Antifragility Feb 20

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Antifragility Feb 20 49 formalizable, theoretizable, codifiable, Sovietizable, bureaucratizable, Chapter 7. A Second Lesson in Harvardifiable, provable, etc. Epistemology from Fat Tony: The Soviet- To make things simple, just look at the second type of knowledge as something so stripped of ambiguity that an autistic Harvard Illusion, or How to Out-Argue person (a high functioning autistic person, that is) can easily Socrates understand it. So could a computer. The error of rationalism is, simply, overestimating the role and necessity of the second type, the academic knowledge, in human Birds rarely write more than ornithologists – Piety for the affairs --and degrading the uncodifiable, more complex, intuitive or impious –Fat Tony does not drink milk – Why not Harvardify? experience-based type. It is a severe error because not only a large –Can Socrates out-argue FT ? -- Mystagogue philosophaster share of our knowledge is not explainable, academizable, rationalizable, formalizable, theoretizable, codifiable, Sovietizable, bureaucratizable, Harvardifiable, etc., but, further, that the role such explainable knowledge plays in life is so minor that it is not even I said earlier that, because of complexity, life and the world are funny. not command-and-control style, but that we tended somehow to think so on the occasion, the wrong occasion. Hence, of course, we We are very likely to believe that skills and ideas that we actually fragilize and stifle antifragilities. Let us call it the error of acquired by doing, or that came naturally to us (as we already knew rationalism. I will outline it in this chapter and the next one will by our innate biological instinct) came from books, ideas, and show its application to the history of medicine. reasoning. We get blinded by it; there may even be something in our brains that makes us suckers for the point. Let us see how. It is not the error of being rational, but the error of thinking that things always have a reason that is accessible to us —that we can Clearly we never think that it is thanks to ornithologists that comprehend easily. In Fat Tony’s language, that would be what birds learn to fly –and if some people do hold such belief, it would be makes us the suckers of all suckers. It is this rationalism that move hard for them to convince the birds. But, let’s anthropomorphize a us away from optionality --which makes us denigrate options and bit: when replace “birds” with “men”, then the idea that people learn trial-and-error because we think we can figure it out by ourselves. to do things thanks to what they learned during pompous lectures becomes plausible. When it comes to human agency, matters Consider two types of knowledge. The first type is not exactly suddenly become confusing to us. “knowledge”; its ambiguous character prevents us from associating it with the strict definitions of knowledge. It a way of doing thing that We tend to believe that it is largely thanks to the beautiful rules we cannot really express in clear language, but that we do of grammar that we can speak, that it is thanks to science that we nevertheless, and do well. The second type is more like what we call have all this technology, thanks to universities that societies can “knowledge”; it is what you acquire in school, can get grades for, can function, thanks to political scientists and political philosophers that codify, what can be explainable, academizable, rationalizable, we have a well-functioning political system, and thanks to 2/22/11 © Copyright 2011 by N. N. Taleb. This draft version cannot be disseminated or quoted. 50 economists that we have an economy. Of course we need to add that was incapable of weaving into a theory. But Sherlock Holmes is not the belief that it is thanks to government planning and nation states all theories-with-no-feedback: he does some grind work in collected that the world is functioning. data, smelling grounds like a dog, and noticing numerous details that In other words, the denigration of practice. This is a dangerous would escape another person, leading to feedback in searching for human disease, a severe sucker problem, to be inclined to think that other details, before building his reasoning. The greater hero is his practice has a debt to theories; that practice is inferior to theories, patently smarter brother Mycroft who was Sherlock's last resource and that theories are necessarily good and better than no-theoriesxv - when the latter hit the wall. Mycroft never left his London -even after the Soviet experiences, even after the literal bankruptcy of gentleman's club; he could solve matters in his head without needs the economic establishment, even after the severe failures of the for the trimmings of the messy reality outside his club. brand of massively destructive thinkers called the neo-conservatives, But we got so many dangerous hubris along with this ability to even after the failure of risk theories in finance that caused the discover by reasoning off other theories, very destructive hubris. So unfettered risk taking, even after fifteen centuries of fiascos in allow my skepticism about the contribution of theories, which I will medicine (I will show in Chapter x how the history of medicine as we show throughout this book by looking carefully at the record. know it today has been blatantly re-narrated in a way to overestimate Consider the bias about the way information gets to us: there are the value of reasoning at the detriment of tinkering leading to many more books on birds written by ornithologists than books by random discoveries. Academia --like governments--will always tell birds written on birds; and certainly even fewer books on you what it did for you, never what it did not do). ornithologists written by birds. Fat Tonys do not write books. It may be right on the occasion; there are numerous (valuable) University professors, particularly in the disciplines with “science” things that came to us thanks to reasoning in the relative or possibly attached to their designation, will over-represent their share of total absence of practical and empirical feedback. The most extreme contribution to knowledge –in their minds what is not explainable, case of a discovery without any feedback is Einstein's discovery of academizable, rationalizable, formalizable, theoretizable, codifiable, relativity using pure reasoning about the structure of time, Sovietizable, bureaucratizable, Harvardifiable, knowledge is not supposedly thanks to a dream. One spectacular case of a discovery knowledge. Books are typically written by those who write books, not with a small number of existing external data is that of the so much by those who do things. So, first, nonFattonys who write astronomer Le Verrier discovery of the existence of the planet books leave you with their side of the story (since they have the Neptune on the basis of solitary computation, using the behavior of books), and, second, as I showed with the metaphor of the birds, we the surrounding planets. When it was actually sited he refused to are naturally suckers for the role of ideas; we have this built-in look at it, so comfortable he was with his result. We are all infatuated tendency to overestimate the role thinking and formal learning play with stories of Sherlock Holmes in which, after collecting what facts in life. he needed, facts he shares with his sidekick and roommate Doctor Watson, he sits in his chamber torturing the violin and formulates a conclusion that surprises the reader, and highly impresses Watson, as it is entirely derived from all the facts that he already knows but 2/22/11 © Copyright 2011 by N. N. Taleb. This draft version cannot be disseminated or quoted. The Error of Rationalism 51 THE ERROR OF RATIONALISM far more than design, meaning that the ideal activity of stochastic tinkering can largely dispense with the theoreticians as they can be This chapter is about this denigration of practice and the error more of a hindrance than anything --much like regulators increase of rationalism of both the overestimation the importance of what we risks and a Wharton School class in introductory, intermediate, or call reason in human affairs, and the normative feeling that we need (especially) advanced economics will stand in your way of to be able to articulate the motives and theories behind what we do understanding the economy. and, worse, things we understand (but have not done) are more Finally, the practical: we will discuss our Fat Tony lessons on important than things we do but do not appear to understand how where the traps and suckers are and how to maneuver. they work. If I consider it the largest error ever made by man, it is For now, let us for now see how we got into this mess by going not without some backing: it is the mother problem behind such to Athens, 4th Century before our era. matters as: overconfidence, expert problems, expert errors, Soviet experiences, medical mistakes, dogmatism, and much, much more. EUTHYPHRO And we have to do things in life without being the suckers. The error has the following manifestations. The first systematic appearance of abstract knowledge, the very First, the philosophical: the difference between the two varieties notion of idea, started with Plato, particularly with his Forms of knowledge is what philosophy is about. Do we need to understand corresponding to the most ideational, abstract definitions, and with things? What do we mean by beliefs? the observable as its mere manifestation. Before Plato, even notions Second, the psychological: the mistake of reversing the arrow of that later became abstract, like God, were extremely the formation of knowledge, the illusion of thinking, is part of the anthropomorphic and embedded in some tangible character, larger mental biases that make us underestimate randomness, embodied in legends and mythical narratives.
Recommended publications
  • Title on the Rejection of Reason by the Early Empiricist Author(S
    Title On the Rejection of Reason by the Early Empiricist Author(s) Nishimura, Seishu Citation 京都大学文学部哲学研究室紀要 (2005), 8: 160-170 Issue Date 2005-12-10 URL http://hdl.handle.net/2433/24239 Right Type Departmental Bulletin Paper Textversion publisher Kyoto University On the Rejection of Reason by the Early Empiricist Seishu Nishimura In his “On the Sects for Beginners,” Galen describes a debate between two primary sects of medicine in antiquity: the empiricist and the rationalist. According to Galen, “medicine is the science of what is healthy and what is unhealthy,” by virtue of which the doctor can prescribe the remedy (SB, 1).1 In this sense, medical knowledge is essentially practical. But the empiricist and the rationalist disagree over the origin of such knowledge. The former claims that “experience alone” is sufficient in order to obtain it (ibid). We will call this the empiricist claim. Roughly speaking, by “experience,” the empiricist means perception and memory. There are three types of experience by which we can acquire medical knowledge: (i) “autopsia,” i.e., one’s own perception, (ii) “history,” i.e., one’s knowledge of the experiences of others, and (iii) “the transition to the similar” (SB, 3).2 Here, (ii) and (iii) supplement (i) because firsthand experience is a limited capacity. The core of the empiricist claim is that, given the experience gained in these ways, we don’t need any other things for medical knowledge. For the empiricist, X is medical knowledge if X is obtained from and confirmed by experience. On the contrary, the rationalist insists that, in addition to experience, the use of “reason” is necessary for medical knowledge (SB, 1).
    [Show full text]
  • The Sceptics: the Arguments of the Philosophers
    THE SCEPTICS The Arguments of the Philosophers EDITOR: TED HONDERICH The purpose of this series is to provide a contemporary assessment and history of the entire course of philosophical thought. Each book constitutes a detailed, critical introduction to the work of a philosopher of major influence and significance. Plato J.C.B.Gosling Augustine Christopher Kirwan The Presocratic Philosophers Jonathan Barnes Plotinus Lloyd P.Gerson The Sceptics R.J.Hankinson Socrates Gerasimos Xenophon Santas Berkeley George Pitcher Descartes Margaret Dauler Wilson Hobbes Tom Sorell Locke Michael Ayers Spinoza R.J.Delahunty Bentham Ross Harrison Hume Barry Stroud Butler Terence Penelhum John Stuart Mill John Skorupski Thomas Reid Keith Lehrer Kant Ralph C.S.Walker Hegel M.J.Inwood Schopenhauer D.W.Hamlyn Kierkegaard Alastair Hannay Nietzsche Richard Schacht Karl Marx Allen W.Wood Gottlob Frege Hans D.Sluga Meinong Reinhardt Grossmann Husserl David Bell G.E.Moore Thomas Baldwin Wittgenstein Robert J.Fogelin Russell Mark Sainsbury William James Graham Bird Peirce Christopher Hookway Santayana Timothy L.S.Sprigge Dewey J.E.Tiles Bergson A.R.Lacey J.L.Austin G.J.Warnock Karl Popper Anthony O’Hear Ayer John Foster Sartre Peter Caws THE SCEPTICS The Arguments of the Philosophers R.J.Hankinson London and New York For Myles Burnyeat First published 1995 by Routledge First published in paperback 1998 Simultaneously published in the USA and Canada by Routledge 29 West 35th Street, New York, NY 10001 Routledge is an imprint of the Taylor & Francis Group This edition published in the Taylor & Francis e-Library, 2005. “To purchase your own copy of this or any of Taylor & Francis or Routledge’s collection of thousands of eBooks please go to www.eBookstore.tandf.co.uk.” © 1995 R.J.Hankinson All rights reserved.
    [Show full text]
  • Philosophy) 15 2.1 References
    Necessity and sufficiency From Wikipedia, the free encyclopedia Contents 1 Abductive reasoning 1 1.1 History ................................................. 1 1.2 Deduction, induction, and abduction ................................. 1 1.3 Formalizations of abduction ...................................... 2 1.3.1 Logic-based abduction .................................... 2 1.3.2 Set-cover abduction ...................................... 2 1.3.3 Abductive validation ..................................... 3 1.3.4 Probabilistic abduction .................................... 3 1.3.5 Subjective logic abduction .................................. 4 1.4 History ................................................. 4 1.4.1 1867 ............................................. 6 1.4.2 1878 ............................................. 6 1.4.3 1883 ............................................. 6 1.4.4 1902 and after ......................................... 6 1.4.5 Pragmatism .......................................... 7 1.4.6 Three levels of logic about abduction ............................. 7 1.4.7 Other writers ......................................... 8 1.5 Applications .............................................. 8 1.6 See also ................................................ 9 1.7 References ............................................... 10 1.8 Notes ................................................. 11 1.9 External links ............................................. 14 2 Condition (philosophy) 15 2.1 References ..............................................
    [Show full text]
  • Cause and Explanation in Ancient Greek Thought Hankinson, R
    Cause and Explanation in Ancient Greek Thought Hankinson, R. J, University of Texas, Austin Abstract: In this book, R. J. Hankinson traces the history of investigation into the nature of cause and explanation, from the beginnings of Ancient Greek philosophy in 600 bc, through the Graeco-Roman world, to the end of pagan antiquity in c.500 ad The book consists of chapter-length studies of the Presocratics, Plato, Aristotle (two chapters), Atomism, Stoicism, Scepticism, and Neoplatonism, as well as the Sophistic movement, and Ancient Medicine. Hankinson is principally concerned with the following questions: ‘What did the Greeks understand by a cause?’, and ‘How did the Greeks conceive adequacy in explanation?’. The Ancient Greeks (excepting the Sceptics) are united in their belief that the world and at least some of its process can be rendered intelligible, and that this can be rendered by an inquiry into the nature of things, with reasoned argument as the appropriate method of exhibiting the real structure of the world. Thus, the Greek thinkers set the standards for science, because they are guided by logic and observation in their analysis of causation; but one can also recognize the growth of interest among the Greeks in the nature of explanation itself. The question that becomes central to the development of Greek philosophical science is whether nature can be understood in terms of teleology, or solely in terms of mechanical laws. Hankinson is interested in how the concepts of cause and explanation function in a properly scientific context; but he extends his investigation of these concepts to questions of freedom and responsibility, and fate and astrology, and also the treatment of disease.
    [Show full text]
  • Epistemological Perspectives in Late
    EPISTEMOLOGICAL PERSPECTIVES IN LATE ANTIQUITY – A DIALOG BETWEEN RATIONALISM AND EMPIRICISM IN THE SCIENTIFIC WRITINGS1 Adrian MURARU ABSTRACT: Given the particular character of Ancient Literature, I considered it useful to approach the issue from the perspective of the Philosophy of Science: Epistemology and the Philosophy of Science stem from the same source, and this aspect is all the more patent for Antiquity. In fact, the two perspectives that I mentioned in the subtitle, Empiricism and Rationalism, both represent epistemological choices and approaches specific to the Sciences, as well as to the Philosophy of Science, in the manner that they were practiced in Antiquity. This present study argues that Empiricism noticeably distinguishes itself from Rationalism, not merely in the philosophical works of the above-mentioned period, but also in its non-philosophical literature, especially the one pertaining to Science. Consequently, this study aims to indicate the major lines of thought in the Ancient Philosophy of Science, which reflect themselves in Epistemology in an unmediated manner. KEYWORDS: Late Antiquity’s epistemology, philosophy of science, Galen, rationalists, empiricists 1. Sources As one might rightly presume, the primary sources for this research consist of documents composed at that time, and successfully preserved onto this very day. They pertain to various disciplines, from Religion to Science, from Theology to sheer Literature. In my previous papers on the subject,2 I have tried to at least partially indicate how the epistemological endeavors of Late Antiquity were structured, and I mainly focused on the science of the period. Nevertheless, as 1 This paper was elaborated within the POSDRU/89/1.5/S/56815 project Knowledge – Based Society – research, debates, perspectives, co-financed by the European Union and the Romanian Government from the Social European Fund, through the Operational Sector Program for the Development of Human Resources 2007-2013.
    [Show full text]
  • Medical History from the Earliest Times
    June 25, 1892. THE HOSPITAL 195 Medical History from the Earliest Times. By E. T. Withington, M.A., M.B. Oxon. " xiy. heraclides and the empiric Cosmetics," and On Diet in Health" (Symposium), SCHOOL. are attributed to Heraclides, both, of which are said to been the first Some readers may have found the name Heraclides, have of their kind. From the former " mentioned among typical Greek physicians in a preced- Galen has extracted two recipes for making the hair ing article, rather strange to them, but in Heraclides of stick together," the first consisting of wax, pitch, glue, Tarentum, Heraclides the Empiric (B.C. 230), we may, and gum-mastich, equal parts, to be warmed before I think, find an almost forgotten hero of medicine, using. Did the ancient Greeks wax their moustaches ? some of whose claims to remembrance shall here he For incipient baldness, Heraclides recommends a briefly repeated. His works have perished?our relics pomade of anemones rubbed up in oil, which he says ?of ancient literature are by no means survivals of all will also darken the hair. Among the scanty extracts the fittest?and what we know of him is gathered from which survive from the Symposium, we may notice the " scattered notices in later writers. Galen calls him a assertion that sheep's trotters, snails, and other if most excellent physician," giving him the high praise glutinous substances cause indigestion taken in well to eat a little before that he never preferred his party to the truth, and excess, and that it is always wrote com- Soranus considered him the only Empiric worth re- drinking.
    [Show full text]
  • Aristotle's Empiricist Theory of Doxastic Knowledge
    Aristotle’s Empiricist Theory of Doxastic Knowledge Hendrik Lorenz and Benjamin Morison Introduction As is well known, Aristotle divides the human power of reason into two distinct powers: one of them is responsible for grasping things whose principles are necessary, the other is responsible for grasping contingent things. He refers to the latter power as the part of reason that is responsible for reasoning or calculating (logistikon, 1139a12) and also as that which is responsible for opinion (doxastikon, 1140b26 and 1144b14). Practical wisdom (phronêsis) and arts or crafts such as medicine are virtues of the doxastikon. In this paper, we suggest that these virtues are best thought of as forms of knowledge. They are acquired states of cognition that equip their bearers reliably to form true opinions about matters in their respective domains. (We are not claiming that they are exhausted by such states of cognition.) We argue that Aristotle’s conception of the forms of knowledge for which the doxastikon is responsible (in short, his conception of doxastic knowledge) is distinctive, and that it can usefully be thought of as Empiricist in a sense of the term familiar to students of ancient medicine. For our purposes, two features of Empiricist epistemology stand out: the ancient Empiricists held that knowledge does not rest on grasping logical relations that hold among relevant propositions; and that knowledge does not rest on grasping unobservable natures or essences of things. While grasping both logical relations and intelligible essences of things is absolutely central to Aristotle’s epistemology of theoretical understanding, neither of these cognitive accomplishments, we argue, is part of acquiring, having, or exercising doxastic knowledge.
    [Show full text]
  • Copyright by Joseph Benjamin Bullock 2015
    Copyright by Joseph Benjamin Bullock 2015 The Dissertation Committee for Joseph Benjamin Bullock certifies that this is the approved version of the following dissertation: Skeptical Science The Pyrrhonian critique of technai in Against the Professors (M I-VI) Committee: ____________________________________ Robert J. Hankinson, Supervisor ____________________________________ Stephen A. White, Co-Supervisor ____________________________________ Richard Bett ____________________________________ Matthew L. Evans ____________________________________ Robert C. Koons ____________________________________ Paul B. Woodruff Skeptical Science The Pyrrhonian critique of technai in Against the Professors (M I-VI) by Joseph Benjamin Bullock, B.S.; M. Theological Stds.; M.A. Dissertation Presented to the Faculty of the Graduate School of the University of Texas at Austin in Partial Fulfillment of the Requirements for the Degree of Doctor of Philosophy The University of Texas at Austin May 2015 Acknowledgements Jim Hankinson is, in a sense, one of the archai of this dissertation because I began working on the concept of technē in Against the Professors (M I-VI) after he suggested that I write about Sextus' least appreciated treatise. It is difficult to express everything that I owe to Jim. He has been my mentor throughout my time at UT, and he has been the greatest influence on my thinking about ancient skepticism and science. I thank him for always being available to talk through my ideas, or to read and discuss some ancient text. I owe similar thanks to Steve White. I literally could not have finished the dissertation without Steve's help, and I am deeply grateful to him for stepping in at the eleventh hour to become co-supervisor.
    [Show full text]
  • General Philosophy of Science and Its Significance
    Having Science in View: General Philosophy of Science and its Significance Stathis Psillos University of Athens & University of Western Ontario Quid tandem harmonia? Similitudo in varietate, seu diversitas identitate compensate. ‘The Confession of a Philosopher’, G W Leibniz 1672-73 1. Preamble General philosophy of science (GPoS) is the part of conceptual space where philosophy and science meet and interact. More specifically, it is the space in which the scientific image of the world is synthesised and in which the general and abstract structure of science becomes the object of theoretical investigation. Yet, there is some scepticism in the profession concerning the prospects of GPoS. In a seminal piece, Philip Kitcher (2013) noted that the task of GPoS, as conceived by Carl Hempel and many who followed him, was to offer explications of major meta- scientific concepts such as confirmation, theory, explanation, simplicity etc. These explications were supposed “to provide general accounts of them by specifying the necessary conditions for their application across the entire range of possible cases” (2013, 187). Yet, Kitcher notes, “Sixty years on, it should be clear that the program has failed. We have no general accounts of confirmation, theory, explanation, law, reduction, or causation that will apply across the diversity of scientific fields or across different periods of time” (2013, 188). The chief reasons for this alleged failure are two. The first relates to the diversity of scientific practice: the methods employed by the various fields of natural science are very diverse and field-specific. As Kitcher notes “Perhaps there is a ‘thin’ general conception that picks out what is common to the diversity of fields, but that turns out to be too attenuated to be of any great use”.
    [Show full text]
  • Logic A-Z from Wikipedia, the Free Encyclopedia Chapter 1
    Logic A-Z From Wikipedia, the free encyclopedia Chapter 1 Antepredicament Antepredicaments, in logic, are certain previous matters requisite to a more easy and clear apprehension of the doctrine of predicaments or categories. Such are definitions of common terms, as equivocals, univocals, etc., with divisions of things, their differences, etc. They are thus called because Aristotle treated them before the predicaments, hoping that the thread of discourse might not afterwards be interrupted. 1.1 References • This article incorporates text from a publication now in the public domain: Chambers, Ephraim, ed. (1728). "*article name needed". Cyclopædia, or an Universal Dictionary of Arts and Sciences (first ed.). James and John Knapton, et al. 2 Chapter 2 Apophasis Not to be confused with Apophysis (disambiguation), Apoptosis, or Apophis (disambiguation). Apophasis is a rhetorical device wherein the speaker or writer brings up a subject by either denying it, or denying that it should be brought up.*[1] Accordingly, it can be seen as a rhetorical relative of irony. Also called paralipsis (παράλειψις) – also spelled paraleipsis or paralepsis –, or occupatio,*[2]*[3]*[4]*[5] and known also as prae- teritio, preterition, antiphrasis (ἀντίφρασις), or parasiopesis (παρασιώπησις), apophasis is usually employed to make a subversive ad hominem attack, which makes it a frequently used tactic in political speeches to make an attack on one's opponent. Using apophasis in this way is often considered to be bad form. The device is typically used to distance
    [Show full text]
  • Philosophie Antique, 12 | 2012, « Autour De La Perception » [En Ligne], Mis En Ligne Le 01 Novembre 2018, Consulté Le 24 Octobre 2020
    Philosophie antique Problèmes, Renaissances, Usages 12 | 2012 Autour de la perception Édition électronique URL : http://journals.openedition.org/philosant/928 DOI : 10.4000/philosant.928 ISSN : 2648-2789 Éditeur Éditions Vrin Édition imprimée Date de publication : 1 novembre 2012 ISBN : 978-2-7574-0400-3 ISSN : 1634-4561 Référence électronique Philosophie antique, 12 | 2012, « Autour de la perception » [En ligne], mis en ligne le 01 novembre 2018, consulté le 24 octobre 2020. URL : http://journals.openedition.org/philosant/928 ; DOI : https://doi.org/ 10.4000/philosant.928 Ce document a été généré automatiquement le 24 octobre 2020. La revue Philosophie antique est mise à disposition selon les termes de la Licence Creative Commons Attribution - Pas d'Utilisation Commerciale - Pas de Modification 4.0 International. 1 Par quelles capacités ou quels mécanismes appréhendons-nous les objets qui nous entourent et généralement le monde ? À cette question, la première qui se pose à qui s'interroge sur la connaissance humaine, n’ont pas manqué de s’intéresser les anciens. À l’heure des sciences cognitives, la question semble échapper à la philosophie, fût-elle phénoménologique, et relever de la psychologie, de la neurologie, voire de la physique ou de la géométrie puisqu’elle fait intervenir les lois de l’optique. L’intérêt de ce numéro est donc, non seulement de nous informer sur les théories de la perception qui avaient cours et entre lesquelles se partageaient les anciens, mais de montrer que, dès l’antiquité, la philosophie était loin d’avoir le monopole de l’analyse de la perception. En réalité, sur ce terrain comme sur d’autres, la philosophie s’est trouvée dès l’origine en concurrence avec d’autres approches et d’autres méthodes, en l’occurrence avec la médecine.
    [Show full text]
  • SKEPTICISM Also Available from Bloomsbury
    SKEPTICISM Also available from Bloomsbury The Bloomsbury Companion to Analytic Philosophy, edited by Barry Dainton and Howard Robinson The Bloomsbury Companion to Epistemology, edited by Andrew Cullison A Critical Introduction to Skepticism, Allan Hazlett SKEPTICISM FROM ANTIQUITY TO THE PRESENT Edited by Diego E. Machuca and Baron Reed Bloomsbury Academic An imprint of Bloomsbury Publishing Plc LONDON • OXFORD • NEW YORK • NEW DELHI • SYDNEY Bloomsbury Academic An imprint of Bloomsbury Publishing Plc 50 Bedford Square 1385 Broadway London New York WC1B 3DP NY 10018 UK USA www.bloomsbury.com BLOOMSBURY and the Diana logo are trademarks of Bloomsbury Publishing Plc First published 2018 © Diego Machuca and Baron Reed, 2018 Diego Machuca and Baron Reed have asserted their right under the Copyright, Designs and Patents Act, 1988, to be identified as the Editors of this work. All rights reserved. No part of this publication may be reproduced or transmitted in any form or by any means, electronic or mechanical, including photocopying, recording, or any information storage or retrieval system, without prior permission in writing from the publishers. No responsibility for loss caused to any individual or organization acting on or refraining from action as a result of the material in this publication can be accepted by Bloomsbury or the editors. British Library Cataloguing-in-Publication Data A catalogue record for this book is available from the British Library. ISBN: HB: 978-1-4725-0771-6 ePDF: 978-1-4725-1436-3 ePub: 978-1-4725-1149-2 Library of Congress Cataloging-in-Publication Data Names: Machuca, Diego E., editor. Title: Skepticism: from antiquity to the present / [edited by] Diego Machuca and Baron Reed.
    [Show full text]