Medical History from the Earliest Times

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Medical History from the Earliest Times June 25, 1892. THE HOSPITAL 195 Medical History from the Earliest Times. By E. T. Withington, M.A., M.B. Oxon. " xiy. heraclides and the empiric Cosmetics," and On Diet in Health" (Symposium), SCHOOL. are attributed to Heraclides, both, of which are said to been the first Some readers may have found the name Heraclides, have of their kind. From the former " mentioned among typical Greek physicians in a preced- Galen has extracted two recipes for making the hair ing article, rather strange to them, but in Heraclides of stick together," the first consisting of wax, pitch, glue, Tarentum, Heraclides the Empiric (B.C. 230), we may, and gum-mastich, equal parts, to be warmed before I think, find an almost forgotten hero of medicine, using. Did the ancient Greeks wax their moustaches ? some of whose claims to remembrance shall here he For incipient baldness, Heraclides recommends a briefly repeated. His works have perished?our relics pomade of anemones rubbed up in oil, which he says ?of ancient literature are by no means survivals of all will also darken the hair. Among the scanty extracts the fittest?and what we know of him is gathered from which survive from the Symposium, we may notice the " scattered notices in later writers. Galen calls him a assertion that sheep's trotters, snails, and other if most excellent physician," giving him the high praise glutinous substances cause indigestion taken in well to eat a little before that he never preferred his party to the truth, and excess, and that it is always wrote com- Soranus considered him the only Empiric worth re- drinking. Finally, this prolific author in con- futing ; had he not been in his grave for three cen- mentaries on several Hippocratic works, where, turies, he might have given the great Methodist some- trast to other Empirics, he showed due respect to the he has received thing more to do. But Heraclides was not fond of memory of the mighty Asclepiad, and controversy, and his lukewarmness in that respect led as an appropriate reward the honourable mention of him to be accused of relapsing into dogmatism. He his successors of every school. was the ?did not, like Serapion, seek notoriety by abusing his To pass to the sect of which Heraclides a and ?colleagues, or by introducing some new and start- greatest ornament; Empiricism is now by-word ling remedy which should excel the virtues of a reproach in medicine, but the system originally so tortoise blood or crocodile dung, but devoted him- called owed its origin mainly to the teaching of one self to the humbler task of weeding the already whose name on the great roll of the Asclepiadaj pre- ?over-luxuriant garden of Empiric medicines. This he cedes even that of Hippocrates, the most scientific of " ?did in his greatest work On the Preparation and the Greeks, the grandest intellect, perhaps, of the Proving of Drugs," which he declared, in the best human race. Aristotle, son of the Asclepiad Nicoma- spirit of Empiricism, contained nothing but what he chus, probably studied medicine in early youth, and had himself observed, and which formed a rich mine may even have practised it; his anatomical discoveries for all future writers on materia medica. In this are worthy to be compared with those of Herophilus treatise Heraclides seems to have first pointed out the and Erasistratus, and his teaching, which brought great value of opium, and to have defined the indica- down the philosophy of Plato from heaven to earth, it at least more suited tions for its use. That drug, indeed, was, as we have from the ideal to the real, made seen, probably nsed from the earliest times, and though for that art which deals with human bodies. As the only once mentioned in the Hippocratic writings, was result, partly of this teaching, partly of the sceptic ?employed by Diodes (b.c. 350) as a remedy for tooth- philosophy taught about the same time by Pyrrho, ache, and is noticed by his contemporary Diagoras, who and partly of the natural reaction against the extrava- at asserts that it acts injuriously on the special senses, gant theorising of the Dogmatists, there arose of medi- and is, therefore, to be avoided in affections of the eye Alexandria, about 280 B.C., the Empiric school two and ear. Heraclides, however, disregards this, and re- cine, of which the more direct founders were pupils commends poultices containing the drug in painful of Herophilus, Philinus and Serapion. Of these the and the latter ophthalmia. We have also prescriptions of his con- former argued with the Dogmatists, even himself. taining opium for cases of sleeplessness, spasm, cough, abused them, not sparing Hippocrates "" been a sort of Greek cholera," and colic, and one with a large dose of the Indeed, Serapion seems to have notorious German, is said to drug for patients bitten by venomous serpents. His Paracelsus, and, like the " an mineral into treatment of brain fever," or phrenitis, of which he have introduced important remedy used in distinguished a cerebral and gastric form, was much medicine, and to have first sulphur chronic a praised, and consisted of a darkened room, cold to the skin diseases. The Empirics, though branch of the head, bleeding, and enemata ; while in opposition to Alexandrine School, despised anatomy. They even its the dominant school, he declared that in acute wrote treatises to prove worthlessness, and we may fevers fluids are not to be withheld from the well fancy Serapion exclaiming, in the language of " is the use thirsty sufferer. He was scarcely less distinguished as Paracelsus, What of knowing the shape a surgeon, asserted the possibility of reducing disloca- and position of the brain and liver, or whether there as brains " tions of the hip, and invented a machine for that pur- are such things and livers at all ? No less pose ; indeed it seems highly probable that it was did they reject the Dogmatic physiology and patho- who first and one of their " Heraclides conceived the idea of utilising the logy, favourite mottoes was, It is the but mechanical inventions of his contemporary and neigh- not cause, the cure of diseases that concerns bour, Archimedes, in surgery. He also invented a us; not how we digest, but what is digestible." In method for separating the eyelid from the ball, when short, they reduced the whole art and science of medi- which was cine to a of adherent after injury, practised for many system therapeutics. A person is ill, that " centuries. Two works of more general interest, On is, he has certain unpleasant feelings or symptoms; 196 THE HOSPITAL. June 25, 1892. " surely the first thing to do is to find something which Empirics, says Galen, were terrible men for names," will remove them, and the whole duty of the physician and in this they were encouraged by Aristotle, who was is to discover what particular treatment, and espe- not only the father of natural science, but had other cially what drugs, will get rid of particular sets offspring, one of whom sprang from his marvellous of symptoms. This he may do in three ways: brain a full-grown Pallas Athene. This was Logic, (1) By his own observations and experiments? and its definitions and syllogisms were seized upon, autopsy; (2) by learning from his contemporaries and with delight by the physicians of the day, who soon predecessors?history; (3) in the case ofinew and strange showed that as much mental energy could be wasted in diseases, by drawing conclusions from those most word-splitting, definitions of the pulse, &c., as in the similar to them?analogy. Thus was established the vaguer speculations of Dogmatism. famous "tripod" of the Empirics, but being found The Empirics existed as a separate school for some rather shaky on its three legs, a fourth was afterwards centuries, and we shall find one of them among the " added, epilogism," or the process of inferring pre- teachers of Galen ; but they finally separated into two ceding events from the present symptoms. Thus, by distinct branches, one philosophical, and culminating, epilogism, the consistent Empiric might conclude from in the sceptic agnosticism of Sextus Empiricus"; while the extreme inflammation of a wound that it was the other, or practical branch, gradually degenerated poisoned, and treat it accordingly without falling into into Empiricism in its modern sense, and found its the Dogmatic heresy of looking for hidden causes. chief exponent in Marcellus the Empiric, in whose Empiricism practically resolved itself into a search for writings human credulity in matters medical seems to> specifics, and its immediate result was the introduction have achieved its utmost. Curiously enough, these two of a great number of drugs, some of very extraordinary are almost the only members of the sect of whose works, nature, such as hare's heart, camel's brain, the flesh of we possess more than fragments, and they may be con- weasles, and of human beings, and the two examples sidered in greater detail later on. given above; but doubtless there was ample evidence, Meanwhile, let us remember that the Empiric school both from "autopsy" and "history," of patients was useful in its generation in checking the extrava- of and in and recovering after taking any of them. gances Dogmatism, extending defining the use of such remedies as and and, It has been said that the sin of men of opium sulphur, besetting above all, that it produced one great physician i3 to have finished off worthy science fancy they all things to stand with the noblest round the Hippocratic throne,.
Recommended publications
  • Title on the Rejection of Reason by the Early Empiricist Author(S
    Title On the Rejection of Reason by the Early Empiricist Author(s) Nishimura, Seishu Citation 京都大学文学部哲学研究室紀要 (2005), 8: 160-170 Issue Date 2005-12-10 URL http://hdl.handle.net/2433/24239 Right Type Departmental Bulletin Paper Textversion publisher Kyoto University On the Rejection of Reason by the Early Empiricist Seishu Nishimura In his “On the Sects for Beginners,” Galen describes a debate between two primary sects of medicine in antiquity: the empiricist and the rationalist. According to Galen, “medicine is the science of what is healthy and what is unhealthy,” by virtue of which the doctor can prescribe the remedy (SB, 1).1 In this sense, medical knowledge is essentially practical. But the empiricist and the rationalist disagree over the origin of such knowledge. The former claims that “experience alone” is sufficient in order to obtain it (ibid). We will call this the empiricist claim. Roughly speaking, by “experience,” the empiricist means perception and memory. There are three types of experience by which we can acquire medical knowledge: (i) “autopsia,” i.e., one’s own perception, (ii) “history,” i.e., one’s knowledge of the experiences of others, and (iii) “the transition to the similar” (SB, 3).2 Here, (ii) and (iii) supplement (i) because firsthand experience is a limited capacity. The core of the empiricist claim is that, given the experience gained in these ways, we don’t need any other things for medical knowledge. For the empiricist, X is medical knowledge if X is obtained from and confirmed by experience. On the contrary, the rationalist insists that, in addition to experience, the use of “reason” is necessary for medical knowledge (SB, 1).
    [Show full text]
  • The Sceptics: the Arguments of the Philosophers
    THE SCEPTICS The Arguments of the Philosophers EDITOR: TED HONDERICH The purpose of this series is to provide a contemporary assessment and history of the entire course of philosophical thought. Each book constitutes a detailed, critical introduction to the work of a philosopher of major influence and significance. Plato J.C.B.Gosling Augustine Christopher Kirwan The Presocratic Philosophers Jonathan Barnes Plotinus Lloyd P.Gerson The Sceptics R.J.Hankinson Socrates Gerasimos Xenophon Santas Berkeley George Pitcher Descartes Margaret Dauler Wilson Hobbes Tom Sorell Locke Michael Ayers Spinoza R.J.Delahunty Bentham Ross Harrison Hume Barry Stroud Butler Terence Penelhum John Stuart Mill John Skorupski Thomas Reid Keith Lehrer Kant Ralph C.S.Walker Hegel M.J.Inwood Schopenhauer D.W.Hamlyn Kierkegaard Alastair Hannay Nietzsche Richard Schacht Karl Marx Allen W.Wood Gottlob Frege Hans D.Sluga Meinong Reinhardt Grossmann Husserl David Bell G.E.Moore Thomas Baldwin Wittgenstein Robert J.Fogelin Russell Mark Sainsbury William James Graham Bird Peirce Christopher Hookway Santayana Timothy L.S.Sprigge Dewey J.E.Tiles Bergson A.R.Lacey J.L.Austin G.J.Warnock Karl Popper Anthony O’Hear Ayer John Foster Sartre Peter Caws THE SCEPTICS The Arguments of the Philosophers R.J.Hankinson London and New York For Myles Burnyeat First published 1995 by Routledge First published in paperback 1998 Simultaneously published in the USA and Canada by Routledge 29 West 35th Street, New York, NY 10001 Routledge is an imprint of the Taylor & Francis Group This edition published in the Taylor & Francis e-Library, 2005. “To purchase your own copy of this or any of Taylor & Francis or Routledge’s collection of thousands of eBooks please go to www.eBookstore.tandf.co.uk.” © 1995 R.J.Hankinson All rights reserved.
    [Show full text]
  • Philosophy) 15 2.1 References
    Necessity and sufficiency From Wikipedia, the free encyclopedia Contents 1 Abductive reasoning 1 1.1 History ................................................. 1 1.2 Deduction, induction, and abduction ................................. 1 1.3 Formalizations of abduction ...................................... 2 1.3.1 Logic-based abduction .................................... 2 1.3.2 Set-cover abduction ...................................... 2 1.3.3 Abductive validation ..................................... 3 1.3.4 Probabilistic abduction .................................... 3 1.3.5 Subjective logic abduction .................................. 4 1.4 History ................................................. 4 1.4.1 1867 ............................................. 6 1.4.2 1878 ............................................. 6 1.4.3 1883 ............................................. 6 1.4.4 1902 and after ......................................... 6 1.4.5 Pragmatism .......................................... 7 1.4.6 Three levels of logic about abduction ............................. 7 1.4.7 Other writers ......................................... 8 1.5 Applications .............................................. 8 1.6 See also ................................................ 9 1.7 References ............................................... 10 1.8 Notes ................................................. 11 1.9 External links ............................................. 14 2 Condition (philosophy) 15 2.1 References ..............................................
    [Show full text]
  • Cause and Explanation in Ancient Greek Thought Hankinson, R
    Cause and Explanation in Ancient Greek Thought Hankinson, R. J, University of Texas, Austin Abstract: In this book, R. J. Hankinson traces the history of investigation into the nature of cause and explanation, from the beginnings of Ancient Greek philosophy in 600 bc, through the Graeco-Roman world, to the end of pagan antiquity in c.500 ad The book consists of chapter-length studies of the Presocratics, Plato, Aristotle (two chapters), Atomism, Stoicism, Scepticism, and Neoplatonism, as well as the Sophistic movement, and Ancient Medicine. Hankinson is principally concerned with the following questions: ‘What did the Greeks understand by a cause?’, and ‘How did the Greeks conceive adequacy in explanation?’. The Ancient Greeks (excepting the Sceptics) are united in their belief that the world and at least some of its process can be rendered intelligible, and that this can be rendered by an inquiry into the nature of things, with reasoned argument as the appropriate method of exhibiting the real structure of the world. Thus, the Greek thinkers set the standards for science, because they are guided by logic and observation in their analysis of causation; but one can also recognize the growth of interest among the Greeks in the nature of explanation itself. The question that becomes central to the development of Greek philosophical science is whether nature can be understood in terms of teleology, or solely in terms of mechanical laws. Hankinson is interested in how the concepts of cause and explanation function in a properly scientific context; but he extends his investigation of these concepts to questions of freedom and responsibility, and fate and astrology, and also the treatment of disease.
    [Show full text]
  • Epistemological Perspectives in Late
    EPISTEMOLOGICAL PERSPECTIVES IN LATE ANTIQUITY – A DIALOG BETWEEN RATIONALISM AND EMPIRICISM IN THE SCIENTIFIC WRITINGS1 Adrian MURARU ABSTRACT: Given the particular character of Ancient Literature, I considered it useful to approach the issue from the perspective of the Philosophy of Science: Epistemology and the Philosophy of Science stem from the same source, and this aspect is all the more patent for Antiquity. In fact, the two perspectives that I mentioned in the subtitle, Empiricism and Rationalism, both represent epistemological choices and approaches specific to the Sciences, as well as to the Philosophy of Science, in the manner that they were practiced in Antiquity. This present study argues that Empiricism noticeably distinguishes itself from Rationalism, not merely in the philosophical works of the above-mentioned period, but also in its non-philosophical literature, especially the one pertaining to Science. Consequently, this study aims to indicate the major lines of thought in the Ancient Philosophy of Science, which reflect themselves in Epistemology in an unmediated manner. KEYWORDS: Late Antiquity’s epistemology, philosophy of science, Galen, rationalists, empiricists 1. Sources As one might rightly presume, the primary sources for this research consist of documents composed at that time, and successfully preserved onto this very day. They pertain to various disciplines, from Religion to Science, from Theology to sheer Literature. In my previous papers on the subject,2 I have tried to at least partially indicate how the epistemological endeavors of Late Antiquity were structured, and I mainly focused on the science of the period. Nevertheless, as 1 This paper was elaborated within the POSDRU/89/1.5/S/56815 project Knowledge – Based Society – research, debates, perspectives, co-financed by the European Union and the Romanian Government from the Social European Fund, through the Operational Sector Program for the Development of Human Resources 2007-2013.
    [Show full text]
  • Aristotle's Empiricist Theory of Doxastic Knowledge
    Aristotle’s Empiricist Theory of Doxastic Knowledge Hendrik Lorenz and Benjamin Morison Introduction As is well known, Aristotle divides the human power of reason into two distinct powers: one of them is responsible for grasping things whose principles are necessary, the other is responsible for grasping contingent things. He refers to the latter power as the part of reason that is responsible for reasoning or calculating (logistikon, 1139a12) and also as that which is responsible for opinion (doxastikon, 1140b26 and 1144b14). Practical wisdom (phronêsis) and arts or crafts such as medicine are virtues of the doxastikon. In this paper, we suggest that these virtues are best thought of as forms of knowledge. They are acquired states of cognition that equip their bearers reliably to form true opinions about matters in their respective domains. (We are not claiming that they are exhausted by such states of cognition.) We argue that Aristotle’s conception of the forms of knowledge for which the doxastikon is responsible (in short, his conception of doxastic knowledge) is distinctive, and that it can usefully be thought of as Empiricist in a sense of the term familiar to students of ancient medicine. For our purposes, two features of Empiricist epistemology stand out: the ancient Empiricists held that knowledge does not rest on grasping logical relations that hold among relevant propositions; and that knowledge does not rest on grasping unobservable natures or essences of things. While grasping both logical relations and intelligible essences of things is absolutely central to Aristotle’s epistemology of theoretical understanding, neither of these cognitive accomplishments, we argue, is part of acquiring, having, or exercising doxastic knowledge.
    [Show full text]
  • Copyright by Joseph Benjamin Bullock 2015
    Copyright by Joseph Benjamin Bullock 2015 The Dissertation Committee for Joseph Benjamin Bullock certifies that this is the approved version of the following dissertation: Skeptical Science The Pyrrhonian critique of technai in Against the Professors (M I-VI) Committee: ____________________________________ Robert J. Hankinson, Supervisor ____________________________________ Stephen A. White, Co-Supervisor ____________________________________ Richard Bett ____________________________________ Matthew L. Evans ____________________________________ Robert C. Koons ____________________________________ Paul B. Woodruff Skeptical Science The Pyrrhonian critique of technai in Against the Professors (M I-VI) by Joseph Benjamin Bullock, B.S.; M. Theological Stds.; M.A. Dissertation Presented to the Faculty of the Graduate School of the University of Texas at Austin in Partial Fulfillment of the Requirements for the Degree of Doctor of Philosophy The University of Texas at Austin May 2015 Acknowledgements Jim Hankinson is, in a sense, one of the archai of this dissertation because I began working on the concept of technē in Against the Professors (M I-VI) after he suggested that I write about Sextus' least appreciated treatise. It is difficult to express everything that I owe to Jim. He has been my mentor throughout my time at UT, and he has been the greatest influence on my thinking about ancient skepticism and science. I thank him for always being available to talk through my ideas, or to read and discuss some ancient text. I owe similar thanks to Steve White. I literally could not have finished the dissertation without Steve's help, and I am deeply grateful to him for stepping in at the eleventh hour to become co-supervisor.
    [Show full text]
  • General Philosophy of Science and Its Significance
    Having Science in View: General Philosophy of Science and its Significance Stathis Psillos University of Athens & University of Western Ontario Quid tandem harmonia? Similitudo in varietate, seu diversitas identitate compensate. ‘The Confession of a Philosopher’, G W Leibniz 1672-73 1. Preamble General philosophy of science (GPoS) is the part of conceptual space where philosophy and science meet and interact. More specifically, it is the space in which the scientific image of the world is synthesised and in which the general and abstract structure of science becomes the object of theoretical investigation. Yet, there is some scepticism in the profession concerning the prospects of GPoS. In a seminal piece, Philip Kitcher (2013) noted that the task of GPoS, as conceived by Carl Hempel and many who followed him, was to offer explications of major meta- scientific concepts such as confirmation, theory, explanation, simplicity etc. These explications were supposed “to provide general accounts of them by specifying the necessary conditions for their application across the entire range of possible cases” (2013, 187). Yet, Kitcher notes, “Sixty years on, it should be clear that the program has failed. We have no general accounts of confirmation, theory, explanation, law, reduction, or causation that will apply across the diversity of scientific fields or across different periods of time” (2013, 188). The chief reasons for this alleged failure are two. The first relates to the diversity of scientific practice: the methods employed by the various fields of natural science are very diverse and field-specific. As Kitcher notes “Perhaps there is a ‘thin’ general conception that picks out what is common to the diversity of fields, but that turns out to be too attenuated to be of any great use”.
    [Show full text]
  • Antifragility Feb 20
    49 formalizable, theoretizable, codifiable, Sovietizable, bureaucratizable, Chapter 7. A Second Lesson in Harvardifiable, provable, etc. Epistemology from Fat Tony: The Soviet- To make things simple, just look at the second type of knowledge as something so stripped of ambiguity that an autistic Harvard Illusion, or How to Out-Argue person (a high functioning autistic person, that is) can easily Socrates understand it. So could a computer. The error of rationalism is, simply, overestimating the role and necessity of the second type, the academic knowledge, in human Birds rarely write more than ornithologists – Piety for the affairs --and degrading the uncodifiable, more complex, intuitive or impious –Fat Tony does not drink milk – Why not Harvardify? experience-based type. It is a severe error because not only a large –Can Socrates out-argue FT ? -- Mystagogue philosophaster share of our knowledge is not explainable, academizable, rationalizable, formalizable, theoretizable, codifiable, Sovietizable, bureaucratizable, Harvardifiable, etc., but, further, that the role such explainable knowledge plays in life is so minor that it is not even I said earlier that, because of complexity, life and the world are funny. not command-and-control style, but that we tended somehow to think so on the occasion, the wrong occasion. Hence, of course, we We are very likely to believe that skills and ideas that we actually fragilize and stifle antifragilities. Let us call it the error of acquired by doing, or that came naturally to us (as we already knew rationalism. I will outline it in this chapter and the next one will by our innate biological instinct) came from books, ideas, and show its application to the history of medicine.
    [Show full text]
  • Logic A-Z from Wikipedia, the Free Encyclopedia Chapter 1
    Logic A-Z From Wikipedia, the free encyclopedia Chapter 1 Antepredicament Antepredicaments, in logic, are certain previous matters requisite to a more easy and clear apprehension of the doctrine of predicaments or categories. Such are definitions of common terms, as equivocals, univocals, etc., with divisions of things, their differences, etc. They are thus called because Aristotle treated them before the predicaments, hoping that the thread of discourse might not afterwards be interrupted. 1.1 References • This article incorporates text from a publication now in the public domain: Chambers, Ephraim, ed. (1728). "*article name needed". Cyclopædia, or an Universal Dictionary of Arts and Sciences (first ed.). James and John Knapton, et al. 2 Chapter 2 Apophasis Not to be confused with Apophysis (disambiguation), Apoptosis, or Apophis (disambiguation). Apophasis is a rhetorical device wherein the speaker or writer brings up a subject by either denying it, or denying that it should be brought up.*[1] Accordingly, it can be seen as a rhetorical relative of irony. Also called paralipsis (παράλειψις) – also spelled paraleipsis or paralepsis –, or occupatio,*[2]*[3]*[4]*[5] and known also as prae- teritio, preterition, antiphrasis (ἀντίφρασις), or parasiopesis (παρασιώπησις), apophasis is usually employed to make a subversive ad hominem attack, which makes it a frequently used tactic in political speeches to make an attack on one's opponent. Using apophasis in this way is often considered to be bad form. The device is typically used to distance
    [Show full text]
  • Philosophie Antique, 12 | 2012, « Autour De La Perception » [En Ligne], Mis En Ligne Le 01 Novembre 2018, Consulté Le 24 Octobre 2020
    Philosophie antique Problèmes, Renaissances, Usages 12 | 2012 Autour de la perception Édition électronique URL : http://journals.openedition.org/philosant/928 DOI : 10.4000/philosant.928 ISSN : 2648-2789 Éditeur Éditions Vrin Édition imprimée Date de publication : 1 novembre 2012 ISBN : 978-2-7574-0400-3 ISSN : 1634-4561 Référence électronique Philosophie antique, 12 | 2012, « Autour de la perception » [En ligne], mis en ligne le 01 novembre 2018, consulté le 24 octobre 2020. URL : http://journals.openedition.org/philosant/928 ; DOI : https://doi.org/ 10.4000/philosant.928 Ce document a été généré automatiquement le 24 octobre 2020. La revue Philosophie antique est mise à disposition selon les termes de la Licence Creative Commons Attribution - Pas d'Utilisation Commerciale - Pas de Modification 4.0 International. 1 Par quelles capacités ou quels mécanismes appréhendons-nous les objets qui nous entourent et généralement le monde ? À cette question, la première qui se pose à qui s'interroge sur la connaissance humaine, n’ont pas manqué de s’intéresser les anciens. À l’heure des sciences cognitives, la question semble échapper à la philosophie, fût-elle phénoménologique, et relever de la psychologie, de la neurologie, voire de la physique ou de la géométrie puisqu’elle fait intervenir les lois de l’optique. L’intérêt de ce numéro est donc, non seulement de nous informer sur les théories de la perception qui avaient cours et entre lesquelles se partageaient les anciens, mais de montrer que, dès l’antiquité, la philosophie était loin d’avoir le monopole de l’analyse de la perception. En réalité, sur ce terrain comme sur d’autres, la philosophie s’est trouvée dès l’origine en concurrence avec d’autres approches et d’autres méthodes, en l’occurrence avec la médecine.
    [Show full text]
  • SKEPTICISM Also Available from Bloomsbury
    SKEPTICISM Also available from Bloomsbury The Bloomsbury Companion to Analytic Philosophy, edited by Barry Dainton and Howard Robinson The Bloomsbury Companion to Epistemology, edited by Andrew Cullison A Critical Introduction to Skepticism, Allan Hazlett SKEPTICISM FROM ANTIQUITY TO THE PRESENT Edited by Diego E. Machuca and Baron Reed Bloomsbury Academic An imprint of Bloomsbury Publishing Plc LONDON • OXFORD • NEW YORK • NEW DELHI • SYDNEY Bloomsbury Academic An imprint of Bloomsbury Publishing Plc 50 Bedford Square 1385 Broadway London New York WC1B 3DP NY 10018 UK USA www.bloomsbury.com BLOOMSBURY and the Diana logo are trademarks of Bloomsbury Publishing Plc First published 2018 © Diego Machuca and Baron Reed, 2018 Diego Machuca and Baron Reed have asserted their right under the Copyright, Designs and Patents Act, 1988, to be identified as the Editors of this work. All rights reserved. No part of this publication may be reproduced or transmitted in any form or by any means, electronic or mechanical, including photocopying, recording, or any information storage or retrieval system, without prior permission in writing from the publishers. No responsibility for loss caused to any individual or organization acting on or refraining from action as a result of the material in this publication can be accepted by Bloomsbury or the editors. British Library Cataloguing-in-Publication Data A catalogue record for this book is available from the British Library. ISBN: HB: 978-1-4725-0771-6 ePDF: 978-1-4725-1436-3 ePub: 978-1-4725-1149-2 Library of Congress Cataloging-in-Publication Data Names: Machuca, Diego E., editor. Title: Skepticism: from antiquity to the present / [edited by] Diego Machuca and Baron Reed.
    [Show full text]