni and Hills, Jill (eds.) 1981: The Poli- tics of the Second Electorate: Women and Public Par- ticipation. Routledge and Kegan Paul. Norris, Pippa 1985: Women’s legislative participation in Western Europe. In Bashevkin 1985. Randall, Vicky 1987: Women and Politics, 2nd edn. Macmillan. Skard, Torild and Haavio-Mannila, Elina 1985a: Mo- bilization of women at elections. In Haavio-Mannila et al. 1985. ——— 1985b: Women in parliament. In Haavio- Mannila et al. 1985. ——— 1986: Equality between the sexes: myth or re- ality. In Graubard 1986. Skjeie, Hege 1988: The Feminization of Power: Nor- way’s Political Experiment (1986– ). Institute for Social Research, Norway. Vallance, Elizabeth 1979: Women in the House. Athlone. 7 INTEREST GROUPS

The Governmental Process: Political Interests and Public Opinion David B. Truman

The Logic of Collective Action: Public Goods and the Theory of Groups Mancur Olson

Neo-Pluralism: A Class Analysis of Pluralism I and Pluralism II John F. Manley

The Theory of Economic Regulation George J. Stigler

Interest Intermediation and Regime Governability in Contemporary Western Europe and North America Philippe C. Schmitter

Inside Campaign Finance: Myths and Realities Frank J. Sorauf The Governmental Process: Political Interests and Public Opinion

David B. Truman

Men, wherever they are observed, are creatures in the course of time that they appear to be in- participating in those established patterns of in- dependent of the overt activities of organized teraction that we call groups. Excepting perhaps interest groups. The judiciary is such a form. the most casual and transitory, these continuing The building of city streets and the control of interactions, like all such interpersonal relation- vehicular tra‰c are examples of such a func- ships, involve power. This power is exhibited tion. However, if the judiciary or a segment of in two closely interdependent ways. In the first it operates in a fashion sharply contrary to the place, the group exerts power over its members; expectations of an appreciable portion of the an individual’s group a‰liations largely deter- community or if its role is strongly attacked, mine his attitudes, values, and the frames of the group basis of its structure and powers is reference in terms of which he interprets his likely to become apparent. Similarly, if street experiences. For a measure of conformity to the construction greatly increases tax rates or if the norms of the group is the price of acceptance control of tra‰c unnecessarily inconveniences within it. Such power is exerted not only by either pedestrians or motorists, the exposure an individual’s present group relationships; it of these functions to the demands of competing also may derive from past a‰liations such as interests will not be obscure. Interests that are the childhood family as well as from groups to widely held in the society may be reflected in which the individual aspires to belong and whose government without their being organized in characteristic shared attitudes he also holds. In groups. They are what we have called potential the second place, the group, if it is or becomes an groups. If the claims implied by the interests interest group, which any group in a society may of these potential groups are quickly and ade- be, exerts power over other groups in the society quately represented, interaction among those when it successfully imposes claims upon them. people who share the underlying interests or Many interest groups, probably an increas- attitudes is unnecessary. But the interest base of ing proportion in the United States, are politi- accepted governmental forms and functions and cized. That is, either from the outset or from their potential involvement in overt group activ- time to time in the course of their development ities are ever present even when not patently they make their claims through or upon the operative. institutions of government. Both the forms and The institutions of government are centers functions of government in turn are a reflection of interest-based power; their connections with of the activities and claims of such groups. The interest groups may be latent or overt and their constitution-writing proclivities of Americans activities range in political character from the clearly reveal the influence of demands from routinized and widely accepted to the unstable such sources, and the statutory creation of new and highly controversial. In order to make functions reflects their continuing operation. claims, political interest groups will seek access Many of these forms and functions have received to the key points of decision within these insti- such widespread acceptance from the start or tutions. Such points are scattered throughout the structure, including not only the formally Excerpted from: David B. Truman, The Governmental established branches of government but also the Process: Political Interests and Public Opinion. West- political parties in their various forms and the port, Conn.: Greenwood Press, 1951. relationships between governmental units and other interest groups. Interest Groups 365

The extent to which a group achieves e¤ective A characteristic feature of the governmental access to the institutions of government is the system in the United States is that it contains a resultant of a complex of interdependent factors. multiplicity of points of access. The federal sys- For the sake of simplicity these may be classified tem establishes decentralized and more or less in three somewhat overlapping categories: (1) independent centers of power, vantage points factors relating to a group’s strategic position in from which to secure privileged access to the the society; (2) factors associated with the inter- national government. Both a sign and a cause of nal characteristics of the group; and (3) factors the strength of the constituent units in the federal peculiar to the governmental institutions them- scheme is the peculiar character of our party selves. In the first category are: the group’s status system, which has strengthened parochial rela- or prestige in the society, a¤ecting the ease tionships, especially those of national legislators. with which it commands deference from those National parties, and to a lesser degree those in outside its bounds; the standing it and its activ- the States, tend to be poorly cohesive leagues of ities have when measured against the widely locally based organizations rather than unified held but largely unorganized interests or ‘‘rules and inclusive structures. Staggered terms for ex- of the game;’’ the extent to which government ecutive o‰cials and various types of legislators o‰cials are formally or informally ‘‘members’’ accentuate di¤erences in the e¤ective electorates of the group; and the usefulness of the group as a that participate in choosing these o‰cers. Each source of technical and political knowledge. The of these di¤erent, often opposite, localized pat- second category includes: the degree and appro- terns (constituencies) is a channel of independent priateness of the group’s organization; the degree access to the larger party aggregation and to the of cohesion it can achieve in a given situation, formal government. Thus, especially at the na- especially in the light of competing group tional level, the party is an electing-device and demands upon its membership; the skills of the only in limited measure an integrated means leadership; and the group’s resources in numbers of policy determination. Within the Congress, and money. In the third category, are: the oper- furthermore, controls are di¤used among com- ating structure of the government institutions, mittee chairmen and other leaders in both since such established features involve relatively chambers. The variety of these points of access fixed advantages and handicaps; and the e¤ects is further supported by relationships stemming of the group life of particular units or branches from the constitutional doctrine of the separa- of the government. tion of powers, from related checks and bal- The product of e¤ective access, of the claims ances, and at the State and local level from the of organized and unorganized interests that common practice of choosing an array of ex- achieve access with varying degrees of e¤ective- ecutive o‰cials by popular election. At the ness, is a governmental decision. Note that these Federal level the formal simplicity of the execu- interests that achieve e¤ective access and guide tive branch has been complicated by a Supreme decisions need not be ‘‘selfish,’’ are not necessar- Court decision that has placed a number of ad- ily solidly unified, and may not be represented by ministrative agencies beyond the removal power organized groups. Governmental decisions are of the president. The position of these units, the resultant of e¤ective access by various inter- however, di¤ers only in degree from that of ests, of which organized groups may be only a many that are constitutionally within the execu- segment. These decisions may be more or less tive branch. In consequence of alternative lines stable depending on the strength of supporting of access available through the legislature and interests and on the severity of disturbances in the executive and of divided channels for the the society which a¤ect that strength. control of administrative policy, many nominally Chapter 7 366

executive agencies are at various times virtually individual’s activities and his attendant inter- independent of the chief executive. ests involve him in a variety of actual and Although some of these lines of access may potential groups. Moreover, the fact that the ge- operate in series, they are not arranged in a sta- netic experiences of no two individuals are iden- ble and integrated hierarchy. Depending upon tical and the consequent fact that the spectra of the whole political context in a given period and their attitudes are in varying degrees dissimilar upon the relative strength of contending inter- means that the members of a single group will ests, one or another of the centers of power in the perceive the group’s claims in terms of a diversity formal government or in the parties may become of frames of reference. Such heterogeneity may the apex of a hierarchy of controls. Only the be of little significance until such time as these highly routinized governmental activities show multiple memberships conflict. Then the cohe- any stability in this respect, and these may as sion and influence of the a¤ected group depend easily be subordinated to elements in the legis- upon the incorporation or accommodation of lature as to the chief executive. Within limits, the conflicting loyalties of any significant seg- therefore, organized interest groups, gravitating ment of the group, an accommodation that may toward responsive points of decision, may play result in altering the original claims. Thus the one segment of the structure against another as leaders of a Parent-Teacher Association must circumstances and strategic considerations per- take some account of the fact that their pro- mit. The total pattern of government over a posals must be acceptable to members who also period of time thus presents a protean complex belong to the local taxpayers’ league, to the of crisscrossing relationships that change in local chamber of commerce, and to the Catholic strength and direction with alterations in the Church. power and standing of interests, organized and The notion of overlapping membership bears unorganized. directly upon the problems allegedly created There are two elements in this conception of by the appearance of a multiplicity of interest the political process in the United States that are groups. Yet the fact of such overlapping is fre- of crucial significance and that require special quently overlooked or neglected in discussions emphasis. These are, first, the notion of multiple of the political role of groups. James Madison, or overlapping membership and, second, the whose brilliant analysis in the tenth essay in The function of unorganized interests, or potential Federalist we have frequently quoted, relied pri- interest groups. marily upon diversity of groups and di‰culty of The idea of overlapping membership stems communication to protect the new government from the conception of a group as a standardized from the tyranny of a factious majority. He pattern of interactions rather than as a collection barely touched on the notion of multiple mem- of human units. Although the former may ap- bership when he observed, almost parentheti- pear to be a rather misty abstraction, it is actu- cally: ‘‘Besides other impediments, it may be ally far closer to complex reality than the latter remarked that, where there is a consciousness of notion. The view of a group as an aggregation of unjust or dishonorable purposes, communication individuals abstracts from the observable fact is always checked by distrust in proportion to the that in any society, and especially a complex one, number whose concurrence is necessary.’’ John no single group a‰liation accounts for all of the C. Calhoun’s idea of the concurrent majority, attitudes or interests of any individual except a developed in his posthumously published work, fanatic or a compulsive neurotic. No tolerably A Disquisition on Government (1851), assumed normal person is totally absorbed in any group the unified, monolithic character of the groups in which he participates. The diversity of an whose liberties he was so anxious to protect. Interest Groups 367

When his present-day followers unearth his doc- even between traditional Republicans and loyal trines, moreover, they usually make the same Democrats, create serious political problems for assumption, although implicitly.4 Others, seek- the interest group. Instances of the way in which ing a satisfactory means of accounting for the such cleavages impose restraints upon an orga- continued existence of the political system, nized group’s activities are infinitely numerous, sometimes assume that it is the nonparticipant almost as numerous as cases of multiple mem- citizens, aroused to unwonted activity, who act bership. Given the problems of cohesion and in- as a kind of counterbalance to the solid masses ternal group politics that result from overlapping that constitute organized interest groups.5 Al- membership, the emergence of a multiplicity of though this phenomenon may occur in times of interest groups in itself contains no dangers for crisis, reliance upon it reckons insu‰ciently with the political system, especially since such over- the established observation that citizens who are lapping a¤ects not only private but also govern- nonparticipant in one aspect of the govern- mental ‘‘members’’ of the organized group. mental process, such as voting, rarely show But multiple membership in organized groups much concern for any phase of political activity. is not su‰ciently extensive to obviate the pos- Multiple membership is more important as a sibility of irreconcilable conflict. There is little restraint upon the activities of organized groups overlapping in the memberships of the National than the rarely aroused protests of chronic Association of Manufacturers and the United nonparticipants. Steelworkers of America, or of the American Organized interest groups are never solid and Farm Bureau Federation and the United monolithic, though the consequences of their Automobile Workers. Overlapping membership overlapping memberships may be handled with among relatively cohesive organized interest su‰cient skill to give the organizations a maxi- groups provides an insu‰cient basis upon which mum of cohesion. It is the competing claims of to account for the relative stability of an operat- other groups within a given interest group that ing political system. That system is a fact. An threaten its cohesion and force it to reconcile its adequate conception of the group process must claims with those of other groups active on the reckon with it. To paraphrase the famous words political scene. The claims within the American of John Marshall, we must never forget that it is Medical Association of specialists and teaching a going polity we are explaining. doctors who support group practice, compulsory We cannot account for an established Ameri- health insurance, and preventive medicine o¤er can political system without the second crucial an illustration. The presence within the Ameri- element in our conception of the political pro- can Legion of public-housing enthusiasts and cess, the concept of the unorganized interest, or labor unionists as well as private homebuilders potential interest group. Despite the tremendous and labor opponents provides another example. number of interest groups existing in the United Potential conflicts within the Farm Bureau be- States, not all interests are organized. If we recall tween farmers who must buy supplementary feed the definition of an interest as a shared attitude, and those who produce excess feed grains for the it becomes obvious that continuing interaction market, between soybean growers and dairymen, resulting in claims upon other groups does not take place on the basis of all such attitudes. One 4. Cf. John Fischer: ‘‘Unwritten Rules of American of the commonest interest group forms, the as- Politics,’’ Harper’s Magazine (November, 1948), sociation, emerges out of severe or prolonged pp. 27–36. disturbances in the expected relationships of 5. Cf. Herring: The Politics of Democracy, [New York: individuals in similar institutionalized groups. W. W. Norton, 1940,] p. 32. An association continues to function as long as it Chapter 7 368

succeeds in ordering these disturbed relation- bility that severe disturbances will be created ships, as a labor union orders the relationships if these submerged, potential interests should between management and workers. Not all such organize necessitates some recognition of the ex- expected relationships are simultaneously or in istence of these interests and gives them at least a a given short period su‰ciently disturbed to minimum of influence. produce organization. Therefore only a portion More important for present purposes than the of the interests or attitudes involved in such ex- potential groups representing separate minority pectations are represented by organized groups. elements are those interests or expectations that Similarly, many organized groups—families, are so widely held in the society and are so businesses, or churches, for example—do not reflected in the behavior of almost all citizens operate continuously as interest groups or as that they are, so to speak, taken for granted. political interest groups. Such ‘‘majority’’ interests are significant not only Any mutual interest, however, any shared because they may become the basis for organized attitude, is a potential group. A disturbance in interest groups but also because the ‘‘member- established relationships and expectations any- ship’’ of such potential groups overlaps exten- where in the society may produce new patterns sively the memberships of the various organized of interaction aimed at restricting or eliminating interest groups.8 The resolution of conflicts be- the disturbance. Sometimes it may be this possi- tween the claims of such unorganized interests bility of organization that alone gives the poten- and those of organized interest groups must tial group a minimum of influence in the political grant recognition to the former not only because process. Thus Key notes that the Delta planters a¤ected individuals may feel strongly attached in Mississippi ‘‘must speak for their Negroes in to them but even more certainly because these such programs as health and education,’’ al- interests are widely shared and are a part of though the latter are virtually unorganized and many established patterns of behavior the dis- are denied the means of active political partici- turbance of which would be di‰cult and painful. pation.6 It is in this sense that Bentley speaks of They are likely to be highly valued. a di¤erence in degree between the politics of These widely held but unorganized interests despotism and that of other ‘‘forms’’ of govern- are what we have previously called the ‘‘rules of ment. He notes that there is ‘‘a process of repre- the game.’’ Others have described these attitudes sentation in despotisms which is inevitable in in such terms as ‘‘systems of belief,’’ as a ‘‘gen- all democracies, and which may be distinguished eral ideological consensus,’’ and as ‘‘a broad by quantities and by elaboration of technique, body of attitudes and understandings regarding but not in any deeper ‘qualititative’ way.’’ He the nature and limits of authority.’’9 Each of speaks of the despot as ‘‘representative of his own class, and to a smaller, but none the less 8. See the suggestive discussion of this general subject real, extent of the ruled class as well.’’7 Obstacles in Robert Bierstedt: ‘‘The Sociology of Majorities,’’ to the development of organized groups from American Sociological Review, Vol. 13, no. 6 (Decem- potential ones may be presented by inertia or by ber, 1948), pp. 700–710. the activities of opposed groups, but the possi- 9. Kluckhohn: Mirror for Man, [New York: Whit- tlesey House, 1949,] pp. 248 and passim; Sebastian de Grazia: The Political Community: A Study of Anomie 6. Key: Southern Politics, [New York: Vintage Books, 1949,] pp. 235 and passim. (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1948), pp. ix, 80, and passim; Almond: The American People and 7. Bentley: The Process of Government, [Chicago: Foreign Policy, [New York: Harcourt, Brace, 1950,] The University of Chicago Press, 1908,] pp. 314–315. p. 158; Charles E. Merriam: Systematic Politics (Chi- Copyright 1908 by and used with the permission of cago: University of Chicago Press, 1945), p. 213. Arthur F. Bentley. Interest Groups 369

these interests (attitudes) may be wide or narrow, game’’ normally will weaken a group’s cohesion, general or detailed. For the mass of the popula- reduce its status in the community, and expose tion they may be loose and ambiguous, though it to the claims of other groups. The latter may more precise and articulated at the leadership be competing organized groups that more ade- level. In any case the ‘‘rules of the game’’ are quately incorporate the ‘‘rules,’’ or they may be interests the serious disturbance of which will groups organized on the basis of these broad result in organized interaction and the assertion interests and in response to the violations. of fairly explicit claims for conformity. In the The pervasive and generally accepted charac- American system the ‘‘rules’’ would include the ter of these unorganized interests, or ‘‘rules,’’ is value generally attached to the dignity of the in- such that they are acquired by most individuals dividual human being, loosely expressed in terms in their early experiences in the family, in the of ‘‘fair dealing’’ or more explicitly verbalized public schools (probably less e¤ectively in the in formulations such as the Bill of Rights. They private and parochial schools), and in similar would embrace . . . ‘‘the democratic mold,’’ that institutionalized groups that are also expected is, the approval of forms for broad mass partici- to conform in some measure to the ‘‘democratic pation in the designation of leaders and in the mold.’’ The ‘‘rules’’ are likely to be reinforced by selection of policies in all social groups and later events. Persons who aspire to, or occupy, institutions. They would also comprehend cer- public o‰ce of whatever sort are particularly tain semi-egalitarian notions of material welfare. likely to identify with these expected behaviors This is an illustrative, not an exhaustive, list of as part of their desired or existing roles. With such interests. varying degrees of e¤ectiveness the group life of The widely held, unorganized interests are government agencies—legislative, executive, and reflected in the major institutions of the society, judicial—reinforces the claims of these unorga- including the political. The political structure of nized interests, which overlap those of the o‰cial the United States, as we have seen, has adopted group itself and those of ‘‘outside’’ political in- characteristic legislative, executive, and judicial terest groups. Marked and prolonged deviation forms through the e¤orts of organized interest from these expected behaviors by public o‰cials, groups. Once these forms have been accepted who are expected to represent what Bentley and have been largely routinized, the supporting calls the ‘‘‘absent’ or quiescent group interests,’’ organized interest groups cease to operate as will normally produce restrictive action by other such and revert to the potential stage. As governmental functionaries, by existing orga- embodied in these institutional forms and in nized interest groups, by ones newly organized in accepted verbal formulations, such as those of consequence of the deviations, or by all three. legal and constitutional theory, the interests of It is thus multiple memberships in potential these potential groups are established expecta- groups based on widely held and accepted inter- tions concerning not only what the governmental ests that serve as a balance wheel in a going institutions shall do, but more particularly how political system like that of the United States. To they shall operate. To the extent that these some people this observation may appear to be a established processes remain noncontroversial, truism and to others a somewhat mystical no- they may appear to have no foundation in inter- tion. It is neither. In the first place, neglect of this ests. Nevertheless, the widespread expectations function of multiple memberships in most dis- will receive tacit or explicit deference from most organized interest groups in consequence of the 10. Cf. Bentley: The Process of Government, p. 397, overlapping of their memberships with these po- and MacIver: The Web of Government, [New York: tential groups.10 Violation of the ‘‘rules of the Macmillan, 1947,] p. 79. Chapter 7 370

cussions of organized interest groups indicates adequately make known particular deviations that the observation is not altogether common- from the behavior indicated by these broad place. Secondly, the statement has no mystical interests. quality; the e¤ective operation of these widely In a relatively vigorous political system, held interests is to be inferred directly from ver- however, these unorganized interests are domi- bal and other behavior in the political sphere. nant with su‰cient frequency in the behavior Without the notion of multiple memberships of enough important segments of the society so in potential groups it is literally impossible to that, despite ambiguity and other restrictions, account for the existence of a viable polity such both the activity and the methods of organized as that in the United States or to develop a interest groups are kept within broad limits. This coherent conception of the political process. The interpretation is not far from Lasswell’s view of strength of these widely held but largely unorga- the state as a relational system defined by a cer- nized interests explains the vigor with which tain frequency of subjective events.13 According propagandists for organized groups attempt to to his definition, ‘‘the state . . . is a time-space change other attitudes by invoking such inter- manifold of similar subjective events. . . . That ests.11 Their importance is further evidenced in subjective event which is the unique mark of the the recognized function of the means of mass state is the recognition that one belongs to a communication, notably the press, in reinforcing community with a system of paramount claims widely accepted norms of ‘‘public morality.’’12 and expectations.’’14 All citizens of the state as The role of the widespread unorganized inter- thus conceived need not experience this ‘‘event’’ ests and potential groups does not imply that continuously or with equal intensity. Nor need such interests are always and everywhere domi- the attitudes of all citizens be favorable toward nant. Nor does it mean that the slightest action these ‘‘claims and expectations.’’ But the exis- in violation of any of them inevitably and tence of the state, of the polity, depends on instantly produces a restrictive response from widespread, frequent recognition of and confor- another source. These interests are not unam- mity to the claims of these unorganized interests biguous, as the long history of litigation con- and on activity condemning marked deviations cerning freedom of speech will demonstrate. from them. ‘‘All this,’’ says Lasswell, ‘‘is fre- Subjectively they are not all equally fundamen- quently expressed as the ‘sense of justice’. . . .’’15 tal. Thus since the ‘‘rules’’ are interests compet- Thus it is only as the e¤ects of overlapping ing with those of various organized groups, they memberships and the functions of unorganized are in any given set of circumstances more or less interests and potential groups are included in the subject to attenuation through such psychologi- equation that it is accurate to speak of govern- cal mechanisms as rationalization. Moreover, mental activity as the product or resultant of in- the means of communication, whether by word terest group activity. As Bentley has put it: of mouth or through the mass media, may not There are limits to the technique of the struggle, this involving also limits to the group demands, all of 11. Cf. Lazarsfeld et al.: The People’s Choice, [New which is solely a matter of empirical observation. . . . York: Columbia Univ. Press, 1948,] preface to 2d edi- Or, in other words, when the struggle proceeds too tion, pp. xxi–xxii. 12. Cf. Paul F. Lazarsfeld and Robert K. Merton: 13. Lasswell: Psychopathology and Politics, [Chicago: ‘‘Mass Communication, Popular Taste and Organized University of Chicago Press, 1934,] pp. 240–261. Social Act,’’ in Lyman Bryson (ed.): The Communica- tion of Ideas (New York: Harper and Brothers, 1948), 14. Ibid., p. 245. pp. 102 ¤. 15. Ibid., p. 246. Interest Groups 371

harshly at any point there will become insistent in the society a group more powerful than either of those involved which tends to suppress the extreme and annoying methods of the groups in the primary strug- gle. It is within the embrace of these great lines of activity that the smaller struggles proceed, and the very word struggle has meaning only with reference to its limitations.16

To assert that the organization and activity of powerful interest groups constitutes a threat to representative government without measuring their relation to and e¤ects upon the widespread potential groups is to generalize from insu‰cient data and upon an incomplete conception of the political process. Such an analysis would be as faulty as one that, ignoring di¤erences in na- tional systems, predicted identical responses to a given technological change in the United States, Japan, and the Soviet Union. . . .

16. Bentley: The Process of Government, p. 372. Copyright 1908 by and used with the permission of Arthur F. Bentley. The Logic of Collective Action: Public Goods and the Theory of Groups

Mancur Olson

zations, and there is then some question whether A Theory of Groups and Organizations there is any single purpose that would be characteristic of organizations generally. One A. The Purpose of Organization purpose that is nonetheless characteristic of most organizations, and surely of practically all Since most (though by no means all) of the organizations with an important economic as- action taken by or no behalf of groups of indi- pect, is the furtherance of the interests of their viduals is taken through organizations, it will be members. . . . helpful to consider organizations in a general or The kinds of organizations that are the focus theoretical way.1 The logical place to begin any of this study are expected to further the interests systematic study of organizations is with their of their members.6 Labor unions are expected to purpose. But there are all types and shapes and strive for higher wages and better working con- sizes of organizations, even of economic organi- ditions for their members; farm organizations are expected to strive for favorable legislation Reprinted by permission of the publisher from: for their members; cartels are expected to strive Mancur Olson, The Logic of Collective Action: Public for higher prices for participating firms; the Goods and the Theory of Groups. Cambridge, Mass.: corporation is expected to further the interests Harvard University Press, 1965. Copyright 6 1965, 1971 by the President and Fellows of Harvard College. 1. Economists have for the most part neglected to de- 6. Philanthropic and religious organizations are not velop theories of organizations, but there are a few necessarily expected to serve only the interests of their works from an economic point of view on the subject. members; such organizations have other purposes that See, for example, three papers by Jacob Marschak, are considered more important, however much their ‘‘Elements for a Theory of Teams,’’ Management members ‘‘need’’ to belong, or are improved or helped Science, I (January 1955), 127–137, ‘‘Towards an Eco- by belonging. But the complexity of such organizations nomic Theory of Organization and Information,’’ in need not be debated at length here, because this study Decision Processes, ed. R. M. Thrall, C. H. Combs, will focus on organizations with a significant economic and R. L. Davis (New York: John Wiley, 1954), aspect. The emphasis here will have something in pp. 187–220, and ‘‘E‰cient and Viable Organization common with what Max Weber called the ‘‘associative Forms,’’ in Modern Organization Theory, ed. Mason group’’; he called a group associative if ‘‘the orienta- Haire (New York: John Wiley, 1959), pp. 307–320; tion of social action with it rests on a rationally moti- two papers by R. Radner, ‘‘Application of Linear vated agreement.’’ Weber contrasted his ‘‘associative Programming to Team Decision Problems,’’ Manage- group’’ with the ‘‘communal group’’ which was cen- ment Science, V (January 1959), 143–150, and ‘‘Team tered on personal a¤ection, erotic relationships, etc., Decision Problems,’’ Annals of Mathematical Statistics, like the family. (See Weber, [Theory of Social and XXXIII (September 1962), 857–881; C. B. McGuire, Economic Organization, translated by Talcott Parsons ‘‘Some Team Models of a Sales Organization,’’ Man- and A. M. Henderson. New York: Oxford University agement Science, VII (January 1961), 101–130; Oskar Press, 1947,] pp. 136–139, and Grace Coyle, Social Morgenstern, Prolegomena to a Theory of Organization Process in Organized Groups, New York: Richard (Santa Monica, Calif.: RAND Research Memoran- Smith, Inc., 1930, pp. 7–9.) The logic of the theory dum 734, 1951); James G. March and Herbert A. developed here can be extended to cover communal, Simon, Organizations (New York: John Wiley, 1958); religious, and philanthropic organizations, but the Kenneth Boulding, The Organizational Revolution theory is not particularly useful in studying such (New York: Harper, 1953). groups. . . . Interest Groups 373

of its stockholders;7 and the state is expected to ual interests, their characteristic and primary further the common interests of its citizens function is to advance the common interests of (though in this nationalistic age the state often groups of individuals. . . . has interests and ambitions apart from those of Just as those who belong to an organization or its citizens). a group can be presumed to have a common in- Notice that the interests that all of these terest,11 so they obviously also have purely indi- diverse types of organizations are expected to vidual interests, di¤erent from those of the others further are for the most part common interests: in the organization or group. All of the members the union members’ common interest in higher of a labor union, for example, have a common wages, the farmers’ common interest in favor- interest in higher wages, but at the same time able legislation, the cartel members’ common each worker has a unique interest in his personal interest in higher prices, the stockholders’ com- income, which depends not only on the rate of mon interest in higher dividends and stock wages but also on the length of time that he prices, the citizens’ common interest in good works. government. It is not an accident that the diverse types of organizations listed are all supposed to B. Public Goods and Large Groups work primarily for the common interests of their members. Purely personal or individual interests The combination of individual interests and can be advanced, and usually advanced most common interests in an organization suggests e‰ciently, by individual, unorganized action. an analogy with a competitive market. The firms There is obviously no purpose in having an or- in a perfectly competitive industry, for example, ganization when individual, unorganized action have a common interest in a higher price for the can serve the interests of the individual as well industry’s product. Since a uniform price must as or better than an organization; there would, prevail in such a market, a firm cannot expect a for example, be no point in forming an organi- higher price for itself unless all of the other firms zation simply to play solitaire. But when a num- in the industry also have this higher price. But a ber of individuals have a common or collective interest—when they share a single purpose or 11. Any organization or group will of course usually objective—individual, unorganized action (as we be divided into subgroups or factions that are opposed shall soon see) will either not be able to advance to one another. This fact does not weaken the as- that common interest at all, or will not be able to sumption made here that organizations exist to serve advance that interest adequately. Organizations the common interests of members, for the assumption can therefore perform a function when there are does not imply that intragroup conflict is neglected. common or group interests, and though organi- The opposing groups within an organization ordinarily have some interest in common (if not, why would they zations often also serve purely personal, individ- maintain the organization?), and the members of any subgroup or faction also have a separate common in- 7. That is, its members. This study does not follow the terest of their own. They will indeed often have a terminological usage of those organization theorists common purpose in defeating some other subgroup or who describe employees as ‘‘members’’ of the organi- faction. The approach used here does not neglect the zation for which they work. Here it is more convenient conflict within groups and organizations, then, because to follow the language of everyday usage instead, and it considers each organization as a unit only to the to distinguish the members of, say, a union from the extent that it does in fact attempt to serve a common employees of that union. Similarly, the members of the interest, and considers the various subgroups as the union will be considered employees of the corporation relevant units with common interests to analyze the for which they work, whereas the members of the cor- factional strife. poration are the common stockholders. Chapter 7 374

firm in a competitive market also has an interest increase output to the point where marginal cost in selling as much as it can, until the cost of equals price and to ignore the e¤ects of its extra producing another unit exceeds the price of that output on the position of the industry. It is true unit. In this there is no common interest; each that the net result is that all firms are worse o¤, firm’s interest is directly opposed to that of every but this does not mean that every firm has not other firm, for the more other firms sell, the maximized its profits. If a firm, foreseeing the lower the price and income for any given firm. fall in price resulting from the increase in indus- In short, while all firms have a common interest try output, were to restrict its own output, it in a higher price, they have antagonistic interests would lose more than ever, for its price would where output is concerned. This can be illus- fall quite as much in any case and it would have trated with a simple supply-and-demand model. a smaller output as well. A firm in a perfectly For the sake of a simple argument, assume that a competitive market gets only a small part of the perfectly competitive industry is momentarily in benefit (or a small share of the industry’s extra a disequilibrium position, with price exceeding revenue) resulting from a reduction in that firm’s marginal cost for all firms at their present out- output. put. Suppose, too, that all of the adjustments will For these reasons it is now generally under- be made by the firms already in the industry stood that if the firms in an industry are max- rather than by new entrants, and that the indus- imizing profits, the profits for the industry as try is on an inelastic portion of its demand curve. a whole will be less than they might otherwise Since price exceeds marginal cost for all firms, be.14 And almost everyone would agree that this output will increase. But as all firms increase theoretical conclusion fits the facts for markets production, the price falls; indeed, since the in- characterized by pure competition. The impor- dustry demand curve is by assumption inelastic, tant point is that this is true because, though all the total revenue of the industry will decline. the firms have a common interest in a higher Apparently each firm finds that with price price for the industry’s product, it is in the inter- exceeding marginal cost, it pays to increase its est of each firm that the other firms pay the output, but the result is that each firm gets a cost—in terms of the necessary reduction in smaller profit. Some economists in an earlier day output—needed to obtain a higher price. may have questioned this result,12 but the fact About the only thing that keeps prices from that profit-maximizing firms in a perfectly com- falling in accordance with the process just de- petitive industry can act contrary to their inter- scribed in perfectly competitive markets is out- ests as a group is now widely understood and side intervention. Government price supports, accepted.13 A group of profit-maximizing firms tari¤s, cartel agreements, and the like may keep can act to reduce their aggregate profits because the firms in a competitive market from acting in perfect competition each firm is, by definition, contrary to their interests. Such aid or interven- so small that it can ignore the e¤ect of its output tion is quite common. It is then important to ask on price. Each firm finds it to its advantage to how it comes about. How does a competitive in- dustry obtain government assistance in main- 12. See J. M. Clark, The Economics of Overhead Costs taining the price of its product? . . . (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1923), p. 417, and Frank H. Knight, Risk, Uncertainty and Profit 14. For a fuller discussion of this question see Mancur (Boston: Houghton Mi¿in, 1921), p. 193. Olson, Jr., and David McFarland, ‘‘The Restoration 13. Edward H. Chamberlin, Monopolistic Competi- of Pure Monopoly and the Concept of the Industry,’’ tion, 6th ed. (Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Quarterly Journal of Economics, LXXVI (November Press, 1950), p. 4. 1962), 613–631. Interest Groups 375

There is a striking parallel between the prob- his plans because of it. Similarly, in a large or- lem the perfectly competitive industry faces as it ganization, the loss of one dues payer will not strives to obtain government assistance, and the noticeably increase the burden for any other problem it faces in the marketplace when the one dues payer, and so a rational person would firms increase output and bring about a fall in not believe that if he were to withdraw from price. Just as it was not rational for a particular an organization he would drive others to do producer to restrict his output in order that there so. . . . might be a higher price for the product of his However similar the purposes may be, critics industry, so it would not be rational for him to may object that attitudes in organizations are sacrifice his time and money to support a lobbying not at all like those in markets. In organizations, organization to obtain government assistance for an emotional or ideological element is often also the industry. In neither case would it be in the involved. Does this make the argument o¤ered interest of the individual producer to assume any here practically irrelevant? of the costs himself. A lobbying organization, or A most important type of organization—the indeed a labor union or any other organization, national state—will serve to test this objec- working in the interest of a large group of firms tion. Patriotism is probably the strongest non- or workers in some industry, would get no assis- economic motive for organizational allegiance in tance from the rational, self-interested individuals modern times. This age is sometimes called the in that industry. This would be true even if age of nationalism. Many nations draw addi- everyone in the industry were absolutely con- tional strength and unity from some powerful vinced that the proposed program was in their ideology, such as democracy or communism, as interest (though in fact some might think other- well as from a common religion, language, or wise and make the organization’s task yet more cultural inheritance. The state not only has many di‰cult). . . . such powerful sources of support; it also is very Some critics may argue that the rational per- important economically. Almost any govern- son will, indeed, support a large organization, ment is economically beneficial to its citizens, in like a lobbying organization, that works in his that the law and order it provides is a prerequi- interest, because he knows that if he does not, site of all civilized economic activity. But despite others will not do so either, and then the organi- the force of patriotism, the appeal of the national zation will fail, and he will be without the benefit ideology, the bond of a common culture, and the that the organization could have provided. This indispensability of the system of law and order, argument shows the need for the analogy with no major state in modern history has been able the perfectly competitive market. For it would to support itself through voluntary dues or con- be quite as reasonable to argue that prices will tributions. Philanthropic contributions are not never fall below the levels a monopoly would even a significant source of revenue for most have charged in a perfectly competitive market, countries. Taxes, compulsory payments by defi- because if one firm increased its output, other nition, are needed. Indeed, as the old saying firms would also, and the price would fall; but indicates, their necessity is as certain as death each firm could foresee this, so it would not start itself. a chain of price-destroying increases in output. If the state, with all of the emotional resources In fact, it does not work out this way in a com- at its command, cannot finance its most basic petitive market; nor in a large organization. and vital activities without resort to compulsion, When the number of firms involved is large, no it would seem that large private organizations one will notice the e¤ect on price if one firm might also have di‰culty in getting the individ- increases its output, and so no one will change uals in the groups whose interests they attempt Chapter 7 376

to advance to make the necessary contributions ation is accordingly necessary. The common or voluntarily.19 collective benefits provided by governments are The reason the state cannot survive on volun- usually called ‘‘public goods’’ by economists, tary dues or payments, but must rely on taxa- and the concept of public goods is one of the tion, is that the most fundamental services a oldest and most important ideas in the study of nation-state provides are, in one important re- public finance. A common, collective, or public spect, like the higher price in a competitive mar- good is here defined as any good such that, if ket: they must be available to everyone if they any person Xi in a group X1; ...; Xi; ...; Xn are available to anyone. The basic and most ele- consumes it, cannot feasibly be withheld from mentary goods or services provided by govern- the others in that group.21 In other words, those ment, like defense and police protection, and the system of law and order generally, are such that 21. This simple definition focuses upon two points that they go to everyone or practically everyone in are important in the present context. The first point is the nation. It would obviously not be feasible, if that most collective goods can only be defined with re- indeed it were possible, to deny the protection spect to some specific group. One collective good goes provided by the military services, the police, and to one group of people, another collective good to an- the courts to those who did not voluntarily pay other group; one may benefit the whole world, another their share of the costs of government, and tax- only two specific people. Moreover, some goods are collective goods to those in one group and at the same time private goods to those in another, because some 19. Sociologists as well as economists have observed individuals can be kept from consuming them and that ideological motives alone are not su‰cient to others can’t. Take for example the parade that is a bring forth the continuing e¤ort of large masses of collective good to all those who live in tall buildings people. Max Weber provides a notable example: overlooking the parade route, but which appears to be ‘‘All economic activity in a market economy is un- a private good to those who can see it only by buying dertaken and carried through by individuals for their tickets for a seat in the stands along the way. The sec- own ideal or material interests. This is naturally just as ond point is that once the relevant group has been true when economic activity is oriented to the patterns defined, the definition used here, like Musgrave’s, of order of corporate groups . . . distinguishes collective good in terms of infeasibility ‘‘Even if an economic system were organized on a of excluding potential consumers of the good. This socialistic basis, there would be no fundamental di¤er- approach is used because collective goods produced by ence in this respect. . . . The structure of interests and organizations of all kinds seem to be such that exclu- the relevant situation might change; there would be sion is normally not feasible. To be sure, for some other means of pursuing interests, but this fundamental collective goods it is physically possible to practice ex- factor would remain just as relevant as before. It is of clusion. But, as Head has shown, it is not necessary course true that economic action which is oriented on that exclusion be technically impossible; it is only nec- purely ideological grounds to the interest of others does essary that it be infeasible or uneconomic. Head has exist. But it is even more certain that the mass of men also shown most clearly that nonexcludability is only do not act in this way, and it is an induction from ex- one of two basic elements in the traditional under- perience that they cannot do so and never will. . . . standing of public goods. The other, he points out, is ‘‘In a market economy the interest in the maximiza- ‘‘jointness of supply.’’ A good has ‘‘jointness’’ if mak- tion of income is necessarily the driving force of all ing it available to one individual means that it can be economic activity.’’ (Weber, pp. 319–320.) easily or freely supplied to others as well. The polar Talcott Parsons and Neil Smelser go even further case of jointness would be Samuelson’s pure public in postulating that ‘‘performance’’ throughout society good, which is a good such that additional consump- is proportional to the ‘‘rewards’’ and ‘‘sanctions’’ tion of it by one individual does not diminish the involved. See their Economy and Society (Glencoe, Ill.: amount available to others. By the definition used here, Free Press, 1954), pp. 50–69. jointness is not a necessary attribute of a public good. Interest Groups 377

who do not purchase or pay for any of the public that no one in the group is excluded from or collective good cannot be excluded or kept the benefit or satisfaction brought about by its from sharing in the consumption of the good, achievement. As the opening paragraphs of this as they can where noncollective goods are chapter indicated, almost all groups and organi- concerned. zations have the purpose of serving the common Students of public finance have, however, interests of their members. . . . It is of the essence neglected the fact that the achievement of any of an organization that it provides an insepa- common goal or the satisfaction of any common rable, generalized benefit. It follows that the interest means that a public or collective good has provision of public or collective goods is the been provided for that group.22 The very fact that fundamental function of organizations generally. a goal or purpose is common to a group means A state is first of all an organization that pro- vides public goods for its members, the citizens; As later parts of this chapter will show, at least one and other types of organizations similarly pro- type of collective good considered here exhibits no vide collective goods for their members. jointness whatever, and few if any would have the And just as a state cannot support itself by degree of jointness needed to qualify as pure public voluntary contributions, or by selling its basic goods. Nonetheless, most of the collective goods to be services on the market, neither can other large studied here do display a large measure of jointness. organizations support themselves without pro- On the definition and importance of public goods, viding some sanction, or some attraction dis- see John G. Head, ‘‘Public Goods and Public Policy,’’ tinct from the public good itself, that will lead Public Finance, vol. XVII, no. 3 (1962), 197–219; Richard Musgrave, The Theory of Public Finance individuals to help bear the burdens of main- (New York: McGraw-Hill, 1959); Paul A. Samuelson, taining the organization. The individual member ‘‘The Pure Theory of Public Expenditure,’’ ‘‘Diagram- of the typical large organization is in a position matic Exposition of A Theory of Public Expenditure,’’ analogous to that of the firm in a perfectly com- and ‘‘Aspects of Public Expenditure Theories,’’ in Re- petitive market, or the taxpayer in the state: his view of Economics and Statistics, XXXVI (November own e¤orts will not have a noticeable e¤ect on 1954), 387–390, XXXVII (November 1955), 350–356, the situation of his organization, and he can en- and XL (November 1958), 332–338. For somewhat joy any improvements brought about by others di¤erent opinions about the usefulness of the concept whether or not he has worked in support of his of public goods, see Julius Margolis, ‘‘A Comment on organization. . . . the Pure Theory of Public Expenditure,’’ Review of Economics and Statistics, XXXVII (November 1955), Nontechnical Summary of Section D 347–349, and Gerhard Colm, ‘‘Theory of Public Expenditures,’’ Annals of the American Academy of . . . [C]ertain small groups can provide them- Political and Social Science, CLXXXIII (January selves with collective goods without relying on 1936), 1–11. coercion or any positive inducements apart from 22. There is no necessity that a public good to one the collective good itself.53 This is because in group in a society is necessarily in the interest of the society as a whole. Just as a tari¤ could be a public 53. I am indebted to Professor John Rawls of the De- good to the industry that sought it, so the removal of partment of Philosophy at Harvard University for the tari¤ could be a public good to those who con- sumed the industry’s product. This is equally true when reminding me of the fact that the philosopher David the public-good concept is applied only to govern- Hume sensed that small groups could achieve common purposes but large groups could not. Hume’s argument ments; for a military expenditure, or a tari¤, or an A immigration restriction that is a public good to one is however somewhat di¤erent from my own. In Treatise of Human Nature country could be a ‘‘public bad’’ to another country, , Everyman edition (London: and harmful to world society as a whole. J. M. Dent, 1952), II, 239, Hume wrote: ‘‘There is no quality in human nature which causes more fatal errors Chapter 7 378

some small groups each of the members, or at lective good can often be provided by the volun- least one of them, will find that his personal gain tary, self-interested action of the members of the from having the collective good exceeds the total group. In smaller groups marked by consider- cost of providing some amount of that collective able degrees of inequality—that is, in groups of good; there are members who would be better o¤ members of unequal ‘‘size’’ or extent of interest if the collective good were provided, even if they in the collective good—there is the greatest like- had to pay the entire cost of providing it them- lihood that a collective good will be provided; selves, than they would be if it were not pro- for the greater the interest in the collective good vided. In such situations there is a presumption of any single member, the greater the likelihood that the collective good will be provided. Such that that member will get such a significant pro- a situation will exist only when the benefit to the portion of the total benefit from the collective group from having the collective good exceeds good that he will gain from seeing that the good the total cost by more than it exceeds the gain is provided, even if he has to pay all of the cost to one or more individuals in the group. Thus, himself. . . . in a very small group, where each member gets a substantial proportion of the total gain simply because there are few others in the group, a col- The ‘‘By-Product’’ and ‘‘Special Interest’’ Theories in our conduct, than that which leads us to prefer whatever is present to the distant and remote, and A. The ‘‘By-Product’’ Theory of Large makes us desire objects more according to their situa- Pressure Groups tion than their intrinsic value. Two neighbours may agree to drain a meadow, which they possess in com- If the individuals in a large group have no in- mon: because it is easy for them to know each other’s centive to organize a lobby to obtain a collective mind; and each must perceive, that the immediate benefit, how can the fact that some large groups consequence of his failing in his part, is the abandoning are organized be explained? Though many of the whole project. But it is very di‰cult, and indeed groups with common interests, like the con- impossible, that a thousand persons should agree in sumers, the white-collar workers, and the mi- any such action; it being di‰cult for them to concert so 1 complicated a design, and still more di‰cult for them grant agricultural workers, are not organized, to execute it; while each seeks a pretext to free himself other large groups, like the union laborers, the of the trouble and expense, and would lay the whole farmers, and the doctors have at least some burden on others. Political society easily remedies both degree of organization. The fact that there are these inconveniences. Magistrates find an immediate many groups which, despite their needs, are not interest in the interest of any considerable part of their organized would seem to contradict the ‘‘group subjects. They need consult nobody but themselves to theory’’ of the analytical pluralists; but on the form any scheme for promoting that interest. And as other hand the fact that other large groups have the failure of any one piece in the execution is con- been organized would seem to contradict the nected, though not immediately, with the failure of the theory of ‘‘latent groups’’ o¤ered in this study. whole, they prevent that failure, because they find no interest in it, either immediate or remote. Thus, bridges are built, harbours opened, ramparts raised, canals 1. ‘‘When lists of these organizations are examined, formed, fleets equipped, and armies disciplined, every- the fact that strikes the student most forcibly is that the where, by the care of government, which, though system is very small. The range of organized, identifi- composed of men subject to all human infirmities, able, known groups is amazingly narrow; there is becomes, by one of the finest and most subtile inven- nothing remotely universal about it.’’ E. E. Schatt- tions imaginable, a composition which is in some schneider, The Semi-Sovereign People (New York: measure exempted from all these infirmities.’’ Holt, Rinehart & Winston, 1960), p. 30. Interest Groups 379

But the large economic groups that are or recreational benefits to individual members, organized do have one common characteristic would have a source of these positive induce- which distinguishes them from those large eco- ments.2 Only such an organization could make a nomic groups that are not. . . . joint o¤ering or ‘‘tied sale’’ of a collective and a The common characteristic which distin- noncollective good that could stimulate a ratio- guishes all of the large economic groups with nal individual in a large group to bear part of the significant lobbying organizations is that these cost of obtaining a collective good.3 There are groups are also organized for some other pur- pose. The large and powerful economic lobbies 2. An economic organization in a perfectly competi- are in fact the by-products of organizations that tive market in equilibrium, which had no special obtain their strength and support because they competitive advantage that could bring it a large perform some function in addition to lobbying amount of ‘‘rent,’’ would have no ‘‘profits’’ or other for collective goods. spare resources it could use as selective incentives for a The lobbies of the large economic groups are lobby. Nonetheless there are many organizations that the by-products of organizations that have the do have spare returns they can use for selective incen- tives. First, markets with some degree of monopoly capacity to ‘‘mobilize’’ a latent group with power are far more common than perfectly competitive ‘‘selective incentives.’’ The only organizations markets. Second, there are sometimes important com- that have the ‘‘selective incentives’’ available are plementaries between the economic and political activ- those that (1) have the authority and capacity ities of an organization. The political branch of the to be coercive, or (2) have a source of positive organization can win lower taxes or other favorable inducements that they can o¤er the individuals government policies for the economic branch, and the in a latent group. good name won by the political branch may also help A purely political organization—an organiza- the economic branch. For somewhat similar reasons, a tion that has no function apart from its lobbying social organization may also be a source of a surplus function—obviously cannot legally coerce indi- that can be used for selective incentives. An organization that is not only political, but eco- viduals into becoming members. A political nomic or social as well, and has a surplus that provides party, or any purely political organization, with selective incentives, may be able to retain its member- a captive or compulsory membership would be ship and political power, it certain cases, even if its quite unusual in a democratic political system. leadership manages to use some of the political or But if for some nonpolitical reason, if because economic power of the organization for objectives of some other function it performs, an organiza- other than those desired by the membership, since the tion has a justification for having a compulsory members of the organization will have an incentive membership, or if through this other function it to continue belonging even if they disagree with the has obtained the power needed to make mem- organization’s policy. This may help explain why many bership in it compulsory, that organization may lobbying organizations take positions that must be uncongenial to their membership, and why organi- then be able to get the resources needed to sup- zations with leaders who corruptly advance their own port a lobby. The lobby is then a by-product of interests at the expense of the organization continue to whatever function this organization performs survive. that enables it to have a captive membership. 3. The worth of the noncollective or private benefit An organization that did nothing except lobby would have to exceed its cost by an amount greater to obtain a collective good for some large group than the dues to the lobbying branch of the organiza- would not have a source of rewards or positive tion, or the joint o¤ering would not be su‰cient to selective incentives it could o¤er potential mem- attract members to the organization. Note that . . . bers. Only an organization that also sold private selective incentives were defined to be values larger in or noncollective products, or provided social absolute magnitude than an individual’s share of the costs of the collective good. Chapter 7 380

for this reason many organizations that have both lobbying functions and economic functions, or lobbying functions and social functions, or even all three of these types of functions at once.4 Therefore, in addition to the large group lobbies that depend on coercion, there are those that are associated with organizations that pro- vide noncollective or private benefits which can be o¤ered to any potential supporter who will bear his share of the cost of the lobbying for the collective good. The by-product theory of pressure groups need apply only to the large or latent group. It need not apply to the privileged or intermediate groups, because these smaller groups can often provide a lobby, or any other collective benefit, without any selective incentives. . . . It applies to latent groups because the individual in a latent group has no incentive voluntarily to sacrifice his time or money to help an organization obtain a collective good; he alone cannot be decisive in determining whether or not this collective good will be obtained, but if it is obtained because of the e¤orts of others he will inevitably be able to enjoy it in any case. Thus he would support the organization with a lobby working for collective goods only if (1) he is coerced into paying dues to the lobbying organization, or (2) he has to support this group in order to obtain some other noncollective benefit. Only if one or both of these conditions hold will the potential political power of a latent group be mobilized. . . .

4. An organization that lobbied to provide a collective good for a large group might even obtain its selective incentives by lobbying also for noncollective ‘‘politi- cal’’ goods, like individual exceptions to (or advanta- geous interpretations of ) a general rule or law, or for patronage for particular individuals, etc. The point is not that the organization must necessarily also be eco- nomic or social as well as political (though that is usu- ally the case); it is rather that, if the organization does not have the capacity to coerce potential members, it must o¤er some noncollective, i.e., selective, benefit to potential members. Neo-Pluralism: A Class Analysis of Pluralism I and Pluralism II

John F. Manley

To anyone interested in understanding political serious doubts have arisen about the theory’s power in the United States, social scientists o¤er ability to explain the American system. Strong three main general theories: pluralism, the most doubts have arisen, too, about the relationship widely accepted theory; pluralism’s old antag- between pluralism and such central issues of onist, elitism, the next most widely accepted democratic theory as equality, distributive jus- theory; and class or structural analysis, whose tice, and peaceful social change. If Kuhn (1962, locus classicus is Karl Marx’s Capital, which is p. 52) is right that scientific understanding generally not accepted at all.1 advances when old paradigms are supplanted by Pluralism, elitism, and class analysis have di- new theories that are thought to be better able to vided students of power for decades, but there is account for strategically important facts, it may little doubt that pluralism is the dominant theory be time to begin the search for a theory that or paradigm of power among American social is better than pluralism at explaining class and scientists. Although research regularly turns group power in the United States. So, at any up evidence supporting the other two theories rate, is the suggestion of this article. (Higley and Moore, 1981, p. 595), it is no empty At one time, pluralism was a reasonably boast for pluralists to claim a generally favorable coherent theory whose claims appeared to many response to their critique of elitism and class analysis (Polsby, 1980, p. 141).2 2. Assessing the pluralist paradigm is complicated by In the past several years, however, political the fact that the three theories of power are by no and economic developments in the United States means neatly distinguished in the literature. In Polsby’s have placed the pluralist paradigm under a good hands, for example, pluralism rejects five central prop- deal of strain. Even inside the pluralist school, ositions of the ‘‘stratificationist literature’’ which em- brace propositions from both elite and class analysis: the upper class rules local community life; political and Excerpted from: John F. Manley, ‘‘Neo-Pluralism: A civic leaders are subordinate to the upper class; a single Amer- Class Analysis of Pluralism I and Pluralism II.’’ ‘‘power elite’’ rules locally; this elite rules in its own ican Political Science Review 77, no. 2 (1983): 368–383. interest; and social conflict takes place between the 6 American Political Science Association. Reprinted upper and lower classes (Polsby, 1980, pp. 8–13). Ad- with the permission of the American Political Science ditional complications are that much leading work on Association and Cambridge University Press. elite theory has been done not on local communities 1. In using the term structural analysis I do not want where pluralist research has often been concentrated, to get embroiled in contemporary controversies among but on the national power structure. And although Marxists over structuralism, instrumentalism, and the some elitists are fairly comfortable with class analysis like. By structural analysis I mean to conjure nothing (Domho¤, 1978, p. 140), such a leading figure as more than Marx’s emphasis on the structure of classes C. Wright Mills takes pains to reject it (Mills, 1959, stemming from the division of society into those who p. 277). own and control the basic means of production, and Porous boundaries among the three theories, cou- those who do not. is a theory that puts class pled with internal variations among those who may be structure at the center of its analysis. Nothing more identified with one of the three camps, make compar- than this perspective is suggested here. I would like to isons di‰cult (Nicholls, 1974). But if these theories are thank the following people for comments on an earlier to be useful in understanding the realities of power, it version of this article: Kennette Benedict, Sue Bessmer, seems necessary to identify some propositions on which Heinz Eulau, Ken Dolbeare, Nancy Hartsock, Henry pluralists tend to agree, and to critique these proposi- Levin, Rick Olquin, Ben Page, and Don Share. tions from opposing perspectives. Chapter 7 382

political scientists to be solidly supported by to buttress the system, many pluralists were empirical research. Pluralism—what we shall scrupulous in noting the system’s flaws and defi- call pluralism I—asserts that the American ciencies. Indeed, the contradiction between the power structure is made up of many competing theory’s tendency to support the system and the elites, not just one. Di¤erent elites with low elite system’s increasingly disturbing performance has overlap operate in di¤erent issue areas. Political generated questions about the paradigm. Plural- and economic power are by no means evenly ism may be partial to the system, but pluralists distributed among the population, but inequality are not necessarily blind. Ironically, some of the is ‘‘noncumulative,’’ i.e., most people have some most thoughtful pluralists are currently among power resources, and no single asset (such as the most severe critics of the workings of Amer- money) confers excessive power. ican polyarchy. Pluralism I also sees the political system as If, as Marxists and non-Marxists agree, it is reasonably open to multiple interests if these important for system maintenance to have a co- interests feel strongly enough about an issue to herent theory that explains and justifies the sys- mobilize pressure. The power system is, to be tem, it is cause for reflection that in recent years sure, untidy, but the pulling and hauling of the theory of pluralism appears no more healthy diverse groups promotes ‘‘polyarchy.’’ ‘‘Poly- than the system itself. Beginning with Vietnam, archy’’ is Robert Dahl’s and Charles Lindblom’s the American has frequently term for systems run according to putative dem- resembled anarchy more than polyarchy. Such ocratic rules of the game (Dahl & Lindblom, debiliating developments as the war, Water- 1976, p. 277.)3 gate, persistent inflation and unemployment, the When, in 1967, Dahl published the first edi- forced retrenchment of the so-called welfare tion of his textbook, Pluralist Democracy in the state, and the deepening of gross inequalities United States, he identified multiple centers of have moved such leading pluralists as Dahl and power and limited popular sovereignty as the Lindblom so far to the ‘‘left’’ that scholars two basic axioms of American pluralism. He now talk of something called ‘‘neo’’ or ‘‘post- claimed, moreover, certain advantages for such pluralism.’’ That pluralism stands in need of re- a system: 1) power was tamed and coercion vision causes no surprise. No theory as closely minimized; 2) the consent of all citizens was tied to the system as pluralism could be unaf- promoted (in the long run); and 3) the system fected by that system’s performance. But it must fostered the peaceful settlement of conflicts to be asked, how far ‘‘left’’ can pluralism go with- the mutual benefit of most if not all the con- out exposing the need for a new, nonpluralist tending parties (Dahl, 1967, p. 24). Pluralism theory that may better fit the realities of political was thus o¤ered as a theory of power in America and economic power in the United States? and as justification as well. As measured by pluralism’s own values, not In addition to the above ideas, pluralists just Marx’s, the performance of the American prided themselves on hard, realistic analyses political economy has been so poor that the of politics. Even though the basic theory tended theory of pluralism, in an e¤ort to adapt, has been thrown into confusion. The two men who 3. From here on, polyarchy will not be placed in quo- probably did more than anyone else in the past tation marks, but this does not mean that I accept it as 30 years to modernize the theory of pluralism, an accurate description of the American system. Poly- Dahl and Lindblom, have been so disturbed archy is a term that contains descriptive and evaluative by the system’s performance that they have meanings that are, at best, highly problematic when issued radical-sounding calls for major structural applied to American political economy. reforms and redistribution of wealth and income, Interest Groups 383

and have even questioned the capitalist system neously to uphold most of the essential elements itself. The problem, from the theoretical point of of pluralism I. Pluralism II now tries to hold in view, is that these changes in pluralism—which balance severe criticisms of the system’s perfor- are so extensive that one may now distinguish mance, the need for major structural reforms, between pluralism I and pluralism II—clash with support for redistribution of wealth and income, previously received wisdom about the nature and and more government ownership of private en- legitimacy of power in America. As a result, terprise, at the same time that it supports social pluralism II now calls into serious question much pluralism as necessary for democracy, denies of what generations of American political scien- the special importance of class, reconfirms the tists have taught and believed is true about plu- inevitability and value of incremental change, ralist democracy in the United States. . . . and sees incrementalism as a way of achieving Pluralism has traditionally downplayed class, major structural reforms. The problem, from the but there is a related and equally important dif- theoretical point of view, is that pluralism II ference between pluralism and class analysis. still defends many features of the system that These theories have historically been caught up perpetuate the social results it now deplores. in the battle between socialism and capitalism Obviously, pluralism is not proved false merely that has raged since the mid-nineteenth century. because the system does not attain the goals Social scientists, however much they may claim held by Dahl and Lindblom. But there is no value-neutrality in their work, can hardly deny doubt that the system’s failure to live up to their the political implications of a position that expectations has induced them to make major denies either the existence or importance of so- alterations in the theory. cial classes. If classes in capitalist society are so Dahl and Lindblom decry the ‘‘incapacities’’ fragmented that the concept of class is of doubt- and even the ‘‘perversities’’ of American poly- ful analytical utility, then the Marxian analysis archy because, even after years of opportunity, it and critique of capitalism are seriously under- failed to live up to their expectations of progress mined. If, on the other hand, class is found to on economic and social equality. They charge be of prime significance, the work of Marx, and that the politico-economic system ‘‘remains both the corresponding socialist critique of capitalism, sluggish and feckless in advancing on problems take on added force. As a theory of how society on which it has the advantage of decades of ex- works, pluralism may claim that all it does is re- perience in policy making: poverty and maldis- port, not evaluate, the facts. In sharp contrast, tribution of income and wealth, racial inequality, class analysis openly deplores the facts it consid- health care, public education, inflation and un- ers of paramount importance to understanding employment, and industrial relations, for exam- capitalist society. Whatever one’s position on the ple’’ (Dahl & Lindblom, 1976, p. xxi). possibility of value-free social research, however, But unless one assumes that capitalist poly- there is no doubt that until recently, pluralism, in archy in time will advance equality to a signifi- sharp contrast with class analysis, rarely raised cant extent, there is no reason for surprise (or questions about the legitimacy of capitalism. . . . lamentation) at its failure to do so. Class analysis To be sure, neither Dahl nor Lindblom is and, to a lesser extent, elitism see the mainte- unmindful of the potential strains between so- nance of inequality under capitalism not as a cialism and pluralist democracy, but their ma- failure of polyarchy—not an incapacity or even ture theory seems to take pluralism far toward a perversity—but as the whole point. Only lib- a reconciliation with Marxist class analysis. It eral reformers lament polyarchy’s failure to pro- may, therefore, come as something of a shock to mote equality. Conservatives oppose most such realize that Dahl and Lindblom appear simulta- e¤orts, whereas those on the left see government Chapter 7 384

as part of a larger problem, the political econ- this contradiction exposes the incompatibilities omy of capitalism. that still divide the two theories. In the final Herein may lie part of the key to understand- analysis, I argue, Dahl and Lindblom try to re- ing why pluralism II is not as radical a departure solve the contradictions of pluralist theory by from pluralism I as it might at first appear. The supporting increased incremental changes in a critical quotes from Dahl and Lindblom, all of system with essential structural inequalities— which express part of what they believe, are held inequalities that they themselves increasingly in tandem with a logically incompatible set of realize. . . . ideas. Only out of complete context is pluralism Class analysis sees capitalism as a political II consistent with such radical ideas as major economy objectively rooted in unequal power structural reform, redistribution of wealth and based on the unequal private ownership and income, and substantive equality. Grave short- control of the necessary means of social produc- comings of polyarchy are noted, to be sure. tion. Changes in capitalism must perforce raise Once-sacred cows, including free enterprise, are questions of class conflict, not mere public opin- seriously questioned. But pluralism still holds ion formation. By failing to take such consid- that the system’s gaps and omissions and down- erations fully into account, Dahl and Lindblom right failures can be corrected without specifying have from the class perspective only weakly how much structural change or redistribution anchored their critical analysis of capitalism. As of wealth and income are needed. The system a necessary consequence, their call for reforms needs major structural reform, to be sure, but, as is likewise only loosely based, theoretically we shall see, major structural reform does not speaking. mean basic alterations in class structure or class power. Despite an appeal by Dahl and Lind- blom for ‘‘Marxist humanists’’ to join pluralists The Pluralist Theory of Equality in a united front behind the integrity of autono- mous groups, pluralism remains profoundly at Historically, pluralism and class analysis have odds with class analysis. Endorsement of such clashed head-on over the issue of equality. Both socialistic-sounding proposals as redistribution theories endorse equality and present themselves of wealth and income seems to close the gap, but as ways of attaining it, but this is possible this is illusory. A closer look indicates that the only because they have meant radically di¤erent theories are, on balance, far apart on most es- things by the term. Pluralist democracy, further- sential questions. Pluralism and class analysis, it more, pits equality as a value against a second appears, cannot be logically integrated without great democratic value, liberty, and tends to see great distortion in the substantive integrity of the two as trade-o¤s. In the nineteenth century, both theories. as Lindblom (1977, p. 163) notes, ‘‘Marx and the To explore this theme it will be useful to ex- socialists became the spokesmen for equality, amine first the issue of social vs. private owner- liberals the spokesmen for liberty.’’ Since then, ship and control of property. Class analysis and as he also notes, the value of equality has been pluralism are then shown to clash, as always, subordinated to liberty in liberal democratic over the question of equality. Pluralist political theory. theory and a capitalist economy, it is argued, Marx and later socialists deny the contradic- are more consistent with social inequality than tion between equality and liberty. True liberty equality. When coupled with the contradiction is impossible without equality; to be truly free, between pluralism’s attachment to incremental individuals in society must be roughly equal in change and the call for major structural reforms, the means necessary to exercise freedom. Far Interest Groups 385

from being opposed to liberty, equality is its separately a few years later, concludes that the necessary condition. ‘‘distribution of advantages and disadvantages is For Dahl (1982, p. 108) ‘‘Democracy is and often arbitrary, capricious, unmerited, and un- has always been closely associated in practice just, and in virtually all advanced countries no with private ownership of the means of produc- longer tolerable.’’ It is so intolerable, in fact, that tion.’’ By democracy, of course, Dahl means he has kind words to say for central government liberal or bourgeois democracy, not democracy tax and transfer payments to reduce inequality, in the socialist sense. But the close connection as long as individuals are free to spend as they between capitalism and liberal democracy raises choose. the knotty issue of substantive equality vs. There are, however, three major defects in equality of opportunity. If the means of produc- pluralism’s treatment of equality. First, plural- tion are privately and unequally owned under ism has no clear criteria or standard for assessing capitalism, capitalism seems to be based on sub- what is just or unjust about the distribution of stantive economic inequality, from which flows, values in society. Second, pluralism treats public as Dahl admits, a certain level of political in- opinion as the explanation of inequality in the equality. The only form of equality that is logi- United States and as the vehicle for future egali- cally compatible with substantive inequality is tarian changes. Third, not all groups in the plu- equality of opportunity which, as Scharr (1967) ralist United States are equal, as pluralism grants and others have argued, is really the equal op- in the privileged-position-of-business argument, portunity to become unequal. From Thomas but the special place of business has not yet been Je¤erson’s defense of the natural aristocracy of fully integrated into a theory rooted in multiple, talent, through social Darwinism’s defense of the independent, and autonomous groups as the survival of the fittest, to present-day exaltations necessary building blocks of pluralist democracy. of individualism and competition, liberal de- mocracy has consistently defended equal oppor- tunity and the inequalities in the distribution of Just and Unjust Distribution rewards that flow naturally from it. The ques- tion this raises is, of course: Can pluralist or Pluralism’s discussion of equality is curiously liberal democracy be reconciled with class or so- indeterminate because pluralism lacks a clear cialist democracy if the two theories conflict so principle or theory for assessing just and unjust profoundly over the priority and meaning of distributions of wealth, income, and property. It equality? lacks a theory of value. Consider the issue of The decisive shift of pluralism II is toward political equality. Because political equality is substantive equality and away from equal op- obviously undermined to some degree by eco- portunity as the preferred democratic ideal. nomic inequality, pluralism’s call for redistribu- Having called for the redistribution of wealth tion makes good logical sense. But in the past, and income, Dahl and Lindblom (1976) logically pluralism has not set equality of conditions as break the historical connection between capital- its goal. Without an underlying theory of value, ism and liberal democracy. They also partially it is impossible to assess clearly and logically correct pluralism’s tendency to separate political why a particular distribution is just or unjust. and economic equality by noting that, ‘‘We can- ‘‘Inequalities in distribution are, of course, not not move closer to greater equality in access to inherently unjust’’ (Dahl & Lindblom, 1976, political resources without greater equality in the p. xxxi). In other words, inequality is not in distribution of, among other things, wealth and principle bad; ceteris paribus, some inequality is income’’ (p. xxxii). Dahl (1982, p. 117), writing in principle just. Inequality, then, is not a matter Chapter 7 386

of principle but of pragmatics: the degree of ical commitment to distributive justice, and such inequality exceeds any principle of distributive major changes are unlikely in the American sys- justice Dahl and Lindblom find acceptable. They tem where intense minorities are powerful. These therefore deplore the gross level of inequality pragmatic objections, however valid, should not and call for (unspecified) egalitarian changes. be allowed to mask the logical dilemma: if, as When Dahl and Lindblom endorse the redis- pluralism now grants, economic resources are tribution of wealth and income, they endorse often directly convertible into political resources, substantive equality, not mere equality of op- it seems to follow that political equality requires portunity. When they endorse structural reforms, the redistribution of economic resources. Dahl, the suggestion is made that structural reforms however, refuses to go this far. He prefers regu- should be made to promote substantive equality. lating the political e¤ects of economic inequal- But when they simultaneously argue that in- ities, a position that, at best, deals only indirectly equality is not unjust per se and do not confront with the problem. Regulating the political e¤ects the key issue of degrees of inequality, they cloud of economic inequality (e.g., by controlling the case for equality. The flip side of the question campaign contributions) may promote equality of how much equality pluralism supports is how indirectly, but it seems a major concession and a much inequality it is willing to tolerate. In Dahl’s move away from pluralism II’s seeming accep- case the argument for redistribution and equality tance of greater substantive equality as a social leads to a box canyon of an indefinite number goal. of principles that might be used to allocate How does class analysis approach equality incomes, no one of which is clearly or theoreti- under capitalist social relations? Such questions cally superior to the others (Dahl, 1982, pp. raise a host of complex issues that cannot be 135–137). Economics, to which Dahl turns for discussed here, but the starting point of any help, lacks a theory of value that can address comparison would have to be Marx’s audacious just and unjust distributions (1982, p. 134). The claim in volume 3 of Capital that he had uncov- marginal theory of value does not tra‰c in ered the innermost secret, the hidden basis of the such philosophical issues and hence is of no entire social structure of capitalism, and with it help. Unless and until pluralism addresses the the political form of the capitalist state. What question of how much equality is just or unjust, was the key that could unlock so much knowl- the critical question of degree goes begging. edge? It was the relationship between capitalists Calls for more equality, however attractive they and workers ‘‘in which unpaid surplus labour may sound politically, remain unsupported is pumped out of direct producers, [and which] theoretically. . . . determines the relationship of rulers and ruled, A related problem with pluralism’s treatment as it grows directly out of production itself and, of equality is the theory’s tendency, still, to sep- in turn, reacts upon it as a determining element’’ arate political equality from economic equality, (Marx, 1967, III, p. 791). a separation which, for class analysis, makes lit- Marx was quick to recognize that although tle sense. Pluralism is quite clear that economic he saw the surplus-labor relationship as the key inequality frequently undermines political equal- to understanding capitalism, the same eco- ity, but in Dahl’s work, for all the apparent sup- nomic base could give rise to infinite variation port for redistribution, the theory actually shies depending on innumerable di¤erent empirical away from making an unequivocal endorse- circumstances, natural environment, and racial ment. In his essay on liberal democracy, Dahl relations, among other determinants. But the (1979a, pp. 65–66) rejects direct redistribution important point for this discussion is that Marx’s on grounds that it would require a major histor- claim points up a key di¤erence between plural- Interest Groups 387

ism and class analysis: class analysis proceeds this is not the main point. Far more significant, from an explicit theory of value; pluralism does from the class perspective, is the unreality of not. relying on public opinion to advance equality. Marx anchors Capital in a theory of value for These are matters that, under capitalism, are a very good reason. Without a theory of value, systematically excluded from the American po- he was at a loss to present a principled attack litical arena. It is hardly the American people’s on capitalism. He might personally deplore fault that wealth and income are highly concen- inequality, but he needed a theory of value to trated. Nor will public opinion necessarily bring establish socialism as qualitatively superior to about more equality. In a capitalist setting eco- capitalism. His answer was the labor theory of nomic equality is not even a virtue, let alone a value and, for all the debate that has surrounded matter to be decided by public debate. The real- that theory of value, at least he had one. . . . ization of equality requires fundamental changes . . . However flawed Marx’s labor theory may in the system that makes inequality a virtue, a be, future comparisons of pluralism and class system strengthened, perhaps inadvertently, by analysis await the former’s attention to a theory theories of distributive justice which, in the name of value that can address the question of just and of equality, justify its opposite. unjust distribution. Until that theory is o¤ered, the two theories cannot join clearly on the most fundamental question of all: why, if everywhere The Imperfect Balance of Group Power men and women are born equal, are the many everywhere regularly chained in submission to If the level of equality is viewed as a structural the few? feature of the political economy and not a matter of public opinion, what is the relationship be- tween equality and another feature of the Amer- Public Opinion ican system, the existence of groups? According to Dahl and Lindblom, social pluralism, defined A second problem with the pluralist treatment of as a diversity of autonomous social organiza- equality is that, again, the problem is laid at the tions, is a necessary condition of polyarchy. But doorstep of the American people. Speaking of pluralism sees two nagging flaws in polyarchy. their call for a ‘‘fairer’’ share of income and First, not all groups are equal; not everyone wealth: ‘‘Until more Americans accept this view organizes at the same rate, and power resources and act on it, the United States will not be the are not evenly distributed. Specifically, the progressive society we wrongly assumed it to be better-o¤ participate more. ‘‘As a consequence, at the time we wrote. Polyarchy may continue government decisions reflect and reinforce a to exist at the present level, but democracy will structure of inequalities’’ (Dahl & Lindblom, still remain a long way o¤’’ (Dahl & Lindblom, 1976, p. xxxvi). This pluralism acknowledges. 1976, p. xxxii). Both Dahl and Lindblom repeat A related inegalitarian feature of polyarchy these arguments in their post-1976 work. is the privileged position of business. Business is There are dangers in conceptualizing the not just another interest group. True, it plays a problem in terms of public opinion. One danger powerful interest-group role. But it also tran- is that one of the best known surveys on equality scends such a limited role. As Dahl and Lind- in America shows that the mass of the American blom describe it, the American political economy people has been more supportive of economic is co-directed unequally by business and govern- equality than the elites (McClosky, 1964, p. 369). ment, and in that order. Great public decisions But public opinion is notoriously volatile, and are left to the market; government’s job is to Chapter 7 388

induce (not command) business to perform its portant here to debate the point than to note functions. Pluralist theories that stress balance that pluralism II is as ideologically committed and countervailing power among interest groups, to social pluralism as was pluralism I. Plural- and fail to take into account the unique ad- ism puts considerable emphasis on the social vantages enjoyed by business, are thereby im- and economic inequalities that undermine po- peached by Dahl and Lindblom. litical equality. It now recognizes the unique Having thus arrived roughly at where Marx position of one elite, business, in the Ameri- began, Dahl and Lindblom nevertheless continue can political economy. But, as E. E. Schatt- to endorse the theory and practice of pluralism. schneider put it years ago, the ‘‘flaw in the Indeed, they even detect a lessening of antipathy pluralist heaven is that the heavenly chorus sings toward pluralism among European ‘‘Marxist with a strong upper-class accent’’ (Schatt- humanists’’ and suggest an emerging consensus schneider, 1960, p. 35). One has to ask whether on the need for autonomous groups as a bridge or not Dahl and Lindblom have faced up to the between the two opposing theoretical camps. contradictions they increasingly perceive among As Dahl and Lindblom see it, the rigidly anti- social pluralism, equality, and polyarchy. Their pluralist Marxism of Stalin is on the way out, so faith in the superiority of social pluralism and the door is open to a reconciliation between plu- polyarchy over currently available alternatives ralism and ‘‘Marxist humanism.’’ remains strong, but the special place accorded ‘‘But what about equality?’’ the skeptic may business has not yet been squared with a theory well ask. If even pluralists agree that business emphasizing a multiplicity of groups as a pre- occupies a superior position in capitalism, if condition of pluralist democracy. pluralists recognize that di¤erential group power The central question, of course, is can the may act as an obstacle to democratization, and if privileged position of business be squared with pluralist politics tends to reflect and reinforce the pluralist democracy? Lindblom suggests it can’t. advantages of the better-o¤, business-oriented Dahl’s answer is less clear. . . . groups may so impede equality that some cen- . . . [I]f it is true that pluralism has always rec- tralizing, democratic, public force may be neces- ognized that not all groups are equal, it is also sary to advance the egalitarian cause. true that pluralism seems to require the assump- Dahl and Lindblom admit this possibility, tion of at least some rough equality among but reject it. In fact, they o¤er no solution to the groups for a system to be a polyarchy. Unless tension between unequal social pluralism and power is decentralized among many groups, democratic equality, but they are clear about pluralism is falsified, and some form of elite defending groups, and while rejecting one form theory or class analysis better fits the empirical of Marxism, they extend an olive branch to an- facts. The balance may be imperfect, but it is other. In their words, ‘‘Whatever the best solu- hard to see how pluralism can dispense with tion to this problem (of equality) may be, for the notion of some sort of balance, some sort of Americans, at least, it is not to be found, in rough parity or countervailing power, without our view, in destroying organizational autonomy sliding over into elite or class explanations of and replacing autonomy with centralization, power. So far pluralism has not specified the command, hierarchy, bureaucracy, and domina- parameters or levels of power distribution neces- tion by an enlightened elite’’ (Dahl & Lindblom, sary for a system to be judged a pluralist de- 1976, p. xxxvi). mocracy. But if business is as privileged and Portraying the alternative to social pluralism as powerful as pluralism now says, vexing ques- as ‘‘domination by an enlightened elite’’ may tions are raised about the democratic character not exhaust the possibilities, but it is less im- of capitalist regimes. Class analysis, of course, Interest Groups 389

asserts that the power of business in a capitalist will work its e¤ects on various problems con- system makes liberal democracy a contradiction fronting American society. in terms. On this point, as on so many others, the From the rea‰rmation of incrementalism, two theories stand so far apart that they are best which by definition ensures at best slow changes seen as implacable opponents than as potential in the status quo, one might expect Dahl and partners for a merger. Lindblom to caution against major reforms, but they do not. They believe major structural reforms follow from their analysis: ‘‘It follows Structural Reform from all we have said that we believe that major structural reforms are required in the American One area of agreement between pluralism II and political-economic system’’ (Dahl & Lindblom, class analysis is the dismal performance of the 1976, p. xli). American political economy in the past few de- It might be asked, however, that if incremen- cades. Both theories support major ‘‘structural’’ talism is a rational aid to change, if incremen- changes. But on close inspection, they mean very talism assures progress (albeit slow) on social di¤erent things by structural reform. In fact, problems, and if in any event nonincremental pluralism’s call for structural reform is so condi- change occurs so rarely, why the call for required tional and narrowly defined that the two theories structural reforms in the American politico- remain fundamentally divided over this question. economic system? As defenders of incremen- ‘‘Structural reform’’ is, of course, an idea talism and incremental change, do Dahl and closely associated with social democratic cri- Lindblom mean by structural reform what most tiques of capitalism. The basic idea is that trans- people mean? Does structural reform mean the formational changes can be made in capitalism replacement of capitalism by a dominantly to reduce or eliminate such serious capitalist socialist political economy? Or is structural re- ‘‘perversities’’ as inequality. The endorsement form another name for incremental change— of structural reform apparently brings pluralism souped-up incremental change, but nonetheless and class analysis, capitalism and socialism, incremental? closer together. The fact is that pluralism II’s support for But here Dahl and Lindblom take a step that government ownership and control is softened radically alters their course and demonstrates the by several caveats: the issue of control precedes continuing split between the two theories. It the issue of ownership, so if other control mech- occurs when they question a feature of polyarchy anisms can be found, they may supersede gov- with which they are prominently associated: ernment; government ownership is declared to be incrementalism. . . . definitely not a su‰cient means to public con- Far from abandoning incrementalism, how- trol; in many cases it is probably not even a ever, Dahl and Lindblom, in their joint work necessary means; and in some cases it may be a and in subsequent individual publications, argue hindrance. . . . pragmatically that to propose nonincremental I think it is fair to conclude that Dahl and changes in a society only capable of incremental Lindblom’s endorsement of government owner- change is virtually a waste of time (Dahl, 1982, ship as a means of public control is, at most, pp. 120–126; Lindblom, 1977, ch. 19). No one limited. knows, they assert, how to design a political More broadly, the case for major structural system regularly capable of more than incre- reforms concentrates on defects in the existing mental change. . . . With the removal of some decision-making and policymaking institutions veto powers, they promise, incremental change of society, not class structure. Perhaps most sur- Chapter 7 390

prising of all, when Dahl and Lindblom face or in the distribution of wealth is necessary the question of how such reforms are to be to achieve such values as freedom and equality, brought about, they answer—by the institutions the basic questions go begging. In contrast, class themselves. . . . theory asserts a contradiction between Lind- . . . Dahl and Lindblom are aware that their blom’s grand issues and the general values for position leaves them open to the charge that which pluralism and class analysis both stand. they su¤er from a ‘‘residual naive optimism of The pluralist position is much less clear. Plural- liberalism.’’ But social institutions, they reply, do ism now admits some connection between grand change. Reforms do occur. And what is the best issues and general values, but is fuzzy about and most common method by which these nec- the crucial question of whether or not there is essary changes occur? Incrementalism. a contradiction, and how much change in the Pluralism II resoundingly a‰rms incremen- grand issues (e.g., private enterprise) is needed to talism as the preferred method of achieving promote the grand values (e.g., political equal- major structural reforms in polyarchy. How does ity). Class or structural analysis insists that the pluralism II arrive at this conclusion? It detects grand values cannot be attained within the con- in incrementalism a hitherto overlooked capacity fines of capitalism; pluralism either takes no such to undermine the status quo. By increasing the clear-cut stand or a‰rms the opposite. This cru- pace of incremental change, small accretions, far cial di¤erence, when added to class theory’s from being ways of ensuring modest changes in insistence on nonincremental changes in class the status quo, will transform the system. . . . structure, and pluralism’s clear preference for It is certainly arguable how much structural incremental changes not in class structure but reform can be smuggled into the American sys- in social institutions, clarify crucial di¤erences tem through incremental methods, but further between the two theories. complications arise from a related contention. Clearly pluralism and class analysis mean very Although a‰rming the need for major structural di¤erent things by the term ‘‘structural reform.’’ reform, Dahl and Lindblom oppose any changes Marxist class theory and even social democratic in the ‘‘general values’’ for which the Ameri- theories use the term to apply to changes in cap- can system stands. Changes in general values italism and the class structure embedded in cap- are neither necessary nor desirable. Structural italist social relations. In sharp contrast, recent reforms, then, are limited to those features of pluralist theory does not address the question the system that inhibit changes in ‘‘proximate of class structure in contemplating structural re- goals,’’ not general values. form. Indeed, pluralism contends that structural When Dahl and Lindblom discuss general reforms may emanate from the market system values, they seem to be referring to such abstract that structural analysis means to transform. In values as freedom, democracy, political equality, assessing pluralism’s call for structural reform, and majority rule. These values are sacrosanct therefore, it is crucial to note the singular inter- (though not absolute). The biases of American pretation given the term. When pluralists pro- institutions against changes in these values pose structural reforms they are not talking should be maintained. Faster incremental change about egalitarian changes in the class structure is therefore restricted to ‘‘proximate goals.’’ Here of American capitalist society. They are not they endorse not only the removal of barriers talking about ‘‘phasing out’’ the capitalist class against change, but their replacement by biases through redistributive taxes, controls on inheri- toward change. . . . tance, or a levelling of work hierarchies and . . . [U]nless pluralism faces squarely how rewards. Major structural reform for Dahl and much change in the private enterprise system Lindblom means changes in the existing deci- Interest Groups 391

sion-making institutions of society; moreover inequality than is tolerable in class theory. This such changes are to be brought about slowly seems true, moreover, even if pluralism accepts through incrementalism. It is hard to see how Rawls’s theory of distributive justice as its own. class analysis and pluralism can be brought It bears repeating that the di¤erence principle closer together unless and until they agree that defends inequalities as just as long as they make such ‘‘grand issues’’ as the private enterprise everyone better o¤; it is not a straightforward system itself, and the class structure that goes argument for substantive equality. with it, should not only be placed on the political Pluralism I and II, then, despite the call (at agenda but resolved in such a way that non- least by Lindblom) for redistribution, seem more incremental progress is made toward true sub- compatible with equality of opportunity than stantive equality. . . . equality of results. Equal opportunity to com- . . . In pluralist theory, classes have merely a pete in a race that necessarily results in a small nominal existence compared to groups; in class number of winners and a large number of losers analysis, groups are seen and analyzed as frac- is Orwellian newspeak. It defends inequality in tions or sub-parts or classes. Until some recon- the name of equality (Scharr, 1967, p. 234), and ciliation of this conflict is o¤ered, it is hard to helps induce mass acquiescence in the perpetua- see how class analysis and pluralism can be tion of an unequal social order. To the extent joined along the lines attempted by Dahl and that pluralism does the same, it belies the es- Lindblom. pousal of substantive equality through the redis- tribution of wealth and income. In the structural view, inequality under capi- Summary and Conclusion talism is not a by-product of the system that is amenable to polyarchal corrections. It is a struc- Pluralism II updates pluralist theory in light tural imperative. It is one of the things that of such incapacities and perversities as Vietnam, makes capitalism capitalism and distinguishes it Watergate, and persistent economic and political from socialism. From the class perspective, in- inequality. Despite an opening to the left, how- equality is as likely to be significantly reduced or ever, pluralism II remains a theory that is logi- eliminated under capitalism as the meek are to cally more compatible with, and supportive of, a inherit the earth. The fundamental reason this is capitalist political economy than a socialist one. so is the essential, structural relationship between Class analysis and pluralism are profoundly capital and labor in a capitalist society: they are, split over equality (Dahl, 1979b; Green, 1979). by definition, unequal. . . . Pluralism now pays attention to the problem of It might be judged excessive to contend that economic and political inequality, but it falls pluralism is in danger of imploding from internal short of endorsing full substantive equality as a contradictions, but in light of the di‰culties social goal. As Bell has noted, the claim for raised above, it might not be excessive to sug- equality of result is a socialist ethic, as equality gest that pluralist theory is in need of some of opportunity is the liberal ethic (Bell, 1972, p. clarification. 48). Marxian socialism points toward substan- A class or structural analysis of American po- tive equality because it is rooted in a theory of litical economy seems more consistent with the value that stresses the collective involvement of fact of gross inequality in wealth, income, and all members of society in producing social goods. power under capitalism. Capitalism makes a Pluralism lacks a clear theory of value, but its fetish of commodities, not equality. Indeed, it historic attachment to equality of opportunity presumes unequal natural talents and abilities seems to ensure the acceptance of more social and rewards, and justifies them under the theory Chapter 7 392

of equal opportunity. Pluralist theories would be Marx, K. Capital (Vols. 1, 3). New York: International more consistent if they dropped the untenable Publishers, 1967. adherence to substantive equality and faced up McClosky, H. Consensus and ideology in American to the reality of inequality in the system of politics. American Political Science Review, 1964, 58, which the theory of pluralism is an integral part. 361–382. Class analysis not only conforms better to many Mills, C. W. The power elite. New York: Oxford Uni- of the empirical realities of American political versity Press, 1959. economy, which saves it from wounded surprise Nicholls, D. Three varieties of pluralism. New York: St. over the system’s performance, but it clearly and Martin’s Press, 1974. consistently adheres to egalitarian standards that Polsby, N. W. Community power and political theory. flow from its analysis of the class structure of New Haven, Conn.: Yale University Press, 1980. capitalism. If American social science means to Scharr, J. Equality of opportunity and beyond. In J. R. explain better, let alone help change the Ameri- Pennock & J. W. Chapman (Eds.), Equality. New can political economy, the pluralist-elitist debate York: Atherton Press, 1967. might well be redirected in favor of explorations Schattschneider, E. E. The semi-sovereign people. New in class analysis. York: Holt, Rinehart and Winston, 1960.

References

Bell, D. Meritocracy and equality. The Public Interest, 1972, 29, 29–68. Dahl, R. A. Pluralist democracy in the United States. Chicago: Rand McNally, 1967. Dahl, R. A., & Lindblom, C. E. Politics, economics, and welfare. Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1976. Dahl, R. A. Liberal democracy in the United States. In W. S. Livingston (Ed.), A prospect for liberal democ- racy. Austin: University of Texas Press, 1979a, 57–72. Dahl, R. A. What is political equality? Dissent, 1979b, 26, 363–368. Dahl, R. A. Dilemmas of pluralist democracy. New Haven, Conn: Yale University Press, 1982. Domho¤, G. W. Who really rules? Santa Monica, Calif.: Goodyear Publishing, 1978. Green, P. What is political equality. Dissent, 1979, 26, 351–368. Higley, J., & Moore, G. Elite integration in the United States and Australia. American Political Science Re- view, 1981, 75, 581–597. Kuhn, T. The structure of scientific revolutions. Chi- cago: University of Chicago Press, 1962. Lindblom, C. E. Politics and markets. New York: Basic Books, 1977. The Theory of Economic Regulation

George J. Stigler

The state—the machinery and power of the What Benefits Can a State Provide to an state—is a potential resource or threat to every Industry? industry in the society. With its power to pro- hibit or compel, to take or give money, the state The state has one basic resource which in pure can and does selectively help or hurt a vast principle is not shared with even the mightiest of number of industries. That political juggernaut, its citizens: the power to coerce. The state can the petroleum industry, is an immense con- seize money by the only method which is permit- sumer of political benefits, and simultaneously ted by the laws of a civilized society, by taxation. the underwriters of marine insurance have their The state can ordain the physical movements of more modest repast. The central tasks of the resources and the economic decisions of house- theory of economic regulation are to explain holds and firms without their consent. These who will receive the benefits or burdens of regu- powers provide the possibilities for the utilization lation, what form regulation will take, and the of the state by an industry to increase its profit- e¤ects of regulation upon the allocation of ability. The main policies which an industry (or resources. occupation) may seek of the state are four. Regulation may be actively sought by an in- The most obvious contribution that a group dustry, or it may be thrust upon it. A central may seek of the government is a direct subsidy of thesis of this paper is that, as a rule, regulation is money. The domestic airlines received ‘‘air mail’’ acquired by the industry and is designed and subsidies (even if they did not carry mail) of $1.5 operated primarily for its benefit. There are reg- billion through 1968. The merchant marine has ulations whose net e¤ects upon the regulated in- received construction and operation subsidies dustry are undeniably onerous; a simple example reaching almost $3 billion since World War II. is the di¤erentially heavy taxation of the indus- The education industry has long shown a mas- try’s product (whiskey, playing cards). These terful skill in obtaining public funds: for exam- onerous regulations, however, are exceptional ple, universities and colleges have received and can be explained by the same theory that federal funds exceeding $3 billion annually in explains beneficial (we may call it ‘‘acquired’’) recent years, as well as subsidized loans for dor- regulation. . . . mitories and other construction. The veterans of . . . We assume that political systems are ra- wars have often received direct cash bonuses. . . . tionally devised and rationally employed, which The second major public resource commonly is to say that they are appropriate instruments sought by an industry is control over entry by for the fulfillment of desires of members of the new rivals. There is considerable, not to say ex- society. This is not to say that the state will serve cessive, discussion in economic literature of the any persons’s concept of the public interest: in- rise of peculiar price policies (limit prices), verti- deed the problem of regulation is the problem of cal integration, and similar devices to retard discovering when and why an industry (or other the rate of entry of new firms into oligopolistic group of likeminded people) is able to use the industries. Such devices are vastly less e‰cacious state for its purposes, or is singled out by the (economical) than the certificate of convenience state to be used for alien purposes. and necessity (which includes, of course, the im- port and production quotas of the oil and to- Excerpted from: George J. Stigler, The Citizen and bacco industries). . . . the State: Essays on Regulation. Chicago: University of We propose the general hypothesis: every in- Chicago Press, 1975. Reprinted by permission. dustry or occupation that has enough political Chapter 7 394

power to utilize the state will seek to control en- tions upon the exercise of cartel policies by an try. In addition, the regulatory policy will often industry. These limitations are of three sorts. be so fashioned as to retard the rate of growth First, the distribution of control of the indus- of new firms. For example, no new savings and try among the firms in the industry is changed. loan company may pay a dividend rate higher In an unregulated industry each firm’s influence than that prevailing in the community in its upon price and output is proportional to its endeavors to attract deposits.2 The power to share of industry output (at least in a simple limit the selling expenses of mutual funds, which arithmetic sense of direct capacity to change is soon to be conferred upon the Securities and output). The political decisions take account also Exchange Commission, will serve to limit the of the political strength of the various firms, so growth of small mutual funds and hence reduce small firms have a larger influence than they the sales costs of large funds. . . . would possess in an unregulated industry. . . . A third general set of powers of the state Second, the procedural safeguards required of which will be sought by the industry are those public processes are costly. The delays which are which a¤ect substitutes and complements. dictated by both law and bureaucratic thoughts Crudely put, the butter producers wish to sup- of self-survival can be large. . . . press margarine and encourage the production of Finally, the political process automatically bread. The airline industry actively supports the admits powerful outsiders to the industry’s federal subsidies to airports; the building trade councils. It is well known that the allocation of unions have opposed labor-saving materials television channels among communities does not through building codes. . . . maximize industry revenue but reflects pressures The fourth class of public policies sought by to serve many smaller communities. The aban- an industry is directed to price-fixing. Even the donment of an unprofitable rail line is an even industry that has achieved entry control will more notorious area of outsider participation. often want price controls administered by a body These limitations are predictable, and they with coercive powers. If the number of firms in must all enter into the calculus of the profitabil- the regulated industry is even moderately large, ity of regulation of an industry. . . . price discrimination will be di‰cult to maintain in the absence of public support. The prohibition The Costs of Obtaining Legislation of interest on demand deposits, which is proba- bly e¤ective in preventing interest payments to When an industry receives a grant of power from most non-business depositors, is a case in point. the state, the benefit to the industry will fall short Where there are no diseconomies of large scale of the damage to the rest of the community. for the individual firm (e.g., a motor trucking Even if there were no deadweight losses from firm can add trucks under a given license as acquired regulation, however, one might expect common carrier), price control is essential to a democratic society to reject such industry achieve more than competitive rates of return. requests unless the industry controlled a majority of the votes.6 . . . To explain why many industries Limitations upon Political Benefits These various political boons are not obtained 6. If the deadweight loss (of consumer and producer by the industry in a pure profit-maximizing surplus) is taken into account, even if the oil industry form. The political process erects certain limita- were in the majority it would not obtain the legislation if there were available some method of compensation (such as sale of votes) by which the larger damage of 2. The Federal Home Loan Bank is the regulatory the minority could be expressed e¤ectively against the body. It also controls the amount of advertising and lesser gains of the majority. other areas of competition. Interest Groups 395

are able to employ the political machinery to process cannot exclude the uninterested voter: their own ends, we must examine the nature of the abuses of any exclusion except self-exclusion the political process in a democracy. are obvious. Hence, the political process does A consumer chooses between rail and air not allow participation in proportion to interest travel, for example, by voting with his pocket- and knowledge. . . . book: he patronizes on a given day that mode of These characteristics of the political process transportation he prefers. A similar form of eco- can be modified by having numerous levels of nomic voting occurs with decisions on where to government . . . and by selective use of direct work or where to invest one’s capital. The mar- decision. The chief method of coping with the ket accumulates these economic votes, predicts characteristics, however, is to employ more or their future course, and invests accordingly. less full-time representatives organized in (dis- Because the political decision is coercive, the ciplined by) firms which are called political decision process is fundamentally di¤erent from parties or machines. that of the market. If the public is asked to The representative and his party are rewarded make a decision between two transportation for their discovery and fulfillment of the political media comparable to the individual’s decision on desires of their constituency by success in elec- how to travel—say, whether airlines or railroads tion and the perquisites of o‰ce. If the repre- should receive a federal subsidy—the decision sentative could confidently await reelection must be abided by everyone, travelers and non- whenever he voted against an economic policy travelers, travelers this year and travelers next that injured the society, he would assuredly do year. This compelled universality of political so. Unfortunately virtue does not always com- decisions makes for two di¤erences between mand so high a price. If the representative denies democratic political decision processes and mar- ten large industries their special subsidies of ket processes. money or governmental power, they will dedi- 1. The decisions must be made simultaneously cate themselves to the election of a more com- by a large number of persons (or their represen- plaisant successor: the stakes are that important. tatives): the political process demands simulta- This does not mean that every large industry can neity of decision. . . . get what it wants or all that it wants: it does The condition of simultaneity imposes a major mean that the representative and his party must burden upon the political decision process. It find a coalition of voter interests more durable makes voting on specific issues prohibitively than the anti-industry side of every industry expensive. . . . To cope with this condition of policy proposal. A representative cannot win or simultaneity, the voters must employ representa- keep o‰ce with the support of the sum of those tives with wide discretion and must eschew direct who are opposed to: oil import quotas, farm expressions of marginal changes in preferences. subsidies, airport subsidies, hospital subsidies, This characteristic also implies that the political unnecessary navy shipyards, an inequitable pub- decision does not predict voter desires and make lic housing program, and rural electrification preparations to fulfill them in advance of their subsidies. realization. The political decision process has as its domi- 2. The democratic decision process must in- nant characteristic infrequent, universal (in prin- volve ‘‘all’’ the community, not simply those ciple) participation, as we have noted: political who are directly concerned with a decision. In a decisions must be infrequent and they must be private market, the non-traveler never votes on global. The voter’s expenditure to learn the rail versus plane travel, while the huge shipper merits of individual policy proposals and to ex- casts many votes each day. The political decision press his preferences (by individual and group Chapter 7 396

representation as well as by voting) are deter- process of producing a commodity, only an es- mined by expected costs and returns, just as they sential final step. The party maintains its orga- are in the private marketplace. The costs of nization and electoral appeal by the performance comprehensive information are higher in the po- of costly services to the voter at all times, not just litical arena because information must be sought before elections. Part of the costs of services and on many issues of little or no direct concern organization are borne by putting a part of the to the individual, and accordingly he will know party’s workers on the public payroll. An oppo- little about most matters before the legislature. sition party, however, is usually essential insur- The expressions of preferences in voting will be ance for the voters to discipline the party in less precise than the expressions of preferences in power, and the opposition party’s costs are not the marketplace because many uninformed peo- fully met by public funds. ple will be voting and a¤ecting the decision.7 The industry which seeks regulation must The channels of political decision-making can be prepared to pay with the two things a party thus be described as gross or filtered or noisy. If needs: votes and resources. The resources may everyone has a negligible preference for policy A be provided by campaign contributions, con- over B, the preference will not be discovered or tributed services (the businessman heads a fund- acted upon. If voter group X wants a policy that raising committee), and more indirect methods injures non-X by a small amount, it will not such as the employment of party workers. The pay non-X to discover this and act against the votes in support of the measure are rallied, and policy. The system is calculated to implement all the votes in opposition are dispersed, by expen- strongly felt preferences of majorities and many sive programs to educate (or uneducate) mem- strongly felt preferences of minorities but to bers of the industry and of other concerned disregard the lesser preferences of majorities industries. and minorities. The filtering of grossness will These costs of legislation probably increase be reduced by any reduction in the cost to the with the size of the industry seeking the legisla- citizen of acquiring information and expressing tion. Larger industries seek programs which cost desires and by any increase in the probability the society more and arouse more opposition that his vote will influence policy. from substantially a¤ected groups. The tasks of The industry which seeks political power must persuasion, both within and without the indus- go to the appropriate seller, the political party. try, also increase with its size. The fixed size of The political party has costs of operation, costs the political ‘‘market,’’ however, probably makes of maintaining an organization and competing the cost of obtaining legislation increase less in elections. These costs of the political process rapidly than industry size. The smallest indus- are viewed excessively narrowly in the literature tries are therefore e¤ectively precluded from the on the financing of elections: elections are to the political process unless they have some special political process what merchandising is to the advantage such as geographical concentration in a sparsely settled political subdivision. . . . 7. There is an organizational problem in any decision in which more than one vote is cast. If because of Conclusion economies of scale it requires a thousand customers to buy a product before it can be produced, this thousand The idealistic view of public regulation is deeply votes has to be assembled by some entrepreneur. imbedded in professional economic thought. So Unlike the political scene, however, there is no need to many economists, for example, have denounced obtain the consent of the remainder of the community, the ICC for its pro-railroad policies that this has because they will bear no part of the cost. become a cliche´ of the literature. This criticism Interest Groups 397

seems to me exactly as appropriate as a criticism of the Great Atlantic and Pacific Tea Company for selling groceries, or as a criticism of a politi- cian for currying popular support. The funda- mental vice of such criticism is that it misdirects attention: it suggests that the way to get an ICC which is not subservient to the carriers is to preach to the commissioners or to the people who appoint the commissioners. The only way to get a di¤erent commission would be to change the political support for the Commission, and reward commissioners on a basis unrelated to their services to the carriers. Until the basic logic of political life is devel- oped, reformers will be ill-equipped to use the state for their reforms, and victims of the perva- sive use of the state’s support of special groups will be helpless to protect themselves. Econo- mists should quickly establish the license to practice on the rational theory of political behavior. . . . Interest Intermediation and Regime Governability in Contemporary Western Europe and North America

Philippe C. Schmitter

Virtually all e¤orts to understand the generic but concludes that the very logic of industri- nature of contemporary political behavior and alization will produce such a multiplicity of its policy products rely on the notion that the dynamic, ephemeral, overlapping and counter- promotion and protection of self-regarding vailing e¤orts to protect and promote self- objectives ‘‘rightly and rationally understood’’ regarding objectives that the resultant ‘‘pluralist’’ provide the motive force, and the capacity to system will be both self-equilibrating and self- prevail over the interest e¤orts of others provides legitimating. All with interests will get a demo- the explanation for likely outcomes. The emer- cratic chance to play in the game; none, gence and triumph of capitalism and industrial- however, will be capable of controlling its course ization have provided not only a di¤erentiated or rigging its outcome. From this perpective, set of categories for identifying and a suitable the danger of ungovernability and/or instabil- means for calculating those interest(s); they ity arises from outside the game of interest have also ensured through interdependence and politics—from passionate, irrational subversives competition that one must indeed consider self- who refuse to play according to the established regarding objectives or su¤er dire consequences. rules, who insist on turning the game toward The purpose of this chapter is not to lament more exalted goals, and who force the otherwise the replacement or e¤acement of more ‘‘noble’’ benevolent umpire to use coercion in order to motives in political life. Nor is it to measure the ensure the continued governability of the system. extent to which selfish, vested behavior is, in fact, The currently fashionable perspective of the characteristic of the politics of advanced indus- ‘‘policy sciences’’ suggests yet another explana- trial/capitalist societies.1 Rather, it assumes the tion for (un)governability or (in)stability. Again, predominance of such motivation and seeks to the pursuit of ignoble, vested interests is explore (and tentatively to test) the consequences acknowledged as providing the predominant that the emergence of di¤erent modes of for- motive for political action, but in contrast to the malized interest intermediation have had on the optimism of pluralists, the ‘‘policy scientists’’ see governability of contemporary Western Euro- a real danger in such unbridled selfishness. Too pean and North American polities. . . . much of it by too wary and too well-organized The neotraditional science of politics may actors leads to ‘‘overload,’’ to an excess of recognize and even exalt the pursuit of interests demands on public authorities beyond their capacity for satisfying such claims. As the gov- Excerpted from: Philippe C. Schmitter, ‘‘Interest Inter- erning systems of advanced industrial/capitalist mediation and Regime Governability in Contemporary societies decline in e‰ciency, e‰cacy, and legiti- Western Europe and North America.’’ In Organis- macy under such an imbalance, more and more ing Interests in Western Europe, edited by Suzanne dissatisfied interests find they must make more Berger. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1983. and more noise and engage in more and more un- Reprinted by permission. conventional behavior to gain e¤ective access— 1. For an excellent, if rather nostalgic and petulant, and this leads only to more and more overload critique of modern political science for having replaced and ungovernability. the more exalted vision of a¤ective ‘‘community’’ with This chapter contends in particular with the a prosaic, limited vision of instrumental ‘‘partnership,’’ latter, ‘‘overload school.’’ In the process it will see Clarke E. Cochran, ‘‘The Politics of Interest: Phi- losophy and the Limitations of a Science of Politics,’’ advance arguments (and marshal some data) American Journal of Political Science 25(4) (1973): to demonstrate that the pursuit of lowly self- 745–66. Interest Groups 399

regarding interests can have high-level con- tional interest intermediation through highly sequences for the governability of advanced formalized and specialized organizations in di- industrial/capitalist polities. Arguments are also rect relation with the bureaucratic apparatus pro¤ered that pluralism is not the likely form of the modern state. The collapse of new social that interest intermediation will take in these contracts; the burgeoning demand for guaran- polities, and moreover that where it has been teed and privileged access; the clash of represen- most prevalent it has had an e¤ect on govern- tative jurisdictions; the quest for authenticity and ability contrary to that presumed by its leading participation at all levels of authority, private as theorists and ideologues. well as public; the mobilization and militancy of previously quiescent groups such as civil servants and public dependents; the clamor for and revolt The ‘‘Mode’’ of Interest Intermediation and the against raising state expenditures and govern- Problem of Governability mental regulation; the increasing sensitivity to relative deprivation and inequalities within as The principal orienting hypothesis of this well as between social classes; the explosion of chapter is simple: The relative governability of subnational ethnicity; the sudden emergence of contemporary, highly industrialized, advanced single-issue movements, not to mention the capitalist polities is less a function of aggregate principal defining characteristics of (un)govern- overload, of ‘‘imbalance’’ between the sum total of ability (to be discussed infra): (1) the tendency societal demands and state capabilities, than of to resort to unprecedented, extralegal means of the discrete processes that identify, package, pro- political expression; (2) the dwindling of elite mote, and implement potential interest claims cohesion and hegemony; and (3) the diminished and commands. In an aggregate sense, there has capacity of the state to secure resources and im- always been more of a demand for imperative plement policies—most, if not all, of these find coordination and authoritative allocation than their expression in and irresolution through the the state was capable of supplying, and the structures of specialized intermediation for class, ‘‘gap’’ was (and still is) filled by physical repres- sectoral, professional, regional, ethnic, sexual, sion and symbolic manipulation. . . . and generational interests. It is not parties and What have changed extensively and irrevers- elections that bring most of these problems, ibly are the processes of political intermedia- dilemmas, or contradictions to the agenda of the tion by which the potential volume of societal state, although they may be indirectly a¤ected demands is captured and focused and through by them. Individual partisan allegiance and the which the eventual pattern of public policies is territorial clustering of notables, those two evaluated and sifted. To an extent this has been pillars of the liberal democratic, civic-cultured, recognized in the literature on ungovernability bourgeois-dominant political order, have been and overload, but the emphasis has always been gradually but firmly overtaken by the third, placed on the party, legislative, and cabinet heretofore less prominent, aspect of that mode nexus. . . . of domination: the implacable pursuit of self- My . . . hunch . . . is that although those who interest, rightly and rationally understood, have emphasized the confusion and decline in through specialized, functionally di¤erentiated party and parliament focus correctly on the dis- organizations. . . . tinctly political processes of intermediation, they Now we are in a position to make our second have mistaken the symptoms for the disease. hunch more explicit. The key to di¤ering degrees The key to understanding the various crises of of governability lies less in the ‘‘objective’’ mag- governability lies in the dimly lit arena of func- nitudes of macroeconomic performance, social Chapter 7 400

cleavages, and class relations than in the way necessary to spell out the definition used here di¤erentiated interests are ‘‘intermediated’’ be- and its operational limitations. First and fore- tween civil society and the state. Our discussion most, ‘‘societal corporatism’’ does not refer to has suggested the specific empirical dimensions any historically specific ideology, world view, relevant to the explanation of di¤erences in political culture, or even any set of collective outcome: representational coverage, member- aspirations.9 . . . Societal corporatism as used ship density, and corporatist structure. Polities here is located in the realm of institutional be- in which interests are processed through formal havior, not that of individual values or collective associations that cover the widest variety of po- aspirations. tential interests with national networks of repre- Second, it refers to a mode of arranging the sentation, that have the highest proportion of political process, indeed, structuring part of the those potentially a¤ected as members, and whose political process. It is not a way of organizing all pattern of interaction with the state is monopolis- of society or running the economy. Societal cor- tic, specialized, hierarchical, and mutually collu- poratism is ‘‘compatible’’ with a wide range of sive should be more orderly, stable, and e¤ective, social institutions and is not an ‘‘alternative’’ at least in the short run, given the conditions of to capitalist exploitation but, at least in some contemporary governance. Put a di¤erent way, countries, an integral part of it. those countries previously ‘‘fortunate’’ enough The part of the political process to which so- to have developed a pluralist mode of interest cietal corporatism refers I have called ‘‘interest intermediation with its multiple, overlapping, intermediation.’’ It encompasses both the means spontaneously formed, voluntaristically sup- through which interests are transferred from, ported, easily abandoned, and politically auton- aggregated over, and articulated for members omous associations, are likely to find it a serious to collective decision-making bodies, public or impediment to governability in the postliberal, private (representation), and the ways in which advanced, capitalist state. . . . interests are taught to, transmitted to, and The use of the concept of ‘‘corporatism’’ by imposed on members by associations (social other authors . . . and the even more varied uses control ). The concept ‘‘intermediation’’ is also to which it has been put elsewhere8 makes it meant to convey the likelihood that interests may be generated from within formal associa- 8. The literature on corporatism in advanced tions themselves, independent of member prefer- industrial/capitalist societies has grown enormously ences and authoritative commands. . . . in recent years. A compilation of most of the more Governability, or better, its inverse, ungov- important theoretical pieces will be appearing shortly ernability, would seem, from the literature on in P. Schmitter and G. Lehmbruch (eds.), Trends To- Western Europe and North America, to be ward Corporatist Intermediation (London: Sage Pub- composed of three general properties:18 (1) un- lications). For a critical summary of this literature and its dissection into divergent ‘‘schools,’’ see Leo Panitch, ‘‘Recent Theorizations of Corporatism: Reflections on 9. For a brief discussion of the extraordinary ideo- a Growth Industry,’’ paper presented at ISA World logical diversity of those who have historically and Congress, Panel on Interest Intermediation and Cor- contemporarily advocated something called or resem- poratism, Uppsala, August 14–9, 1978, and Kevin bling corporatism, see P. Schmitter, ‘‘Still the Cen- Bonnett, ‘‘Corporatist Developments in Advanced tury of Corporatism?’’ [Review of Politics 36(1) (1974): Capitalist Society: Competing Theoretical Perspec- 85–131,] pp. 87–9. tives,’’ paper presented at the SSRC (Great Britain) 18. Actually, the American literature either tends to Conference on Institutionalisation, University of Sus- stress or is criticized for ignoring yet a fourth dimen- sex, September 8–11, 1978. sion: unlawfulness or e¤orts by high-level corporate Interest Groups 401

ruliness or citizen-initiated e¤orts to influence standing macrolevel ruliness, stableness, and public choices in violent, illegal, or unprece- e¤ectiveness. The coordinal relationship between dented ways; (2) unstableness or the failure of the indicator of societal corporatism and that of e¤orts by elite political actors to retain their citizen unruliness (À0.73) is the most significant positions of dominance or to reproduce preex- we have yet observed. The fit is so close that rel- isting coalitional arrangements; (3) ine¤ective- atively few deviant cases arise to challenge our ness or the decline in the capacity of public finding. . . . The correlation with fiscal ine¤ec- executives or administrators to secure compli- tiveness (À0.63) is also highly significant. Again, ance with or to attain desired collective goals we find it impossible to predict the rank ordering through the imperative coordinations or author- of governmental unstableness. Perhaps this is yet itative allocations of the state. . . . another indication that it is simply not part of the contemporary governability–ungovernability syndrome or that, if it is, our operationalization Interest Promotion and Partisan Mobilization as is defective. Density of membership was not im- Possible Causes of (Un)governability pressively related to any of the three dimensions. What seems to count is not whether everyone is Having identified . . . three dimensions of getting organized for the pursuit of specialized (un)governability . . . we can now turn to interest class and sectoral self-interest but how they are intermediation for a possible rival explanation. doing so. Two aspects of the pursuit of self-regarding goals One is tempted to exclaim ‘‘Eureka!’’ at this have attracted our attention. One is quantitative: point and rest the analysis. Given the likely Are the polities of Western Europe and North measurement error and the crudeness of the sta- America less ruly, stable, and e¤ective simply tistical instrument, it is doubtful that any rank- because everyone is finally getting organized? order correlation between independent variables The other is qualitative: Does the form that could top 0.73 without being a tautological or intermediation has taken historically determine spurious measure of the same underlying phe- the relative governability of these polities today? nomenon. We might, therefore, conclude with The first we have measured by the density of the counterintuitive finding that ( pace Madison) membership in working-class associations; the corporatism, not pluralism, is the best formula latter by a rank-ordered indicator of corporatist ‘‘to break and control the violence of faction’’ features in national labor peak associations. in the post-liberal, advanced-capitalist polity. The statistical measures (Spearman’s rank- Rather than proliferating the ‘‘number of citi- order coe‰cients) . . . provide a rather clear zens’’ and the ‘‘sphere of interests,’’ the modern answer to both the general question of the im- conservative ruler concerned with governability portance of interest intermediation for regime would diminish their number, encourage their governability and the more specific question centralization and concentration of authority, of which aspect of the pursuit of interests— grant them privileged monopolistic access, and, quantity or quality—is more relevant to under- above all, extend the sphere of governance by licensing or devolving upon them powers to take power holders, public or private, to escape legal and decisions binding on their members and even on constitutional constraints in their pursuit of advan- nonmembers. In this way, ‘‘responsible,’’ private tage and survival. Euro-centric treatments may occa- governments can collaborate in controlling citi- sionally mention leadership incompetence, but rarely zen-initiated protest and in ensuring proper fiscal dishonesty or illegality as part of the ungovernability discipline and management. The direct burden syndrome. on the state is lightened, and the resulting policy Chapter 7 402

outputs are made a good deal less visible. On The most obvious supportive change in the the other side, the relative autonomy of these party system was the emergence and eventual associations is respected, so that periodic with- participation in power of reformist Social Dem- drawals from collusion with those in power ocratic or Labour parties.25 Although they did is tolerated when the disparity between ruling not often stress corporatism at the ideologi- imperatives, organizational goals, and member cal level—if only because their Catholic or con- interests becomes too great and threatens to servative opponents had often preempted the provoke direct action by the grass roots or to idea—their own internal organizational rela- spill over into the electoral arena. Interest asso- tionship with the trade-union movement cer- ciations, and not just political parties, can take a tainly resembled it, and their acceptance of a cure d’opposition.23 ‘‘responsible’’ promotion of working-class inter- Ruling elites in many of the more troubled ests within the framework of capitalism definitely Western European and North American polities was a prerequisite for its eventual success. . . . seem to have arrived at the same conclusion as . . . [A]nother dimension of partisan mobiliza- we have in this chapter: In advanced capitalist, tion may be of even greater importance than highly industrialized societies, there is a strong Social Democratic predominance. . . . [O]ne can positive relationship between a societal corpora- roughly estimate the predictability of individual tist mode of interest intermediation and relative voting preferences from knowledge of that governability (or at least citizen ruliness and individual’s occupation, religion, and regional fiscal e¤ectiveness). . . . location. The aggregate predictive capacity of Much of the resistance to corporatization these three potential cleavage dimensions varies comes from existing interest associations that enormously. . . . [B]ut what seems to be most sig- prize their organizational autonomy and defend nificantly associated with ‘‘governable’’ macro- their traditionally pluralistic ways of operating. outcomes is the predictability produced by some In fact, previous e¤orts in imposing a solution combination of all three—the extent to which from above were accompanied by the severe the voter’s individual partisan choice is firmly repression of such associations, especially those ‘‘locked into’’ the basic elements of di¤erentia- representing the working class, and the estab- tion in the society, regardless of which of those lishment of a wide range of other authoritarian elements is performing the task. practices—vide Fascist Italy or Franco Spain. These additional findings strengthen consider- Where, however, this mode of interest inter- ably the credibility of our earlier hypothesis that mediation evolved gradually and voluntarily the relative governability of Western European within a liberal democratic regime, it depended and North American polities is more a¤ected by on concordant and supportive changes in a sec- the qualitative nature of their systems of inter- ond realm of formal intermediation between civil mediation than by the quantitative magnitude of society and the state—partisan mobilization. the economic and social problems they face. The mode of organization of and control over func- 23. The instability of such corporatist arrangements tion- and issue-specific interests emerges as most is stressed in Birgitta Nedelmann and Kurt G. Meier, significant, but its role is contingent on two ‘‘Theories of Contemporary Corporatism: Static or major coordinant developments in the mode of Dynamic,’’ Comparative Political Studies 10(1) (April 1975): 39–60. Also, the article by Gerhard Lehmbruch 25. Leo Panitch is largely responsible for my seeing the in the same special issue entitled ‘‘Liberal Corporatism ‘‘Social Democratic connection.’’ ‘‘The Development and Party Government,’’ pp. 91–126, deals with vol- of Corporatism in Liberal Democracies,’’ Comparative cures d’opposition untary, tactical taken by corporatist Political Studies 10(1) (1977): 61–90. actors. Interest Groups 403

partisan articulation: its relative domination by liberal polities of Western Europe and North Social Democratic-type parties and its predict- America. able rootedness in the cleavage structure of the society. It is, of course, not clear from these cross-sectionally associated outcomes whether, Instead of a Conclusion as Stein Rokkan has suggested, the functional ‘‘second tier’’ of corporatist intermediation was The foregoing empirically grounded conclusions created out of an elite reaction against the emer- about the relevance of intermediation processes, gence of in the ‘‘primary tier’’ especially societal corporatism, for contempo- of territorial representation,26 or whether it rary governability seem compelling. They may emerged as a direct product of the e¤orts of even lead some to the comforting thought that Social Democrats at integrating themselves the problems, dilemmas, and contradictions of within the structures of the capitalist economy the status quo do not have to be resolved. It and liberal polity.27 ... might seem that ruling elites have only to tinker Societal corporatism and the ‘‘locking in’’ of with their systems of partisan and interest inter- voter preferences to the cleavage structure do mediation to dissipate their current troubles. If not appear to be parts of a tightly related his- this should be the lesson they draw (and there torical process. It could be argued that they rep- is considerable evidence many have), they are resent independent e¤orts to organize networks destined to be disappointed. Not only are such of intermediation between civil society and the institutional networks the product of very state—the one focusing on functional, especially lengthy and complex historical forces but they occupational and sectoral interests; the other are also subject to strong emergent organiza- appealing more to territorial, religious, and tional properties that guide their development cultural interests, with class as the crucial area and insulate them from ameliorative meddlings for their competition and/or cooperation. When, from above. Previous attempts at molding inter- however, they combine through highly predict- est and partisan intermediation systems to ‘‘fit’’ able patterns of party identification and highly the needs of the mode of political domination specialized patterns of monopolistic representa- and the exigencies of economic exploitation have tion and social control, the relative ruliness had to involve much more than mere tinkering. and e¤ectiveness of the outcome is impressive. Even where societies have protractedly su¤ered This speculative finding seems diametrically through the repression necessary to impose such contrary to pluralist orthodoxy, which identifies comprehensive state corporatist ‘‘solutions,’’ ‘‘political stability’’ (the lexical forerunner of dominant classes have only managed to buy time ‘‘governability’’) with moderate, broadly aggre- and accumulate tensions, as in contemporary gative, sociologically diverse, and weakly struc- Spain and Portugal. tured political parties, and with voluntaristic, However compelling, the conclusions reached multiple, overlapping, and autonomous interest in this chapter are time contingent. They refer associations. From our data manipulations, this to a rather narrow period, roughly the 1960s emerges almost as a formula for trouble in the through the early 1970s. . . . highly industrialized, advanced-capitalist, post- Those polities that did acquire highly cen- tralized, monopolistic interest associations and 26. Citizens, Elections, Parties (New York: David well-structured, ‘‘pillared’’ political parties and McKay, 1970), pp. 40–3. which, therefore, were better able to negotiate 27. Something like this seems to be implied by Leo voluntaristically and to enforce e¤ectively a Panitch, op. cit. series of collaborative policy arrangements and Chapter 7 404

crisis-induced pacts are, indeed, beginning to the substantive issues at stake involve an exacer- show strains. That delicate combination of ruling bation or rupture within existing problem con- imperatives, organizational goals, and member tent, or a shift in the definition of actor interest interests that lies at the heart of the corporatist to some new domain of concern. . . . e¤ort has been called increasingly into question. For most convinced liberals or pluralists, the The decline of public, that is, system-wide, de- principal di‰culty of societal corporatism lies liberative processes, the segmentation of policy in the internal political process of interest asso- into discrete functional compartments, and the ciations. Their stress on professionalized repre- inequity produced by mutually supportive deals sentation by experts, long-term calculations of among organizationally privileged minorities interest, high-level aggregation of demands, and have led to a revived concern with ‘‘the public o‰cial recognition of status, on the one hand, interest.’’ The legitimacy of leaders protected and their practices of oligarchic co-optation, within highly oligarchic and professionalized centralized organization, bureaucratized ex- interest associations from direct contact with changes, and interdependence with public au- and accountability to members has diminished, thority, on the other, make these associations as has the willingness of members to comply vulnerable to member dissatisfaction. The most with the constraints of private governments. The common type of challenge, according to this overaggregation of interests through peak asso- perspective, comes from ‘‘rank-and-file revolts’’: ciations has left un- or underrepresented certain wildcat strikes, internal factionalism, organiza- emergent, more specialized groups, just as their tional splits, ‘‘voting with one’s feet,’’ ideological close collusion with power has made the exclu- gambits, accusations of traitorous behavior, and sion of di¤use, dispersed, underorganized cate- so on—all in the name of authenticity in repre- gories more obvious and less bearable. The sentation and democracy in procedure. demand for personal authenticity and demo- Without denying this latent threat or the oc- cratic participation on the part of individuals has casional presence of some of these phenomena grown at the expense of mere role satisfaction in even the most established and accomplished and vicariously obtained advantage. New ‘‘style of societal corporatist arrangements, such revolts and quality’’ issues have emerged, cutting across are not, in my view, capable of countermand- established functional hierarchies and resulting ing the trend. They may cause collaborative in numerous single-issue movements and spon- associations to take a cure d’opposition by with- taneous protest actions. Awareness that inflation drawing from corporatist practices for a period is the real hiding hand equilibrating outcomes of time; they may even compel some associations and invisibly determining the distribution of to engage in imprudent tactics of confronta- benefits has upset many a carefully negotiated tion and intransigence—especially where the social contract or sectoral arrangement. All this revolt is backed by accountability to some extra- points to an uncertain future for today’s ‘‘cor- associational political process, such as Mitbes- poratist successes.’’ timmung or e´lections sociales—but normally The sources of contradiction/dilemma inher- these revolts are easy to encapsulate or even ent in this scheme are multiple and of unequal exploit for corporatist ends. It is not just that importance. Generically, they can be reduced to association leaders have at their disposition that four types, depending on (1) whether the institu- arsenal of incumbency resources that Michels tional locus of emerging di‰culty comes from and his successors have so extensively docu- within the universe of interest associations or mented but that this pluralist view ignores the from other organizations, such as political extent to which the modern interest association parties and social movements, and (2) whether has become more and more a service agency and Interest Groups 405

less and less a focus of political aspiration or thinking and ex post retractions. If the institu- personal identity. The member pays a fee for tions and practices of societal corporatism, by services performed (and increasingly does so and large forged during the post-World War II involuntarily) and demands in return some mea- boom years, manage to survive the present gen- sure of e‰ciency and e¤ectiveness in their per- eral crisis of capitalism (and even to do so at less formance. To the extent that he or she aspires cost to subordinate classes in terms of job secu- to fellowship, authenticity, participation, self- rity, real wages, and social benefits), then some expression, and so forth, the political party or revision of the class-mobilization scenario of its social movement o¤ers a much more attractive demise will definitely be in order. outlet for such passions and moral imperatives. A third source of contradiction and type It is this tendency for the contradictions of of response suggests that corporatism will be corporatism to spill over into wider arenas of threatened by the emergence of new substantive public choice and forms of political mobili- interests or by a shift in the salience of older, zation—while remaining basically within the previously subordinate, interests. These should nexus of class, sectoral, and professional inter- provide the basis for a new wave of aggressive ests—that is stressed by Marxist critics of the associability that will seek access to the estab- trend. Because societal corporatism is but a lished corporatist arrangement. According to superstructural rearrangement of institutions this perspective, societal corporatism has suc- that cannot dissolve the class-based, structural ceeded so far largely because it has been partial. contradictions of capitalism (not to mention ac- It has involved primarily or exclusively those complish the lesser task of resolving sectoral interests generated by the economic division of clashes and professional disputes), they argue it labor in society—classes, sectors, and profes- must ultimately fail. It may succeed in the short sions for short. This has permitted these better- run in making ad hoc adjustments and generat- organized, collaborative actors to pass on the ing crisis-induced palliatives, but these are bound costs of their mutually self-serving agreements to accumulate, to produce further policy irra- to the un- or underorganized. If the latter inter- tionalities, and to establish greater rigidities in ests, for example, tenants, renters, pensioners, the system. These may even contribute to the pedestrians, taxpayers, foreigners, workers, au- system’s demise. Although the proponents of this tomobile drivers, students, su¤erers from pollu- view of corporatism often point to the same tion, payers of insurance premiums, television ‘‘rank-and-file’’ events as the pluralists, they watchers, welfare recipients, hospital patients, all stress the extent to which these go beyond the ‘‘policy takers’’ (to use an appropriate phrase limited agenda of specialized interests, personal from Claus O¤e’s chapter) were to create sin- moral sentiments, and/or formal democratic gular, monopolistic, hierarchically structured, aspirations, and serve to mobilize a broad class o‰cially sanctioned associations, previous exter- consciousness and activity across a wider variety nalities would become internalized within the of intermediary institutions: political parties, so- system of organized interest politics and make cial movements, intellectual currents, and so decisions vastly more di‰cult. Also, some of forth. the new or more recently salient criteria of Although this approach to the contradictions di¤erentiation/exploitation—ethnic identity, re- of corporatism is more sensitive to the changing gional location, religion, sex, age, language, and nature of modern interest associations, it fre- so on—might cut across existing functional cat- quently overestimates the evidence for class mo- egories or, where they did not, infuse them with bilization and underestimates the barriers to it, renewed passion or ideological fervor. Either thus indulging in a great deal of ex ante wishful shift could seriously jeopardize the stable orga- Chapter 7 406

nizational base, the long-term interest definition, territorial loyalties, and/or qualitative demands and the predictable contractual capacity of cor- prove to be permanent. Are they capable of dis- poratist intermediaries. placing over a protracted period the ‘‘func- The problem with this scenario is that in order tional’’ cleavages inherent in capitalist property for dispersed ‘‘entitled’’ interests, oriented almost relations and the industrial division of labor? exclusively around the provision of public goods, Some may turn out to be ephemeral, especially to obtain su‰cient resources and access, they in conditions of renewed scarcity. Others may be must depend on the sponsorship and connivance successfully accommodated through symbolic of public authorities. Their corporatization is less concessions, territorial readjustments, partisan likely to be ‘‘societal’’ than ‘‘state’’ in inspira- restructuring, and so forth. If so, the apparent tion, and this raises the question of why those shifts in content, despite their raucousness and in formal power would take such an initiative occasional attention-gathering capability, are or whether they would be permitted to do so by not likely to be successful in countervailing the vested established interests already sharing the trend toward societal corporatism. At most, they benefits of privileged access. In the event that might delay its emergence for a while, or keep it the source of new interest or salience lies in the confined to a narrower range of policy arenas.30 ‘‘cultural division of labor,’’29 the resultant need All the sources of contradiction discussed to mobilize identities around broad ideological briefly here originate within civil society, that goals should make corporatization insu‰cient. is, in the economic, social, and cultural division Mere specialized participation in a complex set of labor. An alternative possibility, not usually of policy compromises and services is no ade- entertained by students of corporatism, is that quate substitute for having one’s own state or problems might arise from within the political dominating the whole political process. order itself, which could limit the spread or en- This brings us to the fourth type of contradic- courage the dissolution of such arrangements. tion in which those new status, style, and identity Instead of just facilitating the management of issues cannot be contained within the bounds the state, they could eventually threaten the of ‘‘mere’’ interest intermediation and spill over status and resources of public authorities and into other forms of collective political activity. party politicians and introduce additional These range from public interest lobbies to rigidities and irrationalities into public policy spontaneous protests, ‘‘green’’ parties, and suc- making. State bureaucrats might find that devo- cessionist movements. Their broader goals, lution of authority to corporatist intermediaries greater intensities, unconventional tactics, and deprives them of their unique status and of im- crosscutting di¤erentiations would both weaken portant instruments for resolving broader public existing corporatist associations and shift the at- issues and intersectoral conflicts. Professional tention of the entire political process away from politicians are likely to resist the progressive the issues and tactics the latter are most capable short-circuiting of party channels, territorial of handling. Whether this would be su‰cient to dissolve existing corporatist arrangements or 30. Cf. a recent essay by Robert Salisbury, where the to arrest further movement in that direction continued strength of constituency is regarded as a depends ultimately on if the emergent cultural fundamental element inhibiting the emergence of soci- identities, status sensitivities, situs calculations, etal corporatism in the United States—along with other factors. ‘‘On Centrifugal Tendencies in Interest Systems: The Case of the United States,’’ paper pre- 29. Michael Hechter, ‘‘Group Formation and the sented at the ISA World Congress, Panel on Interest Cultural Divisions of Labor,’’ American Journal of Intermediation and Corporatism, Uppsala, August Sociology [84(2) (1978): 293–318]. 14–9, 1978. Interest Groups 407

constituencies, and legislative processes. To the extent these dilemmas become important, the result is less likely to be renewed militancy, ideological mobilization, or new collective strug- gles than a legalistic reform e¤ort to preserve the ‘‘sanctity’’ and ‘‘distinctiveness’’ of state/public institutions and to regulate the activities and resources of interest associations.31 All these potential sources of di‰culty for the future of societal corporatism, and for the rela- tive governability that has accompanied it, can be discerned, to di¤ering degrees, in the contem- porary politics of advanced industrial/capitalist societies. Corporatism’s very success at keeping political life ruly and e¤ective has been pur- chased at the price of organizational sclerosis, rigidification of di¤erentials, perpetuation of inequalities, and, most of all, disregard for the individualistic norms of citizen participation and accountability characteristic of a liberal demo- cratic order. How long this form of corporatism can continue in its pragmatic manner to produce such negative behavioral e¤ects and to ignore such fundamental normative aspirations, with- out resort to coercion, is questionable. Just as it has proved hard to ‘‘tone down’’ established pluralist structures unsuccessful in dealing with existing problems, so it may be di‰cult to ‘‘tune up’’ previously successful corporatist ones to meet emerging issues.

31. Here the recent discussion of a Verba¨ndegesetz in Western Germany is a case in point. . . . Inside Campaign Finance: Myths and Realities

Frank J. Sorauf

The question of motive haunts every campaign data are easily accessible, and the ‘‘law of avail- finance system relying on voluntary contribu- able data’’ has led to a flowering of research on tions. Why do they give? When a disclosure sys- them, both by the scholarly community and tem discloses as much as the American one does by journalists and public-interest organizations. about a visible set of organized givers represent- Their industriousness has produced works of ing society’s major interests, the question rises to many genres, but one of the most common—a a salience that campaign finance rarely achieves. veritable industry in itself—is the exploration The answer to it is beyond dispute; they give of the pac-Congress nexus. The variants on the to influence governmental decisions. The hard theme, too, are recognizable: the largest pac questions come next: the nature of the influence contributors to congressional candidates over a the contributors seek, the ways they go about cycle or a decade, the major recipients of pac seeking it, and the extent to which they achieve money in the Congress, the contributions from it. pacs of one industry to the members of one The debate over the purchase of legislatures is committee or to supporters of a particular bill or not about generic contributors. It is about pac cause, the mounting flow of pac money from one contributors, whether they appear explicitly or sector of the economy as its interests are threat- are merely implied in such phrases as ‘‘the best ened or challenged. Often the investigations have Congress money can buy.’’ Their splendid visi- a current stimulus; they are the campaign finance bility as the organizations of the ‘‘special inter- angle on the broader story, say, of the savings- ests’’ links them and their contributions to the and-loan crisis, the rewriting of the federal tax ongoing, century-long debates over the three- code, or the attempt to pass the Brady bill’s way alliance of money, organization, and in- restrictions on the sale of handguns. terest in American politics. Now that pacs Such reports share one limiting defect: they increasingly give to secure legislative access, a establish correlation, not cause. Yes, pacsdo strategy in which their ties both to incumbents largely give money to candidates who will vote and to lobbyists are closer, they underscore all the way they want them to; it would be surpris- of the old concerns. We no longer talk of pac ing if that were not the case. Contributors con- attempts to penetrate electoral politics but of tribute to like-minded candidates, just as voters their part in the traditional struggle of interests vote for like-minded candidates. That relation- in American legislatures. Almost imperceptibly, ship is easy to document, but the harder question but fundamentally, the debate has shifted from remains: do pacs contribute to candidates be- influence in election outcomes to influence over cause they know how they will vote, or do legis- legislative outcomes. lators conform to the wishes of pacs that gave Thanks to the reporting and publicity the feca money to their campaigns? Does the money fol- forced on candidates, pacs, and parties, the fec low the votes, or do the votes follow the money? oversees the largest data archive on any system It is a problem in simultaneous cause, cause that of campaign finance anywhere in the world. Its seems to move both ways between one act and another. Any analysis of campaign finance is Excerpted from: Frank J. Sorauf, Inside Campaign Fi- repeatedly bedeviled by such problems. . . . nance: Myths and Realities. New Haven: Yale Univer- Academic scholars, for their part, attack the sity Press, 1992. 6 Yale University Press. Reprinted by same questions in more systematic ways. They permission. cannot, however, escape the need to establish Interest Groups 409

correlations and to infer cause from them, nor Political scientists Richard Hall and Frank can they escape the problem of simultaneity in Wayman begin the report of their research on doing so. Using larger bodies of data—large pac money and House committees by recon- numbers of roll-call votes, for instance—and structing the logic of what pacs seek with their more sophisticated measures of correlation, they contributions. . . . Hall and Wayman focus . . . on generally find little if any relationship between three House committees and three di¤erent the money and the votes. . . . issues before them—and on the e¤ects of pac How does one explain the gap between popu- contributions to members of the committees. lar knowledge and academic conclusion? In part Instead of using votes in committee as the de- it results from the usual popular overestimation pendent variable, Hall and Wayman construct of pac will and capacity. pacs themselves are a measure of various kinds of participation in more realistic about their bargaining position the business of committees (such as speaking with incumbents than is the general public. They in committee or o¤ering amendments during say over and over that they want to support like- markup). In each of the three cases they found minded men and women in public o‰ce and that that pac contributions had a moderate but sig- they seek only ‘‘access’’ to legislators, an oppor- nificant degree of influence, explaining more tunity to persuade or make a case. Organiza- than 55 percent of the variance in participation tionally they are not adapted to greater political by individual members. pac money, therefore, ambitions than that, and they have come slowly mobilized already like-thinking members to to realize it. . . . more active support of the pacs’ interests in Such conclusions run counter to the conven- committee. . . . tional wisdom, and like most academic writing . . . Regardless of why the pacs give, they seem on campaign finance, they fail to disturb or dis- to get heightened activity and support from their lodge it. The supporters of the conventional wis- congressional sympathizers. We are left, how- dom are tireless, and they have a platform. They ever, to speculate about the ultimate results also have telling testimony from members of of such support and activity on congressional Congress that pacs do indeed change votes— decisions. always the votes of other members—with their A consensus about pac influence is emerg- contributions. . . . ing among scholars of campaign finance. It is The common sense of the word access also founded on two central conclusions. First, makes the case for the conventional wisdom. If the influence of pac contributions tends to be access is indeed the goal of pac contributions, strongest on the narrower, less visible issues be- will pacs settle merely for the ‘‘opportunity to fore the Congress. Members have long called persuade’’? Won’t they expect success in a cer- them ‘‘free votes,’’ free in that they are liberated tain number of instances? Will they be satisfied from the usually dominant influences of party, with an invitation to the gaming table if they lose district, leadership, and mass opinion. These every spin of the wheel? Moreover, the nature of are the votes available for less influential con- influence in a legislative body involves much stituencies (such as contributors) or even for more than final roll-call votes. pacs exert influ- classic legislative log-rolling or horse-trading. ence at other points in the legislative process—in Second, the influence of contributions can be initiatives not taken, in committee amendments, directed at all the points of access and influence or in special rules a¤ecting floor consideration. in the legislative process in the Congress. The Some academic political scientists, one should kinds of policy refinements and strategic maneu- add, have long shared reservations about an ex- vers crafted in committee may be important for clusive reliance on roll calls. . . . specific interests even though they do not involve Chapter 7 410

great issues of policy. The same can be said of money and votes or other activity in the Con- many appointments to the courts and to execu- gress. One of the greatest strengths of any con- tive agencies. Contributors do not necessarily ventional wisdom is that by definition it is seek, or even expect, to score impressive policy validated by the sheer number of people who victories measured by final roll-call votes. In the subscribe to it. Such validation does not yield world of reduced expectations in which pacs are easily to the desiccated numbers and equations forced to live, the smaller accomplishments have of empirical social science. to su‰ce. The conventional wisdom is vulnerable also The Hall and Wayman findings narrow the for its assumption that pacs dominate the ex- gulf between the academy and conventional wis- change between contributor and candidate—an dom, but the gulf remains. In part it results analytical predisposition that comes out of the from major disagreements about evidence and late 1970s. But we now have abundant evidence authority, about the credibility of participants that the exchange is bilateral rather than unilat- and observers in the Congress versus the data- eral, that candidates have leverage in it, and based analyses of scholars, and about funda- that the incumbents among them increased that mental questions of what evidence it takes to leverage in the 1980s as their reelection rates come to conclusions. In essence, the gulf reflects soared. As pacs have shifted more and more di¤erent wills to believe. Some scholarship, to be to the support of incumbents, and to the search sure, but even more journalistic analysis, begins for access to them, their freedom of action has with deeply set convictions, rooted in the Pro- diminished. Whereas incumbents have organized gressive worldview, about the impact of money with increasing e¤ectiveness, pacs have not. Nor on public o‰cials. The line between dispositions have they maintained their ability to enforce to believe and foregone conclusions is very thin. expectations. pac sanctions depend on the value Most durable are the di¤erences across the of withdrawn contributions, and since pacs have gulf on analytical issues. One concerns the cred- continued to disperse their contributions widely, ibility of the testimony of participants, and even the average pac contribution amounts to well the weight their words carry vis-a`-vis the detailed less than one-half of 1 percent of the average data of the scholars. . . . House incumbent’s receipts in an electoral cycle. . . . The danger of granting authority status to Even a major contribution of $5,000 or more participants—contributors or recipients—is that accounts for only a few percent of the average authority is conferred even on clearly self-serving candidate’s receipts. Consequently, the pac po- conclusions merely because the authority’s mes- sition in the 1990s is not what it was in the 1970s. sage is useful or congenial. Finally, the countervailing controls of Amer- Beneath the controversies over the conven- ican pluralism constrain even the most deter- tional wisdoms, there are also great di¤erences mined pacs. Organizations of interests have over who carries the burden of proof. Scholars greatly proliferated since the 1970s. The larger will not readily consent to demands that they the number of groups (that is, pacs), the greater accept responsibility for proving or disproving the o¤setting and limiting e¤ect on the political an assertion they do not make: the one about claims of any one of them. The greater the pacs’ buying influence over the making of policy. number of pacs making contributions to a spe- Nor will they concede that any assertion is valid cific member of Congress, the greater the like- until it is disproven. Ultimately, however, the lihood that the claims of one on his or her debate comes down to the kinds and weight loyalties will be opposed by the claims of of evidence that will establish the tie between another. . . . Interest Groups 411

A caveat to that conclusion is, however, in alleged buying of the elections to the Congress order. The mechanism of o¤setting, counter- that most worries Americans. Many of them are vailing group activity probably best fits policy convinced that incumbents are winning reelec- disputes over the larger issues that are part of tion at such stunning rates precisely because the broader ideological positions—over issues such incumbents have too much money and their as medicaid funding or hazardous waste dis- challengers have too little. posal. The model works less well when the dis- The facts are undeniable. Challenger financing pute is single-sided, where the activity of one set has deteriorated in the 1980s by all measures. . . . of interests does not jolt another set of interests, . . . General-election challengers found it in- perhaps those of consumers, into action. The creasingly di‰cult to raise money from pacs; nonresponding interests may be too general, too pacs gave them 25.8 percent of their contribu- invisible, or of too low a priority to warrant tions to House candidates in 1980, but only political action. So, the hypothesis of counter- 6.7 percent in 1990. House challengers, in fact, vailing interests meshes well with the conclusion became increasingly dependent on their own that pacs have their greatest impact on the less resources. . . . visible politics of narrow and particularistic For mass opinion and its shapers, such data interests in which the conflicts, and thus the lead to an easy conclusion. Incumbents win so controls, of pluralism are not joined. . . . often because they outspend their opponents so That an increasingly national ‘‘contributor greatly, and challengers fail to win because they constituency’’ has entered American electoral lack the resources with which to mount a win- politics seems beyond contest. Electoral politics ning campaign. For the scholarly community the remain local because the constituencies are geo- conclusion does not come as easily, for once graphically defined with only one representative again they see a problem in simultaneous cause. and two senators per constituency and because Do candidates win because they spend more the American political parties have been decen- money, or do they get more money, and spend it, tralized and local. Now pacs and other repre- because they are likely to win? The structure sentatives of national interests find a small but of the causal problem is much like the problem measurable additional edge in electoral politics. of simultaneous cause in pac contributions and They increasingly ally themselves with the lob- policy outcomes in the Congress: Is the financial bying of the interests they share, and it becomes contribution made because of expectations about increasingly di‰cult to say whether their victo- the recipient’s victory some months hence, or ries come through contributing or lobbying. It is does the contribution actually buy the cam- far easier to say simply that contributions have paigning that shapes the election outcome? That become one more limited means among many in is, do underfunded candidates fail because con- the pursuit of policy goals—and one more piece tributors think their fate is sealed months before of evidence that the localism of American elec- election day? toral politics is increasingly anomalous. Cam- The other side of the argument is equally paign finance serves as a shaper of national straightforward: challengers lose because they politics as well as one of its consequences . . . cannot spend enough. It is a fact not only that . . . It is precisely on the maldistribution of challengers in the aggregate fail to raise and campaign money, especially the paucity of it in spend the sums incumbents do, but also that the the hands of challengers, that the second great challengers who spend the most collectively win argument of the post-1974 regime centers. After the greater share of the two-party vote. The per- the alleged buying of the Congress, it is the centage of challengers’ general-election vote rises Chapter 7 412

Table 7.1 easily be traced, not to their campaign treasuries, Relationship between challenger spending and chal- but to all of the advantages of o‰ce they enjoy. lenger vote share: 1984–1988* The postal frank, their easy access to the media, Median general election their district o‰ces, and their sta¤s for ‘‘servic- vote (%) ing’’ constituents all have grown in recent de- Challenger: Incumbent cades, at least partly to buttress their reelection spending ratios 1984 1986 1988 chances.17 Less obviously, perhaps, the growing Up to 1:3 28 27 27 di¤erence between the receipts and the expendi- 1:3 to 1:2 36 35 37 tures of incumbents—their larger sums of cash 1:2 to 1:1 43 41 40 on hand—suggests that contributors give to 1:1 to 2:1 45 38 43 them not to help them win but because they are More than 2:1 46 41 39 going to win, a conviction that accounts for the pacs’ having reduced their support of chal- Challenger total lengers. But all of these clues aside, the major spending ranges 1984 1986 1988 attack on this problem in simultaneity has come Up to $5,000 24 23 24 in the scholarly work of Gary Jacobson. $5,000 to $25,000 27 26 26 The problem is easily defined. The percentage $25,000 to $75,000 32 30 29 of the vote the challengers get is related to the sums they spend; the greater the dollars, the $75,000 to $250,000 38 35 36 greater the votes. Money and votes are recipro- More than $250,000 45 43 42 cally related, however, because challengers raise *Includes only major-party, general-election House money on expectations about their ability to get challengers running against an incumbent in the gen- votes. So, how to show that the spending of eral election. challengers actually does a¤ect the size of the Source: Federal Election Commission. vote they get? One way is through the same two- stage least-squares procedures Janet Grenzke used to stipulate the direction of cause in the as they narrow the incumbent-challenger spend- similar problem of the correlation between ing ratio or as they increase their dollar spending pac contributions and the roll-call votes of their in the campaign (table 7.1). recipients in Congress. A second is to use poll Before one leaps to the conclusion that data to relate incremental changes in spending incumbents win and challengers lose because of to incremental changes in probable vote stage the state of their campaign resources, there are by stage during the campaign. Both avenues contrary bits of data to reckon with. House brought Jacobson to the conclusion that chal- incumbents won reelection at rates well above 90 lenger spending did indeed lead to increases in percent long before they established their pres- challenger votes.18 ent funding superiority; the cumulative reelection percentage of House incumbents from 1950 through 1970 was 91.8 percent.16 Furthermore, 17. Generally on the use of congressional perquisites the general political strength of incumbents can for developing constituent support, see Morris A. Fiorina, Congress: Keystone of the Washington Estab- lishment (New Haven: Yale University Press, 1977). 16. That is, 4064 of 4428 incumbents seeking reelec- 18. Gary C. Jacobson, Money in Congressional Elec- tion were successful. Data from Norman J. Ornstein, tions (New Haven: Yale University Press, 1980). See Thomas E. Mann, and Michael J. Malbin, Vital Sta- also Jacobson’s restatement and reconsideration in tistics on Congress, 1989–1990 (Washington: Congres- ‘‘Money and Votes Reconsidered: Congressional Elec- sional Quarterly, 1990), p. 56. tions, 1972–1982,’’ Public Choice 47 (1985), pp. 7–62. Interest Groups 413

The dynamic that relates challenger money Incumbents continue to outspend and then to challenger votes can then be outlined. Spend- to outpoll their challengers, but to conclude that ing money in the campaign buys visibility and incumbents ‘‘buy’’ reelection or that spending greater ‘‘likely support’’ for challengers, which leads to the margin of victory misstates the also means that spending results in the rising problem somewhat. Incumbents build support in expectations that enables them to raise even their constituencies largely by virtue of the per- more money. . . . The problem, therefore, is that quisites of o‰ce and by reason of the visibility although money would help them greatly, chal- and name recognition they routinely achieve. lengers have increasing trouble in raising it in the Ultimately the greatest advantage the incum- first place. bents have is not their campaign money; it is the The importance of campaign funds for chal- expectation early in the election cycle that they lengers, moreover, was highlighted by Jacob- can and will win reelection. It is that expectation son’s conclusion that incumbent spending that makes it so di‰cult for challengers to raise produced no increase in the incumbent’s share the money by which they might e¤ectively over- of the vote. In fact, the more incumbents spent, come the incumbents’ advantage in the cam- the worse they did—not because their spending paign and election. lost them votes, but because they had to spend For Americans who value competitiveness in more when challengers began to encroach on elections, the issue is of the greatest magnitude. their electoral margins. Other scholars have It is simply that the campaign finance system challenged that finding about incumbent spend- o¤ers challengers no weapons with which to ing, and the debate is yet to be resolved.20 overcome the advantages of incumbency. The Nonetheless, few would argue that the e¤ect of challengers lack money because the incumbents’ incumbent spending matches that of challenger reelection prospects are so strong as to discour- spending; it seems likely, at least, that one incre- age both the emergence of appealing challengers ment of challenger spending, an extra $25,000 and the willingness of potential contributors to perhaps, has more e¤ect on voter awareness than invest in electoral politics. The solution to the does the same increment in incumbent spending. problem, therefore, rests either in reducing the If the challenger is spending at lower levels than advantages of incumbency or in getting money is the incumbent, challenger spending will also to challengers in time to entice both strong can- be more e‰cacious per increment because of the didates and more contributors. The post-74 re- decreasing marginal utility—the smaller succes- gime faces no greater challenge. sive impact on the vote of each increment—of campaign spending. Artful Dodging and Skillful Avoiding For another review of the theoretical problem and ad- ditional poll data, see Jacobson, ‘‘The E¤ects of Cam- The conventional wisdom is right at last: the paign Spending in House Elections: New Evidence for regulatory vessel is in fact leaking. Important Old Arguments,’’ American Journal of Political Science activity and individuals escape its requirements 34 (May 1990), pp. 334–362. for reporting, and money flows outside of its 20. Contra the Jacobson conclusion, see Donald P. controls in swelling torrents. One need only tick Green and Jonathan S. Krasno, ‘‘Salvation for the o¤ the specifics: bundling, soft money, brokers, Spendthrift Incumbent: Reestimating the E¤ects of independent spending, fund-raisers netting six- Campaign Spending in House Elections,’’ American figure totals in America’s urban centers. How- Journal of Political Science 32 (November 1988), ever one may wish to describe the structural pp. 884–907. flaws—as ‘‘leaks’’ or ‘‘loopholes’’—the integrity Chapter 7 414

of the post-1974 regulatory structure is at grave reporting of all contributions. The Supreme risk. Court, however, struck down those limits in The assault on the structure of regulation, Buckley v. Valeo, leaving only the requirement the statutorily defined campaign finance system, that independent expenditures be reported to the comes in various ways. There are, first, the fec.... actors and the activity in violation of explicit The post-1974 beginnings of independent statutory limits. The individuals exceeding the spending are obscure. Record keeping at the fec $25,000 annual limit on contributions are the was in its infancy in 1976, and its data on inde- most widely publicized case; ambitious inves- pendent spending in that cycle are incomplete; tigators now vie to find new miscreants in the the best guess is that about $2 million was spent computer records of the fec. Second, there are independently, with all but $400,000 spent in the the invisible brokers and transactions that re- presidential campaign. Another $300,000 or so main only partially within the governance of the was spent in the 1978 congressional elections, system; the money they raise, and its origins, are and then came the eye-grabbing jump to a total reported, but neither their role nor the aggregate of $16.1 million in 1980 (table 7.2). . . . sums they organize are. Similar are the formal Even at their zenith, independent expenditures bundlers, many of whom press the limits of per- on congressional elections never accounted for missible control over contributions. Third, there major sums. The record $9.4 million in 1986 are the sums raised and spent outside of the was only 2 percent of the cash expenditures limits of the system. Soft money (previously dis- ($450.3 million) by all candidates in that year’s cussed) and independent spending provide the campaigns. Moreover, the e¤ective sums were major examples. The 1974 amendments to the greatly exaggerated. The splashiest spenders in feca set strict limits on the sums of money that the 1980s—ncpac and an assortment of pacs groups or citizens could spend independently in supporting Republican presidential candidates— a campaign—that is, without the control or even were pacs without parent organizations, ‘‘non- the knowledge of any candidate. Like everything connected pacs’’ in the parlance of the fec. They else in the feca those provisions have a history. raised their money in costly direct-mail solic- Spending by groups other than the candidates itations; and with no parent to pay overhead, had been the stock device for dodging earlier not to mention fund-raising expenses (postage, attempts to control spending and insure full printing, computerized mailing lists), they had to

Table 7.2 Independent spending in presidential and congressional elections: 1980–1988 Presidential Congressional Year Total $ % against % rep Total $ % against % rep

1980 $13.75 m 5.9% 96.6% $2.34 m 58.9% 83.9% 1982 $ .19 m .8% 50.2% $7.10 m 72.5% 75.9% 1984 $17.47 m 4.8% 93.4% $5.95 m 44.3% 49.7% 1986 $ .84 m 5.4% 88.9% $9.36 m 14.2% 58.9% 1988 $14.13 m 24.8% 94.9% $7.21 m 16.5% 64.1% 1990 $ .50 m 35.1% 98.0% $1.77 m 15.7% 48.6% Source: Federal Election Commission. Interest Groups 415

absorb all of these costs out of the money they intermediaries securely within the regulatory raised. Estimates vary, but shrewd and careful structure. So, the natures of the leaks di¤er; they reports found that only 5 to 20 percent of their are far too varied in both origin and purpose receipts went into campaign activity as it is usu- to bear the single pejorative label of loophole. ally understood—into television or newspaper Calling them loopholes blurs moral and ethical ads or campaign brochures or mailings. distinctions in a subject in which moral and eth- . . . Independent spending created intra- ical judgments abound. organizational problems for the pacs that tried Such judgments are the first reason for con- it; some of their donors either did not approve of cern about the integrity of the regulatory struc- it generally, or they were outraged at the pacs’ ture. Its impairments invite and receive public choice of targets. It also raised the wrath of denunciation of campaigns, campaigners, and incumbents, especially when it was spending in campaign finance. Americans do not take kindly favor of challengers, and they quickly learned to avoidance, no matter how legal or even ethi- to ignite voter backlash to it. Indeed, candidates cal, of systems of regulation; avoidance carries complained even when the spending favored the stigma of self-servingness compounded by them; none of them wanted any part of what the excessive cleverness. Independent spenders may public sees as their campaigns to be beyond their be exercising a First Amendment right in the control. most open and direct way, but they are not Those explorations by mainline pacs opened treated much more charitably than the trimmers up another issue that had festered for some and shavers who bundle ever more creatively to years: the meaning of independence. How, for escape the statutory limits on the size of con- instance, could a large pac making contributions tributions. In short, breaches in the integrity of to congressional candidates and discussing their the structure give rise to blanket judgments campaigns with them also make independent untempered or ungraded by any fine distinctions expenditures in which there was no cooperation among the kinds of breaches. or contact with the candidate? Or what of an The problems, however, extend beyond those independently financed media campaign sup- of public judgment. The breaches create massive porting candidate J when the commercials are administrative problems, especially in reporting. designed and placed by the same media con- Again, independent spending is a splendid case sultants working for candidate J’s campaign? in point. The only other spending in the cam- And how are voters to know who is responsible paign permitted by the feca is that by the can- for independent expenditures on television when didates and the party committees, both of which the credit line is invisible to most viewers? Inde- must register with the fec and make periodic pendence comes down in the end to very small reports to it. Their o‰cials become institution- but very important details. . . . alized reporters and trained compliers, most of Independent expenditures happen to exploit them also aided by accountants, lawyers, and a gap in the regulatory system created by the computer software. . . . Supreme Court’s application of the First On this and other matters of administration Amendment to it. Soft money, however, flows in and enforcement, the fec su¤ers from an uncer- presidential campaigns as a result of an intended tain authority. The placement of exchanges and exclusion from the system and the constitutional flows of money on the peripheries of the regula- status of American federalism. Most of the bun- tory system means, in e¤ect, that they sit also on dling and high-stakes brokering result from the the peripheries of the fec’s authority. One need failure of the authors of the feca, whether out only cite the great controversies, including the of faintheartedness or lack of foresight, to place intervention of the federal district court for the Chapter 7 416

District of Columbia, over the fec’s handling of while those guys have been getting away with the soft-money controversy. It has been almost murder’’ has a corrosive e¤ect on compliance. equally vexed by the bundling inventions of And compliance is that act of self-enforcement the National Republican Senatorial Committee. on which all legitimate and e¤ective systems of Underfunded by the Congress and kept on a regulation depend. short leash for 15 years, the fec has never been It almost goes without saying that breaches in able to establish its independence as a regulator; the regulatory system sabotage the achievement its even division between three Democrats and of the initial purpose of the regulation. If the three Republicans has additionally made it di‰- purpose was to limit pac contributions to $5,000 cult for the Commission to deal with problems per candidate per election, any modus operandi that are inevitably partisan. These leaks in the that permits groups of potential pac contributors regulatory system have only further embarrassed to give their cash instead as individuals defeats it and given its sterner critics more reason for both the limit and the congressional intent that criticism.23 their money be identified with the interest that Administrative problems are closely related recruited it. to mechanisms of responsibility. The major in- stitutionalized actors—pacs, parties, and candi- dates—respond to various systems of control Are Campaigns Too Expensive? or responsibility: voters, members, parent orga- nizations, representative bodies, public o‰cials, Each round of debates over congressional cam- or mass opinion, as the case may be. On the paign finance is, in the words of Yogi Berra, de´ja` other hand, brokers such as Charles Keating or vu all over again. Putting a cap on campaign a well-heeled individual contributor make no expenditures was high on the agenda of reform reports to the fec, and no other institutions or in 1974, and it still is. The Supreme Court struck responsible bodies stand behind them. With no down the feca’s limits on all spending in Buck- visibility and no long-term interest in the politi- ley, and reformers have been trying to find a way cal system, the brokers may have no political of restoring them ever since. So strongly con- reputation at stake; often, too, they o¤er no tar- vinced are the American people that campaigns get at which the wrath of voters can be directed. cost too much, so firmly placed on the agenda of The political controls of reputation and the bal- reform is the issue, that it flourishes in the 1990s lot box are imperfect at best, but they do work despite the stability of expenditures in congres- more e¤ectively on visible, committed political sional campaigns. Not only does the issue per- actors with continuing stakes in politics. sist, but its rhetoric about skyrocketing and When the integrity of the regulatory system escalating expenditures remains impervious to su¤ers, so too do the morale and the law- any new realities. abidingness of those clearly within the regulatory It is virtually a truism that the case for spend- perimeters. Compliance with both the letter and ing limits rests on the premise that the costs of the spirit of a regulatory structure cannot easily campaigning are too great. It is far less easy, survive the impression that the structure catches though, to establish that they are in fact too only some of the players while others go free. great. For many American adults the standards The belief that ‘‘I’ve been playing by the rules for making such a judgment are implicit; the spending is just ‘‘too much’’—too much perhaps 23. See, for example, Brooks Jackson, Broken Prom- by standards of middle-class personal finance, ise: Why the Federal Election Commission Failed (New too much because of the imagined rate of run- York: Priority Press, 1990). away increase in them. Or too much perhaps Interest Groups 417

in terms of value, in terms of the worth of the the take at a brokered fundraiser in Los Angeles. product or service the money produces. The A senator can make a flying trip to a distant spot campaigns, or the parts of them they happen to for a quick reception and return to Washington notice, are simply not worth those sums, just as with $50,000 or $100,000 in campaign resources. $40 is not too much for a good steak dinner but Spending levels, that is, a¤ect how money is is an outrageous price for a bad one. raised, where it is raised, and with whose help it The many cries of ‘‘too much’’ reflect negative is raised. judgments about politics and the entire public . The ability to raise funds becomes a substan- sector. Those judgments similarly govern public tial qualification for candidates. Candidates of opinion about the salaries of public o‰cials. In- knowledge, experience, and even wisdom may herent in them is a double standard, one code lack the skills or the stomach for begging funds of behavior for the private sector and another from people they scarcely know; the need to do it for the public sector. Political scientists are may discourage them from seeking o‰ce. Worse fond of making the public-private comparison than such a shrinking of the pool of talent is in campaign finance with data on advertising the possibility that the consequence will be to expenditures, for advertising campaigns are, like recruit and elect candidates whose skills in rais- campaigns for public o‰ce, an exercise in infor- ing money and conducting a campaign are their mation and persuasion. Americans are shocked chief or even their only major attributes. by total expenditures of $445.2 million in the congressional campaigns of 1990, but in that The problem with elevated spending levels seems same year Sears Roebuck, the giant merchan- to be that one needs to raise the money in the diser, had an advertising budget in excess of $1.4 first place. . . . billion. Leaving aside the strength of popular and The case against present spending levels is reformist feelings on the point, there is a basic much stronger on pragmatic or consequential conceptual problem here. Not one, but two grounds. These arguments are, however, not issues are entwined: the need for the money and about spending per se but about the need to raise the costs to the system of raising it. It is easier to the money in order to spend it. They go this way: justify the spending levels than the e¤ort that . has to go into raising the cash in the first place. Present levels of spending are too high because So, we are raising too much money and yet not in order to raise the funds to spend, elected pub- really spending enough in the campaigns for lic o‰cials must take too much time and energy Congress. . . . Even the experts and activists find from their public responsibilities. It is now al- it di‰cult to reach a judgment about American most a commonplace that a U.S. senator must campaign finance. The mass public necessarily raise $12,000 a week for six years in order to comes to its understandings about it without any amass the $3.5 to $4 million for a typical Senate profound knowledge, often without even basic campaign. information. Citizens are compelled to watch the . Furthermore, the pressures to raise those sums shadows projected on the vast wall in front of for a Senate race, or close to half a million for them. They take their conclusions and judgments a House campaign, drive candidates to seek as they see them in the dance of distorted images. money in large sums at a time when contribution Of necessity, their judgments are the judgments limits are shrinking because of inflation. Initially, of those who project the images. candidates replaced small individual contrib- In the opinions on all of the major concerns utors with large pac contributions, and now even about the post-1974 system, the consonances and the usual pac contribution is small compared to dissonances are consistent. Whether it is the pac- Chapter 7 418

Congress connection, the impact of money on in the case of ‘‘corruption or the appearance of the winning of elections, or the judgments about corruption,’’ either in the instance of certifiable spending levels, mass opinion and image-making corruption by some unspecified standards, or opinion are in agreement. Their consensus, in the instance of some widespread belief that moreover, diverges in all three instances from institutions were being corrupted. So, Congress much of scholarly and other expert opinion.27 might apparently act on the basis of one reality . . . It is hardly a novel outcome, for expert or the other, on the basis of the image behind the opinion is often at odds with mass opinion over viewer or the image projected on the wall. Is it the analysis of public problems and policy solu- to make no di¤erence if one reality could meet tions. It is, in fact, one of the oldest and most standards of truth or validity and the other could troubling dilemmas in the governance of mass, not? The answer, in the world of democratic popular democracies. politics, depends on crafting reforms that serve The successes and failures of the post-1974 re- both reality and its appearances. gime present the dilemma in a heightened form. Mass opinion about campaign finance increas- ingly feeds a cynicism about, even a rejection of, basic democratic processes. Any threat to mass involvement in or acceptance of electoral politics threatens the essence of representative govern- ment. The resulting conflict of equities could not be more disturbing. Is one to adopt policies that address the real problems of the system, as the informed best understand them, or ought one to devise change that will lay to rest the fears and anger of a disa¤ected public? Can we indeed win back disa¤ected citizens and solve real public problems at the same time? It is the hard- est of the policy questions, this intersection of image and reality, of mass politics and expert prescription—especially when the divergence is not only over ultimate policy goals, but over the reality of the problem itself. Whether by accident or prescience, the justices of the U.S. Supreme Court recognized the di- lemma in the majority opinion in Buckley v. Valeo. Congress could act to limit the constitu- tionally protected flow of campaign money only

27. I want to be clear that in referring to scholarly opinion I am talking about more than my judgments. I have cited examples of scholarly opinion about the first two issues; as for the question of spending levels, see, inter alia, Larry J. Sabato, Paying for Elections: The Campaign Finance Thicket (New York: Priority Press, 1989), especially chapters 2 and 3. 8 DEMOCRACY’S EFFECTS

The Economics and Politics of Growth Karl de Schweinitz, Jr.

Rent Seeking and Redistribution under Democracy versus Dictatorship Ronald Wintrobe

Dictatorship, Democracy, and Development Mancur Olson

Freedom Favors Development Amartya Sen

Political Regimes and Economic Growth Adam Przeworski, Michael E. Alvarez, Jose´ Antonio Cheibub, and Fernando Limongi

Democracy in America Alexis de Tocqueville

Does Democracy Engender Justice? John E. Roemer

Facing up to the American Dream: Race, Class, and the Soul of the Nation Jennifer L. Hochschild

Beyond Tocqueville, Myrdal, and Hartz: The Multiple Traditions in America Rogers M. Smith The Economics and Politics of Growth

Karl de Schweinitz, Jr.

Economic growth may be defined as the process ment decisions involve uncertainty? How are the which gives rise to an increase in per capita, or benefits of investment distributed? average, income. . . . In attempting to answer these questions it will . . . The concern here is with the political con- be convenient to distinguish between private and sequences of the economic transition from one public motives for investment. Assuming that a stage to another, rather than with the measure- private individual maximizes profit, he will in- ment of economic welfare. . . . vest if he anticipates that his income will increase The proximate requirements for economic at least as much as the added costs he incurs. . . . growth may be stated quite briefly: increased The public motivation for investment is simi- employment of resources per capita and/or lar, but with this di¤erence: a public authority, in increased e‰ciency in the employment of exist- calculating the feasibility of an investment proj- ing resources. . . . ect, balances social income against social costs Whether growth is achieved through the in- and will carry out the project only if he expects a creased use of inputs per capita or through in- greater return to society from resources in the creased e‰ciency, one process stands out as contemplated project than in alternative uses. being crucially important—investment. Invest- Where the private investor is maximizing values ment may be defined as an addition to plant and derived from his own utility function, the public equipment and/or inventories. It involves the investor is maximizing values derived from a so- production of that type of output which expands cial welfare function.2 ... the capacity of an economy. Obviously, when an Though private and public investment are economy grows through the accumulation (the motivated by di¤erent rationales, they both increase) of capital, investment is taking place. focus on the expansion of future output and, Perhaps less obviously, investment also is basic therefore, have characteristics in common. First to growth through an increase of the other of all, to greater or less extent the decision to in- resources—land and labor. . . . vest is made in the face of uncertainty. . . . One may infer from its inherent uncertainty that investment requires a person with rather The Rationale of Investment and the Nature of Entrepreneurial Activity 2. The question of investment criteria is a good deal more complex than indicated in the text. Of all the The paramount importance of investment in phases of economics, capital theory is perhaps the most economic growth necessitates further inquiry di‰cult and obscure because of ineluctable theoretical about its rationale and the conditions which problems involved in the treatment of time. Those who make it possible. Who invests and why? What is are interested in these problems in the context of eco- the nature of the decision-making process which nomic development may find the following references induces some individuals to commit resources to useful: A. E. Kahn, ‘‘Investment Criteria in Develop- the expansion of future output? Do all invest- ment,’’ Quarterly Journal of Economics, LXV, Febru- ary, 1951, pp. 38–61; W. Galenson and H. Leibenstein, ‘‘Investment Criteria, Productivity, and Economic De- Excerpted from: Karl de Schweinitz, Jr., Industrializa- velopment,’’ idem, LXIX, August, 1955, pp. 343–370; tion and Democracy: Economic Necessities and Political R. C. Blitz, ‘‘Capital Longevity and Economic Devel- Possibilities. Glencoe, Ill.: The Free Press. opment,’’ American Economic Review, XLVIII, June, 1958, pp. 313–329. Democracy’s E¤ects 421

uncommon, if not unique, characteristics. He unity. Yet growth requires that resources be must have the capacity to calculate his chances released from present consumption for allocation of success on the basis of signals that the exist- to investment. ing economic environment flashes to him. He How can this impasse be surmounted? In gen- must have the ability to obtain and organize the eral there are two answers to the question. One, resources for constructing additional or new income can be distributed in such a way that a plant and equipment. Above all, he must have disproportionate share is placed at the disposal confidence that the future will validate his pres- of those who will be willing to refrain from con- ent choice of action, which is to say that he suming it. This method, of course, involves the believes that he can manipulate the environ- generation of saving through an unequal distri- ment to achieve the ends he has set for himself. bution of income. Two, government may impose We enumerate these characteristics because they taxes on households which reduce the level of suggest that entrepreneurial talents will not be disposable income available for consumption. widespread in any society and will be particu- Neither with the one alternative nor the other larly limited in a subsistence society.4 For the does the mass of individuals make an unencum- latter tends to obviate problems of uncertainty bered choice between consumption and saving. by adhering to customary or traditional patterns In both cases they are forced to save, in the one of performance. The typical individual in a sub- through the medium of capitalists, in the other sistence economy then will not be accustomed to through the medium of government o‰cials. change, and still less to the notion that he can Let us restate the problem now in terms that influence the shape of the environment by his will bring out the essential preference conflict actions. involved in growth at low levels of income. In The inference that entrepreneurs are a mi- a subsistence economy, the time preference of nority group is further supported by a second the overwhelming majority of the population characteristic that private and public investment will be so high that no monetary reward, how- have in common, namely their dependence on ever great, can induce them to forego present the withdrawing of resources from present con- consumption. If growth is to take place, some sumption. The restriction of consumption, that is members of the community with a low enough saving, raises issues which are particularly ger- time preference to allow them to calculate the mane to our analysis, for they relate to problems advantages of future versus present output must of conflicts in preferences. In a subsistence econ- gain title to resources. In short, the preferences omy, the members of the community will neces- of a minority must take precedence over those of sarily try to consume all output produced. No a majority. . . . matter how they may feel about the virtues of allocating resources to investment, they have no choice, given the immediacy of the struggle for Economic Obstacles to the Industrial existence, but to maximize present consumption. Transformation In short, their propensity to consume approaches With these notions about investment before us, 4. See Clark Kerr, John T. Dunlop, Frederick H. we come now to the crucial issue of economic Harbison, and Charles A. Myers, Industrialism and In- growth. We know that a subsistence economy dustrial Man, Cambridge, Mass., 1960 for an analysis hardly invests more than the amount necessary of the role of entrepreneurial or industrializing elites in to maintain the value of its meager capital stock, economic development, especially as it a¤ects the rela- reflecting a set of social institutions which max- tionships between labor and management. imize traditional and customary values. We also Chapter 8 422

know that high-income economies invest a high it may allocate to transportation and the other proportion of their national income and have utilities a disproportionate share of its invest- acquired the kinds of institutions and attitudes ment. This is done in order to construct the which more or less automatically sustain the social overhead capital which provides manu- saving and investment processes essential to facturing concerns with the means for marketing growth. How, then, in the words of Professor output and employing inputs. Accordingly, one Lewis, does an economy change from a situation would expect capital-output ratios to rise during in which it is investing less than 5 percent of its this period of utility construction. Subsequently national income to one in which it is investing when this sector of the economy does not require more than 12 percent?7 ... a disproportionate share of the community’s . . . [T]he capital-output concept is a useful investment, the output of sectors with lower means for suggesting the dimensions of the tasks capital-output ratios may experience a relatively confronting an economy which intends to rise greater expansion, thus leading to a decline in above the subsistence status. What is at issue the overall capital-output ratio. Furthermore, here is the amount of investment that is required during the early stage of growth when the labor on the average to produce a unit of output. The force has not yet acquired the habits of industrial lower the capital-output ratio the more rapidly discipline, a given stock of capital will not yield a given amount of investment will give rise to its maximum output because of absenteeism, ex- increased output.10 ... cessive turnover, and because of improper and . . . [I]t would appear to be a reasonable hy- inadequate capital maintenance. These problems pothesis that when a subsistence economy enters will be resolved as the industrial labor force upon a stage of development in which its rate comes of age, leading to labor’s more e‰cient of net investment rises to a permanently higher utilization of the existing capital stock. level, marginal capital-output ratios at first rise If this hypothesis is correct, it suggests that and then subsequently fall. The reasons for sug- ‘‘the take-o¤’’ is characterized not only by a gesting this hypothesis are as follows. Technical proportionate rise in net investment, but by a capital coe‰cients tend to be highest in the period in which there is a longer than ‘‘normal’’ transportation, communication, and utility sec- wait for the appearance of the increased output tors of an economy and lowest in manufacturing. contingent upon investment. Consider what this This is to say, it takes a greater amount of capi- means in more concrete terms. During the take- tal to produce one unit of transportation than it o¤, or what conventionally is called an industrial does to produce one unit of manufactured goods. revolution, railways, canals, roads, harbors, steel When, however, an economy first starts to grow plants, and other facilities essential to an in- terdependent industrial economy are being con- 7. W. Arthur Lewis, ‘‘Economic Development with structed. The limit to the development of the Unlimited Supplies of Labor,’’ The Manchester School, economy is the availability of saving rather than XXII, May, 1954, pp. 139–191. the existence of investment opportunities. 10. In part the rapid growth of output in the Soviet Indeed, so great is the pressure on resources Union is attributable to the emphasis planners have for the construction of industrial and social cap- placed on activities characterized by low capital-output ital that not all demands can be satisfied simul- ratios at the expense of activities characterized by high taneously. Something has to give. In the face of capital-output ratios. Thus the industrial and manu- capital scarcities some projects will be post- facturing sectors of the Soviet economy have been poned, or, if undertaken, constructed with mate- given greater weight than the housing and transporta- rials that economize capital. Thus it may be the tion sectors, which typically absorb a large volume of resources before yielding increments to output. case, for example, that urban housing is not Democracy’s E¤ects 423

expanded at a fast enough rate to take care of view represents a fundamental change and re- the influx of workers from the rural sector of orientation of values, economic growth can be the economy leading to overcrowded conditions expected to induce it, if ever it does, only after in cities. Or perhaps additional housing is con- the passage of a considerable length of time. In structed from flimsy, nondurable materials which the meantime, mortality rates decline and popu- deteriorate rapidly. Urban communities may ne- lation explodes. glect their health and recreational services. Fac- tories may be constructed with inadequate safety devices. The Welfare Problem during the Industrial While the economy is cutting corners on some Revolution kinds of investment and refraining from other kinds, the investment being undertaken yields its The take-o¤, then, raises a formidable standard return slowly. . . . of living, or what for shorthand purposes we shall call a welfare problem. . . . The take-o¤ stage is characterized by forces which tend to The Population Barrier to Growth prevent marked improvement in the standard of living of the masses of people...... The most commonly discussed barrier to Given the utilitarian idea of welfare, there are growth, the surmounting of which seems to re- three factors a¤ecting it which we consider par- quire the expenditure of a concentrated dose of ticularly relevant to our analysis, two relating to social energy, is the possible population explo- supply conditions and one to demand conditions. sion it induces. In a subsistence economy birth Consider first the level of income and employ- rates and mortality rates are both relatively high. ment. If a subsistence economy fully employed If with the onset of economic growth mortality available resources including labor and produced rates decline before birth rates, then the rate of enough only to provide the members of society population growth will increase. If it increases with a minimal standard of living, then a rise in rapidly enough, it may abort per capita income the rate of net investment would imply a de- increases and, indeed, may even lower per capita crease in the output of consumers’ goods and a income. The reasons why output growth and decline in short-run welfare.13 . . . The assump- population growth may be functionally related tion of full employment, however, does not ap- are well known. The increased production of pear to be especially valid in the conditions of a subsistence goods such as grain may lower mor- subsistence economy. First of all, there is likely tality rates by improving diets and increasing re- to be a surfeit of population with many workers sistance to disease. The draining of swamps and unable to find full-time employment under the the use of DDT reduce the incidence of malaria and yellow fever. Increased educational oppor- 13. This proposition is correct if welfare is measured tunity facilitates the spread of higher standards solely in terms of the current output of consumer of public health and hygiene. While the expan- goods. If, however, welfare is measured in terms of the sion of the output of consumers’ goods and/or pattern of consumption over time, then it may not be investment goods may decrease the mortality valid. For it is conceivable that people might be willing rate, the birth rate, at least for a time, remains to have their subsistence reduced now, if they thought insensitive to these changes. Only when house- it would lead to the expansion of consumable output tomorrow. In addition to the di‰culties mentioned in holds come to recognize family limitation as a the text previously, problems of this sort involving time desirable goal and have the knowledge for and preferences and intertemporal comparisons make the means of doing so will birth rates fall. Since this concept of welfare in economics all the more elusive. Chapter 8 424

existing organization of production. Second, simply devalued the housing component in their many workers who are ostensibly employed utility function, there might be no di‰culty. But may not be contributing much, if anything, to this is most unlikely. Indeed, expectations may output. . . . Unemployed labor, whether overt or be raised under the influence of new preferences covert in ine‰cient employments, permits the and demands acquired in the industrial-urban expansion of investment without an absolute de- community. We are referring to the impact of crease in the output of consumption goods. . . . the so-called demonstration e¤ect. As first for- The proportionate rise of net investment, there- mulated by Duesenberry, the demonstration ef- fore, comes out of an increasing rather than a fect related to the propensity of people when given income. confronted by a decline in disposable income to While the conditions of aggregate invest- try to maintain the highest standard of living ment during the industrial revolution do not they had attained in the past.16 Here it refers to preclude increases of welfare, the allocation of the tendency of people to acquire higher con- investment—the second supply factor—raises sumption aspirations when they come in contact some problems for which there is no easy solu- with a standard of living higher than that to tion. As indicated previously, capital scarcities which they have been accustomed. The urban- during the period will compel the cutting back or industrial community is an active disseminator holding back of certain types of investment of the demonstration e¤ect. If people live in projects. . . . squalid and cramped gerrybuilt houses, they can In raising this question we have introduced observe others who live in sumptuous quarters. the third factor a¤ecting welfare, namely the If they cannot pay the price of admission to the subjective element of demand, preferences, and theater or other forms of urban entertainment, expectations. . . . A number of things may hap- they at least know something about the enter- pen to people’s expectations during the period of tainment that is available. To put it another way, the industrial revolution. As workers move into in the urban community the inequality of wealth the industrial community, their image of reality and income is more visible than in the rural more adequately reflects conditions as they are community and therefore acts as a greater stim- and they become aware of the shortcomings of ulant in the formation of new preferences among their new environment in concrete terms. Prior the less privileged members of society. to moving, rumors of high wages may have The welfare problem of the industrial revolu- subordinated rumors about crowded housing tion may be contrasted to the problems which facilities. After moving, high wages become a J. K. Galbraith sees a¿icting the A¿uent Soci- particular bundle of goods and services that ur- ety. In the latter the basic wants have been more ban society a¤ords the workers. If the welfare or less satisfied and production is geared to the component of this bundle of goods and services satisfaction of wants of less urgency. . . . during the industrial revolution is constrained On the other hand, the opposite problem holds by investment priorities necessitated by growth, for the economy entering upon the early stages then the expectations formed at one remove of development. Wants increase faster than the from the industrial-urban environment are likely output of consumer goods, for while the struc- to be frustrated. tural capital of an industrial economy is being This might not be a matter of great moment built, the wants of the community grow with- if it were safe to assume that expectations of people were quickly and easily adjusted to cir- 16. James S. Duesenberry, Income, Saving and the cumstances as they found them. When housing Theory of Consumer Behavior, Cambridge, Mass., turned out to be worse than expected, if people 1949. Democracy’s E¤ects 425

out the special e¤ort and blandishments of the The Political Problem of the Industrial advertisers. So basic are they that when people Revolution become aware of higher standards in their satis- faction, they can quickly revise their preferences We are now at a point in our analysis where and acquire greater expectations. . . . we can state the essence of the political prob- lem raised by the process of economic growth. The Individual and Collectivist Response to the Whatever the specific institutional factors which Welfare Problem trigger it, a small group of men assume respon- sibility for the investment projects which mark Another aspect of the ‘‘hump’’ implicit in our out the path of the economy’s development. discussion of the welfare problem during the in- While this group has first claim to the increased dustrial revolution suggests an important link output generated in the early stages of growth, a between economic growth and the problems of far larger number of people is thrust into cir- the political system. If wants expand more rap- cumstances where their wants start to run ahead idly than the output of consumers’ goods, it is of the capacity of the economy to satisfy them. reasonable to expect that the people whose The resulting discontent and dissidence may expectations are frustrated and who do not re- manifest itself in disorders—riots, strikes, mob ceive what they think they are entitled to will demonstrations—which threaten the political attempt to do something about it. . . . Generally, stability of the society. Governmental leaders, one may distinguish two quite di¤erent re- therefore, as a necessary part of maintaining the sponses. One, individuals might accept the eco- prerogatives of o‰ce and political power, must nomic order as they see it with the goals it deal with these disorders and attempt to main- represents and the drives it maximizes and try tain social order in the community. But in per- to acquire the perquisites of the privileged mem- forming this task there is one thing they cannot bers of society by their own individual e¤orts. If do, if they are concerned with facilitating the entrepreneurship is the route to wealth, so be it. continued growth of the economy: they cannot Alternatively, individuals might band together try to solve the political problem by acceding to in organizations in order to improve their status the demands of the masses of workers and in society. Working through trade unions, they granting them rights commensurate with the might try to raise wage rates and influence other rights of the privileged members of society. For conditions of labor through the exercise of their growth at the early critical stage of the take-o¤ is collective strength. Similarly, they might engage a discriminatory process which favors the few in political activity to achieve a change in the who are able to take the steps necessary to raise institutional environment favorable to their in- the rate of net investment. If the political system terests, e.g., minimum wage legislation. chooses to support the consumption goals of the . . . Entrepreneurship requires a rare combina- many against the growth goals of the few, then tion of qualities, the capacity to evaluate the growth, if not aborted, will surely be slowed uncertainties of the future, a belief in one’s abil- down. ity to manipulate and control the environment, Suppose, for example, that trade unions are and command of scarce capital resources. These able to organize e¤ectively as rapidly as workers qualities only fall to a minority. The majority, move into the urban-industrial sector of the therefore, may react to the frustrations of the economy and therefore can bring pressure on industrial revolution by turning to some kind of entrepreneurs for increased wages. Profit rates collective action. . . . will fall diminishing the volume of retained Chapter 8 426

earnings which at early stages of development governmental leaders at early stages of develop- very likely are the most important source of ment are not themselves particularly interested in saving. Or, perhaps more significantly, suppose fostering the democratic potential of workers. trade unions are able to impose on entrepreneurs They are not trying to create a democratic soci- rules and regulations with respect to the em- ety. Rather they are trying to maximize their ployment of workers which inhibit the ability of tenure of power by taking the steps necessary to the former to experiment with di¤erent uses of retain o‰ce. The question then can be rephrased: capital. Growth through increased e‰ciency in How can nondemocratic governmental leaders the utilization of resources might then be so far cope with the tensions of the industrial labor restricted. Again, consider a political branch of force in such a way as to allow economic growth a labor movement which is well organized to to continue to take place without destroying the pressure government into granting workers the democratic tendencies which growth may con- many benefits of the welfare state. The resulting tain? We will seek the answer to this paradoxical old age, health, and unemployment measures question in the experience of the industrialization may divert resources away from the construction of the western world. First, however, we must of the utilities essential for subsequent growth pose a hypothesis about growth and democracy through their e¤ect on the distribution of in- which relates the emergence of the latter to the come. If taxes on entrepreneurs rise to finance point or period in history when the former takes these programs the funds available for the accu- place. . . . mulation of real capital will be decreased. Granted that the aspirations and demands of dissident workers must somehow be contained or repressed in order to preserve the conditions for further growth, how can governmental author- ities be sure that the measures they take do not also kill o¤ the democratic potential to which the organized activities of workers give rise? The subsistence economy, we have argued, cannot sustain a democratic political society and one of the things which must happen to foster develop- ment towards democracy is the dissemination of the idea that individual action does matter and that individuals can influence the state of the community through participation in political life. The dissidence and discontent of the early stages of the industrial revolution are among the in- fluences which may lead individuals to acquire democratic attitudes. Irritated by the circum- stances in which they find themselves and no longer able to believe in the immutability of an environment which is visibly changing, workers may be induced to remedy their own condition rather than accept the writ of tradition and au- thority. The answer to the question raised at the beginning of this paragraph, of course, is that Rent Seeking and Redistribution under Democracy versus Dictatorship

Ronald Wintrobe

ment has gained currency, especially in political 1 Introduction science and among theorists of development from both economics and political science who The idea that ‘‘too much’’ democracy is bad for specifically point to the capacity of authoritarian economic development has resurfaced again in states to resist distributional pressures as the key recent years. In the economic literature, the main to successful development. The most influential reason advanced is that democracy is ‘‘plagued’’ contemporary exponent of this view seems to be by redistributional impulses. Perhaps the most Stephen Haggard (1990), although the argument famous work to advance this theme is Mancur is much older. . . . Olson’s (1982) The Rise and Decline of Nations, This essay considers the popular idea that in which interest groups are reclassified as ‘‘dis- democratic governments inhibit growth because tributional coalitions’’ that pursue their own of excess redistributory activity or rent-seeking. I selfish interests at the expense of overall eco- ask the question: on theoretical grounds, which nomic e‰ciency. The older and more established type of regime can be expected to engage in more the democracy, the larger the number of dis- redistribution—democracy or dictatorship? tributional coalitions that have a chance to form and the more the economic landscape is ‘‘rent’’ with ine‰cient laws, regulations, and other 2 Dictatorship, Democracy, and Redistribution practices that hinder growth. In a similar vein, the vast literature on rent-seeking, originated by . . . Although I do not present a formal proof, Tullock(1967),Krueger(1974),andPosner(1975), I develop and defend a simple proposition: identified rent-seeking and its associated social Dictatorships tend to redistribute income more costs with democratic government and thus made than democracies do. If the analysis is correct, it it possible, by a strange twist of logic in which obviously casts doubt on the proposition that democracy is identified with the proliferation of democracies are less e‰cient than dictatorships economic monopolies, for monopoly to be ele- because they are more capable of resisting de- vated to the status of a serious problem. mands for redistribution. . . . Although critical of democratic processes, . . . [T]he argument proceeds essentially by none of the above-named authors has embraced taking existing models of the level of redistribu- the notion that authoritarianism can facilitate tion under democracy and then showing that, in economic development, and indeed, Mancur a well-defined sense, the amount of redistribution Olson in particular has forcefully argued the in the model of dictatorship is larger than this. opposite (Olson, 1993). However, the closely Specifically, suppose that, under the benchmark related idea that insulating economic policy free-market case, the distribution of income is from democratic processes—‘‘a little bit’’1 of dic- given by x1; ...; xn. Now suppose we assume a tatorship—can be good for economic develop- normal (not necessarily minimal) democratic government and ask what happens to this distri- Excerpted from: Ronald Wintrobe, ‘‘Rent Seeking and bution. Of course, what happens depends on the Redistribution under Democracy versus Dictatorship.’’ model of democracy used, and there is at present In Understanding Democracy: Economic and Political Perspectives. Ed. Albert Breton, Gianluigi Galeotti, Pierre Salmon, and Ronald Wintrobe. Cambridge: 1. The case for massive dictatorship, for instance that Cambridge University Press, 1997. Reprinted with the communism is better able to promote economic growth permission of Cambridge University Press. than capitalism, is no longer fashionable. Chapter 8 428

no common agreement on the e¤ect of demo- paralyzed by inaction. The ‘‘allure’’ of dictator- cratic government on the distribution of income. ship under these circumstances is obvious; either In the standard, median-voter model, there is the left or the right, if it takes power by force, no solution to this problem, because, under will be able to eliminate its opposition through majority rule, no majority coalition is dominant repression and in this way be able to implement and the outcome simply cycles among the al- its program. Either alternative implies a massive ternatives available. There are, however, other redistribution of income compared to that typi- models that do obtain determinant results: cal under democracy. Meltzer and Richard’s (1981) model, in which A second explanation of the redistributive income is redistributed from the mean to the tendencies of dictatorship is implicit in Przewor- median (in terms of income) voter; Becker’s ski’s (1991) analysis of ‘‘self-enforcing’’ democ- (1983) model of interest group pressure; and the racy. Przeworski suggests that for democracy to probabilistic voting model of Coughlin (1986) be stable, it must be self-enforcing, and for that and others. We will consider all three of these to be true, the competitive political process can- models. Each of them can be thought of as pro- not result in outcomes highly adverse to any ducing a vector of incomes y1; ...; yn. major group’s interest. If it did, it would benefit The next step is to impose a dictatorship that group to subvert democracy rather than and see what happens to the distribution of in- support it. The dictator faces no such constraint. come. Call the resulting distribution of in- A third line of thought concerns the rent- come z1; ...; zn. Our central proposition is that seeking process. To elaborate the process, we the distribution of income under dictatorship first have to discuss a serious flaw in the standard z1; ...; zn is ‘‘further away’’ from the benchmark model of rent-seeking. Explaining this flaw will free-market cases x1; ...; xn than the distribution illustrate some of the ways in which the distri- of income under any of the three models of bution of rents di¤ers between democracies and democracy y1; ...; yn. Alternatively, and more dictatorships. In the standard model, citizens formally, the proposition is that dictatorship is and interest groups compete for rents through characterized by more redistributive ‘‘activity,’’ ‘‘wasteful’’ activities such as lobbying, hiring that is, lawyers, and so on. Thus in the case of a $10,000 ‘‘prize,’’ with 10 groups competing, each of Xn Xn which has an equal chance of getting the rent, (z x )2 > (y x )2 1 i i i i ð Þ the expected value of the rent to each competitor i¼1 i¼1 is $1,000. If the competitors are risk neutral, Why would this be so? Before proceeding to a each of them will waste up to $1,000 attempting more formal analysis, let us consider a couple of to obtain the prize. The problem with this model reasons why we should expect this result. The is that the process is irrational from the point of first has to do with the origins of dictatorship. As view of politicians. They give out a monopoly discussed elsewhere, the simplest explanation for rent worth $10,000 and receive nothing in return. the rise of dictatorship is that in societies with A rational politician would organize the process polarized preferences, or low trust between the di¤erently. For example, she would suggest to citizens and the parties, or where there is no the competitors that they should o¤er cash pay- willingness to compromise, there are really only ments instead of wasting the time of politicians two possibilities: Either the party that gains through their lobbying activities. (It is essential o‰ce in democratic voting tries to implement to the model that it makes no di¤erence which of its preferred position, in which case large social the competitors gets the prize; hence the lobby- conflict will ensue, or the society will be simply ing activity is pure waste to the politicians as well Democracy’s E¤ects 429

as to society.) But if bribes instead of lobbying lic such as the worth of the project, costs, etc., are used, the $10,000 that is received in bribes by and not on the political connections, race, eth- the politicians is not waste, but a pure transfer to nicity, status, and so on of the bidders. politicians from interest groups, which represents (3) The process of bidding should be as open as no social waste or deadweight loss at all. possible and be open to review by an indepen- To see some other ways in which the rent- dent judiciary. seeking process can be organized consider what typically happens under dictatorship. Dictators, The ine‰ciency of democracy, according to at least of the more ‘‘successful’’ (i.e., relatively the rent-seeking model, is now exposed. All of long-lived) variety, often know how to organize these conditions imply that more resources will things so that they get a substantial return out of be wasted under the bidding process in democ- the process of rent-seeking. Indeed, under many racy. In short, democracy is a much more waste- regimes the distribution of rents reached legend- ful system than dictatorship. ary proportions. . . . The problem with the theory is that losses In . . . these systems, resources are not wasted from pure rent-seeking implies that there are bidding for the rents of the public sector. Rents gains from trade between politicians and rent are given out, and the dictator receives political seekers. To the extent that trade between these support or money payments or other things . . . groups takes place (through bribery, corruption, in return. In other words, there is no waste,in extortion, etc.), the waste in the process will be the economic sense. One explanation for the dif- eliminated. Consequently, if transaction costs ference in the way rents are distributed under between these groups are low, the equilibrium dictatorship versus under democracy is that dic- will not be as described in the rent-seeking tators typically impose restrictions on entry into model, but instead will be the ‘‘corruption’’ competition for the rents given out by the state. equilibrium with no waste but with a defrauded Sometimes the rents are reserved for specific public. On the other hand, suppose that these groups. . . . transactions are prevented, because the rules In part, the reason for this is obvious: If free against influence peddling, bribery, and extor- competition for rents is allowed, and support tion (the existence of which are characteristic of depends on receiving net benefits from the state, democracy everywhere) are well-enforced by then, because rent-seeking results in net losses, alert and powerful independent authorities. This dictators would lose support by distributing rents gives a second possible equilibrium, in which fair through an openly competitive process! competition among bidders is enforced. If this How does democracy di¤er? Restrictions on bidding results in rents being distributed to those entry into bidding processes for rights and priv- who bid the lowest or who o¤er the public the ileges, goods, and services distributed by the most in the way of benefits, then this process state, which are characteristic of authoritarian produces something useful. The natural name to governments, are clearly inconsistent with the give this equilibrium is ‘‘strong democracy.’’ very notion of democracy. A typical democracy The rent-seeking model rules out this outcome will impose conditions like the following in any by assuming that it makes no di¤erence who process of allocating public resources: wins the contest and that no social benefits re- sult from the bidding process. Combining these (1) No restrictions are imposed on who can bid, assumptions with the assumption that the rules except of a technical nature. against corruption and the enforcement of them (2) The winning bid should be selected on the are so powerful that corruption is eliminated basis of criteria involving net benefit to the pub- gives a third possible equilibrium: waste. A Chapter 8 430

more appropriate name for this equilibrium is nition of dictatorship in the literature of politi- ‘‘irrational’’ because it implies that political cal science essentially distinguishes dictatorship institutions are fundamentally irrational in de- from democracy on this ground. In this third sign: They are there to ensure the persistence of line of analysis we will hold to this definition waste. . . . but pursue the analysis in a bit more depth At this point, the reader may be tempted to by looking at models of redistribution under ask, What di¤erence does it make? Suppose that democracy. . . . the losses from rent-seeking are not genuine The simplest model of political redistribution waste in the economic sense, but ‘‘merely’’ under democracy is probably Becker’s (1983) unauthorized (in e¤ect, fraudulent) transfers to model of competition among interest groups. politicians and bureaucrats. It is true that these Most of the analysis is conducted with just two are not waste in the sense of economic theory, homogeneous groups, s and t, who engage in but they are certainly not what the cost–benefit political activity in order to raise the incomes of analysis promised! If the proper equilibrium their members. Both groups produce political involves corruption, not rent-seeking, isn’t that ‘‘pressure,’’ and in equilibrium, group s receives bad enough? a subsidy financed by taxes on group t. The size One reason for insisting on the distinction be- of the tax and subsidy is determined by dead- tween corruption and rent-seeking is that the weight losses (which rise as the tax or subsidy solutions to these two problems can be vastly rises) and by the fact that the ‘‘loser’’ in the di¤erent. In particular, it is easy to imagine that political game (the taxed group t) need not a ‘‘little bit of authoritarianism’’ might possibly passively accept his losses but can limit them reduce rent-seeking (which after all is a form of through lobbying, threats, disobedience, migra- political competition). It is much more di‰cult tion, and other kinds of political pressure. to believe that autocracy is the solution to cor- However, no model of the political system is ruption. Under autocracy, there are fewer or no presented; rather, the analysis is explicitly in- constraints on the practice of rent distribution by tended to apply to many di¤erent kinds of pol- independent courts or an inquisitory free press; itical systems including dictatorship (Becker, political dictatorships have a significantly larger 1983, p. 375). capacity to organize the distribution of rents Suppose, however, that the equilibrium de- in order to maximize their own ‘‘take’’ in the scribed by Becker corresponds to that under de- case of bribes or to generate the most political mocracy. How would it change if this democracy support. Moreover, the dictator is capable of were taken over by a dictatorship? There are two sanctioning nonrepayment directly, solving the main forces that would a¤ect the outcome. The enforcement problem that is inherent in rent- first is that the dictator has the power to repress seeking trades in a way that no democracy is opposition to his policies; the second is that the capable of. In addition, as I have suggested else- dictator is more insecure about his political sup- where, the dictator lacks the alternative ways port, because, as discussed in the previous sec- of creating trust or support characteristic of de- tion, among other things, the overt pro¤ering of mocracy. The distribution of rents in exchange support from those over which he has power is for loyalty is therefore her major avenue for necessarily less reliable than o¤ers of support to developing political support or trust. a democratic politician. If the preferences and This reasoning relies on the capacity of dicta- constellation of power relations between the two tors to repress the political or economic rights groups is unchanged (the analysis would be of its citizenry as the key to its redistributive unchanged if many groups were assumed), the tendency. And indeed, the most common defi- most reasonable assumption to make is that Democracy’s E¤ects 431

the dictator achieves power with the support of ductive) poor and middle-income voters. In one the subsidized group. The dictator, however, has sense, the model is already a model of dictator- the power, which was unavailable to a demo- ship because the tax rate is chosen by a ‘‘decisive cratic politician, to directly repress pressure by voter’’ who, under democracy, is taken to be the taxed group by banning their political the median voter. The tax rate in turn determines organizations, refusing to permit their views to the level of redistribution. If, on the other hand, appear in the media, refusing to allow them to the decisive voter was poor, he would choose a meet or organize, and jailing, torturing, or even higher tax rate, resulting in more redistribution; executing their leaders. Moreover, the dictator but if rich he would choose a lower one, resulting either maximizes power or consumption, subject in less redistribution. to the power constraint. In either case, repressing However, the model simply does not allow for the opposition is obviously beneficial to him. In any mechanism by which redistribution can be terms of Becker’s analysis, the e¤ect of political e¤ected from the poor. Thus none of the strat- repression is the same as if the taxed group ex- egies discussed in Stigler’s (1970) famous paper perienced a reduction in its capacity to produce on Director’s law, which alleged that redistri- pressure, as described in Becker’s Proposition 1. bution in a democracy was typically from both The result is an increase in the size of the subsidy the rich and the poor to the middle classes, to group s and an increase in the tax on group t, and included such practices as tax exemptions, that is, more redistribution than in the demo- minimum-wage laws, farm policy, regulation, cratic case. licensing practices, and so on, can be intro- This conclusion seems straightforward and duced into the model, in which redistribution is obvious enough and is derived solely on the financed by a single tax rate that applies equally assumption that the dictator has an interest in to everyone. Nor can any of the practices used power and possesses an instrument—the ca- by dictators who have drastically redistributed pacity for political repression—that is unavail- from the poor to the rich . . . be discussed within able to a democratic politician. If, in addition, this model. So the model is not very useful for we were to consider the second characteristic our purposes. However, given these qualifica- of dictatorship discussed above—namely, his tions, a genuine dictatorship could be introduced insecurity—this would only reinforce the con- into the model by empowering the ‘‘decisive clusion just obtained. The dictator will want to voter’’ with the capacity to repress opposition. In increase the size of the subsidy to the winners of that case, provided only that this permits higher the political game in order to guarantee their taxation than is possible under democracy at any loyalty. To put it di¤erently, repressing the op- given level of productivity, the dictator in the position would appear to raise the probability model would presumably repress the rich, lead- of the dictator’s survival in o‰ce, as would ing, again, to more redistribution, in this case the distribution of extra rents to keep her sup- from the rich to the poor and middle-income porters loyal. Again, therefore, more redistribu- members of society. tion (larger taxes on the losers and bigger The third widely used model of income redis- subsidies to the winners) is to be expected. tribution under democratic governments is the A second, widely used model of redistribution probabilistic voting model. In simplified form is that developed by Meltzer and Richard (1981). (Mueller, 1989), there are two candidates, each In that model, the decisive voter in a democracy of which maximizes expected votes. Let P1i equal is the median voter, and so long as her income is the probability that voter i will vote for Party 1, less than the mean income, there is redistribution and consider a pure redistribution problem in from the (more productive) rich to the (less pro- which the government is faced simply with the Chapter 8 432

problem of distributing $X among the n voters. is, they will realize that loyalty does not pay and Each party’s ‘‘platform’’ is then simply a pro- will refuse to extend it. So the political strategy posed allocation of the $X among the n voters. unravels. . . . So each party maximizes Coughlin et al. (1990) develop a model of in- "#terest group influence on democratic government X X that solves this problem in a di¤erent way. In the P ¼ f (U (x ) U (x )) 1i i i 1i i 2i model each member of an interest group has a i i "# (nonpolicy) bias b .Ifb > 0, this implies a X ij ij positive bias in favor of the government. The bij þ l X x1i (2) i are not known to the government or the opposi- tion, but are represented by a random variable Because Party 2 maximizes its expected vote distributed uniformly over the interval (li; ri) total as well, the two parties propose a common with density ai. Candidates are assumed to know platform, the equilibrium condition for which is the distribution of bias terms, but not their indi- vidual values. So although they cannot know f 0U 0 ¼ f 0U 0 ð3Þ i i j j with certainty how a given individual will vote, so in democratic equilibrium, each party max- they can predict that they will pick up a greater imizes a weighted sum of voters’ utilities, where fraction of an interest group’s vote, the greater a voter’s ‘‘weight’’ (and therefore the sum al- the di¤erence in the utility their platform prom- located to that voter) is proportional to her ises the representative interest group member ‘‘responsiveness’’ ( fi ) to an increase in U1i U2i. over that of their opponent. In our terms, this In a sense, then, the more ‘‘disloyal’’ the voter to gives candidates an incentive to distribute rents 0 either party, the more that voter will receive as to interest groups. Now fi can be interpreted as the result of democratic political competition. the probability of winning the vote of a member This conclusion makes sense if voters are sen- of interest group i. The greater the density of the 0 sitive or responsive to changes in the utilities distribution ai the larger fi is and the more that promised by the parties for nonpolicy reasons, interest group will receive from both the govern- that is, if a voter is a Democrat because his ment and opposition in equilibrium. parents were Democrats, and he doesn’t care Consequently, interest group influence is neg- about the policies of the Democratic party but atively related to the dispersion of the bias terms, cares about pleasing his parents. Voters like that that is, to the degree of uncertainty on the part of can be ‘‘exploited’’ by politicians by actually politicians about the preferences of the members giving them less than they would get if they were of the interest group. In equilibrium, democratic less loyal to the Democratic party. However, if politicians act as if they maximized a weighted the reason a Democratic voter will not easily sum of voters’ utilities, where the weights are switch to the Republican side is because the positively related to interest group influence, that voter is relying on the reputation of the Demo- is, negatively related to the dispersion of the bias cratic party to take care of him and others like terms. him by giving him a disproportionate share of Now suppose that a dictator takes over this the spoils, then the party that attempts this democratic polity, as before. The dictator can be strategy of exploitation will lose its reputation. presumed to face some opposition and to be able Indeed, voters who would be tempted to be loyal to win support from interest groups to the extent to a particular party will anticipate that the par- that he can ‘‘credibly’’ promise more than the ties will take advantage of them in this way, that opposition. Assume that the distribution of the bias terms is unchanged, as before. The dictator Democracy’s E¤ects 433

is unlike a democratic politician in two main those groups with low f 0 and positive bias will respects: (1) He has the power to repress opposi- not be repressed (they support him, on the aver- tion to his policies; and (2) he does not and is not age) but need not be showered with gifts, because driven by competition to maximize expected a low f 0 implies that the expected increase in ‘‘votes’’ (support). Is there a way that the dicta- loyalty from so doing is not large. tor can improve on the democratic equilibrium; Of course, other factors besides those consid- that is, is there a way that funds can be reallo- ered in this simple model might be relevant in cated among the citizens in such a way as to in- determining the dictator’s optimal choices, such crease the dictator’s power? It seems clear that he as the nature of the regime’s ideology or the de- can, although a precise description of the opti- gree of ideological ‘‘connectedness’’ among dif- mal strategy is di‰cult. From his point of view, ferent groups.7 If we ignore these and assume there are two dimensions along which the voters only two groups, the ‘‘winners’’ (high f 0) and can be ordered: in terms of the size of their f 0, ‘‘losers’’ (low f 0 and negative bias) in the analy- and in terms of the size of their bij. Thus imagine sis above, then it is clear that the benefits and that the dictator is sitting at a table, and in front burdens of the public sector will be distributed of him he has a list of the interest groups under more unequally among these groups under dic- his control, to each of which is attached esti- tatorship than democracy. Thus, letting ai rep- 0 mates of that group’s fi and bij (prepared by a resent the weights on the utilities of di¤erent consulting firm). The dictator wants to order groups in the dictator’s social welfare function, these groups for the purpose of deciding whom or in the social welfare function implicitly maxi- to repress, and to whom to distribute rents so as mized in the probabilistic voting model of de- to buy their loyalty. The problem he faces is that mocracy, and specifying group 1 (high f 0) as the the ordering produced by the f 0 is not the same taxed group, the analysis implies as the ordering produced by the bij. For example, az ay some of those groups with low f 0 support the 1 < 1 ð4Þ dictator (high, positive bij) whereas others favor and if group 2 is the favored group (low f 0 and the opposition (negative bij). negative bias), However, some decisions are easy to make. 0 z y Those who rank low on the f scale and who are a2 > a2 ð5Þ opposed to his policies (negative bias) are obvi- Proposition (1) above—that dictatorships tend ous candidates for repression. They oppose him, to redistribute more than democracies—follows and they cannot easily be turned around with the directly. kind of rents he is prepared to distribute (low f 0). So long as repression is not too expensive, the dictator can gain power by silencing these 3 Redistribution in Capitalist Authoritarian people. This also makes it easy to subject them States to taxation and regulation. These funds can then be redistributed in the form of rents to those So far in this paper I have argued that one pop- whose loyalty can be purchased more easily or ular explanation for the success of many devel- assuredly, namely, those with high f 0. They can be bought, and it is better to make sure they re- 7. Axelrod (1984, ch. 4) finds ‘‘minimum connected main so by giving them more than they received winning coalition’’ to be superior to the minimum under democracy. Through these gifts, the dic- winning coalition concept in explaining coalition for- tator again accumulates more power. Finally, mation in democratic politics. Chapter 8 434

oping countries with authoritarian political sys- capital investment, the marginal product of labor tems such as South Korea or Singapore— is raised, possibly bringing long-run increases in namely, that the authoritarian governments real wages as well [though as of 1990, real wages there redistribute less or are less subject to in Chile, for example, were not much above their ine‰ciencies caused by rent-seeking than de- 1970 levels (Bresser-Pereira, et al. 1993)]. This mocracies—is misguided. I have tried to show, is not a complete explanation of the economic on the contrary, that all dictators can be ex- success of these countries, because many other pected to redistribute more than democracies elements (especially their export orientation) do. As far as the facts are concerned, I know of obviously enter the picture as well. But, insofar no systematic evidence on this question, but it is as the rent-seeking and redistributive elements of well known that there is massive redistribution in policy are concerned, this explanation strikes me totalitarian dictatorships and that most left-wing as superior to the idea that their success is due to dictatorships tend to be redistributive in nature. an absence of redistribution. It might appear more controversial to contend that the analysis applies also to ‘‘capitalist authoritarian’’ dictatorships, but I have no hesi- References tation in suggesting that it applies to these coun- tries as well. The point has been missed, in my Becker, G. 1983. A theory of competition among pres- view, because of the ‘‘fallacy of the free market,’’ sure groups for political influence, Quarterly Journal of that is, the common assumption in this literature Economics, 98, 371–400. that markets operate costlessly, so that to have Bresser Pereira, L. C., J. M. Maravall, and A. Prze- free markets, it is only necessary for the govern- worski. 1993. Economic Reform in New Democracies: A Social Democratic Approach, Cambridge University ment to get out of the way. Once the central Press, Cambridge. point of the e‰ciency wage literature is grasped, Coughlin, P. 1986. Elections and income redistribu- that power relationships are central to competi- tion, Public Choice, 50, 27–99. tive market behavior, then it is clear that how Coughlin, P., D. Mueller, and P. Murrell. 1990. Elec- markets work depends on how property rights toral politics, interest groups and the size of govern- are specified and enforced. . . . ment, Economic Inquiry, 28, 682–705. Although I do not have the space here to pro- Haggard, S. 1990. Pathways from the Periphery: The vide proper details, perhaps enough has been Politics of Growth in the Newly Industrializing Coun- said to suggest that the economic success of tries, Cornell University Press, Ithaca, N.Y. ‘‘capitalist authoritarian’’ governments is not Krueger, A. O. 1974. The political economy of the di‰cult to explain. It is not because they do not rent-seeking society, American Economic Review, 64, redistribute income, but because they do redis- 291–303. tribute income—in particular, by adopting mea- Meltzer, A. H., and S. F. Richard. 1981. A rational sures that transfer rights over the control of theory of the size of government, Journal of Political labor from labor to capital. Dictators whose Economy, 89, 914–927. support is based on capital (either domestic or Mueller, D. 1989. Public Choice II, Cambridge Uni- international) have an obvious reason to be fu- versity Press, New York. ture oriented, because the future returns to capi- Olson, M. 1982. The Rise and Decline of Nations, Yale tal are capitalized into its price, and an increased University Press, New Haven, Conn. prospect of economic growth that raises those ———. 1993. Dictatorship, democracy and develop- returns increases the wealth of capital owners in ment, American Political Science Review, 87, 567–575. the present. Moreover, to the extent that these Posner, R. A. 1975. The social costs of monopoly and regimes successfully discipline labor, and attract regulation, Journal of Political Economy, 83, 807–827. Democracy’s E¤ects 435

Przeworski, A. 1991. Democracy and the Market: Po- litical and Economic Reforms in Eastern Europe and Latin America, Cambridge University Press, New York. Stigler, G. 1970. Director’s law of public income re- distribution, Journal of Law and Economics, 13, 1–10. Tullock, G. 1967. The welfare cost of tari¤s, monopo- lies, and theft, Western Economic Journal, 5, 224–232. Dictatorship, Democracy, and Development

Mancur Olson

In my student days, in reading Edward Ban- from providing domestic tranquility and other field’s (1958) account of the beliefs of the people basic public goods. These gains can be shared in a poor village in Southern Italy, I came upon in ways that leave everyone in a society better a remarkable statement by a village monarchist. o¤. . . . He said, ‘‘Monarchy is the best kind of govern- ment because the King is then owner of the country. Like the owner of a house, when the The First Blessing of the Invisible Hand wiring is wrong, he fixes it’’ (p. 26). The vil- lager’s argument jarred against my democratic Why, then, have most populous societies convictions. I could not deny that the owner of a throughout history normally avoided anarchy? country would have an incentive to make his An answer came to me by chance when reading property productive. Could the germ of truth in about a Chinese warlord (see Sheridan 1966). In the monarchist’s argument be reconciled with the the 1920s, China was in large part under the case for democracy? control of various warlords. They were men who It is only in recent years that I have arrived at led some armed band with which they conquered an answer to this question. It turns out that for a some territory and who then appointed them- satisfactory answer one needs a new theory of selves lords of that territory. They taxed the dictatorship and democracy and of how each of population heavily and pocketed much of the these types of government a¤ects economic de- proceeds. The warlord Feng Yu-hsiang was velopment. Once this new theory is understood, noted for the exceptional extent to which he used one can begin to see how autocracies and de- his army for suppressing bandits and for his de- mocracies first emerge. I shall set out this con- feat of the relatively substantial army of the rov- ception in a brief and informal way and use it to ing bandit, White Wolf. Apparently most people explain some of the most conspicuous features of in Feng’s domain found him much preferable to historical experience. the roving bandits. The starting point for the theory is that no At first, this seems puzzling: Why should war- society can work satisfactorily if it does not have lords, who were stationary bandits continuously a peaceful order and usually other public goods stealing from a given group of victims, be pre- as well. Obviously, anarchic violence cannot be ferred, by those victims, to roving bandits who rational for a society: the victims of violence soon departed? The warlords had no claim to and theft lose not only what is taken from legitimacy and their thefts were distinguished them but also the incentive to produce any goods from those of roving bandits only because they that would be taken by others. There is accord- took the form of continuing taxation rather than ingly little or no production in the absence of a occasional plunder. peaceful order. Thus there are colossal gains In fact, if a roving bandit rationally settles down and takes his theft in the form of regular Excerpted from: Mancur Olson, ‘‘Dictatorship, De- taxation and at the same time maintains a mo- mocracy, and Development.’’ American Political Sci- nopoly on theft in his domain, then those from ence Review 87(3) (Sep. 1993): 567–576. 6 1993 whom he exacts taxes will have an incentive to American Political Science Association. Reprinted with produce. The rational stationary bandit will take the permission of the American Political Science Asso- only a part of income in taxes, because he will be ciation and Cambridge University Press. able to exact a larger total amount of income Democracy’s E¤ects 437

from his subjects if he leaves them with an in- Thus government for groups larger than tribes centive to generate income that he can tax. normally arises, not because of social contracts If the stationary bandit successfully monopo- or voluntary transactions of any kind, but rather lizes the theft in his domain, then his victims do because of rational self-interest among those not need to worry about theft by others. If he who can organize the greatest capacity for vio- steals only through regular taxation, then his lence. These violent entrepreneurs naturally do subjects know that they can keep whatever pro- not call themselves bandits but, on the contrary, portion of their output is left after they have paid give themselves and their descendants exalted their taxes. Since all of the settled bandit’s vic- titles. They sometimes even claim to rule by tims are for him a source of tax payments, he divine right. Since history is written by the also has an incentive to prohibit the murder or winners, the origins of ruling dynasties are, of maiming of his subjects. With the rational mo- course, conventionally explained in terms of nopolization of theft—in contrast to uncoordi- lofty motives rather than by self-interest. Auto- nated competitive theft—the victims of the theft crats of all kinds usually claim that their subjects can expect to retain whatever capital they accu- want them to rule and thereby nourish the un- mulate out of after-tax income and therefore also historical assumption that government arose out have an incentive to save and to invest, thereby of some kind of voluntary choice. . . . increasing future income and tax receipts. The Any individual who has autocratic control monopolization of theft and the protection of the over a country will provide public goods to that tax-generating subjects thereby eliminates anar- country because he has an ‘‘encompassing inter- chy. Since the warlord takes a part of total pro- est’’ in it.5 The extent of the encompassing in- duction in the form of tax theft, it will also pay terest of an o‰ce-holder, political party, interest him to provide other public goods whenever the group, monarch, or any other partial or total provision of these goods increases taxable in- ‘‘owner’’ of a society varies with the size of the come su‰ciently. stake in the society. The larger or more encom- In a world of roving banditry there is little or passing the stake an organization or individual no incentive for anyone to produce or accumu- has in a society, the greater the incentive the or- late anything that may be stolen and, thus, little ganization or individual has to take action to for bandits to steal. Bandit rationality, accord- provide public goods for the society. If an auto- ingly, induces the bandit leader to seize a given crat received one-third of any increase in the in- domain, to make himself the ruler of that do- come of his domain in increased tax collections, main, and to provide a peaceful order and other he would then get one-third of the benefits of the public goods for its inhabitants, thereby ob- public goods he provided. He would then have taining more in tax theft than he could have an incentive to provide public goods up to the obtained from migratory plunder. Thus we have point where the national income rose by the re- ‘‘the first blessing of the invisible hand’’: the ra- ciprocal of one-third, or three, from his last unit tional, self-interested leader of a band of roving of public good expenditure. Though the society’s bandits is led, as though by an invisible hand, to settle down, wear a crown, and replace anarchy 5. For the definition of an encompassing interest and with government. The gigantic increase in out- evidence of its importance, see Olson 1982. The logical put that normally arises from the provision of a structure of the theory that encompassing interests will peaceful order and other public goods gives the be concerned with the outcome for society whereas stationary bandit a far larger take than he could narrow groups will not is identical with the logic that obtain without providing government. shows that small groups can engage in voluntary col- lective action when large groups cannot. Chapter 8 438

income and welfare would obviously be greater but rather to the owner of all wealth, both tan- from a larger expenditure on public goods, the gible and human, in a country. The autocrat gain to society from the public goods that a ra- does indeed have an incentive to maintain and tional self-interested autocrat provides are none- increase the productivity of everything and ev- theless often colossal. Consider, for example, the eryone in his domain, and his subjects will gain gains from replacing a violent anarchy with a from this. But he also has an incentive to charge minimal degree of public order. a monopoly rent and to levy this monopoly From history, we know that the encompassing charge on everything, including human labor. interest of the tax-collecting autocrat permits a In other words, the autocratic ruler has an in- considerable development of civilization. From centive to extract the maximum possible surplus not long after the first development of settled from the whole society and to use it for his own agriculture until, say, about the time of the purposes. Exactly the same rational self-interest French Revolution, the overwhelming majority that makes a roving bandit settle down and pro- of mankind was subject to autocracy and tax vide government for his subjects also makes him theft. History until relatively recent times has extract the maximum possible amount from the been mostly a story of the gradual progress of society for himself. He will use his monopoly of civilization under stationary bandits interrupted coercive power to obtain the maximum take in by occasional episodes of roving banditry. From taxes and other exactions. . . . about the time that Sargon’s conquests created Although the forms that stationary banditry the empire of Akkad until, say, the time of Louis has taken over the course of history are diverse, XVI and Voltaire, there was an impressive de- the essence of the matter can be seen by assum- velopment of civilization that occurred in large ing that the autocrat gets all of his receipts in the part under stationary banditry.6 form of explicit taxation. The rational autocrat will devote some of the resources he obtains through taxation to public goods but will impose The Grasping Hand far higher tax rates than are needed to pay for the public goods since he also uses tax collections We can now begin to reconcile the village mon- to maximize his net surplus. The higher the level archist’s insight and the foregoing argument of provision of public goods, given the tax rate, with the case for democracy. Though the village the higher the society’s income and the yield monarchist was right in saying that the absolute from this tax rate. At the same time, the higher ruler has as much incentive to fix what needs the tax rate, given the level of public-good pro- repair as the owner of a house, his analogy is vision, the lower the income of society, since nonetheless profoundly misleading. The autocrat taxes distort incentives. . . . is not in a position analogous to the owner of a Though the subjects of the autocrat are better single house or even to the owner of all housing, o¤ than they would be under anarchy, they must endure taxes or other impositions so high that, if 6. Many of the more remarkable advances in civiliza- they were increased further, income would fall tion even in historic times took place in somewhat by so much that even the autocrat, who absorbs democratic or nondictatorial societies such as ancient only a portion of the fall in income in the form Athens, the Roman Republic, the North Italian city– of lower tax collections, would be worse o¤. states, the Netherlands in the seventeenth century, and There is no lack of historical examples in (at least after 1689) Great Britain. The explanation for which autocrats for their own political and mili- the disproportionate representation of nonautocratic jurisdictions in human progress is presented later in the tary purposes collected as much revenue as they article. possibly could. . . . Democracy’s E¤ects 439

does? That is, would a vote-buying democratic The Reach of Dictatorships and Democracies leader, like the rational autocrat, have an incen- Compared tive to push tax rates to the revenue-maximizing level? How would government by a rational self- No. Though both the majority and the auto- interested autocrat compare with a democracy? crat have an encompassing interest in the society Democracies vary so much that no one conclu- because they control tax collections, the majority sion can cover all cases. Nonetheless, many in addition earns a significant share of the mar- practical insights can be obtained by thinking ket income of the society, and this gives it a more first about one of the simplest democratic sit- encompassing interest in the productivity of the uations. This is a situation in which there are society. The majority’s interest in its market two candidates for a presidency or two well- earnings induces it to redistribute less to itself disciplined parties seeking to form the gov- than an autocrat redistributes to himself. This is ernment. This simplifying assumption will be evident from considering an option that a dem- favorable to democratic performance, for it ocratic majority would have if it were at the gives the democracy an ‘‘encompassing’’ interest revenue-maximizing tax rate. At the revenue- rather like the one that motivates the station- maximizing tax rate, a minuscule change in the ary bandit to provide some public goods. I tax rates will not alter tax collections. A minus- shall make the opposite assumption later. But cule increase in the tax rate will reduce the na- throughout, I shall avoid giving democracy an tional income by enough so that even though a unfair advantage by assuming better motivation. larger percentage of income is taken in taxes, the I shall impartially assume that the democratic amount collected remains unchanged, and a tiny political leaders are just as self-interested as the reduction in the tax rate will increase the national stationary bandit and will use any expedient to income so much that even though a smaller per- obtain majority support. centage is taken in taxes, receipts are unchanged. Observation of two-party democracies tells us This is the optimal tax rate for the autocrat be- that incumbents like to run on a ‘‘you-never-had- cause changes in the national income a¤ect his it-so-good’’ record. An incumbent obviously income only by changing tax collections. would not leave himself with such a record if, But a majority at the revenue-maximizing like the self-interested autocrat, he took for him- tax rate is bound to increase its income from a self the largest possible net surplus from the so- reduction in tax rates: when the national in- ciety. But we are too favorable to democracy if come goes up, it not only, like the autocrat, col- we assume that the incumbent party or president lects taxes on a larger national income but also will maximize his chances of reelection simply by earns more income in the market. So the optimal making the electorate as a whole as well-o¤ as tax rate for it is bound to be lower than the possible. autocrat’s. . . . A candidate needs only a majority to win, and More generally, it pays a ruling interest he might be able to ‘‘buy’’ a majority by trans- (whether an autocrat, a majority, or any other) ferring income from the population at large to a to stop redistributing income to itself when prospective majority. The taxes needed for this the national income falls by the reciprocal of the transfer would impair incentives and reduce share of the national income it receives. If the society’s output just as an autocrat’s redistribu- revenue-maximizing tax rate were one-half, an tion to himself does. Would this competition to autocrat would stop increasing taxes when the buy votes generate as much distortion of incen- national income fell by two dollars from his last tives through taxation as a rational autocracy dollar of tax collection. A majority that, say, Chapter 8 440

earned three-fifths of the national income in the who is taking a long view will try to convince his market and found it optimal to take one-fifth of subjects that their assets will be permanently the national income to transfer to itself would protected not only from theft by others but also necessarily be reducing the national income by from expropriation by the autocrat himself. If his five-fourths, or $1.25, from the last dollar that it subjects fear expropriation, they will invest less, redistributed to itself. Thus the more encom- and in the long run his tax collections will be passing an interest—the larger the share of the reduced. To reach the maximum income attain- national income it receives taking all sources able at a given tax rate, a society will also need together—the less the social losses from its to enforce contracts, such as contracts for long- redistributions to itself. Conversely, the narrower term loans, impartially; but the full gains are the interest, the less it will take account of the again reaped only in the long run. To obtain the social costs of redistributions to itself. full advantage from long-run contracts a country This last consideration makes it clear why the also needs a stable currency. A stationary bandit assumption that the democracy is governed by will therefore reap the maximum harvest in an encompassing interest can lead to much-too- taxes—and his subjects will get the largest gain optimistic predictions about many real-world from his encompassing interest in the productiv- democracies. The small parties that often emerge ity of his domain—only if he is taking an indef- under proportional representation, for example, initely long view and only if his subjects have may encompass only a tiny percentage of a soci- total confidence that their ‘‘rights’’ to private ety and therefore may have little or no incentive property and to impartial contract enforcement to consider the social cost of the steps they take will be permanently respected and that the coin on behalf of their narrow constituencies. The or currency will retain its full value. special interest groups that are the main deter- Now suppose that an autocrat is only con- minant of what government policies prevail in cerned about getting through the next year. He the particular areas of interest to those interest will then gain by expropriating any convenient groups have almost no incentive to consider the capital asset whose tax yield over the year is less social costs of the redistributions they obtain. . . . than its total value. He will also gain from for- It would therefore be wrong to conclude that getting about the enforcement of long-term con- democracies will necessarily redistribute less than tracts, from repudiating his debts, and from dictatorships. Their redistributions will, how- coining or printing new money that he can spend ever, be shared, often quite unequally, by the even though this ultimately brings inflation. At citizenry. Democratic political competition, even the limit, when an autocrat has no reason to when it works very badly, does not give the consider the future output of the society at all, leader of the government the incentive that an his incentives are those of a roving bandit and autocrat has to extract the maximum attainable that is what he becomes.10 social surplus from the society to achieve his personal objectives. 10. When war erodes confidence about what the boundaries of an autocrat’s domain will be, an auto- crat’s time horizon with respect to his possession of any Long Live the King given territory shortens—even if he believes that he will remain in control of some territory somewhere. In We know that an economy will generate its the limit, complete uncertainty about what territory maximum income only if there is a high rate of an autocrat will control implies roving banditry. The investment and that much of the return on long- advantages of stationary banditry over roving banditry term investments is received long after the in- are obviously greatest when there are natural and mil- itarily defensible frontiers. Interestingly, the earliest vestment is made. This means that an autocrat Democracy’s E¤ects 441

To be sure, the rational autocrat will have an to confiscate the property of his subjects, to ab- incentive, because of his interest in increasing the rogate any contracts he has signed in borrowing investment and trade of his subjects, to promise money from them, and generally to ignore the that he will never confiscate wealth or repudiate long-run economic consequences of his choices. assets. But the promise of an autocrat is not Even the ever-present possibility that an autoc- enforceable by an independent judiciary or any racy will come to be led by someone with a short other independent source of power, because au- time horizon always reduces confidence in in- tocratic power by definition implies that there vestments and in the enforcement of long-run cannot be any judges or other sources of power contracts. What do the individuals in an econ- in the society that the autocrat cannot overrule. omy need if they are to have the maximum con- Because of this and the obvious possibility that fidence that any property they accumulate will any dictator could, because of an insecure hold be respected and that any contracts they sign will on power or the absence of an heir, take a short- be impartially enforced? term view, the promises of an autocrat are never They need a secure government that respects completely credible. Thus the model of the ra- individual rights. But individual rights are nor- tional self-interested autocrat I have o¤ered is, in mally an artifact of a special set of governmental fact, somewhat too sanguine about economic institutions. There is no private property without performance under such autocrats because it government! In a world of roving bandits some implicitly assumed that they have (and that their individuals may have possessions, but no one has subjects believe that they have) an indefinitely a claim to private property that is enforced by long planning horizon. the society. There is typically no reliable contract Many autocrats, at least at times, have had enforcement unless there is an impartial court short time horizons: the examples of confisca- system that can call upon the coercive power of tions, repudiated loans, debased coinages, and the state to require individuals to honor the inflated currencies perpetrated by monarchs and contracts they have made. dictators over the course of history are almost But individuals need their property and their beyond counting. . . . contract rights protected from violation not only by other individuals in the private sector but also by the entity that has the greatest power in the Democracy, Individual Rights, and Economic society, namely, the government itself. An econ- Development omy will be able to reap all potential gains from investment and from long-term transactions only We have seen that whenever a dictator has a if it has a government that is believed to be both su‰ciently short time horizon, it is in his interest strong enough to last and inhibited from violat- ing individual rights to property and rights to states in history emerged mainly in what one anthro- contract enforcement. What does a society need pologist calls ‘‘environmentally circumscribed’’ areas, in order to have a government that satisfies both that is, areas of arable land surrounded by deserts, of these conditions? mountains, or coasts (see Carneiro 1970). The envi- Interestingly, the conditions that are needed to ronmental circumscription not only provides militarily have the individual rights needed for maximum viable frontiers but also limits the opportunity for economic development are exactly the same defeated tribes to flee to other areas in which they could support themselves (as Carneiro points out). This conditions that are needed to have a lasting de- in turn means that the consensual democracy charac- mocracy. Obviously, a democracy is not viable if teristic of the earliest stages of social evolution is, in individuals, including the leading rivals of the these geographical conditions, replaced by autocratic administration in power, lack the rights to free states earlier than in other conditions. speech and to security for their property and Chapter 8 442

contracts or if the rule of law is not followed twice as likely to win wars as have dictatorships even when it calls for the current administration (Lake 1992). . . . to leave o‰ce. Thus the same court system, in- dependent judiciary, and respect for law and individual rights that are needed for a lasting The Di¤erent Sources of Progress in Autocracies democracy are also required for security of and Democracies property and contract rights. As the foregoing reasoning suggests, the only ... societies where individual rights to property and The use of the same motivational assumption contract are confidently expected to last across and the same theory to treat both autocracy and generations are the securely democratic soci- democracy . . . illuminates the main di¤erence in eties. In an autocracy, the autocrat will often the sources of economic growth and the obsta- have a short time horizon, and the absence of cles to progress under autocracy and under de- any independent power to assure an orderly mocracy. In an autocracy, the source of order legal succession means that there is always sub- and other public goods and likewise the source stantial uncertainty about what will happen of the social progress that these public goods when the current autocrat is gone. History pro- make possible is the encompassing interest of the vides not even a single example of a long autocrat. The main obstacle to long-run progress and uninterrupted sequence of absolute rulers in autocracies is that individual rights even to who continuously respected the property and such relatively unpolitical or economic matters contract-enforcement rights of their subjects. as property and contracts can never be secure, at Admittedly, the terms, tenures, and time hori- least over the long run. zons of democratic political leaders are perhaps Although democracies can also obtain great even shorter than those of the typical autocrat, advantages from encompassing o‰ces and polit- and democracies lose a good deal of e‰ciency ical parties, this is by no means always under- because of this. But in the secure democracy with stood (Olson 1982, 1986); nor are the awesome predictable succession of power under the rule of di‰culties in keeping narrow special interests law, the adjudication and enforcement of indi- from dominating economic policymaking in the vidual rights is not similarly short-sighted. Many long-stable democracy. On the other hand, individuals in the secure democracies confidently democracies have the great advantage of pre- make even very-long-term contracts, establish venting significant extraction of social surplus by trusts for great-grandchildren, and create foun- their leaders. They also have the extraordinary dations that they expect will last indefinitely and virtue that the same emphasis on individual thereby reveal that they expect their legal rights rights that is necessary to lasting democracy is to be secure for the indefinite future. also necessary for secure rights to both property . . . Though experience shows that relatively and the enforcement of contracts. The moral poor countries can grow extraordinarily rapidly appeal of democracy is now almost universally when they have a strong dictator who happens appreciated, but its economic advantages are to have unusually good economic policies, such scarcely understood. growth lasts only for the ruling span of one or two dictators. It is no accident that the countries that have reached the highest level of economic References development and have enjoyed good economic performance across generations are all stable Banfield, Edward. 1958. The Moral Basis of a Back- ward Society. Glencoe, IL: Free Press. democracies. Democracies have also been about Democracy’s E¤ects 443

Lake, David A. 1992. ‘‘Powerful Pacifists: Democratic States and War.’’ American Political Science Review 86: 24–37. Olson, Mancur. 1982. The Rise and Decline of Nations. New Haven: Yale University Press. Olson, Mancur. 1986. ‘‘A Theory of the Incentives Facing Political Organizations: Neo-corporatism and the Hegemonic State.’’ International Political Science Review 7: 165–89. Sheridan, James E. 1966. Chinese Warlord: The Career of Feng Yu-hsiang. Stanford: Stanford University Press. Freedom Favors Development

Amartya Sen

. . . It is true that some relatively authoritarian The fundamental importance of political states (such as Lee’s Singapore, South Korea rights is not refuted by some allegedly negative under military rule and, more recently, China) e¤ect of these rights on economic performance. have had faster rates of economic growth than In fact, the instrumental connections may even some less authoritarian states (such as India, give a very positive role to political rights in Costa Rica and Jamaica). But the overall picture the context of deprivations of a drastic and ele- is much more complex that such isolated obser- mentary kind: whether, and how, a government vations might suggest. responds to intense needs and su¤erings may Systematic statistical studies give little support well depend on how much pressure is put on it, to the view of a general conflict between civil and whether or not pressure is put on it will de- rights and economic performance. . . . The gen- pend on the exercise of political rights such as eral thesis in praise of the tough state su¤ers not voting, criticizing and protesting. only from casual empiricism based on a few Consider the matter of famine. I have tried to selected examples, but also from a lack of con- argue elsewhere that the avoidance of such eco- ceptual discrimination. Political and civil rights nomic disasters as famines is made much easier come in various types, and authoritarian intru- by the existence, and the exercise, of various lib- sions take many forms. It would be a mistake, erties and political rights, including the liberty of for example, to equate North Korea with South free expression. Indeed, one of the remarkable Korea in the infringement of political rights, facts in the terrible history of famine is that no even though both have violated many such substantial famine has ever occurred in a country rights. . . . with a democratic form of government and a It is also necessary to examine more rigor- relatively free press. . . . ously the causal process that is supposed to un- Is this historical association between the ab- derlie these generalizations about the impact of sence of famine and the presence of political authoritarianism on prosperity. The processes freedom a causal one, or is it simply an acciden- that led to the economic success of, say, South tal connection? The possibility that the connec- Korea are now reasonably well understood. A tion between democratic political rights and the variety of factors played a part, including the use absence of famine is a ‘‘bogus correlation’’ may of international markets, an openness to compe- seem plausible when one considers the fact that tition, a high level of literacy, successful land democratic countries are typically rather rich, reforms and the provision of selective incentives and thus immune to famine for other reasons. to encourage growth and exports. There is noth- But the absence of famine holds even for those ing to indicate that these economic and social democratic countries that happen to be poor, policies were inconsistent with greater democ- such as India, Botswana and Zimbabwe. racy, that they had to be sustained by the ele- There is also what we might call ‘‘inter- ments of authoritarianism actually present in temporal evidence,’’ which we observe when a South Korea. country undergoes a transition to democracy. Thus India continued to have famines right up to Excerpted from: Amartya Sen, ‘‘Freedom Favors De- the time of independence in 1947. . . . Since in- velopment.’’ New Perspectives Quarterly 13, no. 4 dependence, however, and the installation of a (1996). 6 Center for the Study of Democratic Institu- multiparty democratic system, there has been no tions. Reprinted by permission. substantial famine, even though severe crop fail- Democracy’s E¤ects 445

ures and food scarcities have occurred often terrible calamity, the government faced no pres- enough (in 1968, 1973, 1979 and 1987). sure from newspapers, which were controlled, or Why might we expect a general connection from opposition parties, which were not allowed between democracy and the nonoccurrence of to exist. . . . famines? The answer is not hard to find. Famines These issues remain relevant in China today. kill millions of people in di¤erent countries in Since the economic reforms of 1979, o‰cial the world, but they do not kill the rulers. The Chinese policies have been based on the ac- kings and the presidents, the bureaucrats and the knowledgment of the importance of economic bosses, the military leaders and the commanders incentives without a similar acknowledgment of never starve. And if there are no elections, no the importance of political incentives. When opposition parties, no forums for uncensored things go reasonably well, the disciplinary role of public criticism, then those in authority do not democracy might not be greatly missed; but have to su¤er the political consequences of their when big policy mistakes are made, this lacuna failure to prevent famine. Democracy, by con- can be quite disastrous. The significance of the trast, would spread the penalty of famine to the democracy movements in contemporary China ruling groups and the political leadership. has to be judged in this light. . . . There is, moreover, the issue of information. Another set of examples comes from sub- A free press, and more generally the practice of Saharan Africa, which has been plagued by democracy, contributes greatly to bringing out persistent famine since the early 1970s. There the information that can have an enormous are many factors underlying the susceptibility of impact on policies for famine prevention, such this region to famine, from the ecological impact as facts about the early e¤ects of droughts and of climatic deterioration—making crops more floods, and about the nature and the results of uncertain—to the negative e¤ects of persistent unemployment. The most elementary source of wars and skirmishes. But the typically authori- basic information about a threatening famine is tarian nature of many of the sub-Saharan Afri- the news media, especially when there are incen- can polities also has something to do with the tives, which a democratic system provides, for frequency of famine. revealing facts that may be embarrassing to the One must not deny that there were African government, facts that an undemocratic regime governments, even in one-party states, that were would tend to censor. Indeed, I would argue that deeply concerned about averting disasters and a free press and an active political opposition famine. Examples of this range from the tiny constitute the best ‘‘early warning system’’ that a country of Cape Verde to the politically experi- country threatened by famine can possess. . . . mental nation of Tanzania. But quite often the The connection between political rights and absence of opposition and the suppression of economic needs can be illustrated in the specific free newspapers gave the respective governments context of famine prevention by considering the an immunity from social criticism and political massive Chinese famines of 1958–61. . . . pressure that translated into thoroughly insensi- The so-called ‘‘Great Leap Forward,’’ ini- tive and callous policies. . . . tiated in the late 1950s, was a massive failure, In making such arguments, of course, there is but the Chinese government refused to admit the danger of exaggerating the e¤ectiveness of it and continued dogmatically to pursue much democracy. Political rights and liberties are per- the same disastrous policies for three more years. missive advantages, and their e¤ectiveness de- It is hard to imagine that this could have hap- pends on how they are exercised. Democracies pened in a country that goes to the polls regu- have been particularly successful in preventing larly and has an independent press. During that disasters that are easy to understand, in which Chapter 8 446

sympathy can take an especially immediate form. Many other problems are not quite so ac- cessible. Thus India’s success in eradicating famine is not matched by a similar success in eliminating non-extreme hunger, or in curing persistent illiteracy, or in relieving inequalities in gender relations. While the plight of famine vic- tims is easy to politicize, these other deprivations call for deeper analysis, and for greater and more e¤ective use of mass communication and politi- cal participation—in sum, for a further practice of democracy. A similar observation may be made about various failings in more mature democracies as well. For example, the extraordinary depriva- tions in health care, education and social envi- ronment of African Americans in the US make their mortality rates exceptionally high. . . . But, again, the remedy of these failures in the practice of democracy turns, to a great extent, on the fuller use of political and civil rights, includ- ing more public discussion, more accessible in- formation and more concrete proposals. . . . Political rights are important not only for the fulfillment of needs, they are crucial also for the formulation of needs. And this idea relates, in the end, to the respect that we owe each other as fellow human beings...... The importance of political rights for the understanding of economic needs turns ulti- mately on seeing human beings as people with rights to exercise, not as parts of a ‘‘stock’’ or a ‘‘population’’ that passively exists and must be looked after. What matters, finally, is how we see each other. Political Regimes and Economic Growth

Adam Przeworski, Michael E. Alvarez, Jose´ Antonio Cheibub, and Fernando Limongi

ceive in a non-democratic system’’ (Huntington Introduction and Domiguez 1975: 60; Huntington 1968). Democracy was thus seen as inimical to eco- With the birth of new nations in Asia and Africa, nomic development. Moreover, via a rather the fear that democracy would undermine eco- dubious inference, proponents of that view con- nomic growth began to be voiced in the United cluded that dictatorships were therefore better States. The first statements to that e¤ect were able to force savings and launch economic perhaps those by Walter Galenson and by Karl growth. To cite a more recent statement: ‘‘Eco- de Schweinitz, who argued, both in 1959, that in nomic development is a process for which huge poor countries democracy unleashes pressures investments in personnel and material are re- for immediate consumption, which occurs at the quired. Such investment programs imply cuts in cost of investment, hence of growth. Galenson current consumption that would be painful at mentioned both the role of unions and that of the low levels of living that exist in almost all governments. He thought that unions ‘‘must or- developing societies. Governments must resort dinarily appeal to the worker on an all-out con- to strong measures and they enforce them with sumptionist platform. No matter how much an iron hand in order to marshal the surpluses ‘responsibility’ the union leader exhibits in his needed for investment. If such measures were put understanding of the limited consumption possi- to a popular vote, they would surely be defeated. bilities existing at the outset of industrialization, No political party can hope to win a democratic he cannot a¤ord to moderate his demands.’’ As election on a platform of current sacrifices for a for governments, he observed that ‘‘the more bright future’’ (Rao 1984: 75).1 democratic a government is, . . . the greater the The reasoning bears reconstruction. First, that diversion of resources from investment to con- argument assumes that poor people have a sumption.’’ According to de Schweinitz (1959: higher propensity to consume.2 This is why 388), if trade unions and labor parties ‘‘are suc- democracy may be compatible with growth at cessful in securing a larger share of the national high but not at low levels of income. Second, the income and limiting the freedom for action of entrepreneurs, they may have the e¤ect of re- stricting investment surplus so much that the rate 1. At least Huntington and his collaborators wrote of economic growth is inhibited.’’ That argument during a period when many dictatorships, ‘‘authoritar- ian’’ and ‘‘totalitarian,’’ did grow rapidly. But Rao’s enjoyed widespread acceptance under the influ- assertion was made in 1984, after the failure of several ence of Huntington, who claimed that ‘‘the in- Latin American authoritarian regimes and Eastern terest of the voters generally leads parties to give European communist regimes was already apparent. the expansion of personal consumption a higher 2. Pasinetti (1961) claimed that the propensity to con- priority via-a`-vis investment than it would re- sume is higher for workers than for capitalists, and Kaldor (1956) believed that it is higher for wages than Excerpted from: Adam Przeworski, Michael E. for profits, whereas the scholars discussed here seem to Alvarez, Jose´ Antonio Cheibub, and Fernando assume that in general the marginal propensity to con- Limongi, Democracy and Development: Political In- sume declines with income. Barro and Sala-i-Martin stitutions and Well-Being in the World, 1950–1990. (1995: 77–79) show that in the optimal growth model Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2000. 6 the savings rate decreases as a result of the substitution Adam Przeworski, Michael E. Alvarez, Jose´ Antonio e¤ect and increases in income as a consequence of the Cheibub, and Fernando Limongi, 2000. Reprinted income e¤ect, the net e¤ect being ambivalent. with the permission of Cambridge University Press. Chapter 8 448

underlying model of growth attributes it to the growth. Then they all show that, depending on increase in the stock of physical capital. Finally, the details of each model, dictatorships of vari- democracy is always responsive to pressures for ous stripes can be expected to undersupply or immediate consumption. The chain of reasoning oversupply government activities. One interest- is thus the following: (1) Poor people want to ing variant of this approach is by Robinson consume immediately. (2) When workers are (1995), who thinks that dictators are afraid, at able to organize, they drive wages up, reduce least under some conditions, that development profits, and reduce investment (by lowering ei- would give rise to political forces that would ther the rate of return or the volume of profit overturn them, and thus they deliberately abstain or both). (3) When people are allowed to vote, from developmentalist policies. governments tend to distribute income away Perhaps the best-known informational argu- from investment (either they tax and transfer or ment is based on the Dre`ze and Sen (1989) ob- they undertake less public investment). (4) Low- servation that no democracy ever experienced a ering investment slows down growth. Note, as famine, which they attribute to the alarm role of well, that this reasoning implies that the im- the press and the opposition. Thus, Sen (1994a: pact of mean-preserving inequality on growth is 34) observes that ‘‘a free press and an active po- ambivalent: In the Kaldor-Pasinetti models, in- litical opposition constitute the best ‘early warn- equality promotes growth, as it increases the ing system’ that a country threatened by famine incomes of those who save more, but in the can possess.’’ He also cites an unlikely source, median-voter models it slows down growth to Mao, reflecting on the great Chinese famine of the extent to which the political system responds 1962, to the e¤ect that ‘‘without democracy, you to demands for redistribution. have no understanding of what is happening Arguments in favor of democracy are not down below.’’ Yet it is not apparent whether this equally sharp, but they all focus in one form or is an argument strictly about avoiding disasters another on allocative e‰ciency: Democracies or about average performance.3 can better allocate the available resources to This summary makes no pretense to being ex- productive uses. One view is that because au- haustive. All we want to highlight is that the thoritarian rulers are not accountable to elec- arguments in favor of dictatorship and those in torates, they have no incentive to maximize total favor of democracy are not necessarily incom- output, but only their own rents. As a result, patible. The arguments against democracy claim democracies better protect property rights, thus that it hinders growth by reducing investment; allowing a longer-term perspective to investors. the arguments in its favor maintain that it fosters There is also a vague sense that by permitting a growth by promoting allocative e‰ciency. Both free flow of information, democracies somehow may be true: The rate at which productive fac- improve the quality of economic decisions. tors grow may be higher under dictatorship, but According to the first view, the state is always ready to prey on the society (North 1990), and 3. Sah and Stiglitz (1988) compared the quality of the only democratic institutions can constrain it to decisions whether or not to undertake a series of eco- act in a more general interest. Hence, dictator- nomic projects made under di¤erent decision rules. ships, of any stripe, are sources of ine‰ciency. Their conclusions are ambivalent: Although majority Barro (1990), Findlay (1990), Olson (1991), and rule is conducive to good decisions under many con- Przeworski (1990) have constructed models that ditions, decisions by smaller groups are better when the di¤er in detail but generate the same conclusion. costs of information are high, whereas decisions by larger groups are superior when the chances of adopt- These models assume that some level of govern- ing a bad project are high. ment intervention in the economy is optimal for Democracy’s E¤ects 449

the use of resources may be more e‰cient under as for a number of other variables in a selection democracy. And because these mechanisms work model, shows that regimes have no overall e¤ect in opposite directions, the net e¤ect may be that on investment.6 ... there is no di¤erence between the two regimes in . . . [E]ven if pressures for immediate con- the average rates of growth they generate. The sumption are higher in poor countries, democ- patterns of growth may di¤er, but the average racies do not transform them into lower rates of rates of growth may still be the same. investment than do dictatorships. Poor countries Rates of growth may thus di¤er between simply invest little regardless of their regime. . . . regimes either because the productive inputs in- In turn, the rate of growth of the labor crease at di¤erent rates or because they are used force (LFG ¼ LL_ =L) is higher under dictator- with di¤erent e‰ciencies. . . . ships. . . . The observed values are 2.27 percent per annum under dictatorships and 1.61 under democracies. . . . Political Regimes and Economic Growth Because the labor force grows at a slower rate in wealthier countries, one might suspect again The observed rate of growth of total income that this di¤erence is due to the distribution of (YG ¼ YY_ =Y ) is higher under dictatorships, 4.42, regimes by income. Some of it is, but not enough than under democracies, 3.95, implying that in- to eradicate the e¤ect of regimes. Even when come doubles in 15.8 years under dictatorship the regimes are matched for their income, their and in 17.7 years under democracy. Yet we al- colonial heritage, and the frequencies of Catho- ready know that one should not draw inferences lics, Protestants, and Moslems, even if they are from the observed values. matched for demand (2SLS), or for the lagged To identify the e¤ect of regimes, we need to rate of population growth (HATANAKA esti- distinguish the e¤ects of the conditions under mator), or for country-specific e¤ects (PANEL which these regimes were observed from the ef- estimator), as well as for the factors a¤ecting se- fect of regimes. We present first the results con- lection, and, in a smaller sample, for the labor- cerning the e¤ect of regimes on the growth of force participation of women (LFPW), the labor productive inputs, then those concerning the ef- force grows faster under dictatorships. . . . ficiency with which these inputs are used under To examine the e¤ect of regimes on the e‰- each regime, and, finally, the conclusions about ciency with which resources are used in produc- the overall e¤ect of regimes on the growth of tion, we need to compare the coe‰cients of the total income. respective production functions. The constant Do productive inputs grow at the same rate measures total factor productivity, and the coef- under the two regimes? The claim that democ- racy undermines investment, whether in general 6. The variables in the investment equation include or only in poor countries, finds no support in the lagged investment share (given that investment deci- evidence. The observed average share of in- sions made one year take time to realize, INVLAG), vestment in gross domestic product (GDP), lagged per capita income (an instrument for expected INV ¼ I=Y, was in fact much higher in democ- domestic demand, LEVLAG), the average rate of racies, 20.90 percent, than in dictatorships, 14.25 growth in the world (a measure of world demand, percent. But because investment shares increase WORLD), and the relative price of investment goods with per capita income, and because, as we al- (PINV). Alternatively, we estimate a 2SLS model with ready know, dictatorships have generally existed the predicted growth rate as an instrument for the cur- rent demand. For a review of econometric models of in poorer countries, this could be just an e¤ect of investment, see Rama (1993). income. Indeed, controlling for income, as well Chapter 8 450

ficients on capital and labor represent the elas- in the countries where regimes were stable was ticities of output with regard to these factors. di¤erent from that in countries where regimes . . . The elasticity with regard to capital is changed.12 slightly higher in dictatorships, but elasticity With this reassurance, we can compare the with regard to labor is higher in democracies. rates of growth of democracies preceding dicta- Hence, one is led to conclude that democracies torships with those of democracies following benefit more from technical progress and use dictatorchips, and vice versa. The average rate of labor more e¤ectively, but dictatorships more growth during all the years of democracies pre- e‰ciently employ the physical capital stock. . . . ceding dictatorships was 4.49 percent (N ¼ 290), What, then, is the overall e¤ect of regimes on and for dictatorships following democracies, growth? Assuming that the two regimes exist 4.37 (N ¼ 425). Hence, transitions from democ- under the same conditions reduces the di¤erence racy to dictatorship did not a¤ect the rate of between the expected growth rates almost to growth. Growth during all the years of dictator- zero. . . . ships preceding democracies was higher, at the Because the labor force grows faster under average of 4.74 percent (N ¼ 607), than the av- dictatorship even when the two regimes are erage of 3.64 percent (N ¼ 371) during all the matched for exogenous conditions, lines with democratic years that followed. But because re- ‘‘LFG endogenous’’ in table 8.1 take the rate of covery from the crises accompanying transitions growth of the labor force at the mean values to democracy is slow, and the observations are observed for each regime. These results are right-hand censored, the conclusion that transi- somewhat more favorable to dictatorships. But tions to democracy slow down growth would be the di¤erence between regimes is still minuscule. erroneous. Just note that many of the democratic Hence, there is no reason to think that the re- observations followed transitions from either gime type a¤ects the rate of growth of total bureaucratic-authoritarian or communist dicta- income. torships during the 1980s, including the very end Another way to test the e¤ect of regimes is to of the decade. Because those democracies did not focus on the countries that experienced regime have time to recover by 1990, they weigh down changes. Here again, however, one should pro- the democratic average. ceed prudently. Countries in which regimes are In sum, neither the selection-corrected values unstable may be di¤erent from those that have for the entire sample nor the paths of growth had single regimes persisting during the entire associated with regime transitions give any sup- period. Yet the observed average rate of growth port to the claim that regime types a¤ect the rate was the same in those countries that did not ex- of growth of total income. Selection-corrected perience any regime transitions and in those that average rates of growth are the same for the two underwent one or more regime changes: The regimes. And there is no reason to think that rate of growth for the former was 4.23 percent steady-state rates of growth would be di¤erent (N ¼ 2;813), and for the latter 4.25 (N ¼ 1;313). under the two regimes when countries experience Stable dictatorships grew at the rate of 4.38 per- regime transitions. cent (N ¼ 1;709), whereas dictatorships in the The first conclusion, therefore, must be that countries that also experienced democracy grew political regimes have no impact on the rate of at the rate of 4.51 (N ¼ 772). Stable democracies growth of total income. The arguments about grew at the rate of 3.98 percent (N ¼ 1;104), and democracies that rose from or gave way 12. For a more extensive discussion of the e¤ect of re- to dictatorships grew at 3.88 percent (N ¼ 541). gime stability on growth, see Chapter 5 [of Democracy Hence, there is no reason to think that growth and Development]. Democracy’s E¤ects 451

Table 8.1 Selection-corrected estimators of the rate of growth of income (YG) Regime means Regime e¤ect Dictatorships Democracies Constant Estimator (N ¼ 2,396) (N ¼ 1,595) (N ¼ 3,991) Individual Biased 4.43 3.92 0.0227 0.0006 (6.94) (4.82) (0.1252) (0.4908) Unconstrained OLS 4.30 4.24 (5.02) (4.48) Constrained OLS (LFG exogenous) 4.22 4.37 (5.17) (4.60) Constrained OLS (LFG endogenous) 4.38 4.11 (5.15) (4.55) PANEL (LFG exogenous) 4.22 4.23 (5.17) (4.34) PANEL (LFG endogenous) 4.38 4.07 (5.15) (4.34) Unobservable 0.0741 0.0461 (0.1312) (0.4871) Observable 0.0926 0.0490 (0.1537) (0.5061)

EDTG sample N ¼ 1,745 N ¼ 1,042 Biased 4.57 3.91 (6.91) (4.71) Unconstrained OLS (LFG exogenous) 4.45 4.34 (4.71) (3.88) Constrained OLS (LFG exogenous) 4.36 4.94 (4.87) (4.01) 2F PANEL (LFG exogenous) 4.45 4.33 (4.71) (3.74) Notes: Probit equations include lagged values of LEVEL, STRA, and RELDIF. The ‘‘barebones’’ model includes KSG, LFG, and, in a smaller sample, EDTG. ‘‘Constrained’’ means that the coe‰cients on the arguments of the production function were constrained to 1.00. PANEL is OLS for dictatorships and 2F for democracies. ‘‘LFG exogenous’’ is based on the assumption that LFG is exogenous; ‘‘LFG endogenous’’ takes LFG at the observed mean of each regime. Chapter 8 452

the superiority of dictatorships in mobilizing seemed persuasive at the time it was advanced, savings for investment find no support in the ev- and it was not implausible. There appear to be idence. Indeed, the input that grows faster under good reasons to think that people in poor coun- dictatorships is not capital but labor. The dif- tries want to consume more immediately: They ferences in the e‰ciency with which productive cannot a¤ord to make intertemporal trade-o¤s inputs are utilized are small. And, as a conse- if they cannot expect to live to benefit from quence, the selection-corrected average expected their short-term sacrifices. It is also plausible that values of growth are almost identical. . . . unions, particularly if they are decentralized, and political parties, competing for votes, would push forward demands for immediate consump- Poor and Wealthy Countries tion. Yet, as likely as that view may seem, it simply is not true. Perhaps this only means that . . . [T]o test whether or not the results depend democracy is not very e¤ective at processing on the samples, we need to estimate produc- what people want; perhaps developmental goals tion functions separately for di¤erent levels of are not any more attractive to people under dic- development. . . . tatorship than under democracy; perhaps pov- erty is so constraining that even dictators cannot Poor Countries squeeze savings out of indigent people. The last explanation is most plausible. . . . In poor countries, the two regimes are almost Thus, poverty constrains. Whatever the re- identical, with observed rates of growth of 4.34 gime, the society is too poor to finance an e¤ec- percent under dictatorship and 4.28 under de- tive state. . . . mocracy. The two regimes generate productive Poor countries cannot a¤ord a strong state, inputs at the same rate and use them in identical and when the state is weak, the kind of regime ways. They invest about 12.5 percent of GDP matters little for everyday life. In a village and increase capital stock at the rate of about 6 located three days’ travel away from the capital, percent, and labor force at the rate of about 2.2 often the only presence of the state is a teacher percent. An increase of 1 percent in the capital and occasionally roving uniformed bandits.17 ... stock raises output by about 0.40 percent under In sum, poor countries are too poor to a¤ord a both regimes, and an increase in the labor force strong state, and without an e¤ective state there by 1 percent augments output by about 0.60 is little di¤erence any regime can make for eco- percent.15 Neither regime benefits much from nomic development. Investment is low in poor technical progress, about 0.1 percent per annum; democracies, but it is not any higher in poor both get 2.8 percent in growth from an increase dictatorships. The labor force grows rapidly in in capital stock, and 1.4 percent from an increase both. Development is factor-extensive: Poor in labor force. With identical supplies of factors countries benefit almost nothing from technical and their identical utilization, they grow at the change. Clearly, this does not imply that all same rate under the two regimes: The selection- poor countries are the same or even that regimes corrected average growth rates are the same. may not make a di¤erence for other aspects of The idea that democracies in poor countries people’s lives; indeed, we show later that they process pressures for immediate consumption, do. But not for economic development in poor resulting in lower investment and slower growth, countries.

15. This is a constrained estimate. Constrained esti- 17. The best portrayal of life under a weak state is by mates are cited in the rest of this paragraph. Alvaro Mutis (1996). Democracy’s E¤ects 453

Wealthy Countries they get most of their growth from capital, 3.05, and in spite of employing many more workers, Once countries reach some level of develop- they get less of it from labor, 0.85. Wealthier ment—somewhere between $2,500 and $3,000, democracies benefit from technical progress, that of Algeria in 1977, Mauritius in 1969, Costa 0.91, get less growth out of capital, 2.20, and Rica in 1966, South Korea in 1976, Czechoslo- more from the labor input, 1.04, even though vakia in 1970, or Portugal in 1966—patterns of they employ fewer additional workers. . . . economic development under democracy and . . . [G]rowth under wealthier dictatorships is dictatorship diverge. In countries with incomes both labor-extensive and labor-exploitative. The above that threshold, regimes do make a di¤er- labor force grows faster under dictatorship, the ence for how resources are used, for how much marginal worker produces less, and the average people produce and how much they earn. . . . worker much less, than under democracy. Even Dictatorships appear not to change their if they were matched for capital stock and labor ways whether they are in poor or wealthy coun- force, workers would produce less under dicta- tries. Although in more-developed economies torship. And labor earns less under dictatorship. they rely somewhat less on growth of the labor Some of this di¤erence is attributable to lower force and somewhat more on the growth of cap- output, but a large di¤erence remains even when ital stock, they use the inputs in almost the same we account for di¤erences in factor endowments way and get little benefit from productivity and even if we assume away di¤erences in pro- growth. Democracies, in turn, exhibit di¤erent ductivity. Democracy entails the freedom for patterns in poor and wealthy countries. Their workers to associate independently of their em- capital stock grows somewhat slower, and the ployers and the state. And strikes are three times labor force much slower, when they are a¿uent; more frequent under democracy than under dic- they use labor more productively and benefit tatorship: 0.2434 per year under the former and more from productivity growth. As a result, the 0.0895 under the latter. Because, in addition, patterns of growth are di¤erent in wealthier dic- under democracy workers also vote, these results tatorships and democracies. are not surprising. Dictatorships repress workers, Note . . . that the factors that di¤erentiate exploit them, and use them carelessly. Democ- wealthy dictatorships from wealthy democracies racies allow workers to fight for their interests, are the patterns, not averages. Corrected for se- pay them better, and employ them better. . . . lection, the average rates of growth of income are again almost identical under the two re- gimes. Although the observed rates of growth References are higher under dictatorships, if the two regimes had used the same inputs in production, they Barro, Robert J. 1989. Economic Growth in a Cross would have grown at the same rate. But they Section of Countries. In NBER Working Paper no. would have grown in di¤erent ways. 3120. Cambridge, MA: National Bureau of Economic Research. Growth under wealthy dictatorships is labor- extensive. The labor force grows at a much faster ———. 1990. Government Spending in a Simple Model of Economic Growth. Journal of Political pace under dictatorships, at 2.03 percent, than Economy 98(5): 103–125. under democracies, where it grows at 1.32 per- ———. 1997. Determinants of Economic Growth. cent. And whereas the elasticity of output with Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. regard to labor is about 0.56 under dictatorship, Barro, Robert J., and Xavier Sala-i-Martin. 1995. it is 0.68 under democracy. Wealthier dictator- Economic Growth. New York: McGraw-Hill. ships benefit little from technical progress, 0.33; Chapter 8 454

de Schweinitz, Karl, Jr. 1959. Industrialization, Labor Rao, Vaman. 1984. Democracy and Economic Devel- Controls, and Democracy. Economic Development and opment. Studies in Comparative International Develop- Cultural Change 7(4): 385–404. ment 19(4): 67–81. Dre`ze, Jean, and Amartya Sen. 1989. Hunger and Robinson, James. 1995. Theories of ‘‘Bad Policy’’. Public Action. Oxford University Press. Policy Reform 1: 1–17. Findlay, Ronald. 1990. The New Political Economy: Sah, Raaj K., and Joseph Stiglitz. 1988. Committees, Its Explanatory Power for LDCs. Economics and Poli- Hierarchies and Polyarchies. The Economic Journal 98 tics 2(2): 193–221. (June): 451–470. Galenson, Walter. 1959. Labor and Economic Devel- Sen, Amartya. 1994a. Freedoms and Needs. The New opment. New York: Wiley. Republic, January 10–17, 31–37. Huntington, Samuel P. 1968. Political Order in Changing Societies. New Haven, CT: Yale University Press. Huntington, Samuel P., and Jorge I. Dominguez. 1975. Political Development. In Macropolitical Theory, edited by F. I. Greenstein and N. W. Polsby, pp. 1– 114. Reading, MA: Addison-Wesley. Kaldor, Nicolas. 1956. Alternative Theories of Distri- bution. Review of Economic Studies 23: 83–100. Mutis, Alvaro. 1996. Adventures of Maqroll: Four No- vellas. New York: Harper-Collins. North, Douglass. 1990. Institutions, Institutional Change, and Economic Performance. Cambridge Uni- versity Press. Olson, Mancur. 1982. The Rise and Decline of Nations: Economic Growth, Stagflation, and Social Rigidities. New Haven, CT: Yale University Press. ———. 1991. Autocracy, Democracy, and Prosperity. In Strategy and Choice, edited by R. J. Zeckhauser, pp. 131–157. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. Pasinetti, Luigi. 1961. Rate of Profit and Income Dis- tribution in Relation to the Rate of Economic Growth. Review of Economic Studies 29 (October): 267–279. Przeworski, Adam. 1975. Institutionalization of Voting Patterns, or Is Mobilization the Source of Decay? American Political Science Review 69: 49–67. ———. 1990. The State and the Economy under Capitalism. Chur, Switzerland: Harwood Academic Publishers. Rama, Martin. 1993. Empirical Investment Equations for Developing Countries. In Striving for Growth after Adjustment: The Role of Capital Formation, Regional and Sectoral Studies, edited by Luis Serven and Andres Solimano, pp. 107–143. Washington, DC: World Bank. Democracy in America

Alexis de Tocqueville

. . . America is the only country in which we can little lots which the owner himself cultivated. But watch the natural quiet growth of society and it is land that is the basis of an aristocracy, where it is possible to be exact about the influ- giving it both roots and support; privileges by ence of the point of departure on the future of a themselves are not enough, nor is birth, but only state. . . . land handed down from generation to genera- When, after careful study of the history of tion. There may be huge fortunes and grinding America, we turn with equal care to the political poverty in a nation; but if that wealth is not and social state there, we find ourselves deeply landed, one may find rich and poor, but not, convinced of this truth, that there is not an using words strictly, an aristocracy. opinion, custom, or law, nor, one might add, an Hence there was a strong family likeness be- event, which the point of departure will not eas- tween all the English colonies as they came to ily explain. . . . birth. All, from the beginning, seemed destined . . . [O]ne observation, to which we shall come to let freedom grow, not the aristocratic free- back later, applies not to the English only, but dom of their motherland, but a middle-class also to the French, Spaniards, and all Europeans and democratic freedom of which the world’s who came in waves to plant themselves on the history had not previously provided a complete shores of the New World; all these new Euro- example. . . . pean colonies contained the germ, if not the full . . . [A]ll the immigrants who came to settle on growth, of a complete democracy. There were the shores of New England belonged to the well- two reasons for this; one may say, speaking to-do classes at home. From the start, when they generally, that when the immigrants left their came together on American soil, they presented motherlands they had no idea of any superiority the unusual phenomenon of a society in which of some over others. It is not the happy and there were no great lords, no common people, the powerful who go into exile, and poverty and, one may almost say, no rich or poor. In with misfortune is the best-known guarantee of proportion to their numbers, these men had a equality among men. Nonetheless, it did happen greater share of accomplishments than could be several times that as a result of political or found in any European nation now. All, perhaps religious quarrels great lords went to America. without a single exception, had received a fairly Laws were made there to establish the hierarchy advanced education, and several had made a of ranks, but it was soon seen that the soil of European reputation by their talents and their America absolutely rejected a territorial aristoc- knowledge. The other colonies had been founded racy. It was obvious that to clear this untamed by unattached adventurers, whereas the immi- land nothing but the constant and committed grants to New England brought with them won- labor of the landlord himself would serve. The derful elements of order and morality; they came ground, once cleared, was by no means fertile with their wives and children to the wilds. But enough to make both a landlord and a tenant what most distinguished them from all others rich. So the land was naturally broken up into was the very aim of their enterprise. No necessity forced them to leave their country; they gave up Excerpted from: Alexis de Tocqueville, Democracy in a desirable social position and assured means of America, translated by Henry Reeve, copyright 1945 livelihood; nor was their object in going to the and renewed 1973 by Alfred A. Knopf, a division of New World to better their position or accumu- Random House, Inc. Used by permission of Alfred A. late wealth; they tore themselves away from Knopf, a division of Random House, Inc. home comforts in obedience to a purely intellec- Chapter 8 456

tual craving; in facing the inevitable su¤erings of At that time in Connecticut all executive o‰- exile they hoped for the triumph of an idea.... cials were elected, including the governor32 of The English government watched untroubled the state. the departure of so many emigrants, glad to see Citizens over sixteen years of age were obliged the seeds of discord and of fresh revolutions dis- to bear arms; they formed a national militia persed afar. Indeed it did everything to encour- which appointed its o‰cers and was bound to be age it and seemed to have no anxiety about the ready to march at any time to the country’s fate of those who sought refuge from its harsh defense.33 laws on American soil. It seemed to consider In the laws of Connecticut and of all the New England as a land given over to the fantasy other states of New England we see the birth of dreamers, where innovators should be allowed and growth of that local independence which is to try out experiments in freedom. still the mainspring and lifeblood of American The English colonies—and that was one of the freedom. main reasons for their prosperity—have always In most European nations political existence enjoyed more internal freedom and political in- started in the higher ranks of society and has dependence than those of other nations; nowhere been gradually, but always incompletely, com- was this principle of liberty applied more com- municated to the various members of the body pletely than in the states of New England. . . . social. All the general principles on which modern Contrariwise, in America one may say that constitutions rest, principles which most Euro- the local community was organized before the peans in the seventeenth century scarcely under- county, the county before the state, and the state stood and whose dominance in Great Britain before the Union. was then far from complete, are recognized and In New England, local communities had taken given authority by the laws of New England; the complete and definite shape as early as 1650. participation of the people in public a¤airs, the Interests, passions, duties, and rights took shape free voting of taxes, the responsibility of govern- around each individual locality and were firmly ment o‰cials, individual freedom, and trial by attached thereto. Inside the locality there was a jury—all these things were established without real, active political life which was completely question and with practical e¤ect. democratic and republican. The colonies still These pregnant principles were there applied recognized the mother country’s supremacy; le- and developed in a way that no European nation gally the state was a monarchy, but each locality has yet dared to attempt. was already a lively republic. . . . In Connecticut the electoral body consisted, I have already said enough to put Anglo- from the beginning, of all the citizens, and that American civilization in its true light. It is the is readily understood.30 In that nascent commu- product (and one should continually bear in nity there prevailed an almost perfect equality of mind this point of departure) of two perfectly wealth and even greater intellectual equality.31 distinct elements which elsewhere have often been at war with one another but which in 30. Constitution of 1638 [Code of 1650], p. 17. America it was somehow possible to incorporate 31. In 1641 the general assembly of Rhode Island into each other, forming a marvelous combina- declared unanimously that the government of the state was a democracy and that power resided in the body 32. Pitkin’s History, p. 47. of free men, who alone had the right to make the laws 33. Constitution of 1638 [Code of 1650], p. 12. [The and provide for their enforcement. Code of 1650, p. 70. reference should read p. 70.] [Should refer to p. 12.] Democracy’s E¤ects 457

tion. I mean the spirit of religion and the spirit of A nation is like a jury entrusted to represent freedom. universal society and to apply the justice which is The founders of New England were both ar- its law. Should the jury representing society have dent sectarians and fanatical innovators. While greater power than that very society whose laws held within the narrowest bounds by fixed reli- it applies? gious beliefs, they were free from all political Consequently, when I refuse to obey an unjust prejudices. law, I by no means deny the majority’s right to Hence two distinct but not contradictory ten- give orders; I only appeal from the sovereignty dencies plainly show their traces everywhere, in of the people to the sovereignty of the human mores and in laws. . . . race. Far from harming each other, these two ap- There are those not afraid to say that in mat- parently opposed tendencies work in harmony ters which only concern itself a nation cannot go and seem to lend mutual support. completely beyond the bounds of justice and Religion regards civil liberty as a noble exer- reason and that there is therefore no need to fear cise of men’s faculties, the world of politics being giving total power to the majority representing a sphere intended by the Creator for the free play it. But that is the language of a slave. of intelligence. Religion, being free and powerful What is a majority, in its collective capacity, within its own sphere and content with the posi- if not an individual with opinions, and usually tion reserved for it, realizes that its sway is all with interests, contrary to those of another indi- the better established because it relies only on its vidual, called the minority? Now, if you admit own powers and rules men’s hearts without ex- that a man vested with omnipotence can abuse it ternal support. against his adversaries, why not admit the same Freedom sees religion as the companion of its concerning a majority? Have men, by joining struggles and triumphs, the cradle of its infancy, together, changed their character? By becoming and the divine source of its rights. Religion is stronger, have they become more patient of ob- considered as the guardian of mores, and mores stacles?3 For my part, I cannot believe that, and are regarded as the guarantee of the laws and I will never grant to several that power to do pledge for the maintenance of freedom itself. . . . everything which I refuse to a single man...... In democratic republics the power direct- ing6 society is not stable, for both its personnel Tyranny of the Majority and its aims change often. But wherever it is brought to bear, its strength is almost irresistible. ... I regard it as an impious and detestable maxim 3. No one would wish to maintain that a nation that in matters of government the majority of a cannot abuse its power against another nation. But people has the right to do everything, and nev- parties form something like little nations within the ertheless I place the origin of all powers in the nation, and the relations between them are like those of will of the majority. Am I in contradiction with strangers. myself? If it is agreed that a nation can be tyrannical toward There is one law which has been made, or at another nation, how can one deny that a party can be least adopted, not by the majority of this or that so toward another party? people, but by the majority of all men. That law 6. Authority may be centralized in an assembly, and in is justice. that case it is strong but not stable. Or it may be cen- Justice therefore forms the boundary to each tralized in one man, and in that case it is less strong but more stable. people’s right. Chapter 8 458

The government of the American republics seems to me as centralized and more energetic than the absolute monarchies of Europe. So I do not think that it will collapse from weakness.7 If ever freedom is lost in America, that will be due to the omnipotence of the majority driv- ing the minorities to desperation and forcing them to appeal to physical force. We may then see anarchy, but it will have come as the result of despotism. . . .

7. There is no need to remind the reader that here, and throughout this chapter, I am speaking not of the fed- eral government but of the governments of each state, where a despotic majority is in control. Does Democracy Engender Justice?

John E. Roemer

Does, or might, democracy engender justice? policies to be increasingly egalitarian in their Whether this question is interesting depends, of e¤ects. There are, evidently, arguments for and course, on the definitions we adopt of democ- against. racy and justice. I begin by arguing for particular I begin with two arguments in favor. The first definitions. is that, with the development of social science We must, I believe, insist upon a division of (economics, psychology, sociology), experts will labor between the concepts of democracy and not credibly be able to di¤er significantly in the justice for the initially posed question to be in- values they assign to the critical parameters of teresting. Democracy should be defined as a set the socio-economic mechanism. All experts will of institutions and practices whose intention is to converge to something near the true values of implement a certain kind of equal participation these parameters. Therefore, any policy which of citizens in the political process. Justice, on can credibly claim to increase the welfare of all the other hand, consists in a set of relations must, in fact, do so. Now just because a policy among persons, and between persons and goods, increases the welfare of all does not mean it cre- in a society. With this division of labor, the ates more equality of condition—it could create initial question becomes a scientific one: will a less. So I must make a stronger argument, that given set of institutions and practices bring about policies with universalistic appeal must claim to the particular set of relationships that justice distribute benefits fairly, where fairness entails a requires? . . . decreasing inequality of condition. To argue that . . . I shall not investigate the general question the conception of fairness will come to entail one could pose here, but a special case: must de- ever-increasing equality of condition is a major mocracy eventually generate justice conceived of undertaking, and it is not one I can pursue here. as equality of condition among citizens? I can- I say, then, that the first argument would go by not here digress to the intensely interesting, and establishing three premises: (1) that democratic controversial, issue of precisely what condition arguments are posed universalistically, (2) that, should be equalized under an egalitarian con- due to the development of social science, experts strual of justice. I will, however, take it that the will not credibly be able to disagree a great deal various candidates for the equalisandum would about the values of parameters in the economic all imply a much more egalitarian distribution of mechanism, and (3) that conceptions of fairness income than we observe in almost all countries entail, or will come to entail, increasing equality today.2 I have already argued that democratic argu- 2. I take equality of income to be the salient equality, ments take a universalistic form. The question is not equality of wealth. Unequal wealths should be sig- whether, over time, the constraint to argue uni- nificant, for an egalitarian, only if they generate un- versalistically will force democratically chosen equal incomes, or unequal streams of lifetime income. If a society were characterized by unequal wealths, but those wealths never generated unequal streams of in- Excerpted from: John E. Roemer, ‘‘Does Democracy come, an egalitarian should have no complaint. This is Engender Justice?’’ Democracy’s Value, edited by Ian not an absurd thing to imagine: there might be returns Shapiro and Casiano Hacker-Cordo´n. Cambridge: to scale in wealth holding, so that a small fraction of Cambridge University Press, 1999. 6 Cambridge Uni- people should hold all the wealth, but the income versity Press, 1999. Reprinted with the permission of stream from those holdings might be distributed in an Cambridge University Press. egalitarian manner. Chapter 8 460

of condition3 (for instance, that condition might of platforms, each of which announces the two- be ‘‘opportunity for the good life’’). dimensional policy that a party will seek to The second argument is that the general pop- implement, if it wins the election, and which to- ulation will become increasingly well educated gether constitute an equilibrium in the voting as economic development continues, which will game.4 ... force political parties/candidates to be less dem- The general result, of which I have reported an agogic, and stick closer to the truth. Essentially, instance, which I am confident is quite robust this argument substitutes ‘‘the increased sophis- (even though the instance I report is associated tication of the citizenry’’ for ‘‘the development of with a particular model of electoral politics), is social science’’ above. that when politics are multidimensional, there I proceed to present several arguments is little reason to think that political equilib- against. The first concerns the multidimension- rium will entail a high degree of redistribution, ality of electoral politics. It is commonly ob- in a polity which is characterized by a sig- served that the relevant issue space of electoral nificant variation in preferences on other, non- politics in the advanced democracies is (at least) distributive issues. In fact, the countries where two-dimensional (see Laver and Hunt 1992; we do see a high degree of redistribution (the Kitschelt 1994; Poole and Rosenthal 1991). One Nordic countries) are characterized by a rare issue, characteristically, concerns redistribution, homogeneity on the ‘‘values’’ issue, due to the and the other concerns ‘‘values’’—what Kit- great degree of religious, ethnic, and linguistic schelt calls the ‘‘authoritarian–libertarian’’ axis. homogeneity of their polities. . . . It might not be far-fetched to say that the second So I claim that, in societies which are het- issue reflects a good part of what makes up dif- erogeneous in regard to preferences on non- ferent religious views in the population. If most economic issues, the democratic process may societies will always be characterized by a spec- well not produce . . . considerable redistribution, trum of religious views, or of views concerning which is to say, it will not tend to produce what constitutes the good, then it is not unrea- equality of condition. The key premise, here, is sonable to think that electoral politics will al- the heterogeneity of values, and I note that such ways, in those societies, be multi-issued. . . . heterogeneity is a key assumption of the Rawls– In a recent paper (Roemer 1998b), I study Cohen–Barry formulation of the problem of the nature of electoral equilibrium when there justice (in Cohen’s case, of deliberative democ- are two parties, which represent di¤erent con- racy). It is, indeed, this heterogeneity which stituencies in the population, competing on a motivates the central issue for these authors, two-dimensional issue space. Call the first party whether or not the definition of justice they pro- Labour: it has pro-redistribution, libertarian pose is indeed neutral with respect to heteroge- preferences; call the second party Conservative: neous conceptions of the good (see Rawls 1993). it has anti-redistribution, authoritarian prefer- Finally, the electoral equilibrium I have been ences. The citizenry have preferences whose ideal discussing satisfies, it seems to me, the conditions points cover the issue space (that is, there are of procedural, impartial justice. That citizens voters with all possible ideal points in the two- vote according to their own preferences, as they dimensional issue space), but the distribution do in my model, does not violate Barry’s re- of such ideal points (voters) can be very gen- quirements of impartiality. eral. A political equilibrium consists of a pair 4. Indeed, the result I shall describe holds for several 3. I do not claim (3) is true, but that it is a premise of definitions of equilibrium. this argument. Democracy’s E¤ects 461

The argument just given assumes that citi- Conclusion zens’ preferences are self-regarding. Recently, Piketty (1995) has produced a fascinating argu- The reader will note that the arguments . . . de- ment showing that, even should voters be other- pend upon subsets of these three features of regarding in their preferences, and care about the society: that there is considerable uncertainty unluckiest in society, democratic political equi- about the (true) values of economic parameters, librium will not necessarily entail a great deal of that there are heterogeneous conceptions of the redistribution from the rich to the poor. Thus, good (values), and that there is a considerable Piketty’s argument shows that, even should spectrum of incomes or wealth before the degree citizens have internalized a Rawlsian kind of of redistribution is chosen by the democratic view, many may well not vote for redistributive process. I argued . . . that it might well be pos- policies. sible for democracy to engender the kind of The important premises of Piketty’s argument procedural, impartial justice that has been most are that: (1) the relationship between e¤ort and recently elaborated by Barry (1995), and is income is stochastic and obscure, (2) individuals advocated as well by Scanlon (1982 and 1988), form beliefs in a rational way, and (3) they are Rawls (1971 and 1993) and Cohen (1996). But other-regarding, rather than self-interested. The my conclusion was that the su‰cient conditions argument produces the unhappy result of possi- for just procedures that these authors propose bly low redistribution even when there are no are incapable of guaranteeing the kind of equal- right-wing parties or media trying to twist the ity of condition that they prize. . . . I asked facts, and even when voters are other-regarding. whether democracy would indeed tend to deliver Piketty’s model is an instance of the general ar- that kind of equality of condition; the two argu- gument I made earlier: that, when parameters of ments I o¤ered in favor of such a conclusion the economic mechanism are obscure, it is pos- both depended upon the elimination of uncer- sible that reasonable people will reach very dif- tainty about the values of economic parameters. ferent views as to their values. Piketty’s model is, I take the last two arguments . . . against con- in one sense, more damaging to the prognosis of cluding that democracy entails equality of con- equality in a Scanlonian world than my earlier dition, to be instances of a general phenomenon, example, for the sharply di¤ering views citizens that the kinds of uncertainty and heterogeneity come to have about economic parameters are postulated in this section’s first sentence push not due to their having listened to experts who against democracy’s engendering justice con- had, themselves, di¤erent ideological (or class) ceived of as equality of economic condition. I positions.5 do think, however, that the two pro arguments o¤ered . . . have some weight, and that, conse- 5. One might argue against the salience of Piketty’s quently, advanced democracies will, over time, model for our purposes, because it assumes that citi- come to be characterized by more equality of zens can observe only their own e¤ort. Thus, condi- economic condition than they currently have. tions of ‘‘full information’’ would require that citizens know the response of income to e¤ort generally in so- My conjecture is that that degree of equality will ciety. But I say this would be to assume away the cen- be considerably less than present-day theorists of tral problem, that economic parameters are, because of equality of condition (Sen 1980; Dworkin 1981; the complexity of the economic mechanism, obscure. Arneson 1989; G. A. Cohen 1989; Roemer Piketty’s model captures that obscurity by the particu- 1998a) think of as necessary for distributive lar assumption that individuals observe only their own justice. . . . e¤ort. Chapter 8 462

References

Arneson, Richard. 1989. ‘‘Equality and equality of op- portunity for welfare.’’ Philosophical Studies 56: 77–93. Barry, Brian. 1989. Theories of Justice. Berkeley: Uni- versity of California Press. ———. 1995. Justice as Impartiality. Oxford: Clar- endon Press. Cohen, G. A. 1989. ‘‘On the currency of egalitarian justice.’’ Ethics 99: 906–944. Cohen, Joshua. 1996. Liberty, Equality, Democracy. Cambridge, MA: Dept of Political Science, MIT (xeroxed). Dworkin, Ronald. 1981. ‘‘What is equality? Part 2: Equality of resources.’’ Philosophy & Public A¤airs 10: 283–345. Kitschelt, Herbert. 1994. The Transformation of Euro- pean Social Democracy. New York: Cambridge Uni- versity Press. Laver, Michael and W. B. Hunt. 1992. Policy and Party Competition. London: Routledge and Kegan Paul. Piketty, Thomas. 1995. ‘‘Social mobility and redis- tributive politics.’’ Quarterly Journal of Economics 110: 551–584. Poole, Kenneth and Howard Rosenthal. 1991. ‘‘Pat- terns of Congressional voting.’’ American Journal of Political Science 35: 228–278. Rawls, John. 1971. A Theory of Justice. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press. ———. 1993. Political Liberalism. New York: Co- lumbia University Press. Roemer, John E. 1998a. Equality of Opportunity. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press. ———. 1998b. ‘‘Why the poor do not expropriate the rich: an old argument in new garb.’’ Journal of Public Economics 70: 399–424. Scanlon, Thomas. 1982. ‘‘Contractualism and utilitari- anism.’’ In Amartya Sen and Bernard Williams (eds.), Utilitarianism and Beyond. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. ———. 1988. ‘‘Levels of moral thinking.’’ In D. Sea- nor and N. Fotion (eds.), Hare and Critics. Oxford: Clarendon Press. Sen, Amartya. 1980. ‘‘Equality of what?’’ In S. Mc- Murrin (ed.), The Tanner Lectures on Human Values. Vol. I. Salt Lake City: University of Utah Press. Facing up to the American Dream: Race, Class, and the Soul of the Nation

Jennifer L. Hochschild

The preface claimed that America’s racial sit- are ambitious themselves. Seventy percent of uation threatened the future of the ideology of black, and 80 percent of white, Californians the American dream in two distinct ways. This agree that ‘‘trying to get ahead’’ is very impor- chapter focuses on the first challenge—blacks’ tant in ‘‘making someone a true American.’’ An and whites’ increasing divergence in their de- even more overwhelming majority of black than scriptions of and explanations for America’s white Americans endorse self-su‰ciency as one racial situation. The two races share an over- of their primary goals. These views are, if possi- whelming support for the American dream as ble, even more strongly and uniformly expressed a prescription for their own and other Ameri- now than four decades ago.1 ... cans’ lives. The races disagree only slightly when people consider the American dream as a de- scription of their own lives, but they disagree Beliefs about One’s Own Chances to Achieve a considerably when people consider the dream as Dream a description of others’ lives. African Americans increasingly believe that racial discrimination is Whites and blacks resemble each other almost worsening and that it inhibits their race’s ability as much when the topic shifts from general en- to participate in the American dream; whites in- dorsement of the American dream to interpreta- creasingly believe that discrimination is lessening tions of one’s own particular life course. . . . and that blacks have the same chance to partici- pate in the dream as whites. I call that finding The Second Tenet the paradox of ‘‘what’s all the fuss about?’’ . . . [F]rom the 1940s forward, majorities of both races have anticipated success for themselves and The American Dream as Prescription their families, just as the second tenet of the American dream prescribes. Members of both Americans are close to unanimous in endorsing races are as sanguine now as they were four the idea of the American dream. Virtually all decades ago. Furthermore, the two races have agree that all citizens should have political been generally close to one another even on sur- equality and that everyone in America warrants veys that show unusually high or low levels of equal educational opportunities and equal op- optimism. And when the races do diverge sub- portunities in general. Three-fourths or more of stantially, blacks are always the more confident. both races agree that all people warrant equal In fact, African Americans’ optimism persists respect, that skill rather than need should de- even when they recognize their comparatively termine wages, that ‘‘America should promote worse circumstances. . . . equal opportunity for all’’ rather than ‘‘equal outcomes,’’ that ‘‘everyone should try to amount The Third Tenet to more than his parents did,’’ and that they Blacks and whites also come close to agreement Excerpted from: Jennifer L. Hochschild, Facing up to on the third tenet—that the key to success lies in the American Dream: Race, Class, and the Soul of the Nation. Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1995. 1. McClosky and Zaller (1984: 64–100, 116); Kluegel Copyright 6 1995 by Princeton University Press. Re- and Smith (1986: 112–13; GSS (1993: vars. 456, 464); printed by permission of Princeton University Press. Citrin et al. (1990: 1132). Chapter 8 464

one’s own hands—when they consider their own commitment to religious beliefs, and social util- lives. In the mid-1960s almost six in ten members ity are all ‘‘very important element[s] of success.’’ of both races endorsed ‘‘plan[ning] your life a ... good way ahead’’ rather than relying on luck, and over eight in ten blacks (compared with slightly fewer whites) insisted that ‘‘no weakness Beliefs about Others’ Chances to Achieve Their or di‰culty can hold us back if we have enough Dreams willpower.’’ By the mid-1980s more African Americans were prepared to admit a partial role . . . When Americans look at the prospects of for fate, but still half (compared with two-thirds others or at the overall pattern of racial in- of whites) insisted that their life course reflected teraction, African Americans are increasingly solely their own abilities.10 dismayed at the height of racial barriers to the American dream while whites are increasingly The First Tenet gratified by the decline of those barriers.15

These findings are especially surprising in light The First Tenet of divergence between the races in their beliefs about the existence and e¤ects of discrimination. Let us begin with beliefs about the first tenet’s The point is easily made: whites see little and claim of equal opportunity to pursue one’s lessening discrimination, and blacks feel them- dream. African Americans are a little more selves to be the objects of a lot, even increasing skeptical of the claim in general, since about 10 amounts, of discrimination. A majority of blacks percent fewer blacks than whites agree that ‘‘a always report discrimination in their lives, and in worker’s child has . . . some chance to get ahead’’ 1970 a quarter experienced it ‘‘almost every day or that ‘‘chances for success are distributed of my life.’’ . . . fairly.’’16 But blacks and whites diverge more sharply when they consider racial discrimination. The Fourth Tenet Blacks see more racial discrimination than do whites. Whites’ perceptions of racial discrimina- What gives the American dream its moral power tion varied widely in the 1960s, and seldom do is the fourth tenet, that success is justified be- more than a third now believe that blacks con- cause (and only when) it is associated with tinue to experience racist treatment in jobs, virtue. When they think about their own lives, housing, the media, or the criminal justice sys- both races, especially African Americans, are tem. Blacks saw it then and continue to see it committed to this claim. In 1986 over two-thirds now.17 For example, only a handful of whites of whites and three-fourths of blacks agreed that good relationships with family and friends, 15. Hochschild (1988) formulates racial disparities in perceptions and beliefs somewhat di¤erently. 10. Survey Research Center (1964: vars. 50a, 50n); 16. Schlozman and Verba (1979: 167). Marx (1964: vars. 50a, 50h, 50m); Campbell and 17. In 1946, 66% of whites but only 28% of blacks Schuman (1968: vars. 176, 178); Roper (1986: var. 36). thought ‘‘most Negroes in the United States are being More blacks than whites insist that they have ‘‘a lot’’ of treated fairly’’ (Erskine 1962: 139). Four decades later, control over their children’s future (Harris 1986b: var. one-third as many whites as blacks thought being of C9). Kluegel and Smith (1986: 94) show no di¤erence the right race was crucial for getting ahead (GSS 1987: between whites and blacks in their attributions for var. 507I). Whites’ perceptions of women’s oppor- personal circumstances. tunity ‘‘are more negative than are corresponding Democracy’s E¤ects 465

think that more than half of whites share the see increasing racial equality declined from be- attitudes of the Ku Klux Klan; a quarter of tween 50 and 80 percent in the mid-1960s to be- blacks see more than half of whites as Klan tween 20 and 45 percent in the 1980s. In some sympathizers. In that context it is not surprising surveys up to half claim that the situation of that over half of blacks but only a quarter to a blacks has worsened since some referent point in third of whites think our nation is moving to- the past.20 ... ward two separate and unequal societies.18 Most importantly, the races di¤er on the spe- Whites, in fact, are increasingly convinced that cific question, crucial to the first tenet of the racial equality is growing in the United States. In American dream, of whether racial discrimina- the mid-1960s, 30 to 45 percent (depending on tion a¤ects Americans’ life chances. . . . the year and the wording of the question) felt In the 1960s a majority, or at least a plurality, that the nation was making progress in solving of blacks were optimistic about blacks’ chances its racial problems; by the 1970s, 50 to 70 per- to succeed. Their conviction was exceeded only cent concurred, and by 1988, fully 87 percent of by whites’ (if we can rely on one survey item). By whites believed that ‘‘in the past 25 years, the the 1980s most blacks were not optimistic about country has moved closer to equal opportunity blacks’ chances to succeed. Whites remained among the races.’’19 African Americans, mean- much more convinced of blacks’ equal chances, while, are becoming increasingly discouraged on and throughout the three decades generally a the same point. The proportion of blacks who majority of whites agreed that race did not im- pede blacks’ attainment of their dreams. perceptions about blacks’’ (Kluegel and Smith 1986: These results are critical for the viability of the 235–39; see also NYT/WCBS News 1985: var. 33; GSS American dream. The first tenet is the founda- 1987: var. 507L). tion of our nation’s faith in liberty and equality See also NORC (1944, vars. 01, 04, 05); Harris for all. Absent disparate views on this tenet, dis- (1966a: var. 21a; 1966b: vars. 11D, 13.1–13.15, 14F, putes over the rest of the American dream lose 14G, 16A, 18A); Campbell and Schuman (1968: var. much of their racial edge. But given the disparate 230); Harris (1978: 4–13, 26–34); CBS News/NYT views . . . one cannot talk about the meaning or (1978: vars. 10a, 11a, 12a, 13a, 20, 21, 25, 38, 39, 40); future of the ideology of the American dream NYT/WCBS News (1985: vars. 20, 21, 32, 35b); Gallup (1987: 36; 1988: 23); Harris (1988: vars. A, D, F, G, without also talking about race. . . . N); Media General/AP (1988: var. RC06); Harris (1989b: 199–202, 213–20, 253–58); ABC News/ 19. Erskine (1962: 138; 1969a: 156); Hutcheson (1973: Washington Post (1989: vars. 22.1, 24.1–24.5; 1991: 56); Harris (1978: 56); CBS News/NYT (1978: var. 17); var. 37); Gordon Black (1989a: vars. 11, 17; 1989b: Converse et al. (1980: 79); Los Angeles Times (1983: var. 19); NBC News (1989: vars. 44, 74, 75); Sigelman tables 86, 94); Media General/AP (1988: vars. RC02, and Welch (1991: 77); Los Angeles Times (1991b: var. RC03, RC10); McLeod (1988b: A4); ABC News/ 49); Gallup (1991b: vars. 9, 34A); Yankelovich Clancy Washington Post (1989: var. 17); Los Angeles Times Shulman (1992: var. 6); CBS News/NYT (1992: var. (1991b: vars. 57, 58); Yankelovich Clancy Shulman R21); People for the American Way (1992: 70–74, 154, (1992: var. 23); CBS News/NYT (1992: var. R29); 157, 159); Washington Post (1992: vars. 3k, 6, 9); People for the American Way (1992: 65–67, 155, 159); D. Garth Taylor (1993: 20, 22, 23, 28; 1994: 29, 32, Washington Post (1992: var. 2). 39); ‘‘Thirty Years After’’ (1993); NYT/WCBS-TV 20. In addition to the citations in the previous note, see Channel 2 News (1994: vars. 25, 27); Welch et al. Brink and Harris (1966: 222–31); Marx (1969: 5–11, (1994: 28–30); National Conference (1994: 16–19, 22, 220); NSBA (1980: var. 1222); Joint Center for Politi- 84–86, 100–102). cal Studies (1984: table 2); Cavanagh (1985: 3); Schu- 18. ABC News/Washington Post (1989: var. 19); Gal- man et al. (1988: xiv, 141–43); Brown et al. (1994: table lup (1992: var. 16); ‘‘Thirty Years After’’ (1993). 15.9); Gallup (1988: var. 4; 1994: var. 30). Chapter 8 466

The Second Tenet risen to just over 20 percent, whereas a majority of blacks remained frustrated at the pace of civil It follows logically that those who think dis- rights progress.27 More generally, whites have crimination is slight, declining, and unimportant more faith than blacks that political o‰cials can in its consequences would anticipate more suc- be brought to attend to the needs and wants of cess for the less favored race than those who ordinary citizens.28 think discrimination is great, increasing, and po- tent in its consequences. And data support logic, The Third Tenet for a change; whites have always been convinced of rapid black economic progress. In 1966 over Blacks and whites di¤er as much over the third two-thirds of whites declared blacks to be tenet—that the key to success lies in one’s own ‘‘moving too fast’’ or ‘‘asking for more than they hands—as over the first two when they focus on are ready for.’’24 By the 1990s whites’ main re- people other than themselves. We saw above that sponse to black aspirations had shifted from blacks are almost as likely as whites to attribute denigration to satisfaction, but their conviction their own success (or lack thereof ) to their own that these aspirations were likely to be fulfilled abilities. Nevertheless, they are less likely than had not changed.25 whites to attribute the success or failure of other Blacks, however, have traditionally felt and Americans to ability rather than to fate or birth. continue to feel frustrated with the past and pes- For example, from 1972 through 1991, up to 70 simistic about the future prospects of their race. For example, in 1989 only 45 percent of 26. Gordon Black (1989a: vars. 18, 19; 1989b: vars. 1, blacks (compared with over 70 percent of whites) 2). See also citations in previous note. thought opportunities for blacks had improved African Americans perhaps see more polarization during the 1980s; a fifth of blacks but only a by class on the second tenet than do whites. On the handful of whites thought opportunities had one hand, more blacks believe that the number of rich worsened. Roughly the same proportions were Americans is increasing (ABC News/Washington Post optimistic or pessimistic about prospects in the 1990: var. 14). On the other hand, more blacks believe that ‘‘the lot of the average man [sic] is getting worse’’ decade to come.26 (GSS 1973; 1974; 1976–77; 1983; 1984–85; 1987; The political arena resembles the economic 1988–89; 1990–91: var. 176B). arena: most whites but few blacks believe that 27. Brink and Harris (1966: 220, 258); Goldman blacks can reasonably anticipate political suc- (1969: 231); Schuman et al. (1988: xiii, xiv, 118–19, cess. In the 1960s no more than 6 percent of 146–47); Harris (1989b: 114, 208; 1989c: 79); NBC whites thought progress in promoting civil rights News (1989: var. 69); Gallup (1991b: var. 5). Over the was too slow, compared with over half of blacks. past three decades, the modal white has shifted from By 1988 the proportion of impatient whites had concern about civil rights moving too fast to satisfac- tion with the pace, whereas the modal black has shifted 24. Harris (1966b: vars. 11B, 18I; 1970a: var. 12A; from satisfaction with the pace to concerns about 1970b: 11A); Schuman et al. (1988: 118–19). sluggishness. The proportion of whites who agree that ‘‘civil rights 25. Harris (1966a: vars. 21D; 1966b: var. 14E); GSS groups are asking for too much’’ has risen since 1963 NYT (1982: var. 148A, 148B); /WCBS News (1985: from 42 to 47%. (It also rose among blacks, but the var. 49); Gallup (1988: var. 4); McLeod (1988b: A4); order of magnitude is entirely di¤erent—from 3 to 7%) Harris (1988: vars. A, N); ABC News/Washington (‘‘Thirty Years After’’ 1993). Post (1989: var. 25); GSS (1990–91: var. 621A, F, G, 28. Shingles (1981: 84); Carr and Hudgins (n.d.); Har- H); Los Angeles Times (1991b: tables 57, 58, 59, 64); Gallup (1992: var. 10). ris (1989b: 192, 196, 275, 279); Harris (1989c: 285, 297); National Conference (1994: 68). Democracy’s E¤ects 467

percent of whites compared with 50 to 60 percent The Fourth Tenet of blacks agreed that people get ahead through hard work rather than through luck or help.29 Just as blacks are slightly more likely than whites Conversely, blacks are at least twice as likely to associate virtue with success in their own lives, as whites to claim that having wealthy or well- they are a little more inclined to judge others’ educated parents, having political and personal lives in moral terms. . . . connections, or being of the right religion, re- gion, political conviction, or sex are crucial for getting ahead in life. Blacks are almost three Implications of Blacks’ and Whites’ Beliefs for times as likely as whites to agree that ‘‘society the American Dream gives some people a head start and holds others back’’ (although a majority of both races also The fact that more whites than blacks see blacks’ agree that hard work is the chief determinant of failure as their own fault reinforces whites’ success).30 belief that discrimination is slight and unim- . . . [H]owever, the two races disagree most portant and that blacks can reasonably antici- sharply over the explanation for blacks’ success pate success. Conversely, the fact that more or lack thereof.31 . . . [W]hites have always been blacks see blacks’ failure as due to forces beyond more likely than African Americans to attribute their control—or due to whites in particular— racial inequality to flaws within individual blacks reinforces blacks’ belief that discrimination is or in the black community. This is hardly sur- powerful and pervasive and that blacks cannot prising, if only because everyone is more likely to anticipate success. More analytically, the beliefs attribute others’ failings to the others’ rather of each race about the first, second, and third than to their own flaws. (If surveyors ever asked tenets are internally consistent, but externally parallel questions about the problems of whites, contradictory. we would presumably see the opposite pattern That finding implies a powerful challenge to in the responses.) Perhaps the only surprise in the ideology of the American dream. Whites be- this table is that the racial gap is not larger. lieve it works for everyone; blacks believe it In some surveys up to half of blacks were willing works only for those not of their race. Whites are to accept responsibility for their race’s lack of angry that blacks refuse to see the fairness and success—perhaps the most persuasive indicator openness of the system; blacks are angry that yet of the strength of the ideology of the Ameri- whites refuse to see the biases and blockages of can dream. the system. If that disparity persists or worsens, as it has every appearance of doing, the Ameri- 29. GSS (1972–73; 1974; 1976–77; 1980; 1982; 1984– can dream cannot maintain its role as a central 35 85; 1987; 1988–89; 1991–92: var. 197). See also GSS organizing belief of all Americans. (1984: vars. 69B, C, D, G); Schlozman and Verba (1979: 167); Verba and Orren (1985: 73–77); Kluegel 35. African Americans may be ahead of white Ameri- and Smith (1986: 90–100); People for the American cans in understanding the racially based threat to Way (1992: 151). American stability. We saw earlier that many more 30. GSS (1987: vars. 507A–507M; 1993: var. 458). blacks than whites think that over half of whites share 31. This table focuses only on what are commonly the views of the Ku Klux Klan. But it is also the case called individualist explanations for racial disparities. that more blacks (24%) than whites (17%) think that Individualists, however, often give structural explana- blacks hold ‘‘racist attitudes toward whites’’ (ABC tions as well (Kluegel and Smith 1986: 201; Sigelman News/Washington Post 1989: var. 20). and Welch 1991: 94–107). Chapter 8 468

Whites’ Quandary to cling to the dream, insist that it really works, and find someone to blame for the lacunae. But this is only the first challenge to the Ameri- can dream. Adding the findings about how the Blacks’ Quandary dream applies to one’s own life produces a curi- ous inconsistency within each race that gen- African Americans face the opposite quandary. erates yet more challenges to it. Consider whites’ They are more sure than whites that racial dis- quandary first: although whites are more sure crimination inhibits black Americans (tenet 1), than blacks that discrimination is not a problem more pessimistic about how much success blacks (tenet 1), more sure that blacks are increasingly can anticipate (tenet 2), more convinced that able to succeed (tenet 2), more sure that people’s blacks’ life chances are not within their control future lies within their own control (tenet 3), and (tenet 3), and slightly less confident that they more sure that they control their own fate (tenet control their own life chances (tenet 3). Never- 3), they are less optimistic about their own future theless, African Americans remain more confi- (tenet 2).36 These reasons combine to make dent than whites about their own prospects blacks’ continued complaints about glass ceilings (tenet 2). That quandary could be resolved sim- or hiring biases ring false to whites. It is only a ply by assuming that each optimistic black be- short step from here to the view, held by one- lieves that ‘‘I am so special, talented, determined, tenth to one-third of whites, that compared with or whatever that I will beat the odds even though whites blacks have more opportunities, are less other blacks cannot.’’ That sentiment is initially vulnerable to economic upheaval, receive better plausible, since everyone sees themselves and health care, are treated better in the courts and their children as special. But in that case why are the media, and are more likely to obtain good not whites equally optimistic for themselves? jobs and be admitted to good colleges.37 It is Alternatively, African Americans could believe only another short step, for a few, to global ra- that they personally are only reasonably talented cial hostility. . . . and so forth, but that other blacks are for some Whites are left at an impasse, which possibly reason especially unable to cope with the de- explains the emotional charge of some whites’ mands of American society. Thus ‘‘I can handle racial views. Something is wrong with the Amer- the challenge of the dream but others like me are ican dream, and the problem is associated with too handicapped by racism, poverty, or whatever blacks in some way. But identifying what is to do so.’’ This sentiment is also plausible but wrong and how blacks are implicated in it is a unappealing to anyone with a sense of collective di‰cult and thankless task for which they receive almost no institutional support.38 It is far easier 38. Thus only 55% of whites, compared with 77% of blacks, agree that it is ‘‘very urgent’’ that America 36. Hochschild (1981: 241–42) demonstrates this ‘‘honestly faces the issue of race.’’ These results are quandary in one person’s reasoning. probably inflated for whites by the fact that the ques- tion comes at the end of a long interview about race in 37. Harris (1978: 52); CBS News/NYT (1978: var. 21); Schlozman and Verba (1979: 169); Roper (1986: var. America (National Conference 1994: 36). Almost the 38); Harris (1988: ques. 1C, 1D; 1989b: 198–202, 213, only institution that provides an explanation of this 271; 1989c: 47, 53, 56, 59, 94, 272); GSS (1990–91: var. quandary is white supremicist groups, which argue that secret cabals of Jews or African Americans (or Catho- 422); Los Angeles Times (1991b: vars. 49, 50); Snider- man et al. (1991: var. skin); People for the American lics, in an earlier era) are manipulating the system to Way (1992: 52, 72–74); Washington Post (1992: var. deprive whites of their deserved rewards. With friends 3g); MCIC (1991–94: vars. 424, 425). like this, the American dream does not need enemies. Democracy’s E¤ects 469

identity. And African Americans have a strong have grown disillusioned with and even embit- sense of collective identity.39 tered about the American dream.1 Blacks are left at as much of an impasse as are Under the spell of the great national suggestion: whites. For them, too, something is wrong with As black poverty has deepened and become the American dream that is vaguely but certainly concentrated, poor African Americans have the fault of the other race. Identifying what is continued to believe in the American dream al- wrong and how whites are implicated in it seems most as much as poor blacks did thirty years easy at first but more di‰cult as one probes ago. But that support is tenuous and under great further. Far easier for African Americans, too, pressure.2 to cling to the dream personally, doubt it col- lectively, and find someone to blame for the In combination these paradoxes produce the lacunae. surprising pattern that poor blacks now believe more in the American dream than rich blacks do, which is a reversal from the 1960s. But these The Next Step paradoxes are more than merely surprising; to- gether they point to the second threat posed by The paradox of ‘‘what’s all the fuss about?’’ has American race relations to the future of the several nuances. Most centrally, whites either do American dream. If poor blacks and all whites not understand or understand but reject blacks’ follow middle-class blacks in their deepening claims that opportunities are racially biased and disillusionment with the American dream, then that blacks cannot control their own life chances. the dream faces an even greater problem than As whites become more and more satisfied with the comparatively simple racial hostility depicted the trajectory of racial change in the United [earlier]. . . . States, African Americans become less and less satisfied with it; on the few occasions when black gratification increases, so does white disappro- The First Tenet bation. Within that central perceptual divide lie several other quandaries that complicate each For African Americans to believe . . . that every- race’s beliefs about the dream and evaluations one, even they, can participate in the search for of each other. These external contradictions and internal puzzles would threaten any dominant 1. I borrowed the construction from the cigarette ad- ideology, but they are especially threatening to vertisement with the tag line, ‘‘Smoking more and one as predicated on equality and on faith as is enjoying it less?’’ (via ’s description of the American dream. . . . the politics of American health care: ‘‘doing better and feeling worse’’). Adding comparisons within each race to com- 2. The phrase comes from Myrdal (1944: 4): ‘‘The parisons across races reveals two additional par- American Negroes know that they are a subordinated adoxes beyond that of what’s all the fuss about? group experiencing, more than anybody else in the na- tion, the consequences of the fact that the [American] They are: Creed is not lived up to in America. Yet their faith in Succeeding more and enjoying it less: As the the Creed is not simply a means of pleading their African American middle class has become larger, unfulfilled rights. They, like the whites, are under the spell of the great national suggestion. With one part of more powerful, and more stable, its members themselves they actually believe, as do the whites, that the Creed is ruling America’’ (emphasis added). 39. Dawson (1994); Gurin et al. (1989); Tate (1993). Chapter 8 470

success, they must believe that the barriers of Well-o¤ African Americans see more racial race, class, and (for half the population) gender discrimination than do poor blacks, see less de- have all been knocked down low enough for cline in discrimination, expect less improvement people like themselves to climb over them. . . . in the future, and claim to have experienced . . . Although many if not most poor blacks3 more in their own lives.7 ... believe that African Americans continue to ex- Comparing perceptions of discrimination over perience racist treatment,4 relatively few report time yields the most surprising results: in the su¤ering from discrimination in their own lives5 1950s and 1960s, well-o¤ African Americans or see it as a dominant problem. . . . frequently saw less racial discrimination, both generally and in their own lives, than did badly- 3. When referring to survey data that I have analyzed, o¤ African Americans. . . . this book has precise meanings for the terms poor The same pattern of reversal in the most dis- (badly o¤ ), well o¤ (a¿uent, middle class), well edu- a¤ected obtains in the more confrontational cated, poorly educated, high status, and low status. question about whether ‘‘most white people want ‘‘Poor’’ and ‘‘well-o¤’’ whites or blacks are those to see blacks get a better break or . . . keep blacks whose family incomes are in the lowest or highest down.’’ . . . thirds of their race, respectively, in the sample for a The absolute level of African Americans’ bit- given survey. Poorly educated blacks or whites are terness about white intentions varies across time survey respondents with less than a high school educa- tion; well-educated blacks or whites are respondents and surveys, and probably any given set of with more than a high school education. When I refer numbers is not to be trusted. What matters here to high- (or low-) status people, I am indicating that is that the relative degree of mistrust switched both the highly (poorly) educated subset of the sample between the 1960s and 1980s. . . . [U]p until 1969, in a given survey and the richest (poorest) third of that whenever the classes varied, lower-status blacks sample hold a particular view. For more detail on how perceived more white hostility than did their the surveys were categorized and why I made those higher-status counterparts. . . . [W]ith the excep- choices, see appendix A. NYT 4. /WCBS News (1985: vars. 20, 21, 45); CBS WCBS News (1985: vars. 26, 27); Adams and Dressler NYT News/ (1978: vars. 10a, 11a, 12a, 13a, 17, 20, 21, (1988: 760); Gordon Black (1989a: vars. 1, 4, 6, 7, 8, 9, 38, 39, 40, 48); NSBA (1980: var. 368); Denton and 16); Marshall and Barnett (1991: 18); GSS (1990–91: Sussman (1981); Parent and Stekler (1985: 533); Gil- var. 625H1); Gallup (1991a: vars. 16A–16D; 1991b: liam (1986: 56); Brown et al. (1994: tables 15.7, 15.9); vars. 12, 34A); Los Angeles Times (1991b: var. 73); Gallup (1988: vars. Q20, Q22); Media General/AP Yankelovich Clancy Shulman (1992: vars. 10, 11); CBS (1988: vars. RC02, RC06, RC10); Adams and Dressler News/NYT (1992: vars. 20, 21). (1988: 760); Harris (1988: ques. D, N); Harris (1989b: 105–61 passim); Gordon Black (1989a: vars. 11, 12, 17, 7. See citations in notes 4 and 5, as well as People for the American Way (1992: 68, 71–72). For mixed 29B); NBC News (1989: vars. 44, 74, 75); ABC News/ Washington Post (1989: var. 22.1; 1991: var. 37); GSS results, see Schuman and Hatchett (1974: 58–59, 68– (1990–91: vars. 395B, 396B); Los Angeles Times 73); NSBA (1980: var. 1222); Sigelman and Welch (1991b: vars. 50, 64); Washington Post (1992: vars. 1, 2, (1991: 71–75). For counterevidence, see NSBA (1980: var. 1223); NYT/WCBS News (1985: vars. 26, 27). 3E, 9); Yankelovich Clancy Shulman (1992: vars. 6, 23); Gallup (1992: var. 12); CBS News/NYT (1992: A study of six ethnic groups (Jews, Irish, WASPs, vars. 29, 30, 31); Gallup (1994: var. 30). blacks, Cubans, Dominicans, and Puerto Ricans) in New York City found that ‘‘among all groups, it is the 5. Campbell and Schuman (1968: vars. 206–21, 225– middle-class respondents that tend to perceive ethnic NYT 27, 259–60, 262–64, 270–72); CBS News/ (1978: bias in city government and their groups as the victims vars. 10b, 11b, 12b, 42); NSBA (1980: vars. 346, 512, of this bias’’ (Robert Smith 1988: 183). 598, 736); Lewis and Schneider (1983: 13); NYT/ Democracy’s E¤ects 471

tion of a single year, that discrepancy was (the di¤erence scores are negative). Although reversed by the end of the 1970s.14 the actual responses fluctuate considerably Perceptions of discrimination, however, do not across surveys and are therefore not trustworthy, necessarily translate into rejection of the first one can discern a general pattern from them that tenet of the American dream. To make that explains this reversal: both classes of African translation, African Americans must see racial Americans were more optimistic for their race in discrimination as not merely an annoyance but a the 1960s than in the 1980s, but a¿uent blacks’ serious impediment to their pursuit of success. optimism has plummeted while poor blacks’ op- . . . [B]lacks do not always assume that dis- timism has declined more gently.18 Thus the crimination keeps them from pursuing their combination of the two paradoxes—succeeding dream. . . . more and enjoying it less and remaining under Nevertheless, Americans’ beliefs about the the spell of the great national suggestion— first tenet of the American dream are un- produces the results seen here. . . . questionably colored by their perceptions of . . . [I]n the 1980s whites have the same pat- discrimination. . . . tern of responses as blacks; poor whites are . . . In many of the 1960s surveys, middle-class always more confident of blacks’ chances than blacks were at least as optimistic, or even more are middle-class whites (the di¤erence scores are so, for their race as were poor blacks (the di¤er- negative). The substantive meaning of this for- ence scores are positive).17 In virtually none of mally similar pattern is, of course, very di¤erent the 1980s and 1990s surveys do the same results across the races. To blacks, these questions ask obtain; poor blacks were almost always more about their race’s chances despite discrimination; optimistic for their race than were a¿uent blacks to whites, these questions ask whether discrimi- nation still exists. . . . 14. Similar sets of questions produce similar reversals . . . Middle-class blacks have become much over time. In 1968 fewer poorly-educated than well- more pessimistic; poor blacks have become educated blacks agreed that ‘‘few white people dislike slightly more pessimistic; middle-class whites are Negroes.’’ By 1983 more poor than well-o¤ blacks fairly confident of blacks’ chances to succeed; thought that ‘‘most white people like [me]’’ (Campbell and poor whites are very confident of blacks’ and Schuman 1968: var. 317; Lewis and Schneider 1983: 13). In 1968 more poorly-educated than well- 18. Academic writings about race also demonstrate educated blacks trusted no whites, but fifteen years later more poor than well-o¤ blacks claimed to like plummeting optimism among the best-o¤. Until the white people (Schuman and Hatchett 1974: 64; Lewis 1960s, ‘‘studies by black scholars always tended to be and Schneider 1983: 13). more positive and optimistic [than those by whites] about the possibilities for improvement [in race rela- 17. More specialized surveys reinforce my claim of tions] and advancement [of blacks’ condition]. . . . For middle-class optimism during the 1960s. For example, most of these researchers, . . . integration of blacks and among blacks who had experienced discrimination in whites was inevitable, despite the objections of most 1967, those with little education mistrusted the political whites and some blacks. Therefore progress in breaking system more than those with a lot (Aberbach and down barriers to black advancement through greater Walker 1970b). Three-fifths or more of seniors in tra- desegregation was a constant source of optimism’’ ditionally black colleges agreed in 1968 that Negro (Franklin 1985: 20, 22). Starting in the 1960s, black college graduates were likely to get at least as good a scholars became more pessimistic and skeptical of the job as whites in most professional settings (Harris desirability of desegregation than the rest of the black 1968: records 55, 73). See also Searles and Williams population or than most white scholars of race. (1962). Chapter 8 472

chances. All three paradoxes obtain19 for the The Second Tenet first tenet of the American dream.20 . . . The ideology of the American dream speci- 19. Judgments of chances for political success di¤er fies not only who may participate but also what slightly from judgments of chances for economic suc- they participate in—the search for success, cess. Poor African Americans have always been much which one can reasonably expect to attain. Afri- less satisfied than better-o¤ African Americans with their own chance to influence the government (Mat- can Americans, like other Americans, do not al- thews and Prothro 1961: var. 428; Langton and Jen- ways translate a clear-eyed view of the past into nings 1972: 63; Aberbach and Walker 1970b; Wright a hard-nosed evaluation of the future. . . . 1976: 141, 176–81; Campbell 1980: 655; Shingles 1981: . . . Well-o¤ blacks are, once again, dispropor- 84; Brown et al. 1994: tables 3.3, 1984 and 1988; 3.4, tionately discouraged in general in the face of 1984 and 1988; 11.10, 11.11, 11.12; GSS 1987: vars. their own well-being, and poor blacks are dis- 337, 340; Colasanto 1988: 46; Gurin et al. 1989: 294; proportionately encouraged in general in the face Smith and Seltzer 1992: 56). But better-o¤ blacks have of their own poverty and poor prospects. always been less satisfied with their race’s chance for Other surveys confirm these findings. From political influence. In particular, high-status blacks are the 1950s into the 1990s, poor blacks almost al- more likely than low-status blacks to think that their race has too little, and whites have too much, political ways felt less pleased with their own progress influence (Gallup 1961: var. 05C; 1964: var. 14C; from the recent or distant past than did well-o¤ NSBA 1980: var. 1217; GSS 1987, var. 353; Brown blacks. The discrepancies were sometimes as et al. 1994: tables 13.10, 1984 and 1988; 6.5, 1984 and great as two to one. . . . 1988; 6.7, 1984 and 1988; 18.12; GSS 1990–91: var. Poor African Americans are similarly more 394; Dawson 1994b: 95; Reese and Brown forthcom- discouraged than are well-o¤ blacks about the ing: tables 1–3). For possible counterevidence, de- United States as a whole and various groups pending on how one interprets the questions, see within it. On the nation: in 1991, 30 percent of Brown et al. (1994: tables 3.7, 1984 and 1988; 3.8, 1984 middle-class but only 6 percent of poor blacks and 1988; 3.11, 1984 and 1988). For clear counter- thought the nation was in better shape than it evidence, see ibid. (table 3.9, 1984 and 1988). had been a year earlier.25 On women: in 1970, 20. The two paradoxes roughly obtain when African almost half of middle-class but only 40 percent Americans consider the e¤ects of class discrimination. In the 1960s middle-class blacks were more convinced of poor blacks thought women received more 26 than were poor blacks that even the poor could succeed respect than a decade earlier. On the poor: (if we can rely on one survey), but from the mid-1970s more a¿uent than poor blacks think poor on, middle-class blacks were no more and sometimes Americans are doing well now, were doing well a less convinced of class-based equality of opportunity decade earlier, or will do well a decade hence.27 (Huber and Form 1973: 91; Schlozman and Verba On ‘‘the average man’’: in three of four surveys 1979: 168, 170; Roper 1986: var. 42, 46; GSS 1987: vars. 507A, 507B; GSS 1990–91: var. 387D; Brown et There are too few questions, with no clear trends, to al. 1994: table 6.10). One survey (Harris 1989b: 193, say anything about how di¤erent race/class groups 276; 1989c: 288) has the opposite finding. view the issue of opportunity for di¤erent genders Whites are less predictable. In the 1960s and 1970s (Roper 1986: var. 45; GSS 1987: var. 507L). middle-class whites resembled middle-class blacks in their relative confidence about the chances of the poor 25. Los Angeles Times (1991a: var. 31; see also var. (Huber and Form 1973: 91; Schlozman and Verba 30); see also Roper (1986: vars. 4, 9, 29) and table 4.3. 1979: 168, 170), but surveys in the 1980s show con- 26. Harris (1970a: var. 1a; 1970b: var. 1a). flicting results (Roper 1986: vars. 42, 46; GSS 1987: 27. Lewis and Schneider (1985: 6, 7, 59); Roper (1986: vars. 507A, 507B; 1990–91: var. 387D). var. 46). Democracy’s E¤ects 473

in the 1970s, more poor than well-o¤ blacks The Third Tenet agreed that ‘‘the lot of the average man is getting worse.’’28 . . . [W]ithin each race, the higher one’s status, But despite this broad and deep pessimism, the more one feels in control of one’s own life. poor blacks are at present more cheerful about In 1962 almost half of low-status urban blacks, the past and future progress of their race than compared with only one-fourth of high-status are their well-o¤ counterparts. . . . urban blacks, demonstrated high ‘‘anomia.’’32 In short, the paradoxes of succeeding more Six times between 1961 and 1976, up to twice as and enjoying it less and remaining under the many poor as well-o¤ blacks agreed that ‘‘a per- spell of the great national suggestion hold with son has to live pretty much for today and let regard to the second tenet of the American tomorrow take care of itself.’’33 In 1968 poorly dream in two ways. First, although the best- educated blacks rated themselves less personally o¤ third of blacks became dramatically better competent than did blacks in general, whereas o¤ during the past three decades, they simulta- highly educated blacks deemed themselves much neously became much more cautious about more competent.34 Twenty years later, fewer anticipating success for their race. As the worst- badly-o¤ blacks than well-o¤ blacks or whites o¤ third of blacks became relatively or even ab- solutely worse o¤, they simultaneously became only a little more cautious about the likelihood Both paradoxes recur in African Americans’ evalua- that members of their race would achieve their tions of their race’s chances for political success. In 1961 well-o¤ blacks scored race relations in their com- dreams. Thus the two classes reversed positions. munity over the previous five years 4.1 out of 10. They Second, the paradoxes hold for comparisons predicted a score of 8.0 five years hence. Poor blacks across substantive topics as well as across time. scored past race relations higher (4.6) but future race During the 1980s and 1990s, well-o¤ African relations lower (7.1) (Matthews and Prothro 1961: Americans were relatively gratified and optimis- vars. 404, 406; see also Campbell and Schuman 1968: tic for themselves, the nation, and other groups vars. 258, 265, 271, 318). But by 1976 twice as many of Americans—but were worried for their race. poor as well-o¤ blacks thought there had been a lot of Conversely, poor African Americans were less civil rights change (Parent and Stekler 1985: 530; see gratified and optimistic for themselves, the na- also Gallup 1991b: var. 5). Similarly, in the 1960s more tion, and other Americans—but were more san- well-o¤ than poor blacks were hopeful about white attitudes toward ‘‘Negro rights’’; by 1984 slightly more guine for their race.30 well-o¤ than poor blacks doubted that American blacks will ‘‘ever achieve full social and economic 28. Since then, poor African Americans have become equality’’ (Brink and Harris 1964: 130; 1966: 258; slightly less discouraged and well-o¤ African Ameri- Brown et al. 1994: table 7.6; Sigelman and Welch 1991: cans slightly more so, so the two groups have con- 76). verged (GSS 1972–73, 1974, 1976–77, 1980, 1982, 32. Killian and Grigg (1962: 663). 1984–85, 1987, 1988–89, and 1990–91: var. 176B). See 33. Matthews and Prothro (1961: var. 427); Marx also Austin and Stack (1988: 363–66); Austin and (1964: var. 50L); Survey Research Center (1964: var. Dodge (1990). 50m); GSS (1972–73, 1974, 1976: var. 176A). See also 30. Despite their relative gratification, badly-o¤ Afri- Middleton (1963: 976); Campbell and Schuman (1968: can Americans, like well-o¤ African Americans, are vars. 176–78); Bullough (1972: 88). In all the surveys, generally skeptical about the prospects of success for whites showed the same class pattern but much lower their race. Thus neither income group contradicts the levels of agreement. findings of chapter 3 that blacks do not much trust the 34. Campbell et al. (1976: 453–54); see also Marx second tenet of the American dream when it does not (1964: var. 50h); Survey Research Center (1964: var. refer to them personally. See Schlozman and Verba 66b); NSBA (1980: vars. 72, 73). (1979) for a similar analysis. Chapter 8 474

of any class claimed that their situation was ‘‘succeeding more’’ does not obtain. Nevertheless within their control rather than a result of luck it remains psychologically and politically very or fate.35 important that well-o¤ African Americans use However, poor African Americans are more the third tenet to explain their own lives but not inclined, and well-o¤ African Americans less those of other blacks. inclined, to hold other people responsible for . . . [P]oor African Americans do precisely the their circumstances. Fully 90 percent of the for- reverse—they use the third tenet to explain the mer agreed in 1964 that ‘‘no weakness or di‰- lives of fellow blacks, even though they recognize culty can hold us back if we have enough will how little control they exercise over their own power,’’ and almost as many agreed that if one lives. Their faith in the American dream is as tries hard enough, one will succeed.36 In re- extraordinary, and in as much need of explana- peated questions since 1970, poor blacks usually tion, as is the lack of faith of the best-o¤ in their agree more than do rich blacks that people get race. ahead mainly through hard work rather than luck.37 That reversal is even clearer when African The Fourth Tenet Americans focus on explanations for racial dis- parities. On this topic, the higher one’s status, . . . This tenet changes the ideology of the Amer- the less likely one is to attribute blacks’ situation ican dream from a mere formula for getting to their own actions. . . . ahead into an ideal that Americans have found . . . Again we see racial di¤erences within each to be worth dying for. But startlingly few survey class and class di¤erences within each race. questions probe it. The previous chapter showed . . . [W]ell-o¤ blacks are least likely to hold that African Americans are arguably more com- African Americans directly responsible for their mitted to the pursuit of virtue (as well as to the unequal status.39 Thus the very group that seems pursuit of material goods) in their own lives than to exemplify the success of the American dream are white Americans, and that they are perhaps believes less than any other racial/class group less likely to equate material and spiritual suc- that the key to black success lies in black cess. But given the indistinctness of these pat- hands.40 That view has not changed since the terns, it is not surprising that class-based patterns 1960s, so the fullest version of the paradox of within each race are even less distinct. . . .

35. Roper (1986: var. 36); see also NSBA (1980: vars. 40. Explanations of class inequality show di¤erent 78, 79, 81); Hughes and Demo (1989: 146–47); Gloria patterns: among whites, more well-o¤ than poor blame Johnson (1989: 38–41). the poor and praise the rich for their respective cir- 36. Marx (1964: vars. 50a, 50m). Poor blacks may cumstances. Among blacks, in the 1960s the well-o¤ have simply been responding to the tautalogous nature also blamed the poor and praised the rich more than did the poor. But by the 1980s that pattern had dis- of these assertions. If so, they were more observant than high-status blacks, of whom about 10% fewer appeared, and none has emerged to take its place agreed with each statement. See also Survey Research (Survey Research Center 1964: var. 13C; Marx 1964: Center (1964: vars. 50a, 50n). vars. 50D, 50H; Alston and Dean 1972: 15; Huber and Form 1973: 101, 106; GSS 1972–73: var. 197; Schloz- less 37. Poor whites are slightly inclined than well-o¤ man and Verba 1979: 168; Jackman and Jackman whites to attribute success to hard work (GSS 1972–73, 1983: 56; GSS 1984: var. 68H; Lewis and Schneider 1974, 1976–77, 1980, 1982, 1984–85, 1987, 1988–89, 1985: 6–7; Kluegel and Smith 1986: 95–100; Harris 1990–91: var. 197; 1993: var. 458; for counterevidence 1986: table 5; Gallup 1988: var. 16; Harris 1989b: 164, see Survey Research Center 1964: var. 50I). 261; 1989c: 240; GSS 1990–91: vars. 197, 443A–C). 39. See also Richard Allen (1994). Democracy’s E¤ects 475

It is a risk both because middle-class African Implications of A¿uent and Poor Blacks’ Beliefs Americans are themselves increasingly important for the American Dream in the political, social, and economic life of the nation and because blacks have always led the We see now the outlines of the second threat way for other Americans in beliefs as in behav- to the future of the ideology of the American iors. The convictions of (mostly middle-class) dream. Blacks and whites increasingly diverge in blacks and their white allies led to the incor- their evaluations of whether the American dream poration of the ideal of equality into the Con- encompasses African Americans. . . . In addition, stitution in the mid-nineteenth century.46 One middle-class blacks are increasingly disillusioned hundred years later, the determination of (mostly with the very ideology of the dream itself, and middle-class) blacks and their white allies to poor blacks may not be far behind—that is the make that ideal a reality led to an expansion of message of this chapter. By the 1990s well-o¤ the political influence and legal rights of all blacks have come to doubt the reality of the women, children, and other previously excluded dream for African Americans. They have also groups. But we cannot assume that African become increasingly pessimistic about the future Americans lead other Americans only along of the dream in general, and more embittered paths that reinforce the American dream; they about American society than white Americans could as well show the way to suspicion and expect, given their class’s improved standing. bitterness. Poor African Americans are relatively less skep- The relative lack of disillusionment of poor tical about blacks’ chances to achieve their African Americans comprises the other threat to dreams, are only a little more pessimistic about the American dream revealed by disaggregation. the dream than they used to be, and are much The ideology has historically relied not only on less embittered about American society than the gratification of the upwardly mobile but also white (and well-o¤ black) Americans expect, on the pacification of the deeply poor. That is, given the deterioration of their circumstances. for the American dream’s vision of success for all Still, they show hints of increasing despair. to stabilize rather than destabilize American so- The ideology of the American dream has al- ciety, the poor must be enticed to believe in the ways relied on previously poor Americans not same process of upward mobility, with the same only achieving upward mobility, but also recog- consequent commitment to the nation at large, nizing that they had done so, feeling gratified, as the no longer poor. That, again very roughly and consequently deepening their commitment speaking, has been the experience of most immi- to the dream and the nation behind it. That, very grants not favored enough to join the middle roughly speaking, has been the experience of class. So far, that remains the experience of most most immigrants. But middle-class blacks are deeply poor African Americans. But any nightly not following the prescribed pattern. They rec- newscast suggests how fragile that continued ognize their own mobility, they are pleased by it, commitment is for those subject to drive-by but their commitment to the American dream is shootings and schools innocent of plumbing, let declining, not rising. That is an unprecedented alone textbooks. Thus if middle-class African risk to an ideology that depends so heavily on Americans may lead other Americans into disil- faith in its ultimate fairness and benevolence.45 lusionment with the ideology despite their suc- cess, so a few poor African Americans may, with 45. For a similar alarm, absent my ambivalence about the value of the American dream, see People for the American Way (1992: e.g., 52). 46. Katz (1988). Chapter 8 476

even greater reason, lead other poor Americans Austin, Roy, and Steven Stack (1988) ‘‘Race, Class, into a rejection of the dream that will make af- and Opportunity: Changing Realities and Percep- fluent alienation seem trivial. tions,’’ Sociological Q. 29, 3: 357–369. Let me repeat: whether one sees these threats Austin, Roy, and Hiroko Dodge (1990) ‘‘Despair, to the American dream as a revelation of hypo- Distrust and Dissatisfaction among Blacks and critical class and racial domination or as an at- Women, 1973–1987,’’ paper at the annual meeting of tack on ‘‘the last, best hope on Earth’’ (or as the ASA, Washington, D.C. something in between) depends on one’s judg- Brink, William, and Louis Harris (1966) Black and White ment about Americans’ potential to make their (Simon and Schuster). ideology live up to its own best values. It also Brown, Ronald, et al. (1994) The 1984–1988 National depends on one’s judgment about its likely re- Black Election Panel Study [NBES]: A Sourcebook (U. of Michigan, Institute for Social Research). placement. But that subject comes later. . . . Bullough, Bonnie (1972) ‘‘Alienation in the Ghetto,’’ in Charles Bullock III and Harrell Rodgers, Jr., eds., Works Cited Black Political Attitudes (Markham), 83–96. CBS News/NYT (1978) ‘‘The Kerner Commission— Abbreviations Ten Years Later,’’ Feb. 16–19. ——— (1992) ‘‘May National Poll,’’ May 6–8. AJPS American Journal of Political Science Campbell, Angus, and Howard Schuman (1968) ‘‘Ra- AJS American Journal of Sociology cial Attitudes in Fifteen American Cities,’’ for Na- APSR American Political Science Review tional Advisory Commission on Civil Disorders (U. of ASR American Sociological Review Michigan, Institute for Social Research), Jan.–March. NYT New York Times Campbell, Angus, , and Willard Rod- APSA American Political Science Association gers (1976) The Quality of American Life (Russell Sage Foundation). ASA American Sociological Association IRP Institute for Research on Poverty Campbell, Bruce (1980) ‘‘The Interaction of Race and Socioeconomic Status in the Development of Political MWPSA Midwest Political Science Association Attitudes,’’ Social Science Q. 60, 4: 651–658. NBER National Bureau of Economic Research Carr, Leslie and John Hudgins (c. 1989) ‘‘Race, Class, USGPO United States Government Printing O‰ce and External Political E‰cacy’’ (Old Dominion U., ABC News/Washington Post (1989) ‘‘ABC News/ Dept. of Sociology). Washington Post 9/89 Poll,’’ Sept. 28–Oct. 3. Cavanagh, Thomas (1985) Inside Black America: The ——— (1990) ‘‘ABC News/Washington Post Poll: Message of the Black Vote in the 1984 Elections (Joint Omnibus-September 1990,’’ Step. 20–24. Center for Political Studies). Aberbach, Joel, and Jack Walker (1970b) ‘‘Political Citrin, Jack, Beth Reingold, and Donald Green Trust and Racial Ideology,’’ APSR 64, 4: 1199–1219. (1990) ‘‘American Identity and the Politics of Ethnic Adams, James, and William Dressler (1988) ‘‘Percep- Change,’’ J. of Politics 52, 4: 1124–1154. tions of Injustice in a Black Community,’’ Human Colasanto, Diane (1988) ‘‘Black Attitudes,’’ Public Relations 41, 10: 753–767. Opinion 10, 5: 45–49. Allen, Richard (1994) ‘‘Structural Equality in Black Converse, Philip et al. (1980) American Social Attitudes and White,’’ Howard J. of Communication 5, 1–2: Data Sourcebook, 1947–1978 (Harvard U. Press). 69–91. Dawson, Michael (1994b) Behind the Mule: Race and Alston, Jon, and K. Imogene Dean (1972) ‘‘Socioeco- Class in African American Politics (Princeton U. Press). nomic Factors Associated with Attitudes toward Wel- Denton, Herbert, and Barry Sussman (1981) ‘‘‘Cross- fare Recipients and the Causes of Poverty,’’ Social over Generation’ of Blacks Expresses Most Distrust of Service R. 46, 1: 13–23. Whites,’’ Washington Post, Mar. 25: A1, A2. Democracy’s E¤ects 477

Erskine, Hazel (1962) ‘‘The Polls: Race Relations,’’ ——— (1970b) ‘‘American Women’s Opinion Survey Public Opinion Q. 26, 1: 137–148. [Men],’’ for the Virginia Slim Division of Liggett and ——— (1969a) ‘‘The Polls: Negro Philosophies of Meyers, Aug. Life,’’ Public Opinion Q. 33, 1: 147–158. ——— (1978) A Study of Attitudes toward Racial and Franklin, V. P. (1985) ‘‘From Integration to Black Religious Minorities and Toward Women, for National Self-Determination,’’ in Margaret Spencer, Geraldine Conference of Christians and Jews, Nov. Brookins, and Walter Allen, eds., Beginnings: The ——— (1986b) ‘‘Children’s Needs and Public Re- Social and A¤ective Development of Black Children sponsibilities,’’ for Group W—Westinghouse Broad- (Erlbaum), 19–28. casting Co., Sept. Gallup, George, ed. (1987) Gallup Poll: Public Opinion, ——— (1988) ‘‘A Nation Divided on Black Progress,’’ 1987 (Wilmington: Scholarly Resources). for Business Week/Harris Poll, Jan. 20–26. Gallup Organization (1961) ‘‘The Gallup Poll,’’ June Harris, Louis, and Associates (1989b) The Unfinished 23–28. Agenda on Race in America, vol. 2, for NAACP Legal Gallup Organization (1963) ‘‘The Gallup Poll,’’ May Defense and Educational Fund, June–Sept. 1988. 23–28. ——— (1989c) The Unfinished Agenda on Race in ——— (1964) ‘‘Hopes and Fears,’’ for Potomac Asso- America (unpublished tables). ciates, Oct. ——— (1990) ‘‘The View from the Trenches,’’ June. ——— (1988) ‘‘Gallup/Newsweek Poll: Race Rela- Hochschild, Jennifer (1981) What’s Fair? American tions,’’ for Newsweek, Feb. 19–22. Beliefs about Distributive Justice (Harvard U. Press). ——— (1991b) ‘‘Gallup News Service Survey: June ——— (1988) ‘‘The Double-Edged Sword of Equal Omnibus, Wave 2,’’ June 13–16. Opportunity,’’ in Ian Shapiro and Grant Reeher, eds., ——— (1992) ‘‘Gallup News Service Survey: May Power, Inequality, and Democratic Politics (Westview Omnibus, Wave 1,’’ May 7–10. Press), 168–200. ——— (1994) ‘‘CNN/USA Today—Report Card #5,’’ Huber, Joan, and William Form (1973) Income and for CNN/USA Today, April. Ideology (Free Press). Gilliam, Franklin Jr. (1986) ‘‘Black America: Divided Hughes, Michael, and David Demo (1989) ‘‘Self- by Class?’’ Public Opinion 9, 1: 53–57. Perceptions of Black Americans,’’ AJS 95, 1: 132–159. Goldman, Peter (1969) Report from Black America Hutcheson, John (1973) Racial Attitudes in Atlanta (Simon and Schuster). (Emory U., Center for Research in Social Change). Gordon S. Black Corporation (1989a) ‘‘USA Today Jackman, Mary, and Robert Jackman (1983) Class Poll: Racism,’’ for USA Today, Aug. 30–31. Awareness in the United States (U. of California Press). Gurin, Patricia, Shirley Hatchett, and James Jackson Johnson, Gloria (1989) ‘‘Estimated Reference Group (1989) Hope and Independence: Blacks’ Response to E¤ects of Underemployment and Underpayment on Electoral and Party Politics (Russell Sage Foundation). Psychosocial Functioning among Working Men,’’ Na- tional J. of Sociology Harris, Louis (1986) ‘‘Yuppie Lifestyle Felt To Be 3, 1: 25–50. Unattractive to Americans’’ (N. Y.: Harris Survey), Joint Center for Political Studies (1984) ‘‘JCPS Feb. 3. Releases In-Depth Survey of Black Political Atti- Harris, Louis, and Associates (1966a) ‘‘Racial Survey: tudes,’’ press release, August 30. Black Sample,’’ for Newsweek, June. Katz, Stanley (1988) ‘‘The Strange Birth and Unlikely Journal of Ameri- ——— (1966b) ‘‘Racial Survey: Random Sample,’’ for History of Constitutional Equality,’’ can History 75(3): 747–762. Newsweek, June. Killian, Lewis, and Charles Grigg (1962) ‘‘Urbanism, ——— (1968) ‘‘College Student Peace Corps Survey: AJS Black Sample.’’ Race, and Anomia,’’ 67, 6: 661–665. Beliefs about ——— (1970a) ‘‘American Women’s Opinion Survey Kluegel, James, and Eliot Smith (1986) Inequality [Women],’’ for the Virginia Slim Division of Liggett (Aldine de Gruyter). and Meyers, Aug. Langton, Kenneth, and M. Kent Jennings (1972) ‘‘Po- litical Socialization and the High School Civics Cur- Chapter 8 478

riculum in the United States,’’ In Charles Bullock III Black Community,’’ Western Political Q. 38, 4: 521– and Harrell Rodgers, Jr., eds., Black Political Attitudes 538. (Markham), 60–71. People for the American Way (1992) Democracy’s Lewis, I. A., and William Schneider (1983) ‘‘Black Next Generation II: A Study of American Youth on Voting, Bloc Voting, and the Democrats,’’ Public Race (Washington, D.C.: People for the American Opinion 6, 5: 12–15, 59. Way). Los Angeles Times (1983) Poll no. 71: ‘‘National Sur- Pettigrew, Thomas (1964) A Profile of the Negro vey,’’ Sept. 18–22. American (Van Nostrand). ——— (1991a) untitled, June 28–30. Reese, Laura, and Ronald Brown (1995) ‘‘The E¤ects ——— (1991b) Poll no. 259: ‘‘Judge Thomas, Race of Religious Messages on Racial Identity and System Relations and Ronald Reagan,’’ Sept. 21–25. Blame among African Americans,’’ J. of Politics 57, 1: McClosky, Herbert, and John Zaller (1984) The 24–43. American Ethos: Public Attitudes toward Capitalism Roper Organization (1986) ‘‘The American Dream and Democracy (Harvard U. Press). Survey,’’ for the Wall Street J., Oct. McLeod, Ramon (1988b) ‘‘Di¤erent Views of Gains by Schlozman, Kay, and Sidney Verba (1979) Injury to Blacks,’’ San Francisco Chronicle, Mar. 30: A1, A4. Insult: Unemployment, Class, and Political Response (Harvard U. Press). Marshall, Nancy, and Rosalind Barnett (1991) ‘‘Race, Class and Multiple Role Strains among Women Schuman, Howard, and Shirley Hatchett (1974) Black Employed in the Service Sector,’’ Women and Health Racial Attitudes (U. of Michigan, Institute for Social 17, 4: 1–19. Research). Marx, Gary (1964) ‘‘Negro Political Attitudes’’ (also Schuman, Howard, Charlotte Steeh, and Lawrence titled ‘‘Anti-Semitism—Negro Oversample’’) (U. of Bobo (1988) Racial Attitudes in America (Harvard U. California, Berkeley, Survey Research Center). Press). ——— (1969) Protest and Prejudice: A Study of Belief Searles, Ruth, and J. Allen Williams Jr. (1962) ‘‘Negro in the Black Community (Harper Torchbooks). College Students’ Participation in Sit-ins,’’ Social Forces 40, 3: 215–220. Matthews, Donald, and James Prothro (1961) ‘‘The Negro Political Participation Study’’ (U. of North Shingles, Richard (1981) ‘‘Black Consciousness and Carolina), March–June. Political Participation,’’ APSR 75, 1: 76–91. Media General/Associated Press (1988) ‘‘National Poll Sigelman, Lee, and Susan Welch (1991) Black Ameri- #21,’’ June 22–July 3. cans’ Views of Racial Inequality (Cambridge U. Press). Middleton, Russell (1963) ‘‘Alienation, Race, and Ed- Smith, Robert (1988) ‘‘Sources of Urban Ethnic Poli- ucation’’ ASR 28, 6: 973–977. tics,’’ Research in Race and Ethnic Relations (JAI Myrdal, Gunnar (1944) An American Dilemma Press), 5: 159–191. (Harper & Brothers). Smith, Robert, and Richard Seltzer (1992) Race, Class, and Culture: A Study in Afro-American Mass Opinion NBC News (1989a) ‘‘R.A.C.E.—Racial Attitudes and (SUNY Press). Consciousness Exam’’ (N. Y.: NBC News). Sniderman, Paul, Philip Tetlock, and Thomas Piazza National Conference (1994) Taking America’s Pulse: The Full Report of the National Conference Survey on (1991) ‘‘Race and Politics Survey’’ (U. of California, Inter-Group Relations, by LH Research (N. Y.: Na- Berkeley, Survey Research Center), Feb. 1–Nov. 21. tional Conference of Christians and Jews). Survey Research Center, U. of California, Berkeley (1964) ‘‘Anti-Semitism in the United States,’’ for Anti- NYT/WCBS News (1985) ‘‘New York City Race Relations Survey,’’ April 27–May 3. Defamation League of B’Nai B’rith, Oct. From Protest to Politics: The NYT/WCBS-TV Channel 2 News (1994) ‘‘New York Tate, Katherine (1993) New Black Voters in American Elections City Poll,’’ June 12–15. (Harvard U. Press). Parent, T. Wayne, and Paul Stekler (1985) ‘‘The Polit- Taylor, D. Garth (1993) 1993 Metro Survey Report ical Implications of Economic Stratification in the (Metropolitan Chicago Information Center). Democracy’s E¤ects 479

——— (1994) 1994 Metro Survey Report (Metropoli- tan Chicago Information Center). ‘‘Thirty Years after ‘I Have a Dream’’’ (1993) The Polling Report 9, 18 (Sept. 13): 2. Verba, Sidney, and Gary Orren (1985) Equality in America: The View From the Top (Harvard U. Press). Washington Post (1992) ‘‘Washington Post Poll: Race Relations,’’ Feb. 28–Mar. 3. Welch, Susan, et al. (1994) ‘‘Justice for All: Still an American Dilemma,’’ Challenge 5, 1: 19–37. Wright, James (1976) The Dissent of the Governed: Alienation and Democracy in America (Academic Press). Yankelovich Clancy Shulman (1992) ‘‘Rodney King Verdict and the Los Angeles Riots,’’ for Time and Cable News Network, April 30. Beyond Tocqueville, Myrdal, and Hartz: The Multiple Traditions in America

Rogers M. Smith

Since the nation’s inception, analysts have and conditions that have shaped the participants described American political culture as the pre- and the substance of American politics just as eminent example of modern liberal democracy, deeply. For over 80% of U.S. history, its laws of government by popular consent with respect declared most of the world’s population to be for the equal rights of all. They have portrayed ineligible for full American citizenship solely be- American political development as the working cause of their race, original nationality, or gen- out of liberal democratic or republican princi- der. For at least two-thirds of American history, ples, via both ‘‘liberalizing’’ and ‘‘democratiz- the majority of the domestic adult population ing’’ socioeconomic changes and political e¤orts was also ineligible for full citizenship for the to cope with tensions inherent in these principles. same reasons. Contrary to Tocquevillian views Illiberal, undemocratic beliefs and practices have of American civic identity, it did not matter how usually been seen only as expressions of igno- ‘‘liberal,’’ ‘‘democratic,’’ or ‘‘republican’’ those rance and prejudice, destined to marginality by persons’ beliefs were.1 their lack of rational defenses. A distinguished line of writers, from Hector St. John Crevecoeur 1. The percentage varies according to whether one in the eighteenth century and Harriet Martineau dates the United States from 1776, the Declaration of and Lord Bryce in the nineteenth century to Independence, or 1789, the ratified Constitution. State Gunnar Myrdal and Louis Hartz in the twen- policies prior to 1789 on the whole made nonwhites tieth century serves as authority for this view. and women ineligible for full citizenship. Women could Today, leading social scientists such as Samuel always formally be U.S. citizens, but they were almost P. Huntington, Walter Dean Burnham, and Ira universally denied the vote until 1920, making them clearly second-class citizens. Other overt legal discrim- Katznelson, legal scholars, historians, and cul- inations on their political and economic rights con- tural analysts such as Kenneth Karst, John Dig- tinued through the 1960s. Naturalization was confined gins, and Sacvan Bercovitch, and many others to whites from 1790 through 1868 and closed to most still structure their accounts on these premises. Asian nationals until 1952. By then, the national ori- Virtually all appeal to the classic analysis of gins quota system of immigration restrictions, enacted American politics, Tocqueville’s Democracy in in the 1920s, prevented most Asians and many south- America. ern Europeans from coming to the United States and Tocqueville’s thesis—that America has been becoming permanent residents or citizens, explicitly most shaped by the unusually free and egali- because of their original nationality or ethnicity. That tarian ideas and material conditions that pre- system was not repealed until 1965. Despite formal constitutional guarantees enacted in the mid-1860s, vailed at its founding—captures important truths. blacks were also widely denied basic rights of citizen- Nonetheless, the purpose of this essay is to chal- ship until the 1964 Civil Rights Act and the 1965 Vot- lenge that thesis by showing that its adherents ing Rights Act (Higham 1975, 29–66; Kettner 1978, fail to give due weight to inegalitarian ideologies 287–322; Smith 1989). Thus, though the specifics changed, denials of access to full citizenship based Excerpted from: Rogers M. Smith, ‘‘Beyond Tocque- explicitly on race, ethnicity, or gender always denied ville, Myrdal, and Hartz: The Multiple Traditions in large majorities of the world’s population any oppor- America.’’ American Political Science Review 87, no. 3 tunity for U.S. citizenship up to 1965. That represents (1993): 549–566. 6 American Political Science Associ- about 83% of the nation’s history since the Constitu- ation. Reprinted with the permission of the American tion, 88% since the Declaration of Independence. If, Political Science Association and Cambridge Univer- controversially, one assumes that women became full sity Press. citizens with the vote in 1920, then a majority of the Democracy’s E¤ects 481

The Tocquevillian story is thus deceptive be- created by God to be morally and politically, as cause it is too narrow. It is centered on rela- well as theologically, superior to Catholics, Jews, tionships among a minority of Americans (white Muslims, and others. men, largely of northern European ancestry) These beliefs were not merely emotional prej- analyzed via reference to categories derived from udices or ‘‘attitudes.’’ Over time, American the hierarchy of political and economic statuses intellectual and political elites elaborated dis- men have held in Europe: monarchs and aristo- tinctive justifications for these ascriptive systems, crats, commercial burghers, farmers, industrial including inegalitarian scriptural readings, the and rural laborers, and indigents. Because most scientific racism of the ‘‘American school’’ of European observers and British American men ethnology, racial and sexual Darwinism, and the have regarded these categories as politically fun- romantic cult of Anglo–Saxonism in American damental, it is understandable that they have al- historiography. All these discourses identified the ways found the most striking fact about the new true meaning of Americanism with particular nation to be its lack of one type of ascriptive hi- forms of cultural, religious, ethnic, and especially erarchy. There was no hereditary monarchy or racial and gender hierarchies.3 Many adherents nobility native to British America, and the revo- of ascriptive Americanist outlooks insisted that lutionaries rejected both the authority of the the nation’s political and economic structures British king and aristocracy and the creation of should formally reflect natural and cultural in- any new American substitutes. Those features of equalities, even at the cost of violating doctrines American political life made the United States of universal rights. Although these views never appear remarkably egalitarian by comparison entirely prevailed, their impact has been wide with Europe. and deep. But the comparative moral, material, and po- Thus to approach a truer picture of America’s litical egalitarianism that prevailed at the found- political culture and its characteristic conflicts, ing among moderately propertied white men was we must consider more than the familiar cate- surrounded by an array of other fixed, ascrip- gories of (absent) feudalism and socialism and tive systems of unequal status, all largely un- (pervasive) bourgeois liberalism and republican- challenged by the American revolutionaries.2 ism. The nation has also been deeply constituted Men were thought naturally suited to rule over by the ideologies and practices that defined women, within both the family and the polity. the relationships of the white male minority with White northern Europeans were thought supe- rior culturally—and probably biologically—to 3. From early on, many American intellectuals and black Africans, bronze Native Americans, and politicians believed that ‘‘like the Chain of Being, the indeed all other races and civilizations. Many races of man consisted of an ordered hierarchy’’ (Hal- British Americans also treated religion as an ler 1971, 11; Russett 1989, 201–3). Some believed in a inherited condition and regarded Protestants as natural order of rank among the races, some that cul- tures fell into a higher and lower levels of civilization. Most thought race and culture linked. Scholars dis- domestic adult population became legally eligible for agreed about the relative ranks of Asiatics, blacks, full citizenship then. This still means that a majority of Native Americans, and other races and cultures, but domestic adults were ineligible for full citizenship on these gradations mattered less than the supremacy of racial, ethnic, or gender grounds for about two-thirds whites over nonwhites. Mulattoes, for example, were of U.S. history (from either starting point). legally treated as an intermediate racial group in ante- 2. Orren (1991), a major alternative critique of bellum America, but by the 1850s whites began to re- Tocquevillian accounts, shows ascriptive inegalitarian duce their status to that of ‘‘pure’’ blacks (Williamson labor systems long prevailed even among white men. 1980). Chapter 8 482

subordinate groups, and the relationships of over contradictions among these traditions, al- these groups with each other. When these ele- most all have tried to embrace what they saw as ments are kept in view, the flat plain of Ameri- the best features of each. can egalitarianism mapped by Tocqueville and Ascriptive outlooks have had such a hold in others suddenly looks quite di¤erent. We instead America because they have provided something perceive America’s initial conditions as exhibit- that neither liberalism nor republicanism has ing only a rather small, recently leveled valley of done so well. They have o¤ered creditable in- relative equality nestled amid steep mountains of tellectual and psychological reasons for many hierarchy. And though we can see forces work- Americans to believe that their social roles and ing to erode those mountains over time, broad- personal characteristics express an identity that ening the valley, many of the peaks also prove to has inherent and transcendant worth, thanks to be volcanic, frequently responding to seismic nature, history, and God. Those rationales have pressures with outbursts that harden into sub- obviously aided those who sat atop the nation’s stantial peaks once again. political, economic, and social hierarchies. But To be sure, America’s ascriptive, unequal sta- many Americans besides elites have felt that they tuses, and the ideologies by which they have have gained meaning, as well as material and been defended have always been heavily condi- political benefits, from their nation’s traditional tioned and constrained by the presence of liberal structures of ascribed places and destinies. democratic values and institutions. The reverse, Conventional narratives, preoccupied with the however, is also true. Although liberal demo- absence of aristocracy and socialism, usually cratic ideas and practices have been more potent stress the liberal and democratic elements in the in America than elsewhere, American politics is rhetoric of even America’s dissenters (Hartog best seen as expressing the interaction of multiple 1987). These accounts fail to explain how and political traditions, including liberalism, repub- why liberalizing e¤orts have frequently lost to licanism, and ascriptive forms of Americanism, forces favoring new forms of racial and gender which have collectively comprised American po- hierarchy. Those forces have sometimes negated litical culture, without any constituting it as a major liberal victories, especially in the half- whole.4 Though Americans have often struggled century following Reconstruction; and the fate of that era may be finding echoes today. 4. A tradition here is comprised by (1) a worldview or My chief aim here is to persuade readers that ideology that defines basic political and economic many leading accounts of American political institutions, the persons eligible to participate in them, culture are inadequate. I will also suggest briefly and the roles or rights to which they are entitled and (2) how analyses with greater descriptive and ex- institutions and practices embodying and reproducing planatory power can be achieved by replacing those precepts. Hence traditions are not merely sets of the Tocquevillian thesis with a multiple-traditions ideas. The liberal tradition involves limited govern- view of America. This argument is relevant to ment, the rule of law protecting individual rights, and contemporary politics in two ways. First, it a market economy, all o‰cially open to all minimally rational adults. The republican tradition is grounded raises the possibility that novel intellectual, po- on popular sovereignty exercised via institutions of mass self-governance. It includes an ethos of civic vir- whites and women should be governed as subjects or tue and economic regulation for the public good. second-class citizens, denied full market rights, and Adherents of what I term ascriptive Americanist tradi- sometimes excluded from the nation altogether. My tions believe true Americans are in some way ‘‘chosen’’ thesis—that an evolving mix of these traditions is visi- by God, history, or nature to possess superior moral ble in America’s political culture, institutions, and the and intellectual traits, often associated with race and outlooks of Americans of all backgrounds—is indebted gender. Hence many Americanists believe that non- to Orren and Skowronek 1993. Democracy’s E¤ects 483

litical, and legal systems reinforcing racial, eth- namely, ‘‘the equality of conditions.’’ This ‘‘fact’’ nic, and gender inequalities might be rebuilt in absorbed Tocqueville’s interest because he saw a America in the years ahead. That prospect does democratic revolution taking place in Europe, not seem plausible if the United States has al- especially in France, breaking down the power ways been essentially liberal democratic, with all of nobles and kings. In the United States this exceptions marginal and steadily eliminated. It revolution seemed ‘‘almost to have reached its seems quite real, however, if liberal democratic natural limits.’’ Thus, by studying America, traditions have been but contested parts of Tocqueville could draw lessons for the future of American culture, with inegalitarian ideologies his own nation and all of European culture and practices often resurging even after major (1969, 9–12, 18). . . . enhancements of liberal democracy. Second, the The impact of Tocqueville’s thesis on mod- political implications of the view that America ern American scholarship was magnified by has never been completely liberal, and that two among many works applying his ideas to changes have come only through di‰cult strug- twentieth-century politics, though in ways that gles and then have often not been sustained, are compounded his deficiencies.5 Each stressed one very di¤erent from the complacency—sometimes aspect of Tocqueville’s account of America’s despair—engendered by beliefs that liberal de- point of departure. First, Gunnar Myrdal’s mocracy has always been hegemonic. (1944) study of American race relations empha- I shall review and critique Tocqueville’s ac- sized the ideals of Enlightenment ‘‘humanistic count of the sources and dynamics shaping de- liberalism.’’ Elaborated by revolutionary leaders mocracy in America, along with two of the most to define and justify their cause, these beliefs be- influential extensions of Tocquevillian analysis in came, in Myrdal’s view, the tenets of the Ameri- modern social science, Gunnar Myrdal’s (1944) can Creed and represented to Americans the American Dilemma and Louis Hartz’s (1955) essential meaning of their struggle for indepen- Liberal Tradition in America. I argue that Toc- dence. It thus served as the cement of the nation, queville himself was much more perceptive than written into all the basic documents comprising his modern ‘‘Tocquevillian’’ followers, though the highest law of the land. This democratic not free from the problems identified here. I shall creed proclaimed the worth and moral equality note how Tocquevillian premises continue to of all individual human beings and their ‘‘in- flaw recent scholarship, especially general works alienable rights to freedom, justice, and a fair on American political identity and citizenship. opportunity.’’ It also denounced ‘‘di¤erences Finally, I shall illustrate the merits of a multiple- made on account of ‘race, creed or color’’’ traditions approach by showing how it o¤ers (pp. 3–4, 7–8, 25, 52). . . . more insight into the qualified but extensive If Myrdal stressed Tocqueville’s argument creation of new systems of ascriptive inequality that early Americans were shaped by egalitarian during the post-Reconstruction and Progressive Enlightenment ideals, Louis Hartz (1955) em- eras. phasized Tocqueville’s account of America’s rel- atively egalitarian and free economic and social conditions. Americans’ lack of feudal institu- The Tocquevillian Thesis tions, classes, and their lived experience of ‘‘atomistic social freedom’’ made the U.S. a Tocqueville began Democracy in America by liberal society. Hartz viewed the presence of calling attention to the immense influence of one ‘‘basic fact’’ that was the creative element from 5. Other major Tocquevillian works include Daniel which each particular fact—and, indeed, the Boorstin’s (1953) Genius of American Politics and S. whole course—of American society is derived, M. Lipset’s (1963) First new Nation. Chapter 8 484

‘‘the liberal idea’’ among early Americans as relegated blacks and Native Americans to the important, but he did not think it was con- status of ‘‘tangents,’’ however important; and sciousness of a specific ideological heritage that he obscured the intellectual respectability of rac- made Americans liberal. Most were instinctive— ism, deeming it only prejudice. Worst of all, he even ‘‘irrational’’—Lockeans, all the more so claimed to reconcile the inferior civic status of because they had no real awareness of any alter- women with democracy by accepting their con- natives. Their comparatively nonascriptive, non- finement to domestic roles as natural. Hence he hierarchical conditions led most Americans to made America seem much more fully a liberal regard liberal beliefs in individual rights and democracy than it was. The less comprehensive liberties, petit bourgeois democracy, and Hor- analyses of Myrdal and Hartz intensified all atio Alger myths of economic mobility as self- these failings. evident. Far more than Myrdal and even more Both were completely silent on women. . . . than Tocqueville, Hartz bemoaned the fixed, Hartz’s mature answer . . . was closer to Myr- dogmatic character of this liberalism born ‘‘of a dal’s. Despite the contrary judgments in his ear- liberal way of life,’’ seeing it as a tyranny of lier book, it turned out that American defenses unanimity that went much deeper than mere of racial inequality were structured in liberal tyranny of the majority. He believed the absence terms after all. And on liberal premises, Ameri- of any real sense of class and the wide regard of cans could only justify racial inequalities by middle-class values as natural supported Mc- denying the humanity of blacks. Carthyite antisocialist policies in domestic and This response remained wholly inadequate. It foreign a¤airs in the early 1950s (pp. 6–23, 35– did not begin to account for why, even after 36, 46, 51, 58, 62–63, 66, 284–309). . . . constitutional recognition of the humanity of Thus, Tocqueville, Myrdal, and Hartz di¤ered blacks, Americans created new systems of racial mildly in their accounts of just why American inequality a¤ecting not only blacks but all non- political culture was pervasively liberal demo- white peoples and maintained them through cratic and more significantly in their assessments much of the twentieth century. Hartz’s appeal of the desirability of that culture. But collec- to recent civil rights struggles left too much his- tively, their arguments powerfully reinforced tory unexplained. That shortcoming reflected the beliefs that the United States’ core values should deeper failure of his whole analysis: If ‘‘Euro- be so described. Yet all wrote at times when the pean ideologies’’ such as liberalism did not know nation was still denying most persons access to race, where did the category of ‘‘race’’ come full standing within the American political com- from that they had to take into account? Why munity on racial, ethnic, or gender grounds. had this ‘‘unknown’’ (and biologically inde- Their ability to stress the democratic nature of fensible) classification been a ‘‘central conscious American values despite these facts is vivid testi- preoccupation’’ throughout U.S. history? The mony to how their focus on the absence of a answer is that it had been burned into American European class system led them to minimize the minds by prestigious intellectual traditions, most significance of other types of ascriptive inequal- of them inarguably nonliberal, that defended ity. Each of them did, however, take some notice subjugation of nonwhites by contending that of America’s exclusionary practices and beliefs, humanity was naturally divided into hierarchi- again in influential ways. . . . cally arrayed ‘‘races.’’ There had always been On close analysis, then, Tocqueville showed much in America’s basic institutions, popular a rich awareness of how limited democracy was sentiments, and moral orthodoxies that rendered in America. But like his successors, he still those traditions compelling. . . . frequently wrote in unqualified terms about In an era marked by controversies over multi- America’s supposedly egalitarian conditions; he culturalism, one might expect the limitations of Democracy’s E¤ects 485

Tocqueville, Hartz, and Myrdal to have long tions of democracy and universal rights, most since been superseded. But for many in the social have not; and though many have tried to blend sciences and the humanities, these Tocquevillian those commitments with exclusionary ascriptive arguments still provide the deep structure within views, the illogic of these mixes has repeatedly which they debate real but lesser di¤erences.6 ... proven a major resource for successful reformers. None of these mainstream approaches to But we obscure the di‰culty of those reforms American politics has given prominence to the (and thereby diminish their significance) if we racial, ethnic, or gender makeup of the Ameri- slight the ideological and political appeal of can citizenry, though neither have they wholly contrary ascriptive traditions by portraying them avoided those issues. In the last three decades, as merely the shadowy side of a hegemonic lib- however, many other scholars have greatly en- eral republicanism. riched understanding of the ethnocultural dimen- At its heart, the multiple-traditions thesis sions of American life. Much of this research holds that the definitive feature of American po- provides evidence for a multiple-traditions ac- litical culture has been not its liberal, republican, count of American politics. But few of these or ‘‘ascriptive Americanist’’ elements but, rather, scholars have addressed the significance of their this more complex pattern of apparently incon- findings for general views of America. And, sistent combinations of the traditions, accom- perhaps because of the real if partial truths panied by recurring conflicts. Because standard grasped by the Tocquevillian orthodoxy, those accounts neglect this pattern, they do not explore who have done so have usually tried to accom- how and why Americans have tried to uphold modate it, not to challenge it. . . . aspects of all three of these heterogeneous tradi- Above all, recognition of the strong attrac- tions in combinations that are longer on political tions of restrictive Americanist ideas does not and psychological appeal than on intellectual imply any denial that America’s liberal and coherency. democratic traditions have had great normative A focus on these questions generates an un- and political potency, even if they have not been derstanding of American politics that di¤ers so hegemonic as some claim.9 Instead, it sheds a from Tocquevillian ones in four major respects. new—and, in some respects, more flattering— First, on this view, purely liberal and republi- light on the constitutive role of liberal demo- can conceptions of civic identity are seen as cratic values in American life. Although some frequently unsatisfying to many Americans, be- Americans have been willing to repudiate no- cause they contain elements that threaten, rather than a‰rm, sincere, reputable beliefs in the pro- 6. As a full survey of pertinent works is impossible, I priety of the privileged positions that whites, shall note some broad categories of scholarship in Christianity, Anglo–Saxon traditions, and patri- which most participants employ a misleading Tocque- archy have had in the United States. At the same villian framework, focusing on recent general discus- time, even Americans deeply attached to those sions of American political culture and citizenship, inegalitarian arrangements have also had liberal where the limits of Tocquevillian premises are most democratic values. Second, it has therefore been damaging. typical, not aberrational, for Americans to em- 9. I also agree that tensions between liberal and dem- body strikingly opposed beliefs in their institu- ocratic ideas and institutions have been vital factors in tions, such as doctrines that blacks should and American history, visible, for example, in the great should not be full and equal citizens. But though struggles between the defenders of property rights and populist and labor movements. Those conflicts have, American e¤orts to blend aspects of opposing however, also always involved battles over the nation’s views have often been remarkably stable, the racial, ethnic, and gender ordering. resulting tensions have still been important Chapter 8 486

sources of change. Third, when older types of right. Over the past two decades women had be- ascriptive inequality, such as slavery, have been come more politically engaged and had begun to rejected as unduly illiberal, it has been normal, gain respect as political actors. not anomalous, for many Americans to embrace Confronted with these developments, what new doctrines and institutions that reinvigorate would Tocquevillian analysts have predicted for the hierarchies they esteem in modified form. the next half-century of American life? Louis Changes toward greater inequality and exclu- Hartz would have insisted that so long as the sion, as well as toward greater equality and in- humanity of blacks, other races, and women was clusiveness, thus can and do occur. Finally, the publicly acknowledged, the United States would dynamics of American development cannot sim- have to grant them equal access to full citizen- ply be seen as a rising tide of liberalizing forces ship. Myrdal, Karst, and Fuchs would have progressively submerging contrary beliefs and anticipated that surviving prejudices might pro- practices. The national course has been more duce resistance to implementation of the new serpentine. The economic, political, and moral legal expressions of the American Creed; but forces propelling the United States toward lib- they would expect this opposition to be gradu- eral democracy have often been heeded by ally, if painfully, overcome. Tocqueville on the American leaders, especially since World War II. other hand, would have been too pessimistic. He But the currents pulling toward fuller expression would have deplored the intrusion of women of alleged natural and cultural inequalities have into politics, expected Native Americans to con- also always won victories. In some eras they tinue toward extinction, and foreseen deepen- have predominated, appearing to define not only ing conflicts between whites and blacks that the path of safety but that of progress. In all would probably end in some sort of destructive eras, including our own, many Americans have cataclysm. combined their allegiance to liberal democracy None would have had the intellectual re- with beliefs that the presence of certain groups sources to explain what in fact occurred. Over favored by history, nature, and God has made the next fifty years, Americans did not make Americans an intrinsically ‘‘special’’ people. blacks, women, and members of other races Their adherents have usually regarded such full and equal citizens, nor did racial and gender beliefs as benign and intellectually well founded; prejudices undergo major erosion. Neither, how- yet they also have always had more or less harsh ever, were minorities and women declared to be discriminatory corollaries. subhuman and outside the body politic. And al- To test these multiple-traditions claims, con- though white Americans engaged in extensive sider the United States in 1870. By then the Civil violence against blacks and Native Americans, War and Reconstruction had produced dramatic those groups grew in population, and no cata- advances in the liberal and democratic character clysm loomed. Instead, intellectual and political of America’s laws. Slavery was abolished. All elites worked out the most elaborate theories of persons born in the United States and subject racial and gender hierarchy in U.S. history and to its jurisdiction were deemed citizens of the partially embodied them in a staggering array of United States and the states in which they re- new laws governing naturalization, immigration, sided, regardless of their race, creed or gender. deportation, voting rights, electoral institutions, None could be denied voting rights on racial judicial procedures, and economic rights—but grounds. The civil rights of all were newly pro- only partially. The laws retained important lib- tected through an array of national statutes. The eral and democratic features, and some were 1790 ban on naturalizing Africans had been strengthened. They had enough purchase on repealed, and expatriation declared a natural the moral and material interests of most Ameri- Democracy’s E¤ects 487

cans to compel advocates of inequality to adopt the Los Angeles riots, the English-Only agita- contrived, often clumsy means to achieve their tion, the popularity of anti-Japanese novels, re- ends. . . . newed patterns of residential segregation, and In sum, if we accept that ideologies and in- the upsurge of separatist ideologies among many stitutions of ascriptive hierarchy have shaped younger minority scholars all indicate. The dis- America in interaction with its liberal and dem- course about the ‘‘ethno-underclass’’ is particu- ocratic features, we can make more sense of a larly striking, for as Lawrence Fuchs notes, poor wide range of inegalitarian policies newly con- urban minorities are often portrayed as histori- trived after 1870 and perpetuated through much cally and socially conditioned to possess foreign of the twentieth century. Those policies were moral values (1990, 487–89). The political mes- dismantled only through great struggles, aided sage that these accounts convey often resembles, by international pressures during World War II however unintentionally, that of Lodge’s similar and the Cold War; and it is not clear that these characterizations of undesirable ‘‘races’’: these struggles have ended. The novelties in the poli- groups appear so irreparably di¤erent and dan- cies and scientific doctrines of the Gilded Age gerous that they do not merit equal status in the and Progressive Era should alert us to the possi- political community. bility that new intellectual systems and political It is too early to assess the significance of these forces defending racial and gender inequalities aspects of current American life. The achieve- may yet gain increased power in our own time. ments of Americans in building a more inclusive The civil rights reforms of the 1960s and democracy certainly provide reasons to believe 1970s are not as seriously threatened today as that illiberal forces will not prevail. But just as were the civil rights measures of the 1860s in the we can better explain the nation’s past by recog- 1890s. Yet leading scholars like Richard Epstein nizing how and why liberal democratic principles now argue that the nation should eliminate all have been contested with frequent success, we race-conscious laws, even the 1964 Civil Rights will better understand the present and future of Act, in favor of programs of black self-help in American politics if we do not presume they are the marketplace—precisely the position many rooted in essentially liberal or democratic values nineteenth-century ‘‘liberals’’ used to justify and conditions. Instead, we must analyze Amer- abandoning Reconstruction (Epstein 1992). ica as the ongoing product of often conflicting Also like these nineteenth-century predecessors, multiple traditions. Epstein ultimately grounds his laissez-faire views not so much on a doctrine of human rights as on evolutionary biology, undaunted by how others References then and now have used such views to explain racial as well as economic inequalities (Epstein Boorstin, Daniel. 1953. The Genius of American Poli- 1985, 341, n. 19; Fairchild 1991). But though this tics. Chicago: University of Chicago Press. blend of economics and sociobiology has dis- Epstein, Richard A. 1985. Takings: Private Property turbing precursors, some influential contempo- and the Power of Eminent Domain. Cambridge: Har- rary black leaders, such as Justice Clarence vard University Press. Thomas and economist Thomas Sowell, like Epstein, Richard A. 1992. Forbidden Grounds: The Booker T. Washington before them, are aligned Case Against Employment Discrimination Laws. Cam- bridge: Harvard University Press. with such ‘‘self-help’’ views. Racial, nativist, and religious tensions are also Fairchild, Halford H. 1991. ‘‘Scientific Racism: The Cloak of Objectivity.’’ Journal of Social Issues 47: prominent in American life, as the Buchanan 101–115. and Duke campaigns, the Christian Coalition, Chapter 8 488

Fuchs, Lawrence H. 1990. The American Kaleidoscope: Race, Ethnicity, and the Civic Culture. Hanover, NH: University Press of New England. Haller, John S. Jr. 1971. Outcasts from Evolution: Sci- entific Attitudes of Racial Inferiority, 1859–1900. Urbana: University of Illinois Press. Hartog, Hendrik. 1987. ‘‘The Constitution of Aspira- tion and ‘The Rights that Belong to Us All.’’’ In The Constitution and American Life, ed. David Thelen. Ithaca: Cornell University Press. Hartz, Louis. 1955. The Liberal Tradition in America: An Interpretation of American Political Thought Since the Revolution. New York: Harcourt, Brace & World. Higham, John. 1975. Send These to Me. New York: Atheneum Press. Kettner, James. 1978. The Development of American Citizenship, 1608–1870. Chapel Hill: University of North Carolina Press. Lipset, Seymour Martin. 1963. The First New Nation. New York: Basic Books. Myrdal, Gunnar. 1944. An America Dilemma: The Negro Problem and American Democracy. Rept. 20th Anniversary ed., 1962. New York: Harper & Row. Orren, Karen. 1991. Belated Feudalism: Labor, the Law, and Liberal Development in the United States. New York: Cambridge University Press. Orren, Karen, and Skowronek, Stephen. 1993. ‘‘Be- yond the Iconography of Order: Notes for a ‘New Institutionalism.’’’ In The Dynamics of American Poli- tics: Approaches and Interpretations, ed. Lawrence C. Dodd and Calvin Jillson. Boulder: Westview Press. Russett, Cynthia Eagle. 1989. Sexual Science: The Victorian Construction of Womanhood. Cambridge: Harvard University Press. Smith, Rogers M. 1989. ‘‘‘One United People’ Second- Class Female Citizenship and the American Quest for Community.’’ Yale Journal of Law and the Humanities 1: 229–293. Tocqueville, Alexis de. 1969. Democracy in America. Ed. J. P. Mayer. Garden City, New York: Anchor Books. Williamson, Joel. 1980. New People: Miscegenation and Mulattoes in the United States. New York: Free Press. 9 DEMOCRACY AND THE GLOBAL ORDER

Perpetual Peace Immanuel Kant

How Democracy, Interdependence, and International Organizations Create a System for Peace Bruce Russett

Dirty Pool Donald P. Green, Soo Yeon Kim, and David H. Yoon

Democracy and Collective Bads Russell Hardin

Representation and the Democratic Deficit Pippa Norris

The Transformation of Political Community: Rethinking Democracy in the Context of Globalization David Held Perpetual Peace

Immanuel Kant

First Definitive Article of a Perpetual Peace: The Second Section Civil Constitution of Every State Shall Be Republican Which Contains the Definitive Articles of a Perpetual Peace between States A republican constitution is founded upon three principles: firstly, the principle of freedom for A state of peace among men living together is all members of a society (as men); secondly, the not the same as the state of nature, which is principle of the dependence of everyone upon a rather a state of war. For even if it does not single common legislation (as subjects); and involve active hostilities, it involves a constant thirdly, the principle of legal equality for every- threat of their breaking out. Thus the state of one (as citizens).y It is the only constitution peace must be formally instituted, for a suspen- sion of hostilities is not in itself a guarantee of peace. And unless one neighbour gives a guar- (2) a constitution based on the international right of antee to the other at his request (which can hap- states in their relationships with one another (ius gentium). pen only in a lawful state), the latter may treat (3) a constitution based on cosmopolitan right, in so far him as an enemy.* as individuals and states, coexisting in an external re- lationship of mutual influences, may be regarded as Excerpted from: Immanuel Kant, Perpetual Peace.In citizens of a universal state of mankind (ius cosmopoli- Kant: Political Writings, edited by Hans Reiss. Cam- ticum). This classification, with respect to the idea of a bridge: Cambridge University Press, 1991. 6 Cambridge perpetual peace, is not arbitrary, but necessary. For if University Press, 1991. Reprinted with the permission even one of the parties were able to influence the others of Cambridge University Press. physically and yet itself remained in a state of nature, *It is usually assumed that one cannot take hostile there would be a risk of war, which it is precisely the action against anyone unless one has already been aim of the above articles to prevent. actively injured by them. This is perfectly correct if y Rightful (i.e. external) freedom cannot, as is usually both parties are living in a legal civil state. For the fact thought, be defined as a warrant to do whatever one that the one has entered such a state gives the required wishes unless it means doing injustice to others. For guarantee to the other, since both are subject to the what is meant by a warrant? It means a possibility of same authority. But man (or an individual people) in a acting in a certain way so long as this action does not mere state of nature robs me of any such security and do any injustice to others. Thus the definition would injures me by virtue of this very state in which he run as follows: freedom is the possibility of acting in coexists with me. He may not have injured me actively ways which do no injustice to others. That is, we do no ( facto), but he does injure me by the very lawlessness injustice to others (no matter what we may actually do) of his state (statu iniusto), for he is a permanent threat if we do no injustice to others. Thus the definition is to me, and I can require him either to enter into a an empty tautology. In fact, my external and rightful common lawful state along with me or to move away freedom should be defined as a warrant to obey no ex- from my vicinity. Thus the postulate on which all the ternal laws except those to which I have been able to following articles are based is that all men who can at give my own consent. Similarly, external and rightful all influence one another must adhere to some kind of equality within a state is that relationship among the civil constitution. But any legal constitution, as far as citizens whereby no-one can put anyone else under a the persons who live under it are concerned, will con- legal obligation without submitting simultaneously to a form to one of the three following types: law which requires that he can himself be put under the (1) a constitution based on the civil right of individuals same kind of obligation by the other person. (And we within a nation (ius civitatis). do not need to define the principle of legal dependence, Democracy and the Global Order 491

which can be derived from the idea of an original basis of every kind of civil constitution, and it contract, upon which all rightful legislation of a only remains to ask whether it is the only con- people must be founded. Thus as far as right is stitution which can lead to a perpetual peace. concerned, republicanism is in itself the original The republican constitution is not only pure in its origin (since it springs from the pure concept since it is always implied in the concept of a political of right); it also o¤ers a prospect of attaining the constitution.) The validity of these innate and inalien- desired result, i.e. a perpetual peace, and the able rights, the necessary property of mankind, is con- reason for this is as follows.—If, as is inevitably firmed and enhanced by the principle that man may the case under this constitution, the consent of have lawful relations even with higher beings (if he the citizens is required to decide whether or not believes in the latter). For he may consider himself as a war is to be declared, it is very natural that they citizen of a transcendental world, to which the same will have great hesitation in embarking on so principles apply. And as regards my freedom, I am not dangerous an enterprise. For this would mean under any obligation even to divine laws (which I can recognise by reason alone), except in so far as I have calling down on themselves all the miseries of been able to give my own consent to them; for I can war, such as doing the fighting themselves, sup- form a conception of the divine will only in terms of plying the costs of the war from their own the law of freedom of my own reason. As for the prin- resources, painfully making good the ensuing ciple of equality in relation to the most exalted being I devastation, and, as the crowning evil, having to can conceive of, apart from God (e.g. a power such as take upon themselves a burden of debt which Aeon), there is no reason, if I and this higher being are will embitter peace itself and which can never be both doing our duty in our own stations, why it should paid o¤ on account of the constant threat of new be my duty to obey while he should enjoy the right to wars. But under a constitution where the subject command. But the reason why this principle of equality is not a citizen, and which is therefore not re- (unlike that of freedom) does not apply to a relation- ship towards God, is that God is the only being for publican, it is the simplest thing in the world to whom the concept of duty ceases to be valid. go to war. For the head of state is not a fellow But as for the right of equality of all citizens as sub- citizen, but the owner of the state, and a war will jects, we may ask whether a hereditary aristocracy is not force him to make the slightest sacrifice so admissible. The answer to this question will depend far as his banquets, hunts, pleasure palaces and entirely on whether more importance is attached to the court festivals are concerned. He can thus decide superior rank granted by the state to one subject over on war, without any significant reason, as a kind another than is attached to merit, or vice versa. Now it of amusement, and unconcernedly leave it to is obvious that if rank is conferred according to birth, it the diplomatic corps (who are always ready for will be quite uncertain whether merit (skill and devo- such purposes) to justify the war for the sake of tion within one’s o‰ce) will accompany it; it will be tantamount to conferring a position of command upon propriety. . . . a favoured individual without any merit on his part, and this could never be approved by the general will of the people in an original contract, which is, after all, the principle behind all rights. For it does not neces- sarily follow that a nobleman is also a noble man. And as for a nobility of o‰ce, i.e. the rank of a higher magistracy which can be attained by merit, the rank does not attach as a possession to the person, but to the post occupied by the person, and this does not violate the principle of equality. For when a person lays down his o‰ce, he simultaneously resigns his rank and again becomes one of the people. How Democracy, Interdependence, and International Organizations Create a System for Peace

Bruce Russett

For nearly half a century the United States and of perpetual peace based partially upon states its allies carried out a policy of containment sharing ‘‘republican constitutions,’’ which is es- during the cold war, to prevent the spread of sentially what we now mean by democracy. As Communist ideology and Soviet power. That the elements of such a constitution he identified policy succeeded, spectacularly. Now it must freedom, with legal equality of subjects, repre- be replaced by another policy, one designed to sentative government, and separation of powers. consolidate the new acceptability of free in- The other key elements of his perpetual peace stitutions around the world. The new century were ‘‘cosmopolitan law’’ embodying ties of in- presents more than just the passing of a ternational commerce and free trade, and a ‘‘pa- particular adversarial relationship; it o¤ers a cific union’’ established by treaty in international chance for fundamentally-changed relations law among republics. among nations. . . . expressed the same vision for the twentieth century. . . . His 1917 war mes- sage to Congress asserted that ‘‘a steadfast con- Three Principles for a Peaceful International cert of peace can never be maintained except by Order a partnership of democratic nations.’’ This vision emerged again after World War II, animating . . . Contemporary policy needs a similar central the founders of what became the European organizing principle. That principle should build Union. It has since been taken up among coun- on the principles which underlay the rhetoric and tries of South America. At the beginning of a much of the practice of containment, rooted in new century, it is newly plausible. beliefs about the success of free political and economic systems. Those principles are democ- racy, free markets—especially on the argument Democracies Rarely Fight Each Other that economic interdependence promotes peace as well as prosperity—and international law Democratization is key to this vision for two and organization. Each makes a contribution to reasons. First, democracy is a desirable form of peace, and in many instances they reinforce each government on its own merit. It both recognizes other (and are themselves reinforced by peace) in and promotes human dignity. Democracy is not ‘‘virtuous circles’’ or feedback loops. . . . perfect, and should not be forced upon peoples A vision of a peace among democratically- who do not wish it. But for many countries it governed states has long been invoked as part of is better than the alternatives under which they a larger structure of institutions and practices to have su¤ered. promote peace. In 1795 Immanuel Kant spoke Second, we now have solid evidence that democracies do not make war on each other. Excerpted from: Bruce Russett, ‘‘How Democracy, In- Some of it can be found in my book, Grasping terdependence, and International Organizations Create the Democratic Peace, and in many more recent a System for Peace.’’ Adapted from a chapter in The works.1 In the contemporary era, ‘‘democracy’’ Global Agenda, sixth edition, edited by Charles Kegley and Eugene Wittkopf. New York: McGraw-Hill, 2000. 1. Bruce Russett, Grasping the Democratic Peace: 6 2000 The McGraw-Hill Companies, New York. Principles for a Post–Cold War World (Princeton, NJ: Reproduced with the permission of The McGraw-Hill Princeton University Press, 1993). There is an enor- Companies. mous body of more recent scholarship on this matter, Democracy and the Global Order 493

denotes a country in which nearly everyone can each other are not spuriously caused by some vote, elections are freely contested, the chief other influence such as sharing high levels of executive is chosen by popular vote or by an wealth, or rapid growth, or ties of alliance. The elected parliament, and civil rights and civil phenomenon of peace between democracies is liberties are substantially guaranteed. Democ- not limited just to the rich industrialized states of racies are not always peaceful—we all know the global North. It was not maintained simply the history of democracies in colonialism, co- by pressure from a common adversary in the vert intervention, and other excesses of power. cold war, and it has outlasted that threat. Democracies frequently resort to violence in The phenomenon of democratic peace can their relations with authoritarian states. But the be explained by the pervasiveness of normative relations between stable democracies are qual- restraints on conflict between democracies. That itatively di¤erent. explanation extends to the international arena Democracies are unlikely to engage in any the cultural norms of live-and-let-live and peace- kind of militarized disputes with each other or to ful conflict resolution that operate within democ- let any such disputes escalate into war. They racies. The phenomenon of democratic peace rarely even skirmish. Pairs of democratic states can also be explained by the role of institutional have been only one-eighth as likely as other restraints on democracies’ decisions to go to war. kinds of states to threaten to use force against Those restraints insure that any state in a conflict each other, and only one-tenth as likely actually of interest with another democracy can expect to do so. Established democracies fought no ample time for conflict-resolution processes to wars against one another during the entire twen- be e¤ective, and democracies’ political decision- tieth century. (Although Finland, for example, making processes are relatively transparent. took the Axis side against the Soviet Union in These two influences reinforce each other. The World War II, it engaged in no combat with the spread of democratic norms and practices in democracies.) the world, if consolidated, should reduce the The more democratic each state is, the more frequency of violent conflict and war. Where peaceful their relations are likely to be. Democ- normative restraints are weak, democratic insti- racies are more likely to employ ‘‘democratic’’ tutions may provide the necessary additional means of peaceful conflict resolution. They are restraints on the use of violence against other readier to reciprocate each other’s behavior, to democratic states. accept third party mediation or good o‰ces in To the degree that countries once ruled by settling disputes, and to accept binding third- autocratic systems become democratic, the ab- party arbitration and adjudication.2 Careful sta- sence of war among democracies comes to bear tistical analyses of countries’ behavior show that on any discussion of the future of international democracies’ relatively peaceful relations toward relations. The statement that in the modern largely confirming or extending the principle, but some 2. Russell Leng, ‘‘Reciprocating Influence Strategies of it critical. See especially James Lee Ray, Democracy and Success in Interstate Bargaining,’’ Journal of Con- and International Conflict (Columbia, University of flict Resolution, 37, 1 (March 1993): 3–41; William South Carolina Press, 1995; Spencer Weart, Never at Dixon, ‘‘Democracy and the Peaceful Settlement of War: Why Democracies Will Not Fight One Another International Disputes,’’ American Political Science (New Haven, CT: Yale University Press, 1998); Bruce Review, 88, 1 (March 1994): 14–32; Gregory Ray- Russett and John R. Oneal, Triangulating Peace: De- mond, ‘‘Democracies, Disputes, and Third-Party mocracy, Interdependence, and International Organi- Intermediaries,’’ Journal of Conflict Resolution, 38, 1 zations (New York: W. W. Norton, 2001), chs. 2, 3. (March 1994): 24–42. Chapter 9 494

international system democracies have almost to the carrot of extending aid on a conditional never fought each other represents a complex basis, broader goals of developing democratic phenomenon: a) Democracies rarely fight each institutions require creation of a civil society. other (an empirical statement) because b) they Recipients may see multilateral aid, with con- have other means of resolving conflicts between ditions of democratic reform attached, as a less them and therefore don’t need to fight each other blatant invasion of their sovereignty than aid (a prudential cost-benefit statement), and c) they from a single country. perceive that democracies should not fight each It would be a terrible loss if the richer and other (a normative statement about principles of older democracies did not make serious e¤orts— right behavior), which reinforces the empirical a loss to themselves as well as to the peoples statement. By this reasoning, the more democ- of the struggling democracies. Any solution re- racies there are in the world, the fewer potential quires external assistance and protection to aid adversaries we and other democracies will have and speed transitions to democracy. It also re- and the wider the zone of peace will be. quires devising institutions, and nurturing norms The possibility of a widespread zone of demo- and practices, of democratic government with cratic peace in the world exists. To turn that respect for minority rights. The creation of insti- possibility into a policy two fundamental prob- tutions, norms, and practices to protect minor- lems must be addressed: the problem of con- ities has never been easy. But it presents the solidating democratic stability, and the prospects fundamental challenge of world political devel- for changing basic patterns of international opment in this era. It is worth remembering that behavior. . . . the most terrible acts of genocide in this century (from Turkey’s slaughter of the Armenians through Hitler, Stalin, Pol Pot, and others) have Strengthening Democracy and Its Norms been carried out by authoritarian or totalitarian governments, not democratic ones.4 . . . Probably most of the conditions a¤ecting the Understanding that democracies rarely fight success of democratization arise from circum- each other, and why, has great consequence for stances internal to any particular state. But this policy in the contemporary world. It should af- list of possible conditions from outside is im- fect the kinds of military preparations believed pressive also. Favorable international conditions to be necessary, and the costs one would be may not be essential in every case, but they can willing to pay to make them. It should encourage make a di¤erence, and sometimes a crucial one peaceful e¤orts to assist the emergence and con- when the internal influences are mixed. solidation of democracy. But a misunderstand- With economic conditions so grim in much ing of it could encourage war-making against of the developing world, eastern Europe, and authoritarian regimes, and e¤orts to overturn the former Soviet Union, and the consequent them—with all the costly implications such a dangers to the legitimacy of new democratic policy might imply. governments, external assistance—technical and Recollection of the post-1945 success with financial—is especially important. New democ- defeated adversaries can be both instructive and racies will not survive without some material misleading. It is instructive in showing that de- improvement in their citizens’ lives. As a stick, mocracy could supplant a thoroughly discredited aid can surely be denied to governments that regularly violate human rights, for example of 4. R. J. Rummel, Death by Government: Genocide and ethnic minorities. A military coup or an aborted Mass Murder in the Twentieth Century (New Bruns- election can be punished by suspending aid. As wick, NJ: Transaction, 1994). Democracy and the Global Order 495

totalitarian regime. It can be misleading if one elections, and advise on the building of demo- forgets how expensive it was (Marshall Plan aid cratic institutions are far more promising and for Germany and Italy, and important economic less costly for all concerned than is military concessions to Japan), and especially if one mis- intervention. The UN experienced highly publi- interprets the political conditions of military cized troubles in Somalia and the former Yugo- defeat. The allies utterly defeated the Axis coali- slavia as it tried to cope with a range of tion. Then, to solidify democratic government challenges not previously part of its mandate. they conducted vast (if incomplete) e¤orts to re- Nonetheless, its successes, though receiving less move the former elites from positions of author- attention, outnumber the failures. It was a major ity. But they had something to build on, in the facilitator of peaceful transitions and democratic form of individuals and institutions from previ- elections in places like Cambodia, El Salvador, ous experiences with democracy. The model of Mozambique, and Namibia. Its Electoral Assis- ‘‘fight them, beat them, and then make them tance Unit has provided election monitoring, democratic’’ is no model for contemporary technical assistance, or other aid to free electoral action. It probably would not work anyway, and processes in over 70 states.5 no one is prepared to make the kind of e¤ort that would be required. Not all authoritarian states are inherently aggressive. Indeed, at any Economic Interdependence and International particular time the majority are not. A milita- Organizations rized crusade for democracy is not in order. Sometimes external military intervention Ties of economic interdependence—interna- against the most odious dictators may make tional trade and investment—form an important sense. With a cautious cost-benefit analysis and supplement to shared democracy in promoting with the certainty of substantial and legitimate peace. Analyses that show how rarely democ- internal support, it might be worthwhile—that racies used or threatened to use military force is, under conditions when rapid military success against each other also show a similarly strong is likely and the will of the people at issue is peaceful e¤ect when states trade heavily with clear. Even so, any time an outside power sup- each other. The e¤ect of economic interdepen- plants any existing government the problem of dence does not supplant, but supplements, the legitimacy is paramount. The very democratic e¤ect of democracy, and like democracy its norms to be instilled may be compromised. At e¤ect remains even when alliances and economic the least, intervention cannot be unilateral. It growth rates are controlled for in the analysis.6 should be approved, publicly and willingly, by ... an international body like the UN or the Orga- The role of international law and institu- nization of American States. When an election tions, and the need for strengthening them, has been held under UN auspices and certified as constitutes the third element of the Kantian/ fair—as happened in Haiti—the UN has a spe- Wilsonian vision. As expressed by former UN cial responsibility, even a duty, to see that the Secretary-General Boutros Ghali, the UN has a democratic government it helped create is not new mission of ‘‘peace-building,’’ attending to destroyed. democratization, development, and the protec- Under most circumstances, international bodies are best used to promote democratic pro- 5. The scope of these e¤orts is evident in Boutros cesses when the relevant domestic parties are Boutros-Ghali, An Agenda for Democratization (New ready. Peacekeeping operations to help provide York: United Nations, 1996). the conditions for free elections, monitor those 6. Russett and Oneal, Triangulating Peace, ch. 4. Chapter 9 496

tion of human rights.8 It is newly strengthened emergence and consolidation of democratic gov- and, paradoxically, also newly and enormously ernments. International threats—real or only burdened. The UN and other international perceived—strengthen the forces of secrecy and organizations promote democratization and authoritarianism in the domestic politics of states peace directly as well as indirectly. As noted involved in protracted conflict. Relaxation of in- above, democracies are much more likely to ternational threats to peace and security reduces use international institutions for peacefully re- the need, and the excuse, for repressing demo- solving disputes among themselves than are cratic dissent. . . . dictatorships. . . . A Kantian peace would be sustained by an The e¤ects of these three Kantian influences interacting and mutually supporting combina- can be found throughout most of the twentieth tion of democratic government, economic century, both before the cold war era and in interdependence, and international law and or- the first few years after it. Two kinds of pairs ganization. Such an international system—an of countries are especially likely to have rea- international society as well as a collection of sons for violent conflict, and the ability to fight sovereign states—might reflect very di¤erent be- each other: geographically contiguous countries, havior than did the previous one composed pre- and pairs of states in which at least one is a ma- dominantly of autocracies. The West won the jor power, with long-range military capability. cold war, at immense cost. If we should now let Among these pairs during the past century, high slip this marvelous but brief window of oppor- levels of shared democracy and of economic tunity to solidify basic change in the interna- interdependence both reduced the chances of a tional order at much lower cost, our children will militarized dispute by more than 40 percent, and wonder why. Some autocratically-governed shared IGO memberships did so by about one- states will surely remain in the system. In their third. And in periods when levels of democracy relations with states where democracy is unsta- and interdependence are generally high through- ble, or where democratization is not begun at all, out the international system, the norms and democracies must continue to be vigilant and institutions that go with them seem to have some concerned with the need for military deterrence. restraining e¤ect even on countries that are not But if enough states do become stable democ- very democratic or interdependent.10 Common racies in the next century, then we will have a perceptions can be misleading: actually, the chance to reconstruct the norms and rules of the number of international wars worldwide has international order. A system created by autoc- dropped precipitously since the 1980s.11 ... racies centuries ago might now be re-created by a critical mass of democratic states, economically interdependent with peaceful relations facilitated Can a Wider Peace Be Built? by international institutions. . . .

New democracies should be supported finan- 11. Monty Marshall, Third World War (Lanham, cially, politically, militarily, and morally. Success- MD: Rowman, Littlefield, 1999); Peter Wallensteen ful transitions to democracy in some countries and Marareta Sollenberg, ‘‘Armed Conflict, 1989–99,’’ can supply a model for others. A stable and less Journal of Peace Research 37, 2 (September 2000): menacing international system can permit the 635–649.

8. An Agenda for Peace (New York: United Nations, 1993), paragraph 81. 10. Russett and Oneal, Triangulating Peace, ch. 5. Dirty Pool

Donald P. Green, Soo Yeon Kim, and David H. Yoon

The quantitative study of international rela- rate, or intercept. For example, year after year, tions is dominated by analyses of pooled cross- trade levels between India and China fall below sections. When analyzing dependent variables, what one would expect based on a regression such as the occurrence of a militarized dispute model that takes into account population size, or the level of trade between two nations, gross domestic product (GDP), and shared bor- researchers tend to work with panel data sets ders. Because such a model fails to take note of NT observations, where N is the number of of the Himalayas, economic endowments, lin- dyads (pairs of nations) and T is the number of guistic dissimilarity, and diplomatic relations, time points (typically years). Thus, for example, this model repeatedly overestimates bilateral when sixty nations are observed annually over trade between India and China, just as it con- the span of forty years, the pooled cross- sistently underestimates trade between Belgium sectional data set consists of 1,770 dyads forty and Switzerland. Pooling data implicitly assumes years ¼ 70,800 observations. These data are said that the independent variables eliminate these to be ‘‘pooled’’ in that no distinction is made persistent cross-sectional di¤erences or render between observations in time and space. A them uncorrelated with the predictors in the datum is a datum, and one can draw inferences model. In this example, the fact that India- with equal certitude across dyads or across years. China di¤er in unmeasured ways from Belgium- Concerned that the e¤ective number of obser- Switzerland makes this assumption implausible. vations is less than the nominal NT, a great deal Given the vagaries of measurement and model of methodological attention has recently focused specification in statistical studies of international on problems of interdependencies among the relations, the statistical assumptions that under- observations; unobserved factors that cause the lie pooling are generally suspect. United States to go to war with Japan in 1941 . . . To demonstrate the importance of this also cause it to go to war with Italy and Ger- issue to students of international a¤airs, we many. . . . [W]e believe that the problems asso- present two empirical examples of how statistical ciated with standard pooled cross-sectional results change when fixed e¤ects are taken into estimation run much deeper.2 account. The first example concerns bilateral We contend that analyses of pooled cross- trade; the second, militarized interstate disputes. section data that make no allowance for fixed In both cases, we find dramatic changes in the unobserved di¤erences between dyads often pro- size and statistical significance of the parameter duce biased results. By ‘‘fixed unobserved dif- estimates. For example, democracy, which seems ferences’’ (or fixed e¤ects, for short) we mean to be a leading predictor of peace in a pooled unmeasured predictors of the dependent variable cross-sectional analysis, has no e¤ect on mili- that would cause each dyad to have its own base tarized disputes when the data are examined longitudinally. We conclude by discussing the Excerpted from: Donald P. Green, Soo Yeon Kim, and implications of our results for methodological David H. Yoon, ‘‘Dirty Pool.’’ International Organi- practices in the field. . . . zation 55, no. 2 (spring 2001): 441–468. 6 2001 by the IO Foundation and the Massachusetts Institute of Technology. Reprinted by permission. Data 2. On count data, see Beck, Katz, and Tucker 1998; on sequential decisions, Signorino 1999; on simultaneous Using a panel of dyads for the period 1951–92, equations, Kim 1998; and on rare events, King and we examine two dependent variables: bilateral Zeng forthcoming. Chapter 9 498

trade volume and the presence or absence of a tions were available, a criterion that admits over militarized interstate dispute.9 For bilateral trade 93,000 of the approximately 117,000 cases in our volume, the independent variables include the data set. The reason for this restriction is that standard gravity model terms—log of GDP, dynamic models are biased when estimated on population, and distance between capitals, and in short time-series. Note, however, that the coef- addition, alliance and democracy. Alliance is ficients we report are not changed appreciably operationalized as the absence (0) or presence (1) when we admit all of the observations or, con- of a formal alliance; democracy as the lower of versely, just those for which complete time-series the net democracy scores within the dyad.10 data are available.16 Trade data are from the Direction of Trade Sta- In the interest of drawing an exact parallel tistics of the International Monetary Fund.11 between pooled-regression and fixed-e¤ects re- Data for GDP and population were obtained gression, we include the same set of regressors in from the Penn World Tables, version 5.6.12 The both models. Note that in the context of a fixed democracy variable was computed from the May e¤ects analysis, regressors such as contiguity and 1996 version of the Polity III data set.13 Data distance vary only insofar as countries divide or for contiguity, capability ratio, and alliance were change their capitals over time. Just sixty dyads obtained from the Correlates of War Project experience change in contiguity over time, but (1995).14 none experience change in distance. Distance is The model of militarized interstate disputes therefore a constant that is absorbed into the features a set of commonly used regressors: intercept associated with each dyad. Fixed- alliance, democracy, geographical contiguity, the e¤ects regression turns a blind eye to such time- absence (0) or presence (1) of a shared land bor- invariant regressors; to learn about their e¤ects, der; capability ratio, the ratio of the higher to one must either study them in a cross-sectional lower capabilities indexes of the countries in the context, braving the usual threats to causal in- dyad, in logs; growth, the lower three-year aver- ference, or investigate particular historical in- age growth in per capita GDP within the dyad; stances in which observations vary over time. and the lower bilateral trade-to-GDP ratio within the dyad.15 We have chosen to include in our analysis Results all dyads for which twenty or more observa- We begin our panel analysis by modeling a con- 9. See Bremer 1996; and Jones, Bremer, and Singer tinuous dependent variable, the total volume of 1996. trade between two states (in logs). Our specifica- 10. For three large states (United States, USSR/ tion includes the three components of the ‘‘grav- Russia, and Canada), the shortest distance from their ity model’’—log of the two states’ total GDP, main ports/capitals is used. The ports include New the log of the two states’ total population, and Orleans and San Francisco for the United States, Vladivostok for USSR/Russia, and Vancouver for 16. In an earlier draft of this article, we reported Canada. This measurement approach follows Bliss results from a ‘‘balanced panel,’’ which is a panel and Russett 1998; and Gowa and Mansfield 1993. restricted to just those dyads with complete data for the 11. IMF 1997. entire time span (1961–89). The coe‰cients were simi- 12. Heston and Summers 1991. lar to those reported here, but the loss of observations made for larger standard errors. Despite a sample of 13. Jaggers and Gurr 1995. more than 29,000 observations, no predictors of mili- 14. Singer and Small 1994. tarized disputes were significant at the 5 percent level in 15. For a summary of the capability index, see Singer a regression that controlled for fixed e¤ects. 1990. Democracy and the Global Order 499

Table 9.1 Alternative regression analyses of bilateral trade (1951–92) Pooled with Fixed e¤ects Variablea Pooled Fixed e¤ects dynamics with dynamics GDP 1.182** 0.810** 0.250** 0.342** (0.008) (0.015) (0.006) (0.013) Population 0.386** 0.752** 0.059** 0.143* (0.010) (0.082) (0.006) (0.068) Distance 1.342** Dropped: no 0.328** Dropped: no within-group within-group variation variation (0.018) (0.012) Alliance 0.745** 0.777** 0.247** 0.419** (0.042) (0.136) (0.027) (0.121) Democracyb 0.075** 0.039** 0.022** 0.009** (0.002) (0.003) (0.001) (0.002) Lagged bilateral 0.736** 0.533** trade (0.002) (0.003) Constant 17.331** 47.994** 3.046** 13.745** (0.265) (1.999) (0.177) (1.676) N ¼ 93,924 NT ¼ 93,924 N ¼ 88,946 NT ¼ 88,946 N ¼ 3,079 N ¼ 3,079 T b 20 T b 20 Adjusted R2 0.36 0.63 0.73 0.76 Note: Estimates obtained using areg and xtreg procedures in STATA, version 6.0. a. GDP, population, distance, and bilateral trade are natural-log transformed. Method of analysis is OLS and fixed-e¤ects regression. b. Lower value within the dyad. ** p <:01. * p <:05, two-tailed test. the log of the distance between the two states.17 political variables. We follow current practice As Je¤rey H. Bergstrand cautions, this model in the spirit of examining the consequences of o¤ers reasonably accurate predictions of trade di¤erent modeling assumptions. We include as volume but lacks firm theoretical foundation.18 regressors the democracy and alliance measures Political scientists have treated the gravity model from the previous analysis. Table 9.1 presents as something of a baseline, appending additional both pooled and fixed-e¤ects models, each with and without a lagged dependent variable as a 17. See Tinbergen 1962; Linneman 1966; Leamer and regressor. We find no support whatsoever for Stern 1970, 145–70; Anderson 1979; and Deardor¤ the null hypothesis that all dyads share the same 1984, 503–504. intercept. For the nondynamic case, F(3078, 18. Bergstrand 1985, 474. 90841) ¼ 23.68, p <:0001; when lagged trade is Chapter 9 500

introduced as an independent variable, F(3078, estimates associated with population, alliance, 85862) ¼ 4.43, p <:0001. . . . and democracy. As expected, the pooled model With large data sets it is sometimes possible to overestimates the e¤ect of the lagged dependent reject parsimonious regression models in favor of variable. The coe‰cient that the pooled model somewhat more complex models that produce assigns to the lagged dependent variable blends substantively identical results. That is manifestly the true parameter with the parameter of unity not the case here. The two regressions paint that should be assigned to its (omitted) intercept. markedly di¤erent pictures of bilateral trade. In Because the e¤ect of the lagged dependent vari- the pooled analysis, population has a strong able is overestimated, it appears that perturba- negative e¤ect on trade. A one-unit change in the tions to trade levels reequilibrate more slowly log of population reduces the log of trade by .39 than they actually do.20 In sum, assumptions units. The tiny standard error associated with implicit in di¤erent regression models greatly this estimate produces a T-ratio of epic propor- shape how one thinks about the determinants of tions, 39.7. Not in a million years could these bilateral trade. data have been generated by a true parameter of To illustrate further the importance of fixed zero or more. Yet, look at the fixed-e¤ects re- e¤ects, we turn our attention to a nonlinear esti- gression results: population has a positive coe‰- mation problem. Table 9.2 reports the results of cient (.75) and a T-ratio of 9.2. As two countries’ alternative logistic-regression models of milita- populations grow over time, other things being rized disputes. The pooled analysis suggests that equal, they trade more.19 Alliance and democ- the likelihood of disputes increases when dyads racy undergo similar turnabouts. In the pooled are contiguous and decreases as the less- model, democracy encourages trade. In the democratic member of the dyad becomes more fixed-e¤ects model, dyads trade less as the less- democratic. Alliances decrease the risk of war, democratic partner becomes more democratic. whereas di¤erences in military capabilities in- In the pooled model, alliance inhibits trade. In crease it. These results are in line with published the fixed-e¤ects model, the formation of alliances research. is associated with much higher levels of trade. These estimates change markedly when fixed Similar turnabouts occur when we introduce e¤ects are controlled. Democracy’s e¤ects be- a lagged dependent variable and focus on the come negligible and statistically insignificant, short-term influences of the independent vari- whereas military capability and alliance prove ables. Again the Hausman test indicates that the much more influential. Consider, for example, pooled cross-sectional regression is biased (a test what the fixed-e¤ects regression results tell us against a null hypothesis of random e¤ects pro- about a dyad with a 5 percent chance of war. If duces w2ð5Þ¼14;754:0, p <:0001), and we see the less democratic of the two nations becomes dramatic changes in the magnitude of the slope fifteen units more democratic, the risk of war decreases to 4.8 percent. The pooled regression 19. As noted earlier, the causal interpretation of coef- would lead us to expect this risk to drop from 5 ficients growing out of the gravity model is problem- percent to 2.2 percent. Conversely, the formation atic. Leamer and Stern (1970, 155) argue persuasively that population change may reflect a variety of un- 20. Results similar to the fixed-e¤ects regression ob- measured variables, such as technological change and tain when we use an alternative estimator that makes changing health care. Note also that the gravity model allowance for the fact that lagged trade is an endoge- makes no distinction between imports and exports, nous regressor. This alternative estimator uses the which might be di¤erentially a¤ected by trade volume. Anderson-Hsiao methodology (instrumental variables) For these reasons, we are loath to say what constitutes described in Hsiao 1986 and Greene 1997. These the ‘‘right’’ sign for the population coe‰cient. results are available from the authors on request. Democracy and the Global Order 501

Table 9.2 Alternative logistic regression analyses of militarized interstate disputes (1951–92) Pooled with Fixed e¤ects Variable Pooled Fixed e¤ects dynamics with dynamics Contiguity 3.042** 1.902** 1.992** 1.590** (0.092) (0.336) (0.120) (0.375) Capability ratio (log) 0.102** 0.387** 0.125** 0.350* (0.024) (0.139) (0.028) (0.151) Growtha 0.017 0.059** 0.026* 0.062** (0.011) (0.012) (0.013) (0.013) Alliance 0.234* 1.066* 0.013 1.090* (0.097) (0.426) (0.118) (0.526) Democracya 0.057** 0.003 0.053** 0.0004 (0.007) (0.015) (0.008) (0.016) Bilateral trade/GDPa 0.194* 0.072 0.028 0.084 (0.087) (0.186) (0.075) (0.217) Lagged dispute 4.940** 1.813** (0.102) (0.103) Constant 5.809** 6.274** (0.090) (0.108) N 93,755 93,755b 88,752 88,752c Log likelihood 3,688.06 1,546.53 2,530.31 1,299.53 w2 1,186.43 75.75 3,074.67 380.40 Degrees of freedom 6677 Prob > w2 < 0.0001 < 0.0001 < 0.0001 < 0.0001 Note: Estimates obtained using logit and clogit procedures in STATA, version 6.0. a. Lower value within the dyad. Method of analysis: Logistic and fixed-e¤ects logistic regression. b. 2,877 groups (87,402 observations) have no variation in outcomes. c. 2,883 groups (82,932 observations) have no variation in outcomes. ** p <:01. * p <:05, two-tailed test. Chapter 9 502

of an alliance decreases the risk of war from 5 Until then, analysts of pooled cross-sectional percent to 1.8 percent, not 4.0 percent, as implied data should proceed with caution, and con- by the pooled regression. Controlling for fixed sumers of this research should begin to demand e¤ects changes the way one views the relative that scholars consider potential problems arising importance of regime type, bilateral accords, and from unmodeled fixed e¤ects. . . . military capabilities. . . . Having cautioned the reader against placing undue faith in fixed-e¤ects models, we nonethe- References less believe that testing for fixed e¤ects will put the quantitative analysis of panel data in inter- Anderson, James E. 1979. A Theoretical Foundation national a¤airs on a path toward more robust for the Gravity Equation. American Economic Review and informative models. Many years after Stim- 69(1): 106–116. son’s watershed essay on the analysis of panel Beck, Nathaniel, Jonathan Katz, and Richard Tucker. data in political science, it seems clear that the 1998. Taking Time Seriously: Time-Series-Cross- Section Analysis with a Binary Dependent Variable. assumptions underlying pooled cross-sectional 23 American Journal of Political Science 42(4): 1260– analysis of trade and conflict are suspect. 1288. Dyads di¤er systematically in ways that are not Bergstrand, Je¤rey H. 1985. The Gravity Equation in captured by the measures used to gauge con- International Trade: Some Microeconomic Founda- structs such as ‘‘capability,’’ ‘‘democracy,’’ and tions and Empirical Evidence. Review of Economics the like. Pooling data under these circumstances and Statistics 67(3): 474–481. leads to biased estimates. Yet analysts of inter- Bliss, Harry, and Bruce Russett. 1998. Democratic national relations seem unaware of this problem Trading Partners: The Liberal Connection, 1962–1989. or unwilling to come to grips with it. The Journal of Politics 60(4): 1126–1147. The persistence of fixed e¤ects in the cases Bremer, Stuart. 1996. Militarized Interstate Disputes, examined here should be seen as a challenge 1816–1992. Version 2.1. Available at hhttp://pss.la. to future scholarship on trade or interstate dis- psu.edu/MID_DATA.HTMi. Accessed June 1997. putes: find new regressors that capture these Deardor¤, Alan V. 1984. Testing Trade Theories and cross-sectional di¤erences. As Stimson points Predicting Trade Flows. In Handbook of International out, fixed e¤ects are merely placeholders await- Economics, edited by Ronald W. Jones and Peter B. ing substantive explanation.24 Scholars rising to Kenen, 467–517. Amsterdam: North-Holland. this challenge may then judge their handiwork Gowa, Joanne, and Edward D. Mansfield. 1993. Power according to whether their revised regression Politics and International Trade. American Political models succeed in transforming any remaining Science Review 87(2): 408–420. dyad-specific intercepts into random noise, as Greene, William H. 1997. Econometric Analysis. 3d ed. gauged by a Hausman test. This approach, if Upper Saddle River, N.J.: Prentice Hall. successful, could resuscitate the cross-sectional Heston, Alan, and Robert Summers. 1991. The Penn component of panel analysis and turn pooled World Table (Mark5): An Expanded Set of Interna- regressions into the kinds of conditional random- tional Comparisons, 1950–88. Quarterly Journal of Economics 106(2): 327–368. e¤ects models envisioned by Simon Jackman.25 Hsiao, Cheng. 1986. Analysis of Panel Data. Cam- bridge: Cambridge University Press. 23. Stimson 1985. It is noteworthy that Stimson is Jackman, Simon. 1999. In and Out of War and Peace: cited by Wang 1999 and Zahariadis 1997, two . . . The Statistical Analysis of Discrete Serial Data on In- works . . . that introduce fixed e¤ects into their inter- ternational Conflict. Unpublished manuscript, Stan- national relations models. ford University, Stanford, Calif. 24. Stimson 1985. 25. Jackman 1999. Democracy and the Global Order 503

Jaggers, Keith, and Ted Robert Gurr. 1995. Tracking Democracy’s Third Wave with the Polity III Data. Journal of Peace Research 32(4): 469–482. Jones, Daniel M., Stuart A. Bremer, and J. David Singer. 1996. Militarized Interstate Disputes, 1816– 1992: Rationale, Coding, and Empirical Patterns. Conflict Management and Peace Science 15(2): 163– 213. Kim, Soo Yeon. 1998. Ties that Bind: The Role of Trade in International Conflict Processes, 1950–1992. Ph.D. diss., Yale University, New Haven, Conn. King, Gary, and Langche Zeng. Forthcoming. Logistic Regression in Rare Events Data. International Organi- zation 55(4). Leamer, Edward E., and Robert M. Stern. 1970. Quantitative International Economics. Boston: Allyn and Bacon. Linnemann, Hans. 1966. An Econometric Study of In- ternational Trade Flows. Amsterdam: North-Holland. Signorino, Curtis A. 1999. Strategic Interaction and the Statistical Analysis of International Conflict. American Political Science Review 93(2): 279–297. Singer, J. David. 1990. Models, Methods, and Progress in World Politics: A Peace Research Odyssey. Boulder, Colo.: Westview Press. Stimson, James A. 1985. Regression in Space and Time: A Statistical Essay. American Journal of Political Science 29(4): 914–947. Tinbergen, Jan. 1962. Shaping the World Economy. New York: Twentieth Century Fund. Wang, T. Y. 1999. U.S. Foreign Aid and UN Voting: An Analysis of Important Issues. International Studies Quarterly 43(1): 199–210. Zahariadis, Nikolaos. 1997. Why State Subsidies? Evi- dence from European Community Countries, 1981– 1986. International Studies Quarterly 41(2): 341–354. Democracy and Collective Bads1

Russell Hardin

Supporters of democracy might take special ing relatively di‰cult problems of coordination pleasure in noting how well democratic decision- within the context of standard collective actions. making, even as messy as it typically is, has It is generally poor at handling more conflicted handled several problems of the generation of issues, such as, especially, straight distributional collective bads, such as air and water pollution.2 issues. The regulation of many collective bads in Many autocratic states, which are often thought our time falls on both sides of the democratic to have advantages in pushing through di‰cult divide. In so far as these problems are purely do- policies, have been environmental disasters while mestic, as in the pollution of, say, Lake Tahoe, Western democracies were actually improving they are relatively easily seen as coordination their environments even while continuing eco- problems by at least the bulk of the relevant nomic growth. At the same time, democratic population. In so far as they are very substan- states—especially, but not only, the United tially international, as in the destruction of the States—have been relatively poor at handling ozone layer or acid rain, however, they often distributive issues such as poverty and equal op- have massive distributive implications that would portunity. These contrary results are inherent in make their resolution di‰cult even in domestic the nature of democracy and the kinds of prob- politics but that make resolution extremely di‰- lems at stake. This fact bodes ill, oddly, for in- cult in international politics. In domestic politics, ternational handling of collective bads. they could, in principle, be handled by simple Democracy is particularly good at handling voting or by majoritarian representative legisla- problems of coordination, sometimes includ- tion. In international politics, they must be han- dled through voluntary cooperation on the part Excerpted from: Russell Hardin, ‘‘Democracy and of many states and, thus, they face the standard Collective Bads.’’ In Democracy’s Edges, edited by problem of the logic of collective action. Even Ian Shapiro and Casiano Hacker-Cordo´n. Cambridge: worse, they face that problem in a normative Cambridge University Press, 1999. 6 Cambridge Uni- context in which fairness as well as mere coop- versity Press, 1999. Reprinted with the permission of eration is often thought to be at issue. Cambridge University Press. Although there might be good abstract argu- 1. Prepared for presentation at the conference, ‘‘Re- ments for the use of democratic procedures to thinking Democracy for a New Century,’’ Yale Uni- serve the general interest of each citizen, in versity, 28 February–2 March 1997. Work on this actual democratic decisions it is almost invari- paper has been supported by New York University, the ably the case that some are losers while others Guggenheim Foundation, the Center for Advanced Study in the Behavioral Sciences, and the National are winners. A rare exception to this aspect of Science Foundation (grant # SBR-9022192). I am democracy as it actually works is the choice of grateful to all of these splendid agencies for their sup- whether to defend a nation under attack from port. I am also grateful to the participants in the Yale outside. At least in the logic of the interests at conference and in the Rational Choice Seminar at stake, another very broad class of exceptions is, the Center for Advanced Study for comments on an or may soon be, the general losses that all might earlier draft and especially to Susan Hurley, Susan su¤er from such collective bads as environmental Moller Okin, and Steven Weber, who wrote lengthy degradation. If collective action to overcome the comments. generation of collective bads must be sponta- 2. On air pollution in the United States, see, e.g., Sci- neously, voluntarily motivated, we generally can entific American (1977). expect such action to fail. In general, we expect Democracy and the Global Order 505

it to succeed only for very small groups and tions, may be especially susceptible to harms for groups, such as labor unions, that have from the increased ultraviolet radiation that sanctioning power, to some extent, just as states comes through the depleted ozone layer.3 But have. When, however, it is determined by demo- other problems of, for example, ocean and air cratic vote with the backing of government to pollution are also predominantly international- enforce the collective choice, we should often ized for many nations that contribute to these expect most individuals who vote to vote for en- problems. . . . forcement, just as they might be expected to vote to defend their nation from attack. Again, in the larger international system in International Collective Bads which individual nations are unable to secure themselves against collective bads, however, the There is a peculiar di¤erence between the tradi- problem of collective action might be replayed at tional problems of securing collective goods and the higher level of states, because it may not be at least some of the contemporary problems of in the interest of a single nation independently to blocking collective bads. The latter are often adopt self-regulative policies. I wish to investi- inherently not national problems—they cross gate the nature and logic of democratic incen- borders, they even straddle hemispheres. Demo- tives in the face of such nested collective action cratic theory has virtually always been conceived problems of overcoming collective bads. In gen- at the level of relatively small populations in eral, one might suppose that geographically very well-defined areas. Its expansion to cover large large nations, such as the United States, Russia, nations has been an evolutionary result in the Brazil, Canada, Australia, and China, might older democracies and a move by analogy rather have greater interest in regulation directly for than by reinvention in such newer democracies their own benefit, so that domestic politics might as that of India with its population of, now, su‰ce for some regulation in these nations, as it about a billion people. In our time there are two also might for the new European Union. Of contrary forces underway that either expand or course, even in these cases the levels of regula- shrink the scope of democracy. The growth of tion that would be popularly chosen would likely ethnic politics has led to the splitting of nations vary with levels of prosperity. Contemporary into smaller units, as most dramatically in the Chinese would presumably be willing to su¤er a case of the former Soviet Union, while the larger trade-o¤ of higher rates of pollution for growth of concern with the benefits of larger higher rates of economic growth than would markets and their e‰ciencies has led to the union contemporary Americans. of nations into larger blocks, as most dramati- Most nations in the world, however, could not cally in the case of the European Union (EU). plausibly justify the expense of certain environ- Pooling decisions at higher levels, as in the mental regulations merely for their own benefit, European Union, is what the international regu- because almost all of the benefit would accrue to the people of other nations. This is most con- 3. The seriousness of this problem may be less than has spicuously true, perhaps, for the use of ozone- been supposed until recently. The worst implication of depleting chemicals. Ozone depletion is almost increased UV radiation exposure has been thought to wholly internationalized, although nations such be an increase in melanoma, a deadly cancer, an asso- as the United States and Australia can reason- ciation that has been questioned by some findings. The lesser harm of superficial skin cancers, which are gen- ably see the problem of ozone depletion as par- erally treatable, is far less ominous than a dramatic in- ticularly costly to their citizens, many of whom, crease in melanoma. with their fair skins and nearly tropical loca- Chapter 9 506

lation of contemporary collective bads requires. was often like the power of the bureaucrat, The pooling of the EU, NAFTA, GATT, and which, according to a joke that is too true to be similar supranational unions is designed to over- entirely funny, is no power but the power to come institutional barriers to better results, bar- deny any reasonable request. Nations essentially riers that get in the way of economic and other just got in the way of individuals and corpo- activities that would spontaneously happen if rations to make certain actions harder than they those barriers were not in the way. This is fun- need have been. damentally a coordination problem rather than a Again, the change entailed in regulating con- problem of the provision of a collective good. temporary international collective bads has vir- Indeed, to date, successful resolution of interna- tually the opposite character: it seems likely to tional problems has typically been resolution of involve intrusions to block individual actions of coordination problems. Contemporary collective many kinds. At the very least, it involves the bads will require institutional devices to motivate creation of artificial incentive structures to alter changes in action by individuals and institutions. behavior relatively unobtrusively. It will require creation of stronger, international At the international level all environmental institutions rather than the weakening of extant, problems are similar to the US national problem national institutions. of auto pollution, whose principal harms are Arguably, the European Union entails an borne by Americans, who must bear the costs of overall reduction in governmental power to reducing those harms. Of course, some of the the benefit of individual and corporate actors. harms are externalized to the larger world, espe- The standard debate over the Union refers to cially the larger world of the northern hemi- the growing strength of government in Brussels, sphere, and some of the regulatory costs are also as though the issue were an old libertarian externalized through the standardization of au- issue of the growth of government. The actual tomotive design in the international market so implication of that Union, at least for the short that, say, Singaporeans drive cleaner cars and term, however, is the weakening of national have to use more expensive fuel in them irre- government controls over individuals and non- spective of whether they would want to do so. If governmental corporate bodies. each nation is responsible for reducing its indus- There would be grievous conceptual and mea- trial emissions, some nations cannot sensibly be surement problems in determining whether the thought to see it as their interest to bear the costs EU gains more or less power than the individual of the reduction even if that means no other na- national governments, taken together, lose. But tion reduces emissions either. a simple and compelling indicator of who loses Hence, it is not conceivable to defend any in- and who gains is that individuals and corporate ternational policy on reduced emissions without actors gain substantially, both economically and making interpersonal comparisons of the evalu- in other ways such as freedom to travel and live ation of the costs and benefits of such reductions. and work at will throughout the nations of the Straightforward policies are not likely to be Union. It seems implausible that overall gov- Pareto improving. In some abstract sense, we ernmental control over individuals—which is might be convinced that there are policies that the core concern of libertarianism—has grown. would be Pareto improving in that they would Surely it has been reduced. This is not to say that reduce pollution for virtually everyone without the power that individual nations had over indi- imposing costs on anyone that outweighed that viduals was beneficial to anyone or was delib- person’s own benefits from the reduction. But erately exercised for some nationally beneficial standard results in choice theory suggest that we reason. Much of it was almost certainly not. It cannot expect to reach agreement on the con- Democracy and the Global Order 507

clusion that any actually proposed policy is Substantial per capita subsidies to the poorer Pareto improving. It would be in the interest of, nations would require massive per capita con- say, Brazil or China or the United States to as- tributions from the wealthier nations. . . . sert that its own interest would be harmed by any given policy that allocated costs in a partic- ular way. ‘‘Property Rights’’ in International Pollution Moreover, only in a world of relative equality could we suppose that such claims must be spe- In a tradition that is not merely Lockean, it is cious. Even without strategic misrepresentation commonly supposed that those who stake out an of evaluations, we cannot expect to resolve the area first have a strong normative claim on it international problems with easy agreement be- thereafter. The notion of national sovereignty, cause of deep inequalities. For example, suppose which is primarily a concern of the third world, the Chinese economy is soon generally a market is a variant of this principle of the rightness of economy, with a small government role in the prior ownership. In part, such a principle could actual production of ordinary goods and ser- be seen as essentially a convention that settles vices. Also suppose the government insists that issues that would otherwise be destructively in its people do not value clean air enough to stop conflict, so that, on the whole, all are better o¤ using coal in antiquated generators that are es- from the stability of expectations and reduction pecially polluting. Finally, suppose that cleaning of conflict that follows from virtually any form up the environment means, at least in large part of property rights. for the short term, buying new equipment from There is a sense in which the advanced indus- abroad and using other fuels that would be in- trial nations staked out a claim on the world’s ternationally marketable, so that, whether they atmosphere and water during the past two cen- are imported or merely not exported, their use turies and that they have left little of these re- involves substantial losses of Chinese capital. sources for those who come after them who wish Among the chief financial losers from any policy to use the atmosphere and water of the world to clean up the environment would be various in similar ways. In John Locke’s (1963 [1690]: industrialists, but Chinese workers could also paras. 27 and 33) argument for the normative lose if the displacement of capital reduced rates derivation of claims of ownership from prior use, of economic growth. there is a condition, the Lockean proviso, that, if One might suppose that the transition of taken very seriously, cannot be met in our world. poorer nations to higher productivity could The proviso states that I have the right to some be subsidized by wealthier nations in ways property if, after my appropriation of it, there is that would benefit both. It would benefit the enough and as good left for others. Those who wealthier nations by reducing the externalities staked out claims to farmland in Iowa cannot be they would su¤er from dirtier economic produc- said to meet this proviso because there is very tion in the poorer nations—but this is likely to little farmland as good as Iowa. Similarly, those be a chimera at present costs of technologies for who put substantial pollutants into the air and environmental protection. The population of into major water resources, including interna- Africa alone is almost twice, and those of India tional rivers and the seas, left little further car- and China are each almost four times, that of the rying capacity in those resources for others to United States. The wealthy nations of North use after them. America, Europe, Japan, and Australia have a If the Chinese and Indians pollute at per small fraction of the population of the poor na- capita levels today that rival the per capita levels tions now hoping for rapid economic growth. of the United States in the era 1880–1960, they Chapter 9 508

must bear huge burdens domestically and must bads and occasional collective goods. We stipu- externalize huge burdens to the rest of the world. late that cars will meet various anti-pollution Except for the massive problems of polluting standards and then let individuals freely decide, energy sources, they might be expected to ac- within this constraint, what cars they buy. We complish industrial growth at earlier American do not necessarily have to enforce the policies levels without polluting at American levels be- against individuals to change their behavior. The cause technology has improved and become central problem of nesting collective actions at much cleaner. But since the scale of their cur- di¤erent levels is that this relatively easy resolu- rent combined populations is roughly twenty tion is not possible at the higher level of interna- times that of the United States at the beginning tional politics. When the issues have di¤erential of its industrial growth, they probably cannot be e¤ects, especially distributional e¤ects, at the in- expected to match American levels of growth ternational level, we cannot simply vote by some without polluting far more in absolute terms kind of majority decision procedure and then than the United States did, especially if they rely expect every nation to follow through as virtu- on using abundant supplies of cheap coal for ally every US citizen might be expected to follow energy. through on Environmental Protection Agency Naturally, Americans and Europeans con- directives. cerned with overburdening the environment tend The creation of larger, supranational govern- to focus relatively heavily on the responsibility of mental bodies such as the European Union may, nations for their rates of population growth. however, make environmental regulation easier Poor nations focus rather on national responsi- because such unification ‘‘domesticates’’ some of bilities for per capita rates of energy consump- the relevant problems of collective bads. Instead tion and pollution. Population is treated more of seeing its own polluting activities as largely nearly as a domestic problem by poor nations internationalized, each nation of the Union can and as an international problem by wealthy na- increasingly see its problem as merely the general tions. It is both, but the di¤erence in emphasis is problem of the larger Union, and at that level essentially a distributional issue. Again, democ- democratic choice might relatively easily reach racy is not good at handling distributional issues, consensus on regulation. A side advantage of and international democracy, which is exceed- supranational organizations intended for the ingly weak, cannot be expected to handle inter- resolution of simple coordination problems in national distributions except in so far as wealthy economic activities may be to domesticate some nations choose to act more or less altruistically problems of collective bads enough to make toward impoverished nations. them consensually, democratically resolvable. This prospect should give many western Euro- pean leaders greater incentive to broaden the Concluding Remarks Union by including the polluting states of east- ern Europe—because much of the cost of the As the problem of collective bads has not been a eastern pollution is visited on the western na- major concern of democratic theory, so too the tions. In the short term, however, economic dif- problem of nested collective actions has not been ferences might make such resolutions harder by addressed in democratic theory, perhaps because making them seem redistributive, because levels democratic theory has not yet gone interna- of economic development di¤er substantially tional. When applied to a domestic population, from east to west. democracy seems to yield relatively easy results Note that this resolution of the European of uniform policies on such issues as collective problems of collective bads is far from creating a Democracy and the Global Order 509

generally powerful supranational government. with sanctioning power, consensus that some The nations could merge little more than eco- pattern of behavior produces a severe bad im- nomic policy, although there are likely to be, as plies good prospects for regulation of the bad. In there have been, more or less inseparable social a quasi-anarchy of states with only dyadic rather issues that the Union might be forced to address. than centralized sanctioning power, a similar But it would not require a supranational police consensus may be less e¤ective in motivating force to control compliance with environmental regulation. The best hope for regulation may lie policies, because these could be coupled with in regional and other supranational organiza- other economic policies that have beneficial tions of states to address issues of economic consequences. The bad to be regulated would be relations. collective and its regulation would require more These organizations form relatively success- or less universal endogenous changes in behav- fully because their central problem is merely co- ior. But the policing of those changes in behavior ordination. Although there are conflictual issues would be done by each domestic government, at the edges and in the details of the coordina- and each domestic government would have its tion, coordination is the modal incentive struc- policies dyadically enforced by negotiation with ture. Once such organizations are established, each member state of the larger Union rather they can e¤ectively use the value of coordinating than by centralized directive, for which there with them as a dyadic sanction against those might be no authority. who do not join in resolutions of other issues Not to couple environmental and other eco- that are not merely coordination. By increasing nomic policies would inherently undercut the the geographical reach of policies on various point of the Union, which is to make internal issues, they can come much closer to domes- trade and production e‰cient across all the na- ticating collective bads that cross borders and tions of the Union. Very dirty production in one that, therefore, would allow member states to nation would allow that nation to externalize its externalize the burdens of the bads they produce costs of production to the other nations, through to other states. At the regional level, there might pollution that crosses borders, thus lowering its therefore be consensus on regulating some bad production costs and increasing its benefits from that none of the member states would have an marketing its production more competitively. interest in regulating on its own. A moderately National leaders who suppose that their nation anarchic world of geographically very large na- must yield economic advantages in submitting to tions and large regional organizations of nations a Union whose members are not all equally might therefore be expected to handle inter- advanced and productive have reason to temper national collective bads relatively well, even if their nationalist inclinations with concern for perhaps not as well as could a functioning de- gaining ways to control the generation of collec- mocracy with central power. tive bads in the less developed nations of the Union. As argued above, the focus of collective action References problems in international politics is distinctively di¤erent from that of domestic politics. Collec- Locke, John. 1963 (1690). ‘‘The second treatise of tive bads that are endogenously generated and government,’’ in Two Treatises of Government. Edited that must be endogenously regulated are now, by Peter Haslett. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. and for the near future of a generation or more, the main concern in the international politics of Scientific American. 1977. April: 27. collective action. In a democratic political order Representation and the Democratic Deficit

Pippa Norris

emphasis of EU institutions seek solutions to the Introduction democratic deficit in improving national super- vision, for instance through strengthening chan- Processes of political representation have to be nels of consultation and information between the understood within the context of the constitu- Commission and national parliaments, or by in- tional framework of the Union. These reflect a creasing the transparency of decision making in number of fundamental but unresolved con- the Council. troversies: whether the EU should be an inter- Governments acting in the Council of Minis- governmental organisation of sovereign states or ters remain accountable on a day-to-day basis to the top level of a federal European state; how their own national parliaments, and at regular decisions should be made and powers allocated intervals, via elections, to their citizens. In this among EU institutions; whether the EU should respect the Council of Ministers is similar to develop as a wider and looser association or a other intergovernmental organisations like the closer and more integrated unit; and how the United Nations, NATO or UNESCO. We people should be represented and the ‘‘demo- would not expect the public to have a direct say cratic deficit’’ cured. This last issue is particu- in issues such as whether the UN deploys peace- larly critical. The electorate influences the EU keeping forces or economic sanctions. Yet if through two channels: indirectly through their there is a popular backlash, for example if the choice of governments in national elections, American public becomes angry about heavy and directly through elections to the European losses for US forces deployed in UN missions, Parliament. . . . then at the next election they can hold their political leaders responsible, and ‘‘throw the ras- Indirect Channels of Representation via National cals out.’’ In this regard retrospective evalua- Governments tions of government performance are critical for accountability. Despite the substantial growth of Union powers, In the same way, it can be argued, following national institutions continue to retain the pri- G. A. Almond (1950) and V. O. Key (1961), that mary responsibility for ensuring democracy and there existed a ‘‘permissive consensus’’ over Eu- accountability in the Union (Kirchner 1992; rope so that governments were authorised to Keohane & Ho¤man 1991). The most important negotiate detailed European policies over com- law-making body remains the Council of Minis- plex issues like CAP, EMU and border controls ters, essentially an intergovernmental negotiating within the Council of Ministers. Surveys con- forum representing member states and acting sistently confirm that the general public is rarely behind closed doors. National governments also attentive to, or informed about, the arcane de- choose who is nominated for the European tails of highly technical and complex issues in Commission, which exercises executive powers. foreign policy. But if the public becomes dis- Those who want to retain the intergovernmental satisfied with the outcome of decisions with clear domestic consequences, for example if they blame the EU for rising levels of unemployment Excerpted from: Pippa Norris, ‘‘Representation and or cuts in the welfare state, and they blame their the Democratic Deficit.’’ European Journal of Political Research 32 (1997): 273–282. Reprinted by permission. government for EU policies (a critical step in the Democracy and the Global Order 511

chain of accountability), citizens always have 1991; Pryce 1987; Nicholl & Salmon 1990; recourse to the ballot box. In foreign policy, Kirchner 1992; Keohane & Ho¤man 1991). The therefore, governments may pay little attention European Commission, a rule-making institu- to public opinion towards technical issues like tion, is essentially a supranational body, as is the the Common Fisheries Policy, since these atti- independent Court of Justice; organised interest tudes may well be ill-informed and weakly groups are consulted through the Economic and rooted. Nevertheless in their negotiations minis- Social Committee, and the European Parliament ters may pay closer attention to the anticipated is chosen through direct election. Among federal reaction of their citizens to the outcome of these bodies, in the original treaties the European policies, and how opinion leaders may judge the parliament was envisaged as the institution actions of ministers on the final day of calling. which directly represented the voice of the Therefore domestic elections provide an indirect people, but with relatively weak powers. The mechanism to link the decisions by the Council original treaty gave the parliament only a con- of Ministers to the preferences of citizens in sultative role in the adoption of EU legislation member states. and the budget, and limited scrutiny over the Yet there are a series of problems with this Commission. The powers of the parliament were model. The lack of transparency about ‘‘who increased in a number of steps (see Du¤ 1994; said what’’ in negotiations behind the closed Jacobs 1992; Pinder 1991). Yet because states doors of the Council of Ministers, and the com- (notably the UK) have been reluctant to allow plexity of relating policy outputs to outcomes, any further erosion of national sovereignty, the makes it extremely di‰cult for the public to Council of Ministers remains the dominant evaluate the actions of their government within decision-making forum. While direct elections to Europe. Moreover the dominance of domestic the Parliament were envisaged, it was not until issues in national elections means that foreign 1979 that they took place (see Lodge 1982). policy is usually of low saliency on the public Moreover, there is almost unanimous agreement agenda. Lastly, the major parties rarely o¤er that these elections have been almost wholly voters clear alternative policy options concerning lacking in public interest: typically they are de- the major issues of European governance. Do- scribed as second-order national elections (Reif mestic elections are therefore an extremely blunt & Schmitt 1980). instrument for citizens to express policy prefer- All the core institutions play a part in EU ences. Nevertheless retrospective judgements decision making. While decision making is gen- about government performance within the Eu- erally labyrinthine in its complexity, the institu- ropean Union may produce a rough justice: if tions involved do have di¤erent constituencies the EU is blamed for economic conditions, ex- and, in principle, accountability is possible cessive bureaucracy or extravagant agricultural through the relationship between each institution spending, all governments may sink or swim and its constituency. Articles within this Special together. Issue focus on central aspects of one such rela- tionship, that between the public and the Euro- pean Parliament. They all address whether weak Direct Channels of Representation via the linkages between voters and the European Par- European Parliament liament, and flaws in the electoral and parlia- mentary mechanism of political representation, Yet much of the EU is federal, meaning that contribute significantly to the democratic deficit certain powers are transferred to European within the European Union. bodies above national governments (see Pinder Chapter 9 512

lined by the June 1994 European elections, with The Breakdown of the ‘‘Permissive Consensus’’? record apathy in voter turnout, and gains for anti-Maastricht protest parties in France, Den- The problem of the ‘‘democratic deficit’’ is mark and Spain (van der Eijk & Franklin 1996). whether these direct and indirect channels are In 1996 these strains to the system were exa- e¤ective in connecting the preferences of citizens cerbated and dramatized by the economic di‰- to the outcome of EU decisionmaking. During culties of achieving the strict convergence criteria the early years of the Community the techno- for European Monetary Union, resulting in se- cratic and diplomatic elite determined the direc- vere cuts in the welfare state in France and Italy. tion of European development, much as they This was compounded by the political problems controlled bodies such as NATO, with the tacit of persuading the public to abandon the familiar approval of a permissive consensus among mass German Mark, French Franc and Pound Ster- publics. The idea of a ‘‘permissive consensus’’ ling in their pockets for the unknown Euro. The implies general support within public opinion, problem of the democratic deficit, given these with passive approval which is widespread if stresses, is not just marginal to the enterprise, but shallowly rooted, and which may allow future central to the European project. . . . government action (Key 1961: 32–35). But there was always concern that public opinion about the future of Europe was somewhat fragile. Public Confidence in the Union Given limited popular participation in, and identification with, the European Union, deci- How serious is the crisis of public confidence in sions might easily be made by elites that would the Union? Is this merely a passing phase, trig- neither reflect, nor be seen to reflect, popular gered by temporary discontent with particular wishes. policies, or a more serious erosion of faith in The breakdown in this consensus first became European integration? . . . The dilemma facing evident in the early 1990s. The defeat of the the European Union, along with many emerging proposal to adopt the Maastricht Treaty in the and consolidating democracies in divided nation- Danish referendum of 1992, and then the ‘‘petit states, is how to build public support simulta- oui’’ in France, produced a realization that at neously across both levels. If there is widespread least some governments might be significantly confidence in the underlying constitutional out of touch with their electorate (Franklin, van order, and a strong sense of identity with the der Eijk & Marsh 1995; Franklin, Marsh & community, then it becomes easier to resolve McLaren 1994). The backlash against Maas- particular policy conflicts. But if the legitimacy tricht and the ratification crisis were attributed, of the basic political system remains under ques- at least in part, to a lack of public engagement tion, if European leaders are largely invisible to and popular debate about integration (Baun the public, and if there is little ‘‘glue’’ provided 1996). The period from 1991–92 saw a sharp fall by a sense of European identity to hold disparate in public support towards the European Union, countries together, then it becomes more di‰cult across the standard indicators in the Euro- to resolve substantive policy conflicts. Moreover Barometer (Niedermayer & Sinnott 1995: 58– many decisions about specific issues—like Euro- 59). This fall was not just confined to opinion pean Monetary Union, border controls, or the polls, as it occasionally found expression in European Social Chapter—have significant ram- violent actions, such as opposition by intense ifications for national sovereignty, and therefore minorities to farming and fisheries policies. cannot be decoupled from the constitutional Problems of EU legitimacy were further under- framework. In this context the rules of the game Democracy and the Global Order 513

are under dispute, as well as the division of these groups are weak umbrella organisations, at spoils. best (Pedersen 1996). Nevertheless Thomassen Although pressing, the di‰cult problems of and Schmitt provide evidence for the roots of institutional reform have consistently taken a an evolving party system in the European Par- back seat to substantive issues of European inte- liament. Their study analyses how far the po- gration. Maastricht was essentially about the litical attitudes of candidates and voters are projects on EMU, common foreign and security constrained by the European party group with policy, and enhanced cooperation in policing which their national party is associated. By and justice (Du¤ et al. 1994; Baun 1996). Prob- comparing the position of candidates and voters lems of institutional reform are part of the towards the issues of a single European cur- agenda of the Inter-Governmental Conference rency, unemployment policy and national bor- (IGC), which first met in March 1996. In his ders, as well as left-right self-placement, the opening address to the European Parliament study found that the roots of a European party the President, Klaus Hansch, emphasized that system is evident among candidates, and, to a the conference would be crucial in injecting lesser extent, among the electorate. This embry- more democracy into existing procedures, and in onic party system is based on the familiar left- making decisionmaking institutions more e¤ec- right ideological cleavages which serve to shape tive. The basic decisionmaking structures were so much of European domestic politics. Never- adopted by the Treaty of Rome, in 1957, when theless there remains a large and significant the Community had six members. By 1996 the gap between the attitudes of mass and elite on EU has fifteen member states and, with more these issues, with political leaders far more in envisaged, the complicated decisionmaking pro- favour of European integration than the general cess threatens to become grid-locked. public. This suggests that the emerging party . . . Yet recently politics within the Union has system in Parliament needs to be strengthened focussed less on institutional reform than on the further—organisationally,programmatically,and serious problems of fiscal discipline, and cut- financially—to increase representation via re- backs in government spending, raised by the at- sponsible parties. tempt by countries to meet the strict convergence Social representation presents other problems criteria required for European Monetary Union for the legitimacy of the European parliament. in 1999. Norris and Franklin consider how far the par- liament ‘‘looks like a mirror of European soci- ety.’’ As in most legislative bodies, there are Conclusions clear social biases which mean that the European parliament underrepresents women, the younger If institutional reforms are to prove e¤ective, generation, and working class socio-economic they must be based on a clear grasp of how the groups. This study considers how far we can ex- representative mechanisms in the Union function plain this pattern is terms of a model of ‘‘supply at present. The conclusions from this Special and demand.’’ The paper concludes that supply- Issue is that there are a variety of channels of side factors proved more strongly related to representation, and some are more e¤ective than candidates gaining winnable seats—and thus others. Thomassen and Schmitt analysed the re- election to the European parliament—than sponsible party model of representation, to see demand-side factors. In other words, the re- whether European party groups are developing sources and motivation which candidates bring distinct and coherent policy positions on the to the recruitment process are the primary fac- major issues facing the Union. Some argue that tors explaining why some aspirants succeed Chapter 9 514

while others fail. Equally important, the results are socialised into prioritising activities during confirmed that women’s representation was their early careers in the European Parliament. strongly influenced by institutional structures, The paper by Michael Marsh and Bernhard including the electoral system, party system and Wessels goes further by analysing candidates political culture. More women are elected in and members as territorial representatives, de- protestant countries, countries with strong left- fending national interests within the European wing parties, and countries with proportional list parliament, rather than being bound by party electoral systems, than elsewhere. This suggests discipline. The study compared the attitudes of that the European parliament, in common with candidates, MEPs and publics within each most legislative bodies, will continue to remain country, to analyse the degree of policy congru- socially unrepresentative for many years, al- ence between them. Marsh and Wessels confirm though parties can take e¤ective action in their the pattern noted earlier that the elite are far recruitment processes to make sure that their more strongly in favour of European integration ticket includes candidates from more diverse so- than the electorate. But, interestingly, the gap cial backgrounds. between mass and elite was far greater in some The roles which MEPs adopt may have im- countries than others. The paper concludes that portant consequences for other types of repre- these cross-national di¤erences are due, at least sentation, including functional linkages with in part, to di¤erent electoral and party systems. interest groups, and service work with individual In particular, more proportional electoral sys- problems. Richard Katz explored the signifi- tems and the inclusion of smaller parties produce cance of these role orientations for members of MEPs who are closer to their general publics on the European Parliament. Looking at the prior- the European issues under comparison. This has ities given to di¤erent tasks, Katz found that important implications, not just for the Euro- three roles clearly predominated among candi- pean parliament, but also for broader debates dates. Some saw themselves in an intergovern- about the consequences of constitutional designs mental view of the Union as representing on political representation. national interests, stressing the importance of Lastly, we can turn to behavioural indicators loyalties to national parties. The second group of public attitudes towards the European Par- saw themselves primarily as constituency agents, liament by comparing turnout in European giving priority to helping people with particular elections. Voting participation is commonly re- problems and service activity. The last group garded as one major indicator of the health of a perceived their roles as ‘‘trustees,’’ using their democracy, reflecting trust and confidence in own judgement about public policy rather than the political system, although systematic studies following national or European party policies. suggest a complex relationship between attitudes Katz goes on to consider explanations for these and behaviour. Blondel, Sinnott and Svensson di¤erences in role priorities, and to explore their consider why there is such cross-national vari- consequences for legislative behaviour. Even if ance in the turnout to European elections. On parties remain weak, this suggests that through average 58.5 percent of the European electorate casework for individuals or local groups MEPs voted in 1994, but the proportion was far lower who prioritise this activity may provide an e¤ec- in some countries like the UK, the Netherlands tive conduit between citizens and the complex- and Portugal. The study concludes that institu- ities of the European decision making process. tional factors played a major role in explaining We need to go further to understand the origins these di¤erences. The e¤ects of compulsory vot- of these role perceptions, and how new MEPs ing and concomitant national elections are obvi- Democracy and the Global Order 515

ous, yet also very important. Other institutional support for Europe in the wake of Maastricht, Journal variables, including proportional electoral sys- of West European Politics 18(3): 101–117. tems and Sunday voting, also proved significant Jacobs, F., Corbett, R. & Shackleton, M. (1992). The although the e¤ects of these factors are not European Parliament, 2nd edn. Harlow: Longman. wholly straightforward. Lastly Blondel et al. Key, V. O. (1961). Public opinion and American de- conclude that as well as improvements to the mocracy. New York: Alfred A. Knopf. practical arrangements for elections, turnout Keohane, R. & Ho¤mann, S., eds. (1991). The new could be boosted by more e¤ective mobilisation European Community: Decision-making and institu- campaigns by parties, and by a more positive tional change. Boulder, CO: Westview Press. image for the European Parliament, the Union, Kirchner, E. (1992). Decision-making in the European and European integration. Voters were some- Community. Manchester: Manchester University Press. what more motivated to go to the polls if they Lodge, J. (1982). Direct elections to the European Par- felt involved with, and knowledgeable about, liament. London: Macmillan. European a¤airs. The results suggest that the Nicholl, W. & Salmon, T. (1990). Understanding the problems of representation in the European European Community. Hemel Hempsted: Philip Allan. Union could be addressed by a series of alterna- Niedermayer, O. & Sinnott, R., eds. (1995). Public tive steps and that, unless reforms are imple- opinion and internationalized governance. Oxford: Ox- mented, the problems of linkage between citizen ford University Press. and the Union . . . can only be expected to be- Norris, P. (1997). Electoral change since 1945. Oxford: come more evident under the stresses of broad- Blackwell. ening and deepening the European Union. Pinder, J. (1991). European Community: The building of a Union. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Pryce, R., ed. (1987). The dynamics of European Union. References London: Routledge. Reif, K. & Schmitt, H. (1980). Nine second-order na- Almond, G. A. (1950). The American people and for- tional elections: A conceptual framework for the anal- eign policy. New York: Praeger. ysis of European election results, European Journal of Baun, M. J. (1996). An imperfect Union: The Maas- Political Research 8: 3–44. tricht Treaty and the new politics of European integra- tion. Boulder, CO: Westview Press. Du¤, A., Pinder, J. & Pryce, R. (1994). Maastricht and beyond. London: Routledge. Easton, D. (1975). A reassessment of the concept of political support, British Journal of Political Science 5: 435–57. van de Eijk, C., Franklin, M. et al. (1996). Choosing Europe? The European electorate and national politics in the face of the Union. Ann Arbor, MI: The Univer- sity of Michigan Press. Franklin, M., Marsh, M. & McLaren, L. (1994). Un- corking the bottle: Popular opposition to European unification in the wake of Maastricht, Journal of Com- mon Market Studies 32(4): 455–472. Franklin, M., van der Eijk, C. & Marsh, M. (1995). Referendum outcomes and trust in government: Public The Transformation of Political Community: Rethinking Democracy in the Context of Globalization

David Held

This chapter focuses on the changing nature of democratic life (see Held 1995 and 1996). It of political community in the context of is argued that only by buttressing democracy, globalization—in brief, the growing inter- within and across nation states, can the ac- connectedness, and intensification of relations, countability of power in the contemporary era be among states and societies. The chapter has a strengthened. . . . number of parts. In the first part, I explore the Built, as it was, upon an emerging concep- changing forms of political association and, in tion of the modern nation state, the development particular, the rise of the modern nation state as of liberal democracy took place within a fairly a background against which modern conceptions delimited conceptual space (cf. Walker 1988; of democracy developed. With this in mind, I Connolly 1991; McGrew 1997). Modern demo- examine some of the key assumptions and pre- cratic theory and practice was constructed upon suppositions of liberal democracy; above all, its Westphalian foundations. National communi- conception of political community. In the second ties, and theories of national communities, were part, I explore changing forms of globalization. based on the presupposition that political In my view, globalization has been with us communities could, in principle, control their for some time, but its extent, intensity, and im- destinies and citizens could come to identify suf- pact have changed fundamentally. In the third ficiently with each other such that they might and final part of the essay, the implications of think and act together with a view of what was changing forms of globalization are explored in best for all of them, that is, with a view of the relation to the prospects of democratic political common good (Sandel 1996: 202). It was taken community. A particular conception of democ- for granted that, bar internal di‰culties, the racy is elaborated, a form of transnational de- demos, the extent of the franchise, the form and mocracy, which, it is argued, is more appropriate scope of representation, and the nature and to the developing structure of political associa- meaning of consent—in fact all the key elements tions today. The future of democracy is set out in of self-determination—could be specified with cosmopolitan terms—a new democratic complex respect to geography: systems of representation with global scope, given shape and form by ref- and democratic accountability could be neatly erence to a basic democratic law, which takes on meshed with the spatial reach of sites of power the character of government to the extent, and in a circumscribed territory. Moreover, as a only to the extent, that it promulgates, imple- consequence of this, clear-cut distinctions could ments, and enforces this law. This is by no means be elaborated—and national institutions built a prescription for the end of the nation state or upon—the di¤erence between ‘‘internal’’ and the end of democratic politics as we know it—far ‘‘external’’ policy, between domestic and foreign from it. Rather, it is a recipe for the enrichment a¤airs. The vast majority of the theories of de- mocracy, liberal and radical, assumed that the Excerpted from: David Held, ‘‘The Transformation of nature and possibilities of political community Political Community: Rethinking Democracy in the could be elaborated by reference to national Context of Globalization.’’ In Democracy’s Edges, structures and national possibilities, and that edited by Ian Shapiro and Casiano Hacker-Cordo´n. freedom, political equality and solidarity could Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1999. 6 be entrenched in and through the nation state. Cambridge University Press, 1999. Reprinted with the This became the cornerstone of modern demo- permission of Cambridge University Press. cratic thought. . . . Democracy and the Global Order 517

. . . [T]he theory of democracy, particularly as in isolation as bounded geographical totalities; it emerged in the nineteenth and twentieth cen- they are better thought of as multiple over- turies, could take for granted the link between lapping networks of interaction. These networks the demos, citizenship, electoral mechanisms, the crystallize around di¤erent sites and forms of nature of consent, and the boundaries of the na- power—economic, political, military, cultural, tion state. The fates of di¤erent political com- among others—producing diverse patterns of munities may be intertwined, but the appropriate activity which do not correspond in any simple place for determining the foundation of ‘‘na- and straightforward way to territorial bound- tional fate’’ was the national community itself. aries (see Mann 1986: chap. 1). The spatial reach In the contemporary era the key principles and of the modern nation state did not fix imperme- practices of liberal democracy are associated able borders for other networks, the scope and almost exclusively with the principles and insti- reach of which have been as much local as in- tutions of the sovereign nation state. Further, ternational or even global. Modern political modern democratic theory and democratic communities are, and have always been, locked politics assumes a symmetry and congruence into a diversity of processes and structures which between citizen-voters and national decision- range in and through them. The theory and makers. Through the ballot box, citizen-voters practice of the democratic sovereign state has are, in principle, able to hold decision-makers to always been in some tension with the actuality account; and, as a result of electoral consent, of state sovereignty and autonomy. National decision-makers are able to make and pursue law political communities do not always make and and policy legitimately for their constituents, ul- determine decisions and policies simply for timately, the people in a fixed, territorially based themselves, and governments do not always community. Accordingly, the heart or ‘‘deep make policies and decisions exclusively for their structure’’ of the system of democratic nation citizens (see O¤e 1985). The freedom of action states can be characterized by a number of of particular political communities has always striking features, which are, broadly: democracy been, to varying degrees, constrained. How in nation states and non-democratic relations should one understand these patterns of inter- among states; the entrenchment of account- connections, and their changing form over ability and democratic legitimacy inside state time? And how should one understand their boundaries and pursuit of reasons of state (and political implications, in particular, for sover- maximum political advantage) outside such eignty, autonomy, and the democratic political boundaries; democracy and citizenship rights for community? those regarded as ‘‘insiders,’’ and the frequent The term ‘‘globalization’’ captures some of the negation of these rights for those beyond their changes which shape the nature of the political borders. and the prospects of political community; un- packing this term helps create a framework for addressing some of the issues raised above. Changing Forms of Regional and Global Globalization can be understood, I believe, in Enmeshment relation to a set of processes which shift the spatial form of human organization and activity At the centre of the dominant theoretical ap- to transcontinental or interregional patterns of proaches to democratic politics is an uncritically activity, interaction and the exercise of power appropriated concept of the territorial political (see Held, McGrew, Goldblatt, and Perraton community. The di‰culty with this is that polit- 1999). It involves a stretching and deepening of ical communities have rarely—if ever—existed social relations and institutions across space and Chapter 9 518

time such that, on the one hand, day-to-day reaching unprecedented levels, particularly in the activities are increasingly influenced by events post–World War II period. Not only has there happening on the other side of the globe and, been an increase in intraregional trade around on the other, the practices and decisions of the world, but there has also been sustained local groups or communities can have significant growth among regions as well (see Perraton, global reverberations (see Giddens 1990). . . . Goldblatt, Held, and McGrew 1997). More Globalization is neither a singular condition countries are involved in global trading arrange- nor a linear process. Rather, it is best thought of ments, for instance, India and China, and more as a multidimensional phenomenon involving people and nations are a¤ected by such arrange- domains of activity and interaction that include ments. If there is a further lowering of tari¤ bar- the economic, political, technological, military, riers across the world, these trends are likely to legal, cultural, and environmental. Each of these continue and to further the extension, intensity, spheres involves di¤erent patterns of relations and impact of trade relations on other domains and activities. A general account of globalization of life. The expansion of global financial flows cannot simply predict from one domain what has, moreover, been particularly rapid in the last will occur in another. It is extremely important, ten to fifteen years. Foreign exchange turnover then, to keep these distinctive domains separate has mushroomed and is now over 1.2 trillion and to build a theory of globalization and its dollars a day. Much of this financial activity is impact on particular political communities from speculative and generates fluctuations in prices an understanding of what is happening in each (of stocks, shares, futures, etc.) in excess of those and every one of them. . . . which can be accounted for by changes in the Against this background, the meaning and fundamentals of asset values. The enormous place of political community, and particularly of growth of global financial flows across borders, the democratic political community, needs to be linked to the liberalization of capital markets re-examined. At least two tasks are necessary in from the late 1970s, has created a more inte- order to pursue this objective. First, it is impor- grated financial system than has ever been tant to illustrate some of the fundamental al- known. terations in the patterns of interconnectedness Underpinning this economic shift has been among political communities and the subsequent the growth of multinational corporations, both shifts in the structure and form of political productive and financial. Approximately 20,000 community itself. Secondly, it is important to set multinational corporations now account for a out some of the political implications of these quarter to a third of world output, 70 percent of changes. In what follows, I start by illustrating world trade, and 80 percent of foreign direct in- some of the transformations which have brought vestment. They are essential to the di¤usion of a change in the organization and meaning of skills and technology, and they are key players in political community. Clearly, these are indicative the international money markets. In addition, transformations only; they obviously fall short of multinational corporations can have profound a systematic account (see Held, McGrew, Gold- a¤ects on macroeconomic policy. . . . blatt, and Perraton 1999). Against this background, the traditional (1) Among the significant developments which claims of democratic theory—above all, the are changing the nature of political community claims to the possibility of a circumscribed, de- are global economic processes, especially growth limited self-determining community of citizens in trade, production, and financial transactions, —begin to appear strained. organized in part by rapidly expanding multina- It is easy to misrepresent the political signifi- tional companies. Trade has grown substantially, cance of the globalization of economic activity. Democracy and the Global Order 519

There are those, earlier referred to as the ‘‘hyper- labour movements’’ (Goldblatt, Held, McGrew, globalizers,’’ who argue that we now live in a and Perraton 1997: 74). As a result, the auton- world in which social and economic processes omy of democratically elected governments has operate predominantly at a global level (see been, and is increasingly, constrained by sources Ohmae 1990; Reich 1991). . . . of unelected and unrepresentative economic But the claims of the hyper-globalizers and power. These have the e¤ect of making adjust- their critics misstate much of what is significant ment to the international economy (and, above about contemporary economic globalization for all, to global financial markets) a fixed point of politics. Nation states continue to be immensely orientation in economic policy and of encourag- powerful, and enjoy access to a formidable range ing an acceptance of the ‘‘decision signals’’ of its of resources, bureaucratic infrastructural ca- leading agents and forces as a, if not the, stan- pacity, and technologies of coordination and dard of rational decision-making. The options control. The continuing lobbying of states by for political communities, and the costs and multinational corporations confirm the enduring benefits of them, ineluctably alter. importance of states to the mediation and regu- (2) Within the realms of the media and culture lation of economic activity. Yet it is wrong to there are also grounds for thinking that there is argue that globalization is a mere illusion, an a growing disjuncture between the idea of the ideological veil, that allows politicians simply to democratic state as an independent, accountable disguise the causes of poor performance and centre of power bounded by fixed borders—in policy failure. Although the rhetoric of hyper- this case, a centre of national culture, able to globalization has provided many an elected pol- foster and sustain a national identity—and itician with a conceptual resource for refusing interlinked changes in the spheres of media and political responsibility, globalization has sig- cultural exchange. A number of developments nificant and discernible characteristics which in recent times can be highlighted. English has alter the balance of resources—economic and spread as the dominant language of elite cul- political—within and across borders. Among the tures throughout the world: it is now the domi- most important of these is the tangible growth nant language in business, computing, law, in the enmeshment of national economies in science, and politics. The internationalization global economic transactions (i.e., a growing and globalization of telecommunications have proportion of nearly all national economies are been extraordinarily rapid: international tele- involved in international economic exchanges phone tra‰c has increased over fourfold between with an increasing number of countries). This 1983 and 1995; there has been a massive increase increase in the extent and intensity of economic in transnational cable links; there has been an interconnectedness has altered the relation be- explosion in satellite links; and the Internet has tween economic and political power. One shift provided a remarkable increase in the infra- has been particularly significant: ‘‘the historic structure of horizontal and lateral commu- expansion of exit options for capital in financial nication capacity within and across borders. markets relative to national capital controls, Moreover, substantial multimedia conglom- national banking regulations and national in- erates have developed, such as the Murdoch vestment strategies, and the sheer volume of empire and Time Warner. In addition, there has privately held capital relative to national re- been a huge increase in tourism—for example, serves. Exit options for corporations making di- in 1960 there were 70 million international tour- rect investments have also expanded . . . the ists, while in 1994 there were nearly 500 million. balance of power has shifted in favour of capital And in television and film there are similar vis-a`-vis both national governments and national trends. Chapter 9 520

None of the above examples, or the accumu- new cultural, scientific, and intellectual net- lative impact of parallel cases, should be taken to works; new environmental movements with imply the development of a single global, media- transnational organizations and transnational led culture (consider the impact of Star television concerns; and new institutions and conventions in India), but certainly, taken together, these such as those agreed in 1992 at the Earth developments do imply that many new forms Summit in Brazil. Not all environmental prob- of communication media range in and across lems are, of course, global; such an implication borders, linking nations and peoples in new would be entirely false. But there has been a ways. The creation and recreation of new forms striking shift in the physical and environmental of identity—often linked to consumption and conditions—that is, in the extent and intensity the entertainment industries—are not to be of environmental problems—a¤ecting human underestimated. In this context, the capacity of a¤airs in general. . . . Thus, questions are raised national political leaders to sustain a na- both about the fate of the idea of political com- tional culture has become more complex and munity and about the appropriate locus for the di‰cult. . . . articulation of the democratic political good. (3) Environmental problems and challenges The proper ‘‘home’’ of politics and democracy are perhaps the clearest and starkest examples becomes a puzzling matter. of the global shift in human organization and (4) Changes in the development of interna- activity, creating some of the most fundamental tional law have placed individuals, governments pressures on the e‰cacy of the nation state and and non-governmental organizations under new state-centric democratic politics. There are three systems of legal regulation. International law types of problems at issue: recognizes powers and constraints, and rights and duties, which have qualified the principle of a) the first is shared problems involving the state sovereignty in a number of important re- global commons, i.e., fundamental elements of spects; sovereignty per se is no longer a straight- the ecosystem—among the most significant forward guarantee of international legitimacy. challenges here are global warming and ozone Entrenched in certain legal instruments is the depletion; view that a legitimate state must be a democratic b) a second category of global environ- state that upholds certain common values (see mental problems involves the interlinked chal- Crawford 1994). One significant area in this re- lenges of demographic expansion and resource gard is human rights law and human rights consumption—pressing examples under this regimes. . . . heading include desertification, questions of bio- In international law, accordingly, there has diversity, and threats to the existence of certain been a gradual shift away from the principle that species; state sovereignty must be safeguarded irrespec- c) a third category of problems is transboundary tive of its consequences for individuals, groups, pollution such as acid rain, or river pollutants, or and organizations. Respect for the autonomy of the contaminated rain which fell in connection the subject, and for an extensive range of human with Chernobyl. rights, creates a new set of ordering principles in political a¤airs which can delimit and curtail the In response to the progressive development of, principle of e¤ective state power. Along with and publicity surrounding, environmental prob- other international legal changes (see Held 1995: lems in the last three decades, there has been chap. 5), these developments are indicative of an interlinked process of cultural and political an alteration in the weight granted, on the one globalization as illustrated by the emergence of hand, to claims made on behalf of the state sys- Democracy and the Global Order 521

tem and, on the other hand, to those made on Democracy and Globalization: In Sum behalf of an alternative organizing principle of world order, in which an unqualified state sov- At the end of the second millennium, as indi- ereignty no longer reigns supreme. cated previously, political communities and civi- (5) While all the developments described so far lizations can no longer be characterized simply have helped engender a shift away from a purely as ‘‘discrete worlds’’; they are enmeshed and state-centered international system of ‘‘high pol- entrenched in complex structures of overlapping itics’’ to new and novel forms of geogovernance, forces, relations, and movements. Clearly, these a further interesting example of this process can are often structured by inequality and hierarchy, be drawn from the very heart of the idea of a but even the most powerful among them— sovereign state—national security and defense including the most powerful nation states—do policy. There has been a notable increase in em- not remain una¤ected by the changing con- phasis upon collective defense and cooperative ditions and processes of regional and global en- security. The enormous costs, technological re- trenchment. Five central points can be noted quirements, and domestic burdens of defense are to help characterize the changing relationship contributing to the strengthening of multilateral between globalization and democratic nation and collective defense arrangements as well as states. All indicate an increase in the extensive- international military cooperation and coordi- ness, intensity, and impact of globalization, and nation (see Held, McGrew, Goldblatt, and Per- all suggest important points about the evolving raton 1999: chap. 2 for an elaborate discussion). character of the democratic political community. The rising density of technological connections First, the locus of e¤ective political power between states now challenges the very idea of can no longer be assumed to be national national security and national arms procure- governments—e¤ective power is shared, bar- ment. Some of the most advanced weapons- tered, and struggled over by diverse forces and systems in the world today, e.g., fighter aircraft, agencies at national, regional and international depend on components which come from many levels. Second, the idea of a political community countries.1 There has been a globalization of of fate—of a self-determining collectivity—can military technology linked to a transnationaliza- no longer meaningfully be located within the tion of defense production. And the proliferation boundaries of a single nation state alone. Some of weapons of mass destruction makes all states of the most fundamental forces and processes insecure and makes problematical the very no- which determine the nature of life-chances within tions of ‘‘friends’’ and ‘‘enemies.’’ and across political communities are now be- Even in the sphere of defense and arms pro- yond the reach of nation states. The system of duction and manufacture, the notion of a singu- national political communities persists of course; lar, discrete, and delimited political community but it is articulated and re-articulated today with appears problematic. Indeed, even in this realm, complex economic, organizational, administra- any conception of sovereignty and autonomy tive, legal, and cultural processes and structures which assumes that they denote an indivisible, which limit and check its e‰cacy. If these pro- illimitable, exclusive, and perpetual form of cesses and structures are not acknowledged and public power—embodied within an individual brought into the political process themselves, state—is increasingly challenged and eroded. they will tend to bypass or circumvent the dem- ocratic state system. Third, there is a growing set 1. I am indebted to Anthony McGrew for this point. of disjunctures between the formal authority of Chapter 9 522

the state—that is, the formal domain of political thought, problems which ultimately concern the authority that states claim for themselves—and very basis of democratic authority. . . . the actual practices and structures of the state and economic system at the regional and global levels. These disjunctures indicate that national Rethinking Democracy in the Context of communities do not exclusively program the ac- Globalization tion and decisions of governmental and par- liamentary bodies, and the latter by no means In the liberal democracies, consent to govern- simply determine what is right or appropriate for ment and legitimacy for governmental action are their own citizens (see Held 1995: chaps. 5 and 6; dependent upon electoral politics and the ballot cf. O¤e 1985: 286¤ ). box. Yet the notions that consent legitimates Fourth, it is not part of my argument that government, and that the ballot box is the ap- national sovereignty today, even in regions propriate mechanism whereby the citizen body with intensive overlapping and divided politi- as a whole periodically confers authority on cal and authority structures, has been wholly government to enact the law and regulate eco- subverted—not at all. But it is part of my argu- nomic and social life, become problematic as ment that there are significant areas and regions soon as the nature of a ‘‘relevant community’’ is marked by criss-crossing loyalties, conflicting contested. What is the proper constituency, and interpretations of rights and duties, intercon- proper realm of jurisdiction, for developing and nected legal and authority structures, etc., which implementing policy with respect to health issues displace notions of sovereignty as an illimitable, such as AIDS or BSE (Bovine Spongiform indivisible, and exclusive form of public power. Encephalopathy), the use of nuclear energy, the The operations of states in increasingly complex management of nuclear waste, the harvesting of regional and global systems both a¤ects their rain forests, the use of non-renewable resources, autonomy (by changing the balance between the the instability of global financial markets, the costs and benefits of policies) and their sover- reduction of the risks of chemical and nuclear eignty (by altering the balance between national, warfare? National boundaries have traditionally regional, and international legal frameworks and demarcated the basis on which individuals are administrative practices). . . . included and excluded from participation in Fifth, the late twentieth century is marked by decisions a¤ecting their lives; but if many a significant series of new types of ‘‘boundary socio-economic processes, and the outcomes of problem.’’ If it is accepted that we live in a world decisions about them, stretch beyond national of overlapping communities of fate, where the frontiers, then the implications of this are seri- trajectories of each and every country are more ous, not only for the categories of consent and tightly entwined than ever before, then new types legitimacy but for all the key ideas of democracy. of boundary problem follow. . . . In a world At issue is the nature of a constituency (how where powerful states make decisions not just for should the proper boundaries of a constituency their peoples but for others as well, and where be drawn?), the meaning of representation (who transnational actors and forces cut across the should represent whom and on what basis?), and boundaries of national communities in diverse the proper form and scope of political participa- ways, the questions of who should be account- tion (who should participate and in what way?). able to whom, and on what grounds, do not As fundamental processes of governance escape easily resolve themselves. Overlapping spheres of the categories of the nation state, the traditional influence, interference, and interest create fun- national resolutions of the key questions of dem- damental problems at the centre of democratic ocratic theory and practice are open to doubt. Democracy and the Global Order 523

Against this background, the nature and accounted for in relation to, democratic public prospects of the democratic polity need re- law. examination. I have argued elsewhere that an The idea of such an order, however, can no acceptance of liberal democratic politics, in longer be simply defended as an idea suitable to theory and practice, entails an acceptance of a particular closed political community or nation each citizen’s equal interest in democracy; that state. We are compelled to recognize that we live is, a recognition of people’s equal interest in self- in a complex interconnected world where the determination (Held 1995: part III). Each adult extent, intensity, and impact of issues (economic, has an interest in political autonomy as a result political, or environmental) raise questions about of his or her status as a citizen with an equal where those issues are most appropriately ad- entitlement to self-determination. An equal in- dressed. Deliberative and decision-making cen- terest in political autonomy requires, I have also tres beyond national territories are appropriately argued, that citizens enjoy a common structure situated when those significantly a¤ected by a of political action. A common structure of polit- public matter constitute a cross-border or trans- ical action entails a shared enjoyment of a cluster national grouping, when ‘‘lower’’ levels of of rights and obligations. This cluster of rights decision-making cannot manage and discharge and obligations has traditionally been thought of satisfactorily transnational or international pol- as entailing, above all, civil and political rights icy questions, and when the principle of demo- and obligations. Again, elsewhere, I have argued cratic legitimacy can only be properly redeemed that this cluster has to bite more deeply than civil in a transnational context (see Held 1995: chap. and political rights alone; for the latter leave 10). If the most powerful geopolitical interests large swathes of power untouched by mecha- are not to settle many pressing matters simply in nisms of access, accountability, and control. At terms of their objectives and by virtue of their stake, in short, is a recognition that a common power, then new institutions and mechanisms of structure of political action requires a cluster of accountability need to be established. rights and obligations which cut across all key In the context of contemporary forms of domains of power, where power shapes and globalization, for democratic law to be e¤ective a¤ects people’s life-chances with determinate it must be internationalized. Thus, the imple- e¤ects on and implications for their political mentation of what I call a cosmopolitan demo- agency. cratic law and the establishment of a community I think of the cluster of rights and obligations of all democratic communities—a cosmopolitan that will create the basis of a common structure community—must become an obligation for of political action as constituting the elements of democrats; an obligation to build a transna- a democratic public law. If power is to be held tional, common structure of political action accountable wherever it is located—in the state, which alone, ultimately, can support the politics the economy, or cultural sphere—then a com- of self-determination. mon structure of political action needs to be In this conception, the nation state ‘‘withers entrenched and enforced through a democratic away.’’ But this is not to say that states and na- public law. Such a notion, I believe, can coher- tional democratic polities become redundant. ently link the ideas of democracy and of the There are many good reasons for doubting the modern state. The key to this is the notion of theoretical and empirical basis of claims that a democratic legal order—an order which is nation states will disappear. Rather, withering bound by democratic public law in all its away means that states can no longer be, and a¤airs. A democratic legal order—a democratic can no longer be regarded as, the sole centres of Rechtstaat—is an order circumscribed by, and legitimate power within their own borders, as is Chapter 9 524

already the case in diverse settings. States need to ical communities, and of the wider regional and be articulated with, and relocated within, an global networks which impacted upon their lives. overarching democratic law. Within this frame- This cosmopolitan polity would be one that in work, the laws and rules of the nation state form and substance reflected and embraced the would be but one focus for legal development, diverse forms of power and authority that oper- political reflection, and mobilization. For this ate within and across borders and which, if framework would respecify and reconstitute the unchecked, threaten the emergence of a highly meaning and limits of sovereign authority. Par- fragmented, neo-medieval order. ticular power centers and authority systems It would be easy to be pessimistic about the would enjoy legitimacy only to the extent that future of democracy. There are plenty of reasons they upheld and enacted democratic law. . . . for pessimism; they include the fact that the es- Thus, sovereignty can be stripped away from sential political units of the world are still based the idea of fixed borders and territories. Sover- on nation states while some of the most power- eignty would become an attribute of the basic ful socio-political forces of the world escape the democratic law, but it could be entrenched and boundaries of these units. . . . drawn upon in diverse self-regulating realms, But there are other forces at work which from regions and states to cities and local asso- create the basis for a more optimistic reading of ciations. Cosmopolitan law would demand the democratic prospects. . . . Today, we live at an- subordination of regional, national, and local other fundamental point of transition, but now sovereignties to an overarching legal framework, to a more transnational, global world. There are but in this framework associations would be self- forces and pressures which are engendering a governing at di¤erent levels. A new possibility is reshaping of political cultures, institutions, and anticipated: the recovery of an intensive and structures. First, one must obviously note the more participatory democracy at local levels as a emergence, however hesitatingly, of regional and complement to the public assemblies of the wider global institutions in the twentieth century. The global order; that is, a political order of demo- UN is, of course, weak in many respects, but it cratic associations, cities, and nations as well as is a relatively recent creation and it is an inno- of regions and global networks. I call this else- vative structure which can be built upon. It is a where the cosmopolitan model of democracy— normative resource which provides—for all its it is a legal basis of a global and divided author- di‰culties—an enduring example of how na- ity system, a system of diverse and overlapping tions might (and sometimes do) cooperate better power centres, shaped and delimited by demo- to resolve, and resolve fairly, common problems. cratic law (Held 1995 and 1996). However the In addition, the development of a powerful re- model is specified precisely, it is based upon gional body such as the European Union is a re- the recognition that the nature and quality of markable state of a¤airs. Just over fifty years ago democracy within a particular community and Europe was at the point of self-destruction. Since the nature and quality of democratic relations that moment Europe has created new mecha- among communities are interlocked, and that nisms of collaboration, human rights enforce- new legal and organizational mechanisms must ment, and new political institutions in order not be created if democracy is to prosper. only to hold member states to account across a In this system of cosmopolitan governance, broad range of issues, but to pool aspects of their people would come to enjoy multiple citizen- sovereignty. Furthermore, there are, of course, ships—political membership in the diverse polit- new regional and global transnational actors ical communities which significantly a¤ect them. contesting the terms of globalization—not just They would be citizens of their immediate polit- corporations but new social movements such Democracy and the Global Order 525

as the environmental movement, the women’s McGrew, Anthony G. 1992. ‘‘Conceptualizing global movement, and so on. These are the ‘‘new’’ politics.’’ In Anthony G. McGrew, Paul G. Lewis et voices of an emergent ‘‘transnational civil soci- al., Global Politics, pp. 1–30. Cambridge: Polity Press. ety,’’ heard, for instance, at the Rio Conference ———. (ed.) 1997. The Transformation of Democracy? on the Environment, the Cairo Conference on Cambridge: Polity Press. Population Control, and the Beijing Conference Mann, Michael. 1986. The Sources of Social Power, on Women. In short, there are tendencies at Vol. I. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. work seeking to create new forms of public life O¤e, Claus. 1985. Disorganized Capitalism. Cam- and new ways of debating regional and global bridge: Polity Press. issues. These are, of course, all in early stages of Ohmae, Kenichi. 1990. The Borderless World. London: development, and there are no guarantees that Collins. the balance of political contest will allow them Perraton, Jonathan, David Goldblatt, David Held, and to develop; but they point in the direction of Anthony McGrew. 1997. ‘‘The globalization of eco- establishing new modes of holding transna- nomic activity.’’ New Political Economy 2(2): 257–277. tional power systems to account—that is, they Reich, Robert. 1991. The Work of Nations. New York: help open up the possibility of a cosmopolitan Simon and Schuster. democracy. Sandel, Michael. 1996. Democracy’s Discontent. Cam- bridge, MA: Harvard University Press. Walker, Robert B. J. 1988. One World, Many Worlds. References Boulder, CO: Lynne Reinner.

Connolly, William. 1991. ‘‘Democracy and territorial- ity.’’ Millennium 20(3). Crawford, James. 1994. Democracy in International Law. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Giddens, Anthony. 1985. The Nation-State and Vio- lence (Vol. II of A Contemporary Critique of Historical Materialism). Cambridge: Polity Press. ———. 1990. The Consequences of Modernity. Cam- bridge: Polity Press. Goldblatt, David, David Held, Anthony G. McGrew, and Jonathan Perraton. 1997. ‘‘Economic globaliza- tion and the nation-state: shifting balances of power.’’ Soundings 7: 61–77. Held, David. (ed.) 1993. Prospects for Democracy: North, South, East, West. Cambridge: Polity Press. ———. 1995. Democracy and the Global Order: From the Modern State to Cosmopolitan Governance. Cam- bridge: Polity Press. ———. 1996. Models of Democracy (2nd edn). Cam- bridge: Polity Press. Held, David, Anthony McGrew, David Goldblatt, and Jonathan Perraton. 1999. Global Transformations: Politics, Economics and Culture. Cambridge: Polity Press.

Appendix: Observing Democracies

Political scientists and sociologists have devel- the world between 1973 and 2002 (found at oped a number of ways to assess empirically http://www.freedomhouse.org/). whether a country is democratic. . The classification of democracies and dicta- One of the first and most influential systematic torships developed by Przeworski et al. (2000) in attempts to identify specific attributes of demo- Democracy and Development (DD), covering all cratic regimes is due to Dahl (1971). He devel- countries in the world between 1946 and 1999 oped a measure of ‘‘polyarchy’’ based on what (found at http://pantheon.yale.edu/~jac236). he considered to be the two main dimensions of democratization: opportunities to participate in Although similar in that they cover a large elections and opportunities to compete for polit- number of countries for a relatively large num- ical power. With data for 1969, he used ten ber of years, these measures di¤er in at least indicators of what he considered to be the seven three important ways: institutional requirements for democracy.1 With . the conception of democracy that underlies these data he produced a scale that placed coun- each of them; tries on a continuum ranging from the least to the greatest opportunity for participation and . the nature of the data used to assess political contestation. This measure was later extended regimes; and for 1985 by Coppedge and Reinicke (1990). . the type of measurement they develop. Although these measures of democracy cover a large number of countries, they are limited to As illustrated by the selections in chapter 1, one or two years.2 Today, there are three di¤er- conceptions of democracy di¤er in terms of ent measures of democracy that cover most, if whether they adopt a strictly procedural view not all, countries for a relatively large number of as opposed to a more substantive one. In the years. These are the measures that are used by first case, democracy depends exclusively on the most political scientists, sociologists, and econo- presence of certain institutions, with no reference mists who study empirically the causes and con- to the kinds of outcomes that are generated by sequences of democratic regimes. They are: their operation. Thus, the authors of DD state that ‘‘ ‘democracy’ is a regime in which those . The Polity IV measures of political regime who govern are selected through contested elec- characteristics and transitions, which cover 1800 tions’’ (2000:15). Since they are interested in to 2000 (found at http://www.bsos.umd.edu/ studying the relationship between democracy cidcm/inscr/polity/). and normatively desirable aspects of political, . The Freedom House (FH) measure of political social, and economic life, they need to define and civil liberties, which covers all countries of democracy narrowly so that they can avoid the tautology that a broader definition might imply 1. These requirements are: freedom to form and join (2000:14). organizations, freedom of expression, right to vote, In substantive conceptions of democracy, in- right of political leaders to compete for support, exis- stitutions are seen as necessary but not su‰cient tence of alternative sources of information, free and to characterize a political regime. Although it fair elections, and institutions that make government may be that no democracy exists that does not policies depend on popular votes. have contested elections, not all regimes that 2. A similar limitation applies to the measure devel- are based on contested elections may be called oped by Bollen (1980). Originally constructed for 1960 democratic. What matters is that, through these and 1965, it has been extended to 1955, 1970, 1975, elections, something else happens: the public and 1980, but not for other years. Appendix: Observing Democracies 528

good is achieved, citizen preferences are repre- media? Are there free trade unions and other sented, governments become accountable, citizen professional organizations, and is there e¤ective participation in political life is maximized, eco- collective bargaining? Is there personal auton- nomic equality is enhanced, rationality is imple- omy? Is there equality of opportunity? Similarly, mented, economic conditions improve, and so the Polity IV democracy scale requires one to on. Those who use FH, therefore, believe that decide whether constraints on the chief execu- the measure of ‘‘freedom’’ it o¤ers can be used to tive in any given country are close to parity, face indicate ‘‘democracy.’’ Similarly, Polity IV con- substantial limitations, or are located in one of ceives of democracy as the presence of institu- two possible intermediate categories. tions that allow citizens to choose alternative The Polity IV approach contrasts with the one policies and leaders, in combination with ‘‘insti- adopted by the authors of DD, who classify de- tutionalized constraints on the exercise of power mocracy on the basis of four observational cri- by the executive’’ and ‘‘the guarantee of civil teria. Thus, for them, in order to be a democracy liberties to all citizens in their daily lives and in a regime has to have an elected executive, an acts of political participation’’ (manual, p. 12). elected legislature, elections in which two or Finally, Bollen (1980:372) defined democracy as more political parties compete, and incumbents ‘‘the extent to which the political power of the who have lost power at least once. These rules elite is minimized and that of the nonelite is unambiguously classify the vast majority of re- maximized.’’ In a later formulation, he stated gimes in all countries in every year since 1946. that ‘‘it is the relative power between e´lites and They do not, however, account for a small pro- none´lites that determines the degree of political portion of cases (8.6 percent between 1946 and democracy. Where the none´lites have little con- 1999) where history has not yet provided the trol over the e´lites, political democracy is low. necessary information to apply the rules. Rather When the e´lites are accountable to the none´lites, than creating ‘‘intermediate’’ categories to ac- political democracy is higher’’ (Bollen 1991:4). commodate these cases, they decide to keep them A second di¤erence between the measures of separate and allow each user to decide how or democracy has to do with the type of informa- whether to use them in their analysis. tion that is used, or required, to assess a polit- Finally, measures of democracy di¤er as to the ical regime. Most measures are based on data level at which they make the observation. Most that require largely subjective judgements by the measures are either continuous or, although cat- coder. Thus, FH requires answers to the follow- egorical, transformed into a continuous scale. ing questions, with no clear attempt to define This is true of both Polity IV and FH. The for- what the relevant terms or qualifiers mean: Are mer o¤ers separate indices of democracy and there fair electoral laws, equal campaigning op- autocracy (each ranging from 0 to 10), which are portunities, fair polling, and honest tabulation of often combined into a 21-point scale for democ- ballots? Are voters able to endow their repre- racy (with high values indicating higher levels of sentatives with real power? Do minorities have democracy). The latter provides separate indica- reasonable self-determination, self-government, tors of civil and political liberties (ranging from 1 autonomy, or participation through informal to 7), which are often combined into a single consensus in the decision-making process? Are measure of the degree of democracy, ranging the people free from domination by the military, from 2 (highest levels of democracy) to 14 (low- foreign powers, totalitarian parties, religious est levels of democracy). In contrast, DD classi- hierarchies, economic oligarchies, or any other fies political regimes simply into two categories: powerful group? Are there free and independent democracies and dictatorships. Appendix: Observing Democracies 529

Among the debates that have engaged those level of democracy in North Korea in 1960 and who study democracy empirically, this is proba- 1965 was about 21 according to Bollen, and it bly the one that has generated the highest level went down to 11 in 1980. The average score for of controversy. The most forceful proponents of Cuba between 1960 and 1999 was 7 in the a continuous measure of democracy have been Polity scale (which, as we know, has a minimum Bollen and Jackman (1989) who assert ‘‘the in- of 10). The level of democracy in Chile be- herently continuous nature of the concept of po- tween 1974 and 1980, according to Bollen was a litical democracy’’ (p. 612) and claim that ‘‘since low, but positive, 5.56; it averaged 7 according democracy is conceptually continuous, it is best to the Polity scale and 11.6 according to the measured in continuous terms’’ (p. 612) and combined Freedom House scale. Singapore was that ‘‘democracy is always a matter of degree’’ more democratic than Cuba, scoring 2as (p. 618). opposed to 7. Zaire under Mobuto, although A di¤erent argument states that measures that almost close to the bottom, was not at the bot- allow for gradation should be preferred over tom of the Polity scale: often it scored a 9, but dichotomies because they will contain more in- sometimes things improved and it scored 8; formation, and that even though dichotomous and according to the FH scale, its score ranged measures may contain less error than continuous from the least democratic 14 to the somewhat measures, they are less sensitive to variations in more democratic 11. According to FH, South the underlying concept of democracy (Elkins Africa under apartheid had scores that were 2000). similar to Russia since 1993, the Dominican Re- This issue has probably been blown out of public in the 1990s, postcommunist Albania and proportion. The matter is not whether one Romania, and Sri Lanka in the 1990s. Thus, if should adopt a continuous or a categorical mea- one believes that democracy can be continuously sure of democracy that is observable across all measured over all regimes, one has to be pre- political regimes. The issue is whether there is a pared to argue that it makes sense to speak of natural zero-point that divides democracies positive levels of democracy in places like Al- and nondemocracies. Even those who develop bania under Hoxa, North Korea and Chile un- and use categorical measures of democracy der Pinochet; that it makes sense to speak of a may agree, given some appropriate criteria to change from one value to another along these use as a yardstick, that democratic regimes can scales; and, finally, that we can meaningfully in- di¤er as to how democratic they are, and that terpret scores across countries. some measure to assess their degree of democ- As for the informational content of di¤erent racy may make sense. Note, however, that this measures, it is not true that a continuous scale refers to democratic regimes, as opposed to will necessarily contain more information than a nondemocratic regimes. It assumes that some dichotomous classification of political regime. regimes fail whatever minimum requirement The informational content of a measure depends there is for them to be called democratic. on the way in which it is conceptualized and The belief that democracy is an attribute that observed, at least as much as it depends on the can and should be measured over the spectrum level of measurement. What kind of information of cases leads to assertions that may be absurd, is being conveyed when we say that the level of for example, the claim that the level of democ- democracy in Singapore in 1965 was 76.94 racy in Albania in 1950 and 1955, under the according to the Bollen scale? Or that the Bur- communist regime of Enver Hoxa, was, accord- mese junta scored a 6 in the Polity scale? ing to the Bollen scale, about 24 out of 100. The Which measure conveys more information: the Appendix: Observing Democracies 530

one that says that North Korea scored 21.04 in assuming that one knows what to do once one Bollen’s democracy scale in 1965, or the one that has the facts, one still has to get the facts about says that North Korea was a dictatorship in 1965 each of these items. What is needed is informa- because leaders were not selected on the basis of tion about the policymaking activities of both contested elections? executive and legislative bodies, political cam- Measures are only as good as their compo- paigning, political parties (both in government nents. Consider the FH scale. It is based on and in opposition), trade unions, professional answers to 8 questions for the political liberty organizations, the judiciary, the military, reli- scale and 14 for the civil liberty scale. Given the gious organizations, economic oligarchies, and nature of the questions and information re- so on. quired, as seen above, these answers often re- If these conditions are met, indeed the FH quire highly subjective judgement on the part of scale will convey more information than a coders. Coders assign ‘‘raw points’’ ranging from dichotomous measure based simply on whether 0 to 4 for each of those questions, for a maxi- or not contested elections took place. However, mum of 32 political rights points and 56 civil if these conditions are not met, then at each step liberties points. Countries are then distributed of the process the numbers that are generated into one of the seven categories that make up the make less and less sense. One is left with a scale final political and civil liberties scales according that is more refined than a dichotomy in the to the number of raw points they received. For sense that it contains more categories and allows example, a country with 28 to 32 raw political for more values, but certainly not because it rights points is placed in category 1 of the politi- conveys more information about the political cal rights scale; with 23 to 27 points, it is placed regime in each country. It is possible that what in category 2; and so on. they convey is information about the subjectivity What needs to be true for the FH scale to of those involved in generating the scale. convey meaningful information? For one, it is So which measure should one use to study de- necessary that each of the 22 items that compose mocracy? As with anything else, the best mea- the checklist of political rights and civil liberties sure is a function of the question being asked and be su‰ciently defined. Adjectives such as equal, of its conceptual clarity. The measures of de- fair, honest, reasonable and so on that appear in mocracy, however, are all very highly correlated, the description of the checklist items must have thus making it irrelevant which measure one been su‰ciently defined so that one may sepa- uses. Indeed, the correlation between Polity IV rate the cases of unequal, unfair, dishonest, and and FH is 0.91. Polity IV predicts correctly 94 unreasonable practices that take place across percent of the cases classified as democracies by countries. Then, there must be rules that allow DD and 95 percent of those classified as dicta- one to decide when a practice related to political torships. FH predicts 88 percent and 95 percent, or civil liberty deserves a 0, as opposed to a 1, 2, respectively. But continuous scales of democracy 3, or 4 in each of these items. Not only must have a bimodal distribution, with a high con- these items make sense, but one must be able to centration of cases at the low and high ends of distinguish the levels in which they materialize. the scales: 56 percent of the cases are classified Moreover, it must also be true that di¤erent in the three lowest and highest categories of constellations of attributes that add up to the FH’s 13-point scale; 73 percent of the cases have same number be equivalent. Having ‘‘personal scores that are 7 and lower or 7 and higher in autonomy’’ with no ‘‘equality of opportunity’’ the 21-point Polity IV scale. If one excludes the must be equivalent to the opposite. Finally, extremes of the democracy scales, the correlation Appendix: Observing Democracies 531

among the di¤erent measures is considerably guish all the cases we encounter in the world. reduced. The correlation between Polity IV and Perhaps rather than gradations of democracy, FH becomes 0.75. Polity IV predicts 70 percent what we need is simply better rules for identify- of the democracies in DD and 83 percent of dic- ing democratic regimes. tatorships, whereas these numbers are 67 percent None of this is necessarily an argument for the and 81 percent for FH. Thus it is the uncon- use of a dichotomous measure such as DD over troversial cases that drive the high correlation scales such as FH, Polity, or Bollen. But given among di¤erent measures of democracy: No that once we get to these di‰cult cases—the measure is likely to produce very di¤erent read- cases that populate the middle of the distribution ings for, say, England, the United States, Swe- in these scales—no consensus seems to exist den, North Korea, or Iraq. The problem arises across measures, the choice must be made on with ‘‘di‰cult’’ cases, such as Mexico, Bot- conceptual grounds and on the basis of the amount swana, Malaysia, Peru, Guatemala, and scores of error each measure may contain. If we can of other countries that do not easily fit into the make sense of what it means to be 4, or to move categories that make up existing measures. These from 4 to 5 in the Polity scale, then one should countries are ‘‘di‰cult,’’ however, not necessar- probably use it. If one cannot make sense of ily because they represent intermediate instances what this means, and, for this reason, doubts the of democracy, thus calling for measures that al- process that generated this number, then one low for gradations; rather, they are di‰cult be- might be better served by using a ‘‘cruder’’ mea- cause the rules we have to sort the types of sure, but one that has some theoretical and em- political regimes are not good enough to distin- pirical meaning.

Table A.1 Distribution of democracies across regions, 1946–1999

Country- % % % % % Region years democratic democracies parliamentary mixed presidential Sub-Saharan Africa 1730 10.23 6.01 36.16 33.90 29.94 South Asia 305 44.26 4.58 88.15 11.85 0.00 East Asia 263 9.51 0.85 4.00 48.00 48.00 South-East Asia 425 16.00 2.31 50.00 0.00 50.00 Pacific Islands/Oceania 242 59.50 4.89 83.33 0.00 16.67 Middle East-North Africa 612 19.12 3.97 100.00 0.00 0.00 Latin America 1026 52.83 18.40 0.00 0.37 99.63 Caribbean/Non-Iberic America 395 77.72 10.42 91.86 5.54 2.61 Eastern Europe/ Ex-Soviet Union 696 22.99 5.43 48.13 32.50 19.38 Industrial countries 1339 94.92 43.14 74.04 13.69 12.27 Oil countries 277 0.00 0.00 0.00 0.00 0.00 All 7311 40.31 100.00 59.57 11.30 29.12 Appendix: Observing Democracies 532

In what follows we use DD to characterize the which governments must enjoy the confidence distribution of democracies in the world across of the legislature are parliamentary; systems in regions and over time since 1946. Table A.1 which they serve at the authority of the elected presents the frequency of democracies in each president are presidential; and systems in which region of the world between 1946 and 1999. governments respond both to legislative assem- These figures refer to 199 countries that either blies and elected presidents are mixed. As we can existed in 1946 or became independent after that see, regional patterns are, again, very clear. Most year. The second column in the table presents the democracies in the industrial countries are par- number of country-years observed in each re- liamentary. The same is true of the relatively few gion. For instance, as indicated in the note to the democracies that exist in South Asia, the Pacific table, there are 19 countries in Latin America, Islands, the Middle East, and the Caribbean. each of which was observed since 1946, yielding Latin America, on the contrary, is overwhelm- a total of 19 countries times 54 years ¼ 1,026 ingly presidential, whereas the democracies that country-years for the region. Sub-Saharan Africa exist in sub-Saharan Africa tend to be equally is composed of 50 countries. However, since split among the three types. most of them became independent after 1946, we Figure A.1 presents the evolution of demo- do not observe them for the full 54 years that cratic regimes since 1946. As we can see, the comprise the period between 1946 and 1999. postwar evolution of democracies can be ap- Therefore, there are 1,730 country-years in this proximated by a U-shaped curve. The propor- region. tion of democracies was relatively high at the The second column in table A.1 presents the end of the 1940s, when it started to decline, percentage of country-years in each region that reaching a low of only 28 percent in 1977 to was spent under democracy. As we can see, the 1978. Since then the proportion of democracy in variation is large across regions. Only a small the world has been increasing, reaching almost proportion of the time in sub-Saharan Africa, 58 percent in 1999, the highest level since 1946. East Asia and the Middle East/North Africa This pattern should not be immediately inter- was spent under democracy. The opposite was preted as evidence that democratization happens true for the Caribbean and the industrial coun- in waves, as argued by Huntington (see chapter tries, where most of the time was spent under 2). As Przeworski et al. (2000) argue, the pattern democracy. Latin America is unique in that it we observe in figure A.1 is not so much the experienced democracy and dictatorship in equal product of democracies becoming dictatorships proportions. and vice versa. Rather it is because many coun- The third column in table A.1 shows how the tries have entered the world, that is, have be- democracies that existed between 1946 and 1999 come independent, in the 1960s and 1970s, and were distributed across the regions. As we can they did so as dictatorships. The proportion of see, there is a clear regional pattern. Almost democracies and dictatorships in countries that half of all democratic regimes existed in the in- existed prior to 1946, as they note, has remained dustrial countries, with a significant but much mostly constant, and the variation that we ob- smaller proportion occurring in Latin America serve is almost entirely due to regime changes in and the Caribbean. No oil country has ever been Latin America. a democracy. Figure A.1 also presents the proportion of Finally, the last three columns in table A.1 democracies that are parliamentary, mixed, or present the distribution of di¤erent types of de- presidential. The most striking feature in this mocracy—parliamentary, mixed, and presiden- picture is the recent increase in the proportion of tial—in each region. Recall that systems in democracies that have adopted a mixed system, Appendix: Observing Democracies 533

Figure A.1 Democracy over time, 1946 to 1999. that is, one in which the government is responsi- Bollen, Kenneth A. 1991. ‘‘Political Democracy: Con- ble to a directly elected president and to a legis- ceptual and Measurement Traps,’’ in Alex Inkeles, ed., lative majority. We know very little about the On Measuring Democracy: Its Consequences and Con- way these regimes operate, and the category in comitants, pp. 3–20. New Brunswick: Transaction Books. fact masks a large amount of variation in the way governments are actually formed and dis- Bollen, Kenneth A., and Robert W. Jackman. 1989. ‘‘Democracy, Stability, and Dichotomies.’’ American missed. There is no doubt, however, that this Sociological Review 54(4): 612–621. is an increasingly popular form of government Coppedge, Michael, and Wolfgang H. Reinicke. 1990. among new democracies, one that needs to be ‘‘Measuring Polyarchy.’’ Studies in Comparative Inter- studied more carefully. national Development 25(1): 51–72. Dahl, Robert A. 1971. Polyarchy: Participation and Opposition. New Haven: Yale University Press. References Elkins, Zachary. 2000. ‘‘Gradations of Democracy: Empirical Tests of Alternative Conceptualizations.’’ Bollen, Kenneth A. 1980. ‘‘Issues in the Comparative American Journal of Political Science 44(2): 293–301. Measurement of Political Democracy.’’ American So- ciological Review 45(3): 370–390. Marshall, Monty G., and Keith Jaggers. Polity IV Project. Political Regime Characteristics and Transi- Appendix: Observing Democracies 534

tions, 1800–1999. Dataset Users’ Manual. University of Maryland, College Park. Accessed at www.bsos. umd.edu/cidcm/inscr/polity. Przeworski, Adam, Mike Alvarez, Jose´ Antonio Chei- bub, and Fernando Limongi. 2000. Democracy and Development: Political Regimes and Economic Perfor- mance in the World, 1950–1990. Cambridge: Cam- bridge University Press. Index

Abortion, 254 manhood su¤rage, 93, 131, 456, 484 Accountability, in deliberative democracy, 19, 22, 39 new petit-bourgeois/worker hybrid a facet of, 129, Acquired Immune Deficiency Syndrome (AIDS), 522 130, 131 Acquired regulation, 393–397 Puritan heritage fueling egalitarianism, 445–447, Africa, 170f. 480–481, 482 African Americans leftist parties not viable in, 59, 129 disa¤ection of in inner cities, 162, 487 multiple traditions analysis of, 482–483, 485–487 disillusionment among middle class, 469, 471–474, political alliances in, 249–250 475 problems of or critique of, 19, 38, 39, 51, 382–384 poor blacks and the American dream, 469 separation of powers in, 193–194 proposal to solve underrepresentation of, 153, 154t. values di¤er from those of other modernized nations, African National Congress (ANC), 99, 103–106 170f., 173–174, 176f., 177f., 179 Agrarian sector American Revolution, 66 elite-alliances with, 67–68 (see also Landed elites) Anarchy/disorder, 81, 425, 436–437 ‘‘labor repressive’’ vs. ‘‘market’’ agriculture, 68, 69t. Ancien regime, 130–132, 483 landed peasantry, 65 Anomia, 473 peasant revolutionary potential, 68–70, 69t., 70n.25 Antipopulism, 321, 325 role of in bourgeois revolutions, 66, 67–68, 70, 75 Apartheid, 153, 154t. AIDS, 522 in South Africa, 99–100, 102–103, 242n.71 Airline industry, 393 Arab world Air pollution, 504, 505, 507 democracy and Islamic religious culture, 36, 95, 96– Ake, Claude, 142 97, 185, 187, 188t., 189t. Albania, 94 liberalization of in early 1990s, 94 Alger, Horatio, 129 oil countries, 531t. Alienation, 38, 162 values associated with culture area, 170f., 175, 176f. Allocative e‰ciency, 448, 449–450 Arbitrary exercise of power, 252, 255 American Civil War, as a bourgeois revolution, 66 Argentina, 76, 83, 87n.54, 170f., 176f., 298, 299, American dream 299n.70, 303 conflicting racial perspectives on, 46n.2, 463, 467, Armenia, 170f., 176f. 469–472, 475–476 Arrow, Kenneth, 321, 326 paradoxical aspects of, 485–486 Arrow’s Theorem, 317–320, 321, 324–325 of social fluidity, 129–130, 131 Asia, 36 ‘‘American exceptionalism,’’ 174 Assemblies. See Legislatures ‘‘Americanization,’’ 179 Associations, 2, 367–369. See also Interest groups American political system, 93, 365–366 as potential interest groups, 366, 367–369 based in material wealth of the land, 129–130 Ataturk, Mustafa Kemal, 97 citizenship and voting policies, 480–483, 480n.1, Australia, 59, 63, 170f., 176f., , 335t., 343, 354 482n.4 Austria, 59, 143, 146, 170f., 176f. class analyses lacking in, 130, 131, 383, 384, 391, Austria-Hungary, 66, 74 484 Authoritarianism, 74, 427 electoral college, 324–325 bureaucratic authoritarianism, 112–113 governability and interest intermediation in, 398, capitalist authoritarianism, 433–434 399–401 democracy compared to in terms of development, historical factors, 66, 486, 487 436, 444–446 early-American homogeneous political culture, 480– elections under, 90–91 483 genocidal acts and, 494 egalitarianism based in small homesteads, 129–130 GNP per capita a predictor of, 186t., 187t., 188t., European struggle against the ancien regime not 189t. present in, 130–131, 483 international threats tending to increase, 496 Index 536

Authoritarianism (cont.) regime transition in, 76, 77n.23, 83–84 legitimacy problems of, 93 Bribes. See Corruption opposition repressed in, 351 Britain, 59, 359 regimes characterized by, 95–96 Bill of Rights, proposal for adoption of, 217–220 reverse waves from democracy to, 93, 94–95 cabinet formation in, 285t. tending to fail with modernization, 109–110, 112 Charter 88 group, 217, 221, 227, 229 transitioning to democracy (see Democratization; common rather than constitutional law in, 210 Extrication from authoritarian regimes) cultural values, 170f., 176f. in wealthy countries, 111 electoral decisiveness in, 289t. ‘‘Authoritarian-libertarian’’ axis, 460 electoral system characteristics, 335t. Authority structures, industrial, 44–45 whether to adopt the European Convention as Autocracy, 30n.12, 430, 437–439, 441–442 domestic law, 218–220 Azerbaijan, 170f., 176f. First Reform Act, 130 July Revolution, 130 Bad politics, 497, 504 the Labour Party, 217–218 Balance of powers, 210, 211, 212–213 influence of opposition in, 288t. Baltics. See Ex-Communist countries as a parliamentary democracy, 66, 226 Banfield, Edward, 436 women’s representation issue in, 359, 360–361 Bangladesh, 170f., 176f. Broadcast media, 25, 26, 167, 370 Barry, Brian, 460 Bryce, James, 15, 57–58, 58n.14 Becker, G., 430–433 Buckley v. Valeo, 414, 415, 416, 418 Beijing Conference on Women, 525 Bulgaria, 76, 94, 111, 170f., 176f. Belarus, 170f., 176f. Bureaucracy, 406–407 Belgium, 38, 59, 170f., 176f., 285t., 288t., 289t., 335t. Burt, Robert, 252–253, 254–255 Benhabib, Seyla, 23n.16, 24n.18 Bentley, Arthur F., 368, 369, 370–371 Cabinet types. See also Minority governments Besette, Joseph, 20n.7 distribution of types by country, 285t. Bill of Rights influence of fractionalization and polarization on, whether Britain should adopt, 218–220, 221–223, 286t., 292t. 227–228, 229–231 majority cabinets, 284 Canadian Charter of Rights, 232n.2, 240 minoritarian cabinets, 284, 285–288, 293–295 New Zealand’s, 232n.2, 241–242 Cairo Conference on population control, 525 of the United States, 248–249, 369 Campaign finance (U.S.) Black, Duncan, 327 decline in (U.S.) challenger financing, 411–413, 412t. Bobbio, Norberto, 14 independent spending, 414–415, 414t. Bolivia, 30, 299, 303 PAC contributions and policy influence of explored, Bollen scale of democracy, 529–530, 531t. 408–410, 413, 414, 417–418 Borda Count, 324, 326 regulation of and concerns over, 414, 415–416, 418 Bosnia, 170f., 176f. soft money, 415 Botswana, 37 Canada, 59, 170f., 176f., 232n.2, 240, 285t., 288t., Boundaries, 517, 519, 522, 524 289t., 294 Bourgeoisie, 67–69, 69t., 77n.25, 399 Capital. See also Property relations; Social capital Bourgeois revolutions, 66–70 elasticity of, 450 Brazil physical capital, 448, 450, 453 coalition governments in, 299, 299n.70, 301, 302 Capitalism. See also Economic development; governability of, 303 Economic organizations; Investment; Market- legislative organization, 298, 304, 353 oriented reforms military coup in, 298 authoritarian capitalism, 433–434 party behavior in, 304 capital output concept, 422 Index 537

commercialization, 67–69, 69t. Civil society, transnational, 525 commodification, 391 Class. See Social class corporations, 372–373, 387–388 Class analysis, 381. See also Capitalism; Inequality; cross-cultural variation in institutions of, 169 Property relations governmental regulation of industries under, 393–397 businesses privileged over other organized interests, inequality under, 383–384, 385, 388, 391–392 387–388 market system, 384 class e¤ects downplayed in analyses of American property relations and, 384, 434 system, 129, 383, 384, 391, 484 reactionary capitalist regimes, 66, 68–69, 74 proposing structural reforms, 389, 391–392 social relations under, 384, 386–387, 390 social vs. private ownership of property, 384 Caribbean countries, 531t. as a theory of power relations, 384, 386–387, 390 Castles and Mair survey, 336n.30 Classical theory of democracy, 2–9, 40–42. See also Catholicism, Second Vatican Council (1963–1965), 93 Social contract Catholic societies, 358 Closed-list PR systems, 301 cultural zones, 170f., 171, 173, 174 Coalitions interpersonal trust levels relatively lower, 175, 176f. coalition formation in Latin America, 299–303 more traditional values in, 170f., 173, 176f. grand coalitions, 142, 148, 149 third wave of democracy involving, 94, 97 interparty coalitions, 300 Center-driven party competition, 331 multipolar coalitions, 150, 151 Central America, 73–74 pre-electoral and post-electoral, 148, 149, 150–151 Centralization of power, 240, 403 Coalition theory Challenger financing, 411–413, 412t. decisiveness for government formation, 288–289 Charter 88, group advocating constitutionalized rights electoral incentives for formation, 150–151, 154, in Britain, 217, 221, 227, 229 288–289, 289t. Checks and balances, 53, 210, 211, 212–213 factors favoring coalition formation in Latin Cheibub, Jose´ Antonio, 277 American, 299–300, 302–303 Chile, 76, 85, 111, 170f., 176f., 299, 299n.70, 303, 434, minoritarian cabinet formation, 284, 285–288, 293– 529 295 China, 170f., 176f., 444, 445, 501 Cohen, Cathy J., and Michael C. Dawson, 162 Christianity, Western. See Catholicism; Protestantism Cohen, G. A., 460 Churches, 158 Collective action, 372, 504–505 Citizen competence, 38–39. See also Civic engagement Collective bads, 504–506, 508–509 Citizens’ access to power. See Congruence between Collective bargaining. See Labor unions citizen-preferences and policymaking; Popular Collective goods, 376n.21. See also Interest groups; sovereignty; Power Public goods Civic disengagement, 38, 162 Collective rationality, 136–138, 375 Civic engagement, 157–158, 162–166. See also Colombia, 170f., 176f., 298, 299, 299n.70, 303 Participatory democracy; Social capital; Social Colonial legacy, 173, 189 networking Commercialization, 67, 68, 69, 69t. Civic virtues, 157–159, 166–167, 370. See also Commodities, 391 Civic engagement; Deliberative democracy; Common good, in classical theory arising from Egalitarianism popular will, 3–4, 5. See also Domestic order; citizen competence, 38–39 Public goods educative aspects of, 41, 44, 45, 460 Communication. See Media; Social networking interpersonal trust, 175, 176f., 183 Communist dictatorships, 66 role of citizenry in a democracy, 182–183 Communist parties, 50–60, 103 Civilian control of the military, 82–84, 528 Comparative analyses of democracy, 32n.36, 72, 527– Civil liberties, 33–34, 36n.5, 107, 444–446, 523. See 531. See also Democratic regimes; Stability of also Human rights; Rights and freedoms regimes Index 538

Competition for leadership. See also Opposition Constitutional Convention, American, 209 competitiveness of elections, 37, 413 Constitutionalism, 14, 29, 34n.42, 101 as criterion for democracy, 9–11, 32–33n.36 ‘‘Constitutional’’ monarchy, 9 instability and, 112 Constitutional republics, 490–491 modernization may create the prerequisites for, 111 Constitutional revolutions, 232, 236–240, 243 must be robust, 37 (see also Opposition) in emergent regimes (case of South Africa), 99, 100, Compulsion, 375–376, 376n.19, 383–384 100n.6, 102, 106–107 Condorcet, Marquis de, 15, 315, 326 Hamilton on the necessity of, 192 Condorcet’s paradox, 134–135, 315–316, 319, 321t. and judicial empowerment, 232 can be resolved in a large society, 326–329 judicial role crucial to (Hamilton), 201, 202, 204 examples of disputed, 321–325 legal innovations, 147–148, 236 Conflict and disagreement. See also Deliberative republican constitutions, 480–491 democracy; Opposition; Rights and freedoms trend toward, 232, 232n.1 consociational model insu‰cient to resolve, 147–151 Constitutional rights, 232ns.1 and 2. See also Bill of engineered polity resolutions to, 153–155, 154t., 155 Rights; European Convention Confucian-influenced societies, 36, 96–97, 170f., 171, a Bill of Rights for Britain, 217–220, 221–223, 227– 173, 174, 176f. 228, 229–231 Congress (U.S.), actions following Supreme Court Charter 88 (British group advocating), 217, 221, 227, decisions holding legislation unconstitutional, 247– 229 248, 247t., 248–249 Charter of Rights and Freedoms, 240 Congruence between citizen-preferences and as entrenched rights, 223–224 policymaking, 330–331, 333, 340–342 in Israel, 236–240, 243 greatest with proportional influence vision (PI), 330, judicial empowerment and, 232, 233–236, 237–238, 332–334, 334t., 335t., 337–340, 337t., 338t., 339t., 240–243 340t., 341 legislative supremacy limited by, 219–220, 222 least with Majority Control vision, 337t., 338t.m, parliamentary supremacy limited by, 219–220, 221– 337–340, 339t., 341–342 223 measurement of, 336–341, 338t. as super-majoritarian and entrenched rights, 223– mixed-vision systems, 335t., 337t., 340t., 341–342, 224, 243 353, 532–533 in the U.S., 225 Connor, Walker, 145 Constitutional Unionists, 323 Conservative Party (S.A.), 104 Consumer interests, 411 Consociationalism, 100, 153, 154t., 351 Consumption critiques of commodification under capitalism, 391 e¤ective coalitions are ensured only by electoral distribution of consumption goods, 61–62 incentives, 150–151, 154 vs. investment, 421, 424, 425–426 fixed elite leadership assumed, 148–149 poverty and, 447–448, 449, 452 is insu‰cient for conflict resolution, 149–150 Contract enforcement, 440 elite-mass relation in, 145–146 Coordination issues, 399–400, 504–505 factors conducive to, 143–146 Corporations, 372–373, 387–388. See also Capitalism grand coalitions, 142, 148, 149 Corporatism, 400–403, 400n.8, 404–407 inter-elite cooperation the basis of, 142–143, 146, 150 Corruption, 38, 418, 429–430 inter-subcultural relations in, 144–145 Cosmopolitan model of democracy, 508, 516, 523–525 maximizing participation, 352 Costa Rica, 73–74, 299, 444 undermining beneficial aspects of opposition, 351–352 Coughlin, P., 432 violating the majority rule principle, 142 Croatia, 170f., 176f. ‘‘Consolidation,’’ 113 Cross-cultural variation, in capitalist institutions, 169 Constituent representation, 355–357, 358. See also Cross-national analyses. See Comparative analyses of Congruence between citizen-preferences and democracy policymaking Cuba, 529 Index 539

Cultural change, 168 process of deliberation in, 20–23, 20n.7 Cultural factors and democracy. See also Civic public discourse in, 19, 22 virtues; Historical-cultural heritage; Participatory reciprocity, 18–19, 21–22, 39, 159 democracy; Religion and national culture Deliberative polling, 25–28 American political culture, 165 Democracy. See also Deliberative democracy; cultural factors not a determinant for democratic Participatory democracy; Procedural democracy; development or longevity, 155, 184–185, 185, 187 Substantive democracy democratic culture is necessary for a viable in America (see American political system; democracy, 36, 96–97, 155, 168, 169, 178–179 Madisonian democracy) habituation to democracy, 185, 213 concepts and types of (see Democratic theory) heterogeneous political culture, 145, 188, 188–189, criterion defining, 1, 9, 527–528 212, 460 cultural interaction with (see Cultural factors and homogeneous political culture, 145, 183, 480–483 democracy) socialization aspects, 185, 213 democratic values, 221, 227 (see also Civic virtues) strongly culturalist view, 181–183 elections must determine leadership in, 9, 10, 11, 32– weakly culturalist view, 181, 183 (see also 33, 37, 50–51 (see also Elections) Modernization theory) formal opposition critical to, 252, 255, 350–351 (see Cumulative voting, 154 also Opposition) Cyclical majorities, 134–135, 317, 319–321, 327. See governments adhering to (see Democratic regimes) also Condorcet’s paradox; Preferences and question of applicability to large nations, 25, 37–38, preference profiles 143, 505 consequences of, 135 redistribution in, 427–430, 436, 439–442 1820 presidential election examined, 322–325 representative democracy, 312–314, 330–331 (see examples of disputed, 321–322, 322–325 also Representation; Representative republics) single-peakedness condition, 135, 136, 327 Democracy and Development (DD) scale, 527, 528, Cynicism, public, 38 531–533, 531t. Cypress, 143 Democracy deficit, 509, 510–511, 512–513 Czech Republic/Czechoslovakia, 59, 111, 170f., 176f. Democracy scales and measures assessing continuous vs. categorical measures, 528– Daalder, Hans, 146 529 Dahl, Robert the ‘‘authoritarian-libertarian’’ axis, 460 on elections and democracy, 40, 49–52, 330–331 Bollen scale, 529–530, 531t. on Madisonian democracy, 207, 213–216. See also correlation among scales, 530–531 Madisonian democracy DD scale, 527, 528, 531–533, 531t. on polyarchy, 32, 38, 48–53, 385, 388–389 Freedom House scale (FH), 32–33n.36, 527, 528, on the U.S. Supreme Court, 238, 246 530 Dahl, Robert, and Charles Lindblom, 382–383, 384, Polity III and IV data and ratings, 498, 527, 528, 385, 387–388, 390 529, 530 DD scale. See Democracy and Development (DD) Democratic norms. See Norms, democratic scale Democratic regimes. See also American political Deadlock situations, 144, 277 system; Europe; Representative republics Decretismo, 298 distribution of, 531t., 532–533, 533t. Defractionalization (political), 343–346, 352–353 distributive problems and inequality in, 504 Dehesa, Grace Ivana, 300 extent of democracy in (see Democracy scales and De Klerk, F. W., 103, 106, 197 measures) Deliberative democracy. See also Civic virtues longevity issues, 113 accountability in, 19, 22, 39 mixed systems (both PR and presidential), 532– heterogeneity of values and, 460 533 moral deliberation, 20–22, 38, 222 must be produced by election, 10, 11, 50–51 political debate, 350–351 potential legitimacy issues of, 95, 98 Index 540

Democratic regimes (cont.) Distribution of wealth. See also Inequality; stability of, 16, 41, 44, 112, 113–114, 347–349 Redistribution strengthening international climate for, 494–496 in democratic regimes, 504 Democratic theory, 2–4, 8n.3, 40–43, 153, 182–183 income level related to democratic norms and Democratic transition. See Democratization; Regime participation, 16, 52–53, 62–63 transition between nations, 98 Democratic values, 221, 227, 368–369, 384–386, 387, within nations, 60, 61–62 390. See also Egalitarianism; Substantive Distributive justice theory, 391, 460. See also democracy Redistribution Democratization. See also Regime transition; Reverse District magnitude, 306, 343, 344, 345 waves District of Columbia, 416 development or regression of, 533t. Domestic order, 436–437, 440–441, 442. See also economic factors related to, 186t., 188t., 189t. Anarchy/disorder as endogenous vs. exogenous, 109, 111–112 Domestic vs. supranational policy, 505, 509 factors influencing, 108 Dominican Republic, 73, 170f., 176f. factors that may reverse, 95 Downs, Anthony, 331–332 first wave of, 93 Dred Scott decision, 249, 249n.27 obstacles to, 95–98, 96–98 Duesenberry, James S., 424 proto-democratic actors, 76, 77–82, 78t., 79t., 80f. Dworkin, Ronald, 217–220, 226–228, 238 relationship to market-oriented reforms, 89–91, 233 second wave, 93 Earth Summit (1992), 520, 525 third wave of, 92, 94–98 East Asia, 36, 96–97 whether economic development is related to (see Eastern Europe, 531t. See also Ex-Communist Economic development and political regimes) countries; and by nation Denmark, 59, 170f., 176f., 285t., 288t., 289t., 335t. East Germany, 111, 157, 170f., 176f. Depression, 73 Economic collapse, 179 Detention without trial, 107 Economic competition, bidding processes, 429– Deutsch, Karl W., 145 430 Developing countries, 75, 98, 433–434. See also Poor Economic development, 420, 448, 449–450 and underdeveloped countries Economic development and political regime, 56n.9, Dewey, John, 58n.16 74–75, 76, 108, 110–114, 447–449. See also Diamond, Larry, 29–32. See also Substantive Industrialization; Investment; Modernization democracy theory; National income Dictatorship, 111, 320, 430–431 argument for a direct relationship, 56–64, 108, Communist dictatorship, 66 110 economic development under, 112, 451t. argument that the relationship is unclear, 65, 178– investment under, 447, 448, 452 179, 420, 436, 447 modernization under, 110–111 labor force growth, 449–450 reactionary capitalist (Fascist) regimes, 66, 68–69, labor-intensive development, 453 74, 402 and market-oriented reforms, 85–86, 90 redistribution under, 427, 432–433, 436, 439–442 and modernization, 88 rent seeking in, 427 national income considered, 450, 451–452, 451t. repression of rights under, 430–431 population growth as a barrier to, 423 wealthy countries, 111, 453 relationship to authoritarian regimes unclear, 112 Disagreement. See Moral disagreement secure property rights and, 441–442, 448 Discourse, 18–19, 22, 23–24, 24n.18. See also Moral service economy related to postmaterialist values, deliberation; Nonviolent resolution 171, 178 Dissidents, 425–426 of subsistence economies, 421, 422, 423–426 Distribution of consumption goods, 61–62 ‘‘threshold of democracy,’’ 111 Index 541

Economic globalization, 518–519 Electoral incentives Economic organizations, 379n.2. See also Campaign for coalition formation, 150–151, 154, 288–289, finance; Corporations; Labor unions 289t. lobbying, 378–380 motivations of political minorities, 142, 143–144, oligarchies, 234–235n.16, 528 148 political power of, 378–380, 386, 395–397, 409– for political parties, 155, 286 410 as a requirement for e¤ective coalitions, 150–151, rank and file revolts in, 404–405 154 role of during regime transition, 86–91 for resolution of ethnic conflict, 153–155 state regulation of, 393–397 Electoral laws. See District magnitude; Electoral Economic reforms. See Market-oriented reforms formulas Economic regulation theory, 393–397 Electoral reform, resistance to, 360 Economic zones, 171 Electoral responsiveness, 289t., 295 Ecuador, 298, 299, 299n.70, 303 Electoral systems. See District magnitude; Electoral Education-level, and level of democratization, 58, 59, formulas 113 Electoral threshold. See District magnitude; Electoral Educative aspects of democracy, 41, 44, 45, 460 formulas Egalitarianism. See also American dream; Inequality; Electoral volatility, 288–289, 292t. Political equality; Rights and freedoms Elite cartels. See Consociationalism American Puritan heritage fueling, 445–447 Elites as a criterion of liberal democracy, 35 bourgeoisie-elite alliances, 67–68 land factors a¤ecting early-American, 129–130 corporatist interest intermediation among, 402 political vs. substantive equality, 385, 386–387, 391 counter-elite formation, 148–149 Elazar, Daniel, 165 elite-agrarian alliances, 67–68 Elections. See also Electoral incentives; Incumbency; landed elites, 69–70, 72, 74 Opposition; Preferences and preference profiles in negotiated transitions, 101–102 competitiveness of, 37, 413 power of inversely related to democracy, 528 decisiveness for government formation, 288–289, power as rational self-interest of, 437–438 289t., 292t. reciprocal control among, 213 in a democracy must produce and determine Empirical approaches leadership, 9, 10, 11, 32–33, 50–51 vs. normative approaches, 40–41, 43 election stage, 49–50, 333 trade volume and military disputes examined, 497– expense of political campaigns, 416–418 500, 499t., 501t., 502 as insu‰cient to prevent nondemocratic outcomes, Enclosure movements, 65 33, 41, 90–91, 210–211, 395 England. See Britain interelection stage, 50–51 English Civil War, as a bourgeois revolution, 66 postelection stage, 333 English-Only movement, 487 property qualifications for voting, 72, 93 English-speaking cultural zones, 170f., 171, 174 tension between preference voting and consistency, Entry, controlled entry into industries, 393–394 317, 319–321 Environmental movement, 525 theory of, 315–316 Environmental pollution Electoral coalitions. See Coalitions domestic policies and, 504–505 Electoral college (U.S.), 324–325 emissions and resource use issues among nations, Electoral fallacy, 33, 41, 90–91 506–508, 520 Electoral formulas, 315, 336n.31, 343. See also global pollution, 505, 520 Plurality-majority elections; Proportional requiring international regulatory institutions, 505– representation (PR) 506, 520 and government stability, 346–349 siting of waste facilities, 163 and party defractionalization, 343–346, 352–353 transboundary pollution, 520 Index 542

Epstein, Richard, 487 Factionalism, 299, 366. See also Polarization Equality. See Egalitarianism; Inequality; Political controlling the e¤ects of, 159, 211–212 equality factions seeking particular rather than unified goods, Estonia, 170f., 176f. 211–212, 214 Ethical (‘‘moralistic’’) political culture, 165 within organizations, 373n.11 Ethnic and cultural divisions, 149 Famine, 444–446, 448 Ethnic conflicts, 153–155, 154t., 155, 189t. See also Fascist dictatorships, 66, 68–69, 74, 402. See also Inter-ethnic political cooperation Authoritarianism EU. See European Union (EU) Federal Elections Commission (FEC), data archive, European Commission, 511 408, 415–416 European Community (EC), 93 Federalism, 151 European Convention, 217–220 Federalist No. 10, 118 European Court of Justice, 511 Federalist No. 14, 123 European political systems, 129. See also by nation Federalists, 25, 209 democracy emerging from revolt against ancien No. 23 on constitutionalism (Hamilton), 192 regime, 131–132 No. 47 on separation of powers (Madison), 193– governability and interest intermediation, 398, 399– 194 401 No. 48 on legislative power in a representative Northwest Europe, 63 republic (Madison), 195–196 spectrum of political views represented in, 129 No. 49 on separation of powers (Madison), 211 having both Whig and Tory traditions, 129 No. 62 on composition of the legislature (Madison), European Union (EU), 232, 505 197–198 ‘‘democracy deficit’’ in evaluated, 510–511, 512–513 No. 70 on election of the by plurality vote economic and environmental policy linked in, 508– (Hamilton), 199–200 509 No. 78 on the judiciary (Hamilton), 201–206 the Euro (replacing the Mark, Franc, etc.), 512 Feminist analysis, 359 the European Convention, 217–218 Feminist issues, 254, 354–355, 356, 360, 361 as a federal power, 511–513 Feudalism, 130–132, 436–437, 483 as an intergovernmental agency, 510–511 FH scale of democracy, 32–33n.36, 527, 528, 530 need for institutional reform in, 513–515 Figueiredo, Argelina Cheibub, and Fernando permissive consensus as basis of, 512, 550 Limongi, 304 power of nation-state members in, 506–507 Finland, 59, 170f., 176f., 285t., 288t., 289t., 360 powers of the elected parliament, 511, 513–514 First Amendment, 248, 415 public confidence in, 512–513 ‘‘First-past-the-post’’ elections, 343, 352 Ex-Communist countries, 93, 111, 505, 531t. Fishkin, James S., 25–28 cultural values of, 170f., 171, 174, 176f. Foreign intervention, 75, 95, 495, 528 democratization of, 94 Founders (American). See Federalists low level of interpersonal trust in, 175, 176f. Foweraker, Joe, on presidential regimes in Latin reverse modernization in, 179 America, 296–303. See also Latin America; Executive powers, 296n.13, 201, 297–298, 302, 304 Presidentialism attempted autogolpe, 298, 302 Fractionalization, 188n.19, 189t., 285, 286t., 292t., limitation of as a criterion of liberal democracy, 35 301 in the U.S., 365–366 France, 38, 58, 59, 66, 129, 170f., 176f., 285t., 288t., Extrication from authoritarian regimes, 76, 111. See 289t., 335t. also Regime transition Franklin, M., et al., 513–514 in Latin America, 76–82 Freedoms. See Rights and freedoms optimal strategy of, 84–85 Free-market fallacy, 434 in Poland, 77n.24, 79n.27, 80, 84, 85n.45 French Revolution, 66, 70 proto-democratic actors, 76, 77–82, 78t., 79t., 80f. Fuch, Lawrence, 487 Index 543

Fukuyama, Francis, 169 Grenzke, Janet, 412 Fundamentalism, 168n.1 Groups, theory of. See Organizational theory Growth. See Economic development Galbraith, J. K., 424 Guatemala, 37, 298, 531t. Game theory, 143 Guinier, Lani, 153 GATT, 506 Guttmann, Amy, and Dennis Thompson, 18–24 GDP per capita. See under National income Gender parity, 259–260, 355–357, 361. See also Habermas, Ju¨rgen, 23–24 Underrepresentation, of women Haggard, Stephen, 427 General Possibility Theorem, 317–320, 321 Hamilton, Alexander, 192 Genocide, 494 The Federalist No. 23, 192 Geographic requirements, 151, 154, 154t. The Federalist No. 70, 199–200 Geopolitical interests, 74, 75, 111–112, 523 The Federalist No. 78, 201–206 Georgia, 170f., 176f. Hamiltonian federalism, 129, 130 Germany, 58, 66, 74. See also East Germany; West Hardin, Russell, 14, 504 Germany Hardliners, role of in transitional regimes, 77–82, 78t., Gerrymandering, race-based, 249n.27, 250 79t., 102 Ghana, 170f., 176f. Hartz, Louis, 126, 480, 483–484 Ginsburg, Ruth, 252, 253–255 Hegemonic theory of judicial empowerment, 232, Global commons, 520 233–238, 240–243 Global economy, 93, 495 Held, David, 516 Globalization, 516 Heterogeneous political culture, 133, 135, 145, 188, Global order. See also Geopolitical interests; Middle- 188–189, 212, 460. See also Pluralism income countries; Poor and underdeveloped Hindu religion, 175, 176f. countries; Supranational political forms; Wealthy Hirschl, Ran, 232 countries Historical-cultural heritage, 169, 173, 174–179, 176f., democracy and, 489, 510, 516 181 global economic processes, 518–519 Hobbesianism, 208 global environmental problems (see Environmental Hobson’s choice, 102, 105, 107 pollution) Hochschild, Jennifer L., on paradoxical racial ‘‘hyperglobalizers,’’ 519 perspectives in America, 463–476 regional and global enmeshment, 517–520, 521 Homogeneous political culture, 133, 135, 145, 183, transnational public health problems, 522 480–483 GNP per capita. See under National income Homosexuality, 171 Governability, 163–164, 302–303, 398–401 Horowitz, Donald, 147–151, 154 Government. See also Military forces; Political Huber, Evelyne, Dietrich Rueschemeyer, and John systems; Security forces Stephens, 71 bureaucracy, 406–407 Huber, John, and G. Bingham Powell, Jr., 330 as center of interest-based power, 364, 365–366 Humana human rights scale, 30–31n.15 compulsory taxation, 375–377, 393 Human rights, 30, 83, 496. See also Civil liberties interest intermediation role of, 398–401 Hungary, 59, 111, 170f., 176f. state coercion, 383–384 Huntington, Samuel P., 88, 93, 110, 447 Governmental stability. See Stability of regimes on cultural factors and democracy, 96–97, 169 Government regulation, 393–397 on levels of economic development and Grand coalitions, 142, 148, 149 democratization, 97–98, 112 Great Britain. See Britain on negotiated transitions, 101–103, 107 Greece, 76, 82, 94, 208, 319 on possible legitimacy issues of democracies, 95, 98 Green, Donald P., Soo Yeon Kim, and David H. on waves and reverse waves of democratization, 93– Yoon, 497–502 95, 97 Index 544

Iceland, 59, 170f., 176f., 285t., 288t., 289t., 347–348, minority governments and, 284–285 359–360 party fractionalization and, 348–349 Ideology, 145, 147, 154. See also Political spectrum Institutional arrangements, 40–42, 81n.33, 84, 169. compulsion and, 375–376, 376n.19 See also Electoral formulas; Government ideological consensus (unorganized), 368–369 Institutional reform, and the European Union (EU), nationalism, 375 513–515 Puritan egalitarianism, 160, 161–162, 456, 457 Interdependence, 492 ‘‘Illiberal democracy,’’ 37n.58 Interelection stage, 50–51 Immobilism, 144, 277 Interest groups, 363, 400. See also Economic Impossibility theorem, 317–320, 321 organizations; Organizational theory Income level, 16, 52–53. See also National income; accessing governmental centers of power, 364, 365– Redistribution 366 Incremental reform, 389–391 as distributive coalitions, 427, 430–432, 430–433 Incumbency, 16, 286, 411, 413, 439 imbalance of interests, 398–399, 404, 406 India, 151, 170f., 175, 176f., 177f., 444, 505 interest-based organizations in pluralist theory, 158– Individual freedoms. See Rights and freedoms 160, 387–388 Individualist political culture, 165 intermediation role of government, 398–401 Individual rationality, 319, 375 lobbying, 378–380 Individual will, 7–8, 14, 40–41, 42. See also Self- multiple overlapping memberships, 366–367 expression and partisan mobilization, 401–403 Industrial authority structures, 44–45 potential interest groups, 366, 367–369 Industrialization. See also Economic development; repressed in authoritarian regimes, 430–431 Modernization theory Inter-ethnic political cooperation, models of, 150, 151, democratization and, 56–57 153–154, 154t. economic obstacles to, 421–423 Inter-Governmental Conference (IGC), 513 e¤ects of, 88, 168, 173, 174, 178–179 Intermediate-income countries. See Middle-income modernization and, 88, 168, 173, 174, 178–179 countries population growth as a barrier to, 423 International law, 521 of subsistence economies, 421, 422, 423–426 International political order. See Global order welfare problem during early phases of, 423–426 International threats, 496 Industrialized countries. See Wealthy countries International Urban Research, 57 Industries, 394–397 Interpersonal trust, 175, 176f., 183 Inequality. See also Racial discrimination; Social class Investment, 420–421, 424, 425–426, 447, 448, 452 in access to political power, 38, 45 Ireland, 170f., 176f., 288t., 335t. under capitalism, 383–384, 385, 388, 391–392 Islamic religious culture. See also Arab world in Central America, 73 whether democracy is compatible with, 36, 95, 96– deepening of in America, 382, 487 97, 185, 187, 188t., 189t. in democratic regimes, 504 values associated with, 170f., 175, 176f. between nations, 98 Israel, 236–240, 243, 285t., 288t., 289t., 352 social stratification in underdeveloped countries, 61– Italy, 38, 59, 66, 74, 163–164, 170f., 176f., 285t., 62 288t., 289t., 335t., 402 Information, 35, 98, 157, 448. See also Media Inglehart, Ronald, and Wayne Baker, 168–179, Jacobson, Gary, 412, 413 171n.5 Jamaica, 444 Instability, 110, 112, 198 Japan, 38, 66, 170f., 176f. crisis duration, 292t. Judicial empowerment, hegemonic theory of, 232, electoral volatility, 288–289, 292t. 233–236, 237–238, 240–243 interest promotion and partisan mobilization Judicial impartiality, 238 causing, 401–403 Judicial review, 223, 223–226, 230–231, 232n.3 Index 545

Judiciary. See also Supreme Court (U.S.) Latin American culture zone, 173 danger of participation in the political arena, 238–239 most governable vs. least governable countries, 303 independence of a criterion of democracy, 35, 202– no clear pattern of economic factors and regime 205 forms in, 112 nondiscriminatory as a criterion of liberal political reform in, 76 democracy, 35 president-assembly relationships in, 297, 298–302 on permanent appointment of judges, 205–206 proportional representation in, 296 reactive/directed judicial approach, 254–255 two-party systems in, 299 role of, 201–202, 203–204, 253–255 Latvia, 170f., 176f. Jung, Courtney, and Ian Shapiro, 99, 350 Law and order. See Domestic order; Peace Justice, distributive. See Redistribution Leadership. See Competition for leadership Justice, in a democracy, 370, 459–461s. See also Lebanon, 143, 148, 149, 150 Egalitarianism; Judiciary Leftist parties, 59–60, 95 Legal innovations, 147–148, 236 Kant, Immanuel, 490–491 Legislatures. See also Parliamentarianism; Preferences Karl, Terry Lynn, 33 and preference profiles; President-assembly Katz, Richard, 514 relationships; Representation; Seat allocation Kitschelt, Herbert, 460 distrust of legislative powers, 209 Knesset, Israeli, 237, 239 Israeli Knesset, 237, 239 Kuhn, Thomas, 381 in Latin American countries, 297–298, 304, 353 law-making supremacy limited by constitutionali- Labor force zation, 219–220, 222 under authoritarian capitalism, 434 legislative committees, 287–288 dissident workers, 425–426 legislative majority power (the ‘‘republican and political regime, 422, 449–450, 453 principle’’), 212 unemployment, 382, 424 parliament of the European Union, 511, 513–514 wildcat strikes, 404 parliaments, 66, 226, 284 women’s participation in, 449 in a representative republic, 195–196, 197–198 Labor theory of value, 386–387, 391 underrepresentation of women in, 354–355 Labor unions, 87–88, 89–90, 372, 425, 426 U.S. Congress actions following Supreme Court Labour Party (British), 217–218 decisions holding legislation unconstitutional, 247– Land 248, 247t., 248–249 early Americans’ access to, 129–130 Legitimacy issues landed elites, 69–70, 72, 74 of authoritarian regimes, 93 landed peasantry, 65 consociationalism undermining legitimate opposition, Large nations, 212, 505 351–352 aspects of democracy may be di‰cult in, 25, 37–38, and constitutional interpretation, 250 143, 505 potential issues of wealthy democracies, 95, 98 Condorcet’s paradox resolvable in, 326–329 in a transnational context, 523 Large organizations, 373, 375–380, 376n.21. See also Less developed countries. See Developing countries Organizational theory Lewis, W. Arthur, 422n.7 Largest remainder PR, 343, 344, 345 Liberal democracy, 30, 483–484. See also Civil Latin America, 170f., 176f., 531t. liberties; Nation-state; Political equality; coalition formation in, 299–303 Substantive democracy commonalities in political systems, 296–298 in America, 485 democratization following di‰cult patterns in, 72–73 concepts developed of national communities, 516– extrication from authoritarian regimes in, 76–82 517 influence of colonial ties in, 173 criteria of, 35–36 landholding elites in, 72–73 equality as a value of, 386 Index 546

Liberal democracy (cont.) tyranny defined as deprivation of natural rights, extending beyond electoral requirement, 34 207, 209, 210, 213–214, 215 globalization and, 521–524 tyranny as unified governmental powers, 207, 208, self-determination in, 252, 523, 528 210, 211 two visions of, 330, 334, 335 (see also Majority Mainwaring, Scott, 266 control vision; Proportional Influence vision) Mainwaring, Scott, and Matthew Shugart, 300–302 Liberalism, 317, 390 Majoritarian systems, 241. See also Britain; Canada Lijphart, Arend, 142–146, 148, 149, 351 single-party majorities, 299, 330, 331, 335t., 337t. Lincoln-Douglas-Bell-Breckenridge race (1820), 322– Majority coalitions, 235, 299n.70, 302 325 grand coalitions, 142, 148, 149 Lindblom, Charles, 388 Majority Control vision Linz, Juan, 38, 258 lesser congruence between citizen-preferences and Lipset, Seymour Martin, 56–64, 108, 110, 112–113 policymaking in, 337t., 338t., 337–340, 339t., 341– Lithuania, 170f., 176f. 342 Lobbying, 378–380 two-party systems characterizing, 330, 331–332, 338 and PAC contributions, 408–410, 413, 414–415, weaker opposition in, 334 414t., 417–418 Majority-minority districting, 153, 154t. Local level, 165–166, 456 Majority rule. See also Cyclical majorities; Elections Locke, John, 129–130, 507 consociationalism violating principle of, 142 Logrolling, 137–138, 352. See also Preferences and as a criterion of democracy, 15–16, 48, 252 preference profiles insu‰cient for democracy, 217 Luxembourg, 59 in legislatures (the ‘‘republican principle’’), 212, 215 Lycurgus, 4 as an issue in South African transition, 103–104 Majority tyranny. See Tyranny of the majority Macedonia, 170f., 176f. Majority rule, may lead to a form of tyranny. See Mackie, Gerry, 321–325 Tyranny of the majority Madison, James. See also Madisonian democracy Malaysia, 37, 37n.58, 95, 111, 148, 150, 154 The Federalist No. 47, 193–194, 207 Mandela, Nelson, 99, 104–105 The Federalist No. 48, 195–196 Manhood su¤rage, 93, 131, 456, 484 The Federalist No. 49, 211 Manley, John F., 381 The Federalist No. 62, 197–198 Manufactured majorities, 345 Madisonian democracy, 20, 48, 207 Maori, New Zealand minority, 242n.70 contradictions in, 207, 213–216 Market-oriented reforms, 76, 87–91. See also factionalism must be controlled, 159, 211–212, 214– Capitalism 215 relationship to democratization, 76, 87–91, 233 factions defined as seeking particular rather than material conditions deteriorating with, 90 unified goods, 211–212, 214 unpopularity of, 85–86, 86n.1, 89 majority rule (the ‘‘republican principle’’), 212, 215 Marsh, Michael, and Bernhard Wessels, 514 minorities’ rights, 208, 209, 215 Marx, Karl, 381, 386–387 representative republic the model of, 209–210 on the working class, 62, 169 separation/balance of powers in, 210, 211, 212–213 Marxism, 67–68, 390, 405. See also Class analysis concerns over tyranny labor theory of value, 386–387, 391 elections insu‰cient to prevent tyranny, 210–211 ‘‘Marxist humanism,’’ 384, 387 limitation of majority tyranny required, 207, 212, Marxist-Leninist regimes, 95 215–216 Mass media, 25, 26, 167, 370 power unchecked inevitably leads to tyranny, 207, McCarthyism, 129, 484 208–209, 212, 213–214 McCloskey, H., 387 tendency toward majority tyranny, 136, 208, 214, Measurements of democracy. See Democracy scales 215, 366 and measures Index 547

Media, 163, 178. See also Information Moderates, role of in transitional regimes, 77–82, 78t., broadcast media, 25, 26, 167, 370 79t., 80f., 102 globalization of, 519–520 Moderation and pluralism, 134 Median legislator, 334t., 335t. Modernization theory, 65–66, 88, 179. See also Median party, 333, 338t. Economic development Median voter, 224, 334t., 335t., 338t., 428 under authoritarian regimes, 110–111 Mexico, 37, 170f., 176f., 301–302, 531 cultural heritage not accounted for in (see also Middle class, 62, 74. See also Social class Historical-cultural heritage), 169, 178–179, 181 African-American, 469, 471–474, 475 e¤ects of industrialization, 88, 168, 173, 174, 178–179 as the bourgeoisie, 69, 69t., 399 (see also view that democracy is related to modernization, Bourgeoisie) 109–110, 112, 168 Middle East–North Africa, 531t. reverse trends, 93, 179 Middle-income countries, 75, 98, 110–111 secularization thesis, 179 Military coalitions and regimes, 74, 112 Moldova, 170f., 176f. Military coups, 82–83, 82f., 298 Monarchy, 436 Military disputes. See Warfare Mongolia, 94 Military forces. See also Security forces; Warfare Monopolies (economic), 427 capacity of a predictor of involvement in disputes, Montagnards, 129 500, 501t., 502 Montesquieu, 181, 193–194 civilian control of, 82–84, 528 Moore, Barrington, 65, 66–70 multilateral defense arrangements, 521 Moral deliberation, 20–22, 38, 222. See also role of in Latin American transitions, 76, 77, 82, 83, Nonviolent resolution; Opposition 88, 102, 206 Moral disagreement, 18–19 Mill, John Stuart, 182, 312–314 Moral/ethical political culture, 165 Miller, Nicholas R., 133 Multiculturalism, 484–485 Minimalist conception of democracy, 5, 9–11, 12–16, Multidimensional policy space, 460 31–33 Multilateral defense arrangements, 521 participatory aspect as unnecessary to, 42, 43– Multinational corporations, 519 44 Multipartism, 37n.58, 266, 344, 345 popular will in, 6–7, 11 and government stability, 348–349 Minority domination of economic policy, 442 median party in, 333, 338t. Minority governments. See also Cabinet types Multiple traditions analysis, 482–483, 485–487 conventional explanations of, 285–286 Multipolar coalitions, 150, 151 factors favoring formation of, 289–291, 290t. Municipal level. See Local level incidence of, 284, 285t. Muslims. See Islamic religious culture minoritarian cabinet formation, 284, 285–288, 293– Myrdal, Gunnar, 469n.2, 480, 483 295 Minority representation, preference clusters and, 136– NAFTA. See North American Free Trade Alliance 138, 137f. See also Opposition (NAFTA) Minority rights, 233, 242n.70, 247, 528 National boundaries, 517, 519, 522, 524 Minority rule, 250, 277, 284 National income, 439–440. See also Middle-income Minority tyranny, 209. See also Apartheid countries; Poor and underdeveloped countries; Minority vetoes, 100 Wealthy countries Minor parties, exclusion of, 345 political regime having no e¤ect on, 450, 451–452, ‘‘Mirror’’ representation, 355–357, 358 451t. Missouri Compromise of 1820, 322 related to democratic norms, 62–63 Mixed systems, congruence between citizen- as GNP or GDP per capita preferences and policymaking in, 335t., 337t., cultural variation in values related to, 65, 178–179, 340t., 341–342, 353, 532–533 420, 436, 447 Index 548

National income (cont.) Normative vs. empirical approaches, 40–41, 43 as the determinant of democracy, 184–185, 186t., Norms, democratic, 43, 62–63 187, 187t., 188t., 189t. Norris, Pippa, 357, 358, 360, 510, 513–514 as higher in democracies, 449, 451t. North, Douglas, and Barry Weingast, 234n.15 as influencing democratization, 183–185 North America, governability and interest as not the sole determinant of democratic/modernist intermediation in, 398, 399–401. See also by values, 174–178, 176f. nation Nationalism, 375 North American Free Trade Alliance (NAFTA), 506 National membership organizations, 163 Northern Ireland, 170f., 176f., 354 National Party, South Africa, 242–243 North Korea, 529 National sovereignty, 507–508, 517, 522, 524 Northwest Europe, 63 Nation-state, 178, 452, 516–517. See also Norway, 59, 170f., 176f., 285t., 288t., 289t., 359–360 Government; Historical-cultural heritage; Large Nyerere, Julius, 142 nations interdependence of states, 492 Oceana, 531t. national sovereignty, 507–508, 517, 522, 524 Ocean pollution, 505 organizational theory of, 373, 375, 376–377 O’Donnell, Guillermo, 76–77, 112–113 as a relational system, 370 O’Donnell, Guillermo, and Philippe Schmitter, 99 territorial boundaries of, 517, 519, 522, 524 OECD (Organization for Economic Development), under globalization, 521–524 169 Native Americans, 484 O¤e, Claus, 405 Natural rights, 207, 209, 210, 213–214, 215, 248 Oil countries, 531t. Negative bias, 432, 433 Oligarchies (economic), 393, 528 Negotiated transitions, 99, 101, 102, 103–104, 105. Olson, Mancur, 372–380, 427, 436 See also South Africa One-party regimes, 37, 37n.58, 112, 344, 445. See also Neopluralism, Pluralism II, 381, 382, 383–384, 388. Authoritarianism See also Pluralism and pluralist theory Open list PR systems, 300, 301 Nepal, 94 Opposition. See also Incumbency; Minority Nepotism, 62 representation Nested collective action, 505, 509. See also challenger financing in political campaigns, 411–413, Supranational political forms 412t. Netherlands, 59, 170f., 176f., 177f., 285t., 288t., 289t., consociationalism undermining beneficial aspects of, 335t., 352 351–352 Netherlands Antilles, 148 extent of influence over policy, 286–287, 288t., 292t., New Zealand, 59, 170f., 176f., 241–242, 242n.70, 351–353 335t. factors associated with weakening of, 142–143, 334 Nigeria, 94, 143, 154, 170f., 176f., 177f. importance to electoral politics of, 135, 138–140, Nonculturalist view. See under Cultural factors and 145, 286–288 democracy institutionalized forms of critical to democracy, 252, Nondemocracies, 36–37, 37n.58, 39, 95–96. See also 255, 350–351 Authoritarianism; Dictatorship motivations of political minorities, 142, 143–144, 148 Nondemocratic outcomes, 33, 41, 90–91, 210–211, 395 must be able to overturn ruling party, 37, 396 Nongovernmental organizations. See Voluntary opposition coalitions, 352 associations proportionality of electoral system creating stronger, Non-Iberic America, 531t. 335t., 341 Nonviolent resolution, 30 repressed under authoritarian regime, 433 Nordic countries, 294, 354, 359–360 role of in transitional regimes, 77–82, 78t., 79t., 80f., Normative/procedural approach. See Procedural 100, 102, 107 democracy in two-party systems, 352 Index 549

Organizational theory. See also Economic democratic republics are likely to be peaceful, 490– organizations; Interest groups; Nation-state; 491, 492–494 Political parties nonmilitarization of democracies is unproven, 497– autonomous organizations essential to pluralist 500, 499t., 501t. theory, 158–160, 387–388 Peasants, 65, 68–70, 69t., 70n.25 by-product theory of large organizations, 378–380 Peoples’ will. See Popular sovereignty competitive market analogy of groups, 373–375 Peru, 170f., 176f. economic organizations, 379n.2 electoral democracy in, 37 large organizations and collective goods, 373, 375– issue of governability in, 303 378, 376n.21 military coup in, 298 lobbying, 378–380 presidential-assembly relation in, 298, 299, 299n.70, purpose of an organization, 372–373 302 small groups, 377–378 Philanthropic groups, 372n.6 subgroups, 373n.11 Philippines, 170f., 176f. Orthodox cultural zone, 169, 170f., 171, 176f. Phillips, Anne, 354–360 Orthodox religion, 176f. Piketty, Thomas, 461 Overload school, 398–399 Pinochet, Augusto, 84 Plattner, Marc F., 30 PAC contributions, 408–410, 413, 414–415, 414t., Pluralism and pluralist theory, 35, 134, 136–138, 149, 417–418 153. See also Interest groups; Organizational Pacific Islands, 531t. theory; Social pluralism Pakistan, Islamic cultural values in, 97, 170f., 176f. autonomous organizations central to, 158–160, 387– Pan-Africanist Congress (PAC), 103. See also South 388 Africa downplaying class e¤ects, 383, 384, 391–392 Paradox of voting. See Condorcet’s paradox; Cyclical democratic values normative rather than inherent to, majorities 384–386, 387, 390 Pareto optimality, 318 as dispersed preferences (see Preferences and Parliament, British, 66, 226 preference profiles) Parliamentarianism, 9, 34, 219–220, 221–223, 257 not ensuring a balance of interests, 398–399, 404 Parliamentary systems, 66, 284, 286–287, 292t., 293– Pluralism I, 381, 382–383 295. See also Electoral formulas; Legislatures Pluralism II, 381, 382, 383–384, 388 Parliament of the European Union (EU), 511, 513– polarized pluralism, 298–299 514 encouraging political stratagems, 134 Participatory democracy, 157, 162, 164. See also polyarchy as a model of power, 32, 38, 48–53, 382, Citizen competence; Social capital; Voting 385 characteristics of, 41–42 of power, 381–382, 387–388 civic engagement, 39 as ‘‘rules of the game,’’ 368–369 in classical theory, 40–41 stability of democratic regime and, 133, 134, 138– under cosmopolitan model of democracy, 523–554 140 educative aspects of democracy, 41, 44, 45 proposing incremental structural reform, 389–391 income level correlated with participation, 16, 52–53 Plurality-majority elections, 199–200, 343, 344, 352. participatory culture, 182–183 See also Single-member district elections Tocqueville on, 157, 162, 164 Poland Party list PR, greatest representation of women in, cultural values in, 170f., 176f. 357–358, 359–360 extrication from authoritarian regime, 76, 77n.24, Pateman, Carole, 40–46 79n.27, 80, 84, 85n.45 Patriotism, 375 market-oriented reforms in, 86 Peace. See also Domestic order; Nonviolent resolution regime-change dynamics, 111 creating a system for, 492, 495–496 Solidarnos´c´,88 Index 550

Polarization Political systems, 42, 44, 153–154, 154t. See also multipolar coalitions, 150, 151 Authoritarianism; Democracy; Government; polarized pluralism, 298–299, 303 Regime transition political, 95, 159–160, 285–287, 286t., 292–293, 292t. Political underrepresentation, 345, 352 Political actors. See also Elites; Interest groups; Polity III and IV data on democracies, 498, 527, 528, Political parties; Popular sovereignty 529, 530 proto-democratic actors in regime transitions, 76, Polling, deliberative, 25–28 77–82, 78t., 79t., 80f. Polsby, Nelson W., 381n.2 turning to the judiciary to preserve hegemony, 233– Polyarchy, 32, 38, 48–53, 382–385. See also Pluralism 236 and pluralist theory Political autonomy, 523 Poor and underdeveloped countries Political campaigns. See Campaign finance; Elections; consumption of goods in, 447–448, 449, 452 Political parties democracy not available to, 98 Political culture, 165, 169, 170f., 171. See also environmental externalities related to development Cultural factors and democracy of, 507 Political economy. See Economic development and industrialization of subsistence economies, 421, 422, political regime 423–426 Political egalitarianism. See Egalitarianism multilateral aid to, 494 Political equality, 8n.3, 358–359, 461 political-regime type not a¤ecting economies of, as a normative value in pluralist theory, 384–385, 452 387, 390 social stratification in, 61–62 as (merely) opportunity versus substantive equality, Popper, Karl, 13 385, 386–387, 391 Popular sovereignty, 2–3, 14, 48, 318, 382. See also Political extremism, 59, 160, 161–162. See also Social Elections; Majority rule revolutions in classical theory, 3–4, 5 Political influence of regimes, 112 individual will, 7–8, 40–41, 42 Political parties, 35, 379 minimalist conception of, 6–7, 11 anti-system and pro-system, 348, 349 popular will, 3–4, 14, 25 during democratic transitions, 88 problem of unequal access to power, 386 electoral incentives and, 155, 286 Population growth, 423, 449–450 partisan mobilization interest promotion, 401–403 Populism, 317, 321 party behavior in Brazil, 304 Populist democracy, 48–49 party competition, 331, 336n.31 Populist parties, exclusion of, 95 party defractionalization patterns, 343–346, 352–353 Portugal, 76, 94, 170f., 176f., 285t., 288t., 289t., 293 party discipline, 300–301 Post–World War II period, 73 party loyalty, 432 Poverty Political power of economic organizations, 378–380, and blacks in America, 469 386, 395–397 and consumption of goods, 447–448, 449, 452 Political reform, in Latin America, 76 and disa¤ection in inner cities, 162, 487 Political science, 321, 499t., 500, 501t., 502 famine, 444–446, 448 Political spectrum, 330, 383–384. See also Congruence lack of access to information a factor of, 162 between citizen-preferences and policymaking; poor nations (see Poor and underdeveloped Ideology; Preferences and preference profiles countries) in Europe a broad spectrum, 129, 130 and whites in America, 471, 474n.37 left-right scale, 330, 336n.31, 338t., 340t. Power. See also Interest groups; Political actors; liberal-conservative continuum, 161–162, 336n.31 Political parties; Political systems median legislator, 334t., 335t. centralization of, 240, 403–404 median party, 333, 338t. competition among elites provides pluralist sources median voter, 224, 334t., 335t., 338t., 428 of, 381–382, 387–388 Index 551

ideology and, 375–376, 376n.19 Proportional influence vision (PI) interest groups providing access to governmental election and postelection stages, 333 centers of, 364, 365–366, 370–371 greater congruence of citizens and policymakers in, pluralist model of polyarchy, 32, 38, 48–53, 382, 330, 332–334, 334t., 335t., 337–340, 337t., 338t., 385 339t., 340t., 341 political power of economic organizations, 378–380, Proportional representation (PR), 343–344 386, 395–397 closed list PR systems, 301 as the exercise of rational self-interest by elites, 437– cumulative voting, 154 438 largest remainder PR, 343, 344, 345 social relations inherent within economic relations, in Latin American countries, 296, 300 384, 386–387, 390 multipartism, 37n.58, 266, 344, 345, 348–349 state coercion or compulsion, 383–384 open list PR systems, 300, 301 if unchecked inevitably leads to tyranny (Madison), encouraging strong parties, 343 207, 208–209, 212, 213–214 party systems more fractionalized, 346, 352 Power-sharing arrangements, 100–101, 103–104, single transferable vote, 357 105 vote pooling, 150, 154, 154t. PR. See Proportional representation (PR) women better represented with, 357–358, 359–360 Preferences and preference profiles. See also Cyclical Protestantism, 93, 170f., 171, 173, 358, 514 majorities; Polarization; Political spectrum associated with democratization, 93–94, 185, 481 cross-cutting divisions in, 136–138, 137f. historical influences of, 176f. dispersed preferences, 133–134 interpersonal trust common in, 175, 176f. equal power of each vote as a criterion of Proto-democratic actors, 76, 77–82, 78t., 79t., 80f. democracy, 50 PR-presidentialism, 277, 298–299, 302–303 pluralism as dispersed preferences, 133–134 Przeworski, Adam, 12–16, 76–91, 181–189, 428. See preference clusters, 133–134, 136–138, 137f. also Cultural factors and democracy; Procedural single-peaked preferences, 135, 136, 327 democracy; Regime transition voting preferences, 10, 14, 327, 395, 396 Przeworski, Adam, et al., 447–453. See also President-assembly relationships, 272, 297–303, 304, Democracy and Development (DD) scale; 352–353 Economic development and political regime; Presidential election of 1820 (U.S.), 322–325 National income Presidentialism, 16, 257, 258, 266 Przeworski, Adam, Jose´ Antonio Cheibub, and Presidential powers. See Executive powers Fernando Limongi, 108–114, 527–528 Price control, regulatory, 393 Pseudodemocracies, 36–37. See also Proactive political systems, 153, 154t., 155 Consociationalism Probabilistic voting model of income redistribution, Public deliberation. See Discourse; Moral deliberation 431–432 Public finance. See Taxation Procedural democracy. See also Consociationalism Public goods, 167, 372, 442 DD scale measuring, 527, 528, 531–533, 531t. under autocracy, 437–438, 442 normative aspects unrecognized, 43 and large organizations, 373, 375–378, 376, 376n.21 Przeworski defending, 12–16, 181 present vs. future goods, 6 Schumpeter defining, 5, 9–11, 12 Public health problems, global, 522 Property relations, 39n.67, 66, 249n.28. See also Land Public opinion, 364, 384–385, 387, 512–513. See also capitalism and, 384, 434 Racial perspectives in America early American egalitarianism based in small Public vs. private spheres, 359 homesteads, 129–130 Public will. See Popular sovereignty; Public opinion market operations based in, 434 Puerto Rico, 170f., 176f. secure property rights related to economic Puritan egalitarianism, 170f., 173, 174, 445–447, 456, development, 441–442, 448 457, 480–481, 482 social capital vs. privately owned, 384 Putnam, Robert D., 157–167, 169 Index 552

Race-based or a‰rmative gerrymandering, 249n.27, democracy movements, 157 250 dual transition to democracy and market economy, Racial discrimination, views on di¤er by race, 463, 89–91, 233 464–465, 470 role of economic actors during, 86–91 Racial hierarchy or inequality, 481n.3, 484 role of military forces during, 76, 77, 77n.23, 82, 83, Racial minorities, 153, 154t., 249n.27, 250, 487 88 Racial perspectives in America per capita income and, 187t., 188t., 189t. black Americans’ quandary, 468–469 political parties role in, 88 degree of optimism, 463, 466, 468, 472–473 proto-democratic actors, 76, 77–82, 78t., 79t., 80f. intra-racial class di¤erences among African reverse waves (from democracy to authoritarianism), Americans attitudes, 469–474 93, 94–95 paradoxes in, 463, 467, 469–472, 475–476 ‘‘snowballing’’ e¤ects, 93, 94, 95 on racial equality, 461, 463, 464, 468, 469–472 social pacts during, 89–90 on success as result of hard work (Algerism), 463– role of unions during, 87–88 464, 466–467, 468, 473–474 Regional autonomy, 151, 154t. on success as result of virtue, 466–467, 474 Regional majorities, 345 white Americans’ quandary, 468 Regulation of industry. See Government regulation Radcli¤e-Brown, 64n.44 Religion and national culture Radicals, 77–82, 78t., 79t., 80f., 106. See also Political Confucian culture, whether democracy is compatible extremism with, 36, 96–97 Rae, Douglas W., 343 democracy is compatible with any religious belief, of coalitions, 284, 286–287, 187 293–295 fundamentalism, 168n.1 Rationality. See Reason Islamic culture, whether democracy is compatible Rawls, John, 391, 460 with, 36, 95, 96–97, 185, 187, 188t., 189t. Reactionary capitalist regimes, 66, 68–69, 74, 402 religious groups, 372n.6 Reactive/directed judiciary, 254–255 religious heritage as an influence on national values, Reactive political systems, 153, 154–155, 154t. 170f., 171, 174, 175, 176f., 178, 456, 457 Reason, 7–8, 18 Rent seeking, 427–430 Reciprocity, 18–19, 21–22, 39, 159, 213 Representation, 311, 312. See also Democracy deficit Redistribution, 427 and the democracy deficit, 510 in capitalist authoritarian states, 433–434 the electoral fallacy of, 33, 41, 90–91 under democracy, 430–433, 439–442 equality of participation, 356–357 under dictatorship, 432–433, 439–442 importance of in a democracy, 312–314, 330–331 in democracy vs. dictatorship, 427–430, 436, 439– mirroring composition of constituency, 355–357, 358 442 of pluralism in legislatures, 153 distributive coalitions, 427, 430–432 as not su‰cient for democracy, 41 distributive justice theory, 391, 460 of women (see Underrepresentation, of women) toward investors or consumers, 448 Representative-constituency relationship. See pluralist vs. class-based arguments for, 383, 385, 386 Congruence between citizen-preferences and tax policy, 421, 439, 440 policymaking Reflective political systems, 153, 154t. Representative republics. See also Democratic Reformers, role of in transitional regimes, 77–82, 78t., regimes, 209–210 79t., 80f., 102 contradictions in Madison’s conception of, 207, 213– Reform governments, 89–91 216 Regimes. See Political systems as the goal of Madisonian democracy, 209–212 Regime transition. See also Democratization, 13–14, likely to be peaceful, 490–491 450 representative government, 25–26, 312–314 civilian control of military di‰cult in, 82–84 Reproductive rights, 21 Index 553

Republicanism. See Representative republics multiple-member districts, 344 Republican Party (U.S.), 414, 416 vote pooling, 150, 154, 154t. Responsiveness to elections, 289t., 295 Secession, 154 Reverse waves, from democracy to authoritarianism, Second Vatican Council (1963–1965), 93 93, 94–95 Secular-rational values, 171, 172f., 173, 174, 179 Revolution. See Social revolution Security forces, 104. See also Military forces Rights and freedoms. See also Civil liberties; Self-determination, 252–253, 523, 528 Constitutional rights; Minority rights Self-expression, 170f., 171, 172f., 173, 177f. economic development related to, 441–442 Semiproportional systems. See Mixed systems as essential to democracy, 24, 36, 217, 221 Sen, Amartya, 444–446, 448. See also Civil human rights, 30, 83, 496 liberties; Poor and underdeveloped countries; natural rights, 207, 209, 210, 213–214, 215, 248 Redistribution as not necessarily connected to democracy, 10–11, Shannon, Lyle, 56n.9 43 Shapiro, Ian, 153–155, 252 U.S. Supreme Court decisions upholding, 248–249, Shugart, Matthew S., and John Carey, 272, 296n.13 248n.25 Singapore, 36, 37n.58, 96, 111, 434, 529 Riker, William H., 143, 317, 321, 324–329 Single-member district elections, 153, 343–345 Rio Conference on the Environment, 520, 525 Single-party majorities, 299, 330, 331, 335t., 337t. Rochester School, 321 Single-peaked preferences, 135, 136, 327 Roemer, John E., 459–461 Single transferable vote, 357 Roe v. Wade, 254 Size principle, 143 Roman Catholic Church. See Catholicism Skerry, Peter, 163 Romania, 94, 170f., 176f. Skocpol, Theda, 65 Roper Social and Political Trends, 160, 161 Slavery, 324, 486 Rosenblum, Nancy, 160 Supreme Court decisions upholding, 249, 249n.27 Rousseau, Jean Jacques, 2–4. See also Classical Slovakia, 170f., 176f. theory of democracy Slovenia, 170f., 176f. Rule, The. See Majority rule Smith, Rogers M., 480–487 Rule of law, 35–36 Social basis of politics, 56 ‘‘Rules of the game,’’ 368–369 Social capital, 39, 384. See also Social networking Russett, Bruce, 492–496 and participatory democracy, 157, 159, 160–161, Russia, 170f., 176f., 301. See also Ex-Communist 162, 166 countries; Soviet Union political e‰cacy related to civic engagement, 163– 166 Sartori, Giovanni, 37, 43 voluntary associations, 157–158, 162–163, 167 Scandinavia. See Nordic countries Social change, 133, 361. See also Social revolution Schattschneider, E. E., 159, 388 Social checks and balances, 53 Schmitter, Philippe C., 398–407 Social class, 16, 52–53, 59, 67–68. See also Class Schmitter, Philippe C., and Terry Lynn Karl, 38 analysis; Elites; Middle class; Poverty; Working School desegregation, 249n.27, 250, 253 class Schudson, Michael, 162 Social contract, 2–4, 89–90, 441–442 Schumpeter, Joseph, 5–11, 31–32, 40–41 Social Democratic parties, 359, 402–403 Schweinitz, Karl de, Jr., 420–426. See also Social income vs. social costs, 420 Investment; Labor Force Socialist governments, 88, 91 Scotland, 354 Socialist parties, 59–60, 81 Seat allocations. See also District magnitude; Socialization, habituation to democracy, 185, 213 Electoral formulas; Proportional representation Social networking, 157, 158–160–162. See also (PR), 345 Voluntary associations in the Icelandic parliament, 347–348 Social pacts, 89–90 Index 554

Social pluralism, 158–160, 366–367, 387–388. See also Spain, 170f., 176f. Pluralism and pluralist theory cabinet formation in, 285t. Social revolution. See also Bourgeois revolutions; civilians gaining control over military in, 82 Political extremism; Social change electoral decisiveness in, 289t. bourgeois revolutions, 66–70 electoral system characteristics, 335t., 337t. factors related to forms of, 68–70, 69t. extraction from authoritarian regime, 76, 94, forms of contemporary, 65–68 111 French Revolution, 66, 70 influence of opposition in, 288t. July Revolution (English), 130 period of fascist regime in, 66, 74, 402 Marxist vision of proletarian revolution, 62, 169 Socialist government in, 91 revolutionary potential of peasants, 68–70, 69t., Stability of regimes. See also Instability 70n.25 authoritarian regimes, 112 Social sciences, 383, 459–460 corporatism and, 401–404 Social stratification. See Inequality; Social class democratic regimes, 16, 41, 44, 112, 113–114, 347– Social training, 44, 52. See also Educative aspects of 349 democracy pluralism and, 133, 134, 138–140 Social welfare, 423n.13 social factors considered in relation to, 58 Societal corporatism, 400–403, 400n.8, 404–407 Standard of living, 16, 52–53. See also National Societies, survival/self-expression dimension, 171, 173, income; Social class 177f. See also Roper Social and Political Trends Stigler, George J., 393–397, 431 Solidarnos´c´, 88. See also Poland Strikes, 404 Sorauf, Frank J., 408–418 Strom, Kaare, 284–295. See also Coalitions; Minority South Africa. See also Apartheid governments African National Congress (ANC), 99, 103–106 Structural analysis, 381n.1, 390. See also Class Communist Party in, 103 analysis Conservative Party, 104 Structural reform, 389–392 cultural values in, 170f., 176f. Sub-Saharan Africa, 37, 96, 445, 531t. extrication from apartheid, 99–100, 102–103 Subsidy, 393 Internal Security Act, 107 Subsistence economies, 421, 422, 423–426 judicial empowerment in, 242–243 Substantive democracy. See also Rights and freedoms majority rule issue, 103–104 criterion of, 29–32, 527–528 Mandela, Nelson, 99, 104–105 minority self-determination in, 528 National Party, 242–243 nonviolent resolution and freedom from military negotiated transition, 99, 104–107, 350 control, 30, 528 Pan-Africanist Congress (PAC), 103 rights and freedoms essential to, 24, 36, 217, 221 power-sharing arrangements in, 103–104, 105 Substitutions and complements, in industrial problems of emergent constitutionalism in, 99, 100, regulation, 394 100n.6, 102, 106–107 Sudan, 94 territorial dispersion of polity, 154 Superpresidential systems, 296n.13, 301 Transitional Executive Council (TEC), 106, 107 Supranational political forms. See also European South America. See Latin America Union (EU); United Nations (U.N.) South Asian cultural zone, 170f., 171, 176f. cosmopolitan model of democracy, 523–525 South-East Asia, 531t. environmental problems requiring, 505–506, 520 Southern European countries, 294 international law, 521 South Korea, 76, 80, 85, 170f., 176f., 434, 444 transnational democracy, 508–509, 516, 523–524 Sovereignty. See National sovereignty; Popular Supreme Court (Canadian), 240 sovereignty; Power Supreme Court (Israeli), 238–240 Soviet Union, 94. See also Russia; Ex-Communist Supreme Court (U.S.), 230, 246, 365 countries Buckley v. Valeo, 414, 415, 416, 418 Index 555

decisions adapted to prevailing ideologies, 238, 249– Trade unions. See Labor unions 250 Traditional political culture, influence of colonial ties, declaring laws unconstitutional and subsequent 173 Congressional actions, 247–248, 247t., 248–249 Traditional values, 165, 167, 168, 170f., 171, 172f., on the judiciary role of, 246–247, 250–251, 253–255 173. See also Historical-cultural heritage; Religion liberties upheld in decisions of, 248–249, 248n.25 and national culture; Survival values privileged groups favored in decisions of, 249, Transformation of political community, 516. See also 249n.26, 249n.72 Regime transition; Social change; Social revolution as the protector of minority rights, 247 Transitional actors, 522, 524–525 Roe v. Wade, 254 Transition to democracy. See Democratization; school desegregation decision, 249n.27, 250, 253 Regime transition striking down limits on independent campaign Transnational organizations. See European Union spending, 414, 415, 416, 418 (EU); United Nations (U.N.); and by name Surinam, 148 Transplacements. See Negotiated transitions Survival/self-expression dimension, 171, 173, 177f. Truman, David B., 364 Survival values, 171, 173, 177f. See also Traditional Turkey, 97, 170f., 176f. values Turner, Frederick Jackson, 131 Sweden, 59, 170, 285t., 288t., 289t., 335t., 337t., 359– Two-party systems, 294, 299, 330, 331–332, 344–345, 360 352 Switzerland, 59, 72, 143, 146, 170f., 176f., 177f., 354 Tyranny. See also Authoritarianism as deprivation of natural rights, 207, 209, 210, 213– Tabarrok, Alexander, and Lee Spector, 324 214, 215 Taiwan, 96, 111, 170f., 176f. power unchecked inevitably leads to (Hobbesian- Tangian, A. S., 326 Madisonian view), 207, 208–209, 212, 213–214 Tanzania, 151 as unified (rather than separated) powers, 207, 208, Taxation, 375–377, 393, 421, 439, 440 210, 211 Taylor, Michael and V. M. Herman study, 348–349 Tyranny of the majority Technology-based societies, 98 Madisonian concern over, 136, 208, 214, 215 Telecommunications, 519–520 Madisonian model of democracy limiting, 136, 208, Temporal dimensions, of goods, 6 212, 214, 215–216, 366 Territorial boundaries, 517, 519, 522, 524 Supreme Court as protection against, 247, 253 Territorial dispersion, 154 Tocqueville on, 457–458 Territory-state relations, 151 Tyranny of the minority, 209 Terrorism, 95 Thailand, 95 Ukraine, 170f., 176f. Third wave of democracy (1974–1990), 93–95, 97–98 U.N. See United Nations (U.N.) Third World, 75, 507–508. See also Developing Unanimity condition, 318 countries; Poor and underdeveloped countries Underdeveloped countries. See Poor and Tocqueville, Alexis de, 62, 98 underdeveloped countries on the American judiciary, 239 Underrepresentation on aspects of participatory democracy, 157, 162, of ethnic/racial minorities, 153, 154t. 164 of political minorities, 345, 352 Democracy in America, 483 of women, 354–355, 358, 360–361, 514 on tyranny of the majority, 457–458 di‰culty in defining shared interests of women, 356, Tocquevillian thesis, of American egalitarianism, 445– 361 447, 480–485 gender parity issues considered, 355–357 Tory political tradition, 129, 217 gender quota systems, 259–260, 361 Totalitarian parties, 528 better representation in Nordic countries, 354, 359– Trade, 497–500, 499t., 501t., 502, 518 360 Index 556

Underrepresentation (cont.) e¤ect of democracy on, 500, 501t., 502 party-list proportional representation ameliorating, factors predicting likelihood of engagement in, 500, 357–358, 359–360 501t., 502 correlated with political egalitarianism index, 358– foreign intervention, 75, 95, 495, 528 359 Vietnam war, 96, 382 Unemployment, 382, 424 Water pollution, 504, 505, 507 Union, The. See European Union (EU) Wealth distribution. See Distribution of wealth; Unions. See Labor unions Redistribution United Kingdom (U.K.). See Britain Wealthy countries United Nations (U.N.), 524–525 potential for authoritarianism in, 98 United Nations International Conference on Women, democracy more sustainable in, 110, 111, 187–188, Beijing, 525 453 United States (U.S), 69t., 93, 94, 354. See also industrial countries, 531t. American political system; Campaign finance investment supported by institutions in, 422 (U.S.); Congress (U.S.); Supreme Court (U.S.) per capita energy and resource use of, 507, 508 auto emissions problem in, 506–507 self-expression and secular-rational values geopolitical interests of, 74, 75 characterizing, 170f., 171, 172f., 174, 424 presidential election of 1860, 322–325 value systems of, 171 presidential-legislative relationship in, 353 Weber, Max, 63, 169, 372n.6 social problems in, 38, 39 Weingast, Barry, 182 underrepresentation of women in legislatures, 354, Western Europe, 398, 399–401 361 West Germany, 59, 170f., 176f., 177f., 335t., 337t., Universal male su¤rage. See Manhood su¤rage 354, 359. See also Germany Urbanization, 57, 57n.11 West Indies, 73–74 Uruguay, 76, 111, 143, 170f., 176f., 298, 299, 299n.70, Whig political tradition, 129, 130, 323 303 Wildcat strikes, 404 U.S. See United States (U.S.) Will of the people. See Popular sovereignty Utilitarianism, 6–7, 319, 423 Winner-take-all systems. See ‘‘First-past-the-post’’ elections Value conflicts. See Moral deliberation Wintrobe, Ronald, 427–434. See also Redistribution; Values, 171, 178. See also Traditional values Rent seeking Venezuela, 170f., 176f., 298–299, 299n.70, 301, 303 Women’s movement, 525. See also Feminist issues Vietnam War, 96, 382 Women’s participation in legislatures, 259–260, 361, Voluntary associations, 157–158, 162–163, 167 354, 357–360. See also Underrepresentation, of Vote asymmetry, 326 women Vote counting, 318 Women’s su¤rage, 480n.1, 484 Vote pooling, 150, 154, 154t. Working class, 62, 71–75, 169 Voter apathy, 38 World Values Surveys, assessment of data from, Voting. See Elections; Legislatures 171n.5, 178–179 Voting paradox. See Cyclical majorities World War II, democratization wave following, 93 Voting preferences. See Preferences and preference Wright, Quincy, 145 profiles Voting Rights Act. U.S., 147 Yugoslavia, 94 Voting systems. See District magnitude; Electoral formulas Zaire, 529

Waldron, Jeremy, 221 Wales, 354 Warfare, 109, 440n.10