Philosophie Antique, 12 | 2012, « Autour De La Perception » [En Ligne], Mis En Ligne Le 01 Novembre 2018, Consulté Le 24 Octobre 2020

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Philosophie Antique, 12 | 2012, « Autour De La Perception » [En Ligne], Mis En Ligne Le 01 Novembre 2018, Consulté Le 24 Octobre 2020 Philosophie antique Problèmes, Renaissances, Usages 12 | 2012 Autour de la perception Édition électronique URL : http://journals.openedition.org/philosant/928 DOI : 10.4000/philosant.928 ISSN : 2648-2789 Éditeur Éditions Vrin Édition imprimée Date de publication : 1 novembre 2012 ISBN : 978-2-7574-0400-3 ISSN : 1634-4561 Référence électronique Philosophie antique, 12 | 2012, « Autour de la perception » [En ligne], mis en ligne le 01 novembre 2018, consulté le 24 octobre 2020. URL : http://journals.openedition.org/philosant/928 ; DOI : https://doi.org/ 10.4000/philosant.928 Ce document a été généré automatiquement le 24 octobre 2020. La revue Philosophie antique est mise à disposition selon les termes de la Licence Creative Commons Attribution - Pas d'Utilisation Commerciale - Pas de Modification 4.0 International. 1 Par quelles capacités ou quels mécanismes appréhendons-nous les objets qui nous entourent et généralement le monde ? À cette question, la première qui se pose à qui s'interroge sur la connaissance humaine, n’ont pas manqué de s’intéresser les anciens. À l’heure des sciences cognitives, la question semble échapper à la philosophie, fût-elle phénoménologique, et relever de la psychologie, de la neurologie, voire de la physique ou de la géométrie puisqu’elle fait intervenir les lois de l’optique. L’intérêt de ce numéro est donc, non seulement de nous informer sur les théories de la perception qui avaient cours et entre lesquelles se partageaient les anciens, mais de montrer que, dès l’antiquité, la philosophie était loin d’avoir le monopole de l’analyse de la perception. En réalité, sur ce terrain comme sur d’autres, la philosophie s’est trouvée dès l’origine en concurrence avec d’autres approches et d’autres méthodes, en l’occurrence avec la médecine. Cette situation perdurera tout au long de l’antiquité, comme c’est encore le cas aujourd’hui, et l’on verra que jusque chez un auteur comme Héron d’Alexandrie, volontiers tenu, parce que méconnu, pour étranger à toute philosophie, la question de la vitesse de la lumière mobilise un concept de causalité qui engage en réalité toute une cosmologie et fait de la physique une philosophie autant que l’inverse. Philosophie antique, 12 | 2012 2 SOMMAIRE L’économie des sensations dans la clinique hippocratique Laurent Ayache Les polémiques sur la perception entre stoïciens et académiciens Jean-Baptiste Gourinat L’absence de préconception du temps chez Épicure Lecture de la Lettre à Hérodote, 72‑73 Marianne Gœury La théorie de la vision chez Galien : la colonne qui saute et autres énigmes Heinrich Von Staden Modernité de la catoptrique de Héron d’Alexandrie Alain Boutot Varia Is there an answer to Socrates’ puzzle? Individuality, universality, and the self in Plato’s Phaedrus Voula Tsouna Les trois amours platoniciens ou la philosophie à hauteur d’homme Anca Vasiliu Sextus Empiricus et l’ombre longue d’Aristote Emidio Spinelli Comptes rendus Jaume PÓRTULAS & Sergi GRAU, Saviesa grega arcaica Livio Rossetti Enrique HÜLSZ PICCONE, Nuevos ensayos sobre Heráclito : Actas del Segundo Symposium Heracliteum Guido Calenda Gabriel DANZIG, Apologizing for Socrates. How Plato and Xenophon created our Socrates Louis-André Dorion Livio ROSSETTI, Le dialogue socratique Agnese Gaile‑Irbe Suzanne HUSSON, La République de Diogène. Une cité en quête de la nature Louis-André Dorion Emmanuel BERMON, Valéry LAURAND, Jean TERREL (éd.), Politique d’Aristote : famille, régimes, éducation Refik Güremen Mary‑Anne ZAGDOUN, L’Esthétique d’Aristote Anne‑Lise Worms Philosophie antique, 12 | 2012 3 Marie‑Odile GOULET CAZÉ (éd.), Études sur la théorie stoïcienne de l’action Christelle Veillard Mauro BONAZZI, Carlos LÉVY, Carlos STEEL (éd.), A Platonic Pythagoras: Platonism and Pythagoreanism in the Imperial Age Constantin Macris Archives internationales d’histoire des sciences, 1-2 : Pline l’Ancien à la Renaissance Pierre Caye Bulletin Bibliographique Philosophie antique, 12 | 2012 4 L’économie des sensations dans la clinique hippocratique Laurent Ayache 1 Aucun texte de la Collection hippocratique, pas même le court traité De la vision, ne présente, pour elle-même, une théorie physiologique de la sensation. Les passages qui concernent sensation ou perception sont insérés dans des développements qui relèvent de trois registres : un registre anatomique, notamment à l’occasion de la description des vaisseaux qui passent par les organes sensoriels ; un registre pathologique, les troubles de la sensation (surdité, cécité, nyctalopie, etc.) apparaissant souvent comme des accidents au cours des maladies ; enfin, un registre méthodologique, la sensation du malade et les perceptions du médecin étant présentées comme des guides pour le jugement médical dans le pronostic et la conduite de la thérapeutique. 2 Cette étude se concentrera sur la question particulière de l’usage des perceptions dans l’activité clinique du médecin, c’est‑à‑dire sur le registre méthodologique. Je chercherai à dégager les modalités du recours aux sensations dans l’élaboration du jugement médical. Ce faisant, j’userai indifféremment des termes « sensation » et « perception », en les comprenant dans toute l’étendue du sens que les textes hippocratiques imposent, sans m’enfermer dans une définition préalable de l’αἴσθησις. Mon étude se concentrera sur quelques traités qui possèdent une certaine homogénéité, essentiellement, les traités chirurgicaux et le Pronostic. 3 Le recours à la sensation lors de l’examen clinique apparaît sous deux formes différentes : tantôt le médecin s’informe des sensations du malade, tantôt il recourt à ses propres perceptions. Il convient donc d’étudier ces deux usages. Le recours à la sensation du patient 4 Les traités chirurgicaux font régulièrement référence à la sensation du blessé pour régler l’activité thérapeutique du médecin. Ainsi, le traité Des fractures expose la technique du bandage d’un membre cassé. L’interrogation du patient sur ce qu’il ressent sert en premier lieu à ajuster le bandage à sa conformation individuelle : Philosophie antique, 12 | 2012 5 Voici les signes d’un beau traitement et d’un bandage correct (ὀρθῶς) : si vous demandez au blessé s’il est comprimé, et s’il dit qu’il est comprimé, mais modérément (ἡσύχως), et s’il dit : « surtout à l’endroit de la fracture (μάλιστα […] κατὰ τὸ κάτηγμα) » (c. 5 : Kühlewein, II, 53 = III, 432 L.)1. 5 Par la suite, la force de la compression est adaptée, lors de chaque nouveau pansement, à l’évolution de la blessure. Le médecin est alors attentif à l’expression précise de l’évolution des sensations du blessé : Interrogé, le blessé répondra qu’il est serré un peu plus qu’auparavant (ὀλίγῳ μᾶλλον […] ἢ τὸ πρότερον), surtout sur la fracture (μάλιστα […] κατὰ τὸ κάτηγμα), et sur le reste proportionnellement (κατὰ λόγον) (ibid. : Kühlewein II, 54-56 = III, 436 L.). 6 L’interrogation du blessé et l’écoute attentive de ses réponses sert également à corriger l’application du bandage pour approcher la compression optimale : Voici les signes de la juste mesure (σημεῖα δὲ τάδε τῆς μετριότητος) : si le jour du pansement et la nuit suivante il se sent serré, non pas moins, mais davantage (μὴ ἐπὶ ἧσσον πεπιέχθαι, ἀλλ᾽ ἐπὶ μᾶλλον), et si le lendemain il survient à la main un peu de tuméfaction molle ; tel est le signe d’une juste mesure de la compression (μετριότητος γὰρ σημεῖον τῆς πιέξιος). Vers la fin du second jour il doit se sentir moins serré (ἐπὶ ἧσσον), et le troisième vous devez trouver l’appareil relâché. Si quelqu’un des caractères ici énumérés est en défaut, il faut savoir que le bandage est plus lâche que la mesure (χαλαρωτέρη ἐστὶν ἡ ἐπίδεσις τοῦ μετρίου) ; si quelqu’un de ces caractères est en excès, il faut savoir qu’il a été serré au-delà de la mesure (μᾶλλον […] τοῦ μετρίου), prenant ces points comme des indications (τούτοισι σημαινόμενος) pour, dans la réapplication du bandage, davantage lâcher ou serrer (ibid. : Kühlewein II, 53 = III, 432 L.). 7 L’évolution de la sensation du patient concourt ainsi à conduire le médecin vers le point exact de la juste mesure (τὸ μέτριον, ἡ μετριότης) de la thérapeutique. Le jugement du médecin épouse l’évolution de la sensation du blessé et ajuste l’action en conséquence. Il n’applique pas uniformément une règle universelle, mais se conforme à une méthode de rectification régulièrement renouvelée dont le guide principal est la sensation du patient. 8 Le recours à la sensibilité du patient dépasse parfois ce rôle d’adaptation des principes conceptuels à la diversité des cas et de leur évolution. Au début de ce même traité Des fractures, l’auteur opère une véritable substitution d’une idée par la sensation du patient. Dans ce passage, l’idée produite par la théorie sert seulement de lieu commun, amorçant une démarche dont l’aboutissement est purement sensible. 9 Ce traité s’ouvre en effet sur la question de l’attitude dans laquelle il faut immobiliser un bras luxé ou fracturé. La réponse théorique est qu’il faut placer le bras dans sa conformation naturelle, κατὰ φύσιν. La théorie apporte même une détermination de cette conformation : l’attitude naturelle comprend l’idée de rectitude (ἰθυωρίη) : Le médecin doit, pour les luxations et les fractures, faire, autant qu’il est possible, les extensions dans l’attitude la plus rectiligne : c’est la conformation la plus juste (ἐχρῆν τὸν ἰητρὸν τῶν ἐκπτωσίων τε καὶ κατηγμάτων ὡς ἰθύτατα ποιεῖσθαι τὰς κατατάσιας· αὕτη γὰρ ἡ δικαιωτάτη φύσις). (c. 1 : Kühlewein II, 46 = III, 412 L.). 10 Et pourtant, la recherche de cette position naturelle par le raisonnement est condamnée
Recommended publications
  • Title on the Rejection of Reason by the Early Empiricist Author(S
    Title On the Rejection of Reason by the Early Empiricist Author(s) Nishimura, Seishu Citation 京都大学文学部哲学研究室紀要 (2005), 8: 160-170 Issue Date 2005-12-10 URL http://hdl.handle.net/2433/24239 Right Type Departmental Bulletin Paper Textversion publisher Kyoto University On the Rejection of Reason by the Early Empiricist Seishu Nishimura In his “On the Sects for Beginners,” Galen describes a debate between two primary sects of medicine in antiquity: the empiricist and the rationalist. According to Galen, “medicine is the science of what is healthy and what is unhealthy,” by virtue of which the doctor can prescribe the remedy (SB, 1).1 In this sense, medical knowledge is essentially practical. But the empiricist and the rationalist disagree over the origin of such knowledge. The former claims that “experience alone” is sufficient in order to obtain it (ibid). We will call this the empiricist claim. Roughly speaking, by “experience,” the empiricist means perception and memory. There are three types of experience by which we can acquire medical knowledge: (i) “autopsia,” i.e., one’s own perception, (ii) “history,” i.e., one’s knowledge of the experiences of others, and (iii) “the transition to the similar” (SB, 3).2 Here, (ii) and (iii) supplement (i) because firsthand experience is a limited capacity. The core of the empiricist claim is that, given the experience gained in these ways, we don’t need any other things for medical knowledge. For the empiricist, X is medical knowledge if X is obtained from and confirmed by experience. On the contrary, the rationalist insists that, in addition to experience, the use of “reason” is necessary for medical knowledge (SB, 1).
    [Show full text]
  • The Sceptics: the Arguments of the Philosophers
    THE SCEPTICS The Arguments of the Philosophers EDITOR: TED HONDERICH The purpose of this series is to provide a contemporary assessment and history of the entire course of philosophical thought. Each book constitutes a detailed, critical introduction to the work of a philosopher of major influence and significance. Plato J.C.B.Gosling Augustine Christopher Kirwan The Presocratic Philosophers Jonathan Barnes Plotinus Lloyd P.Gerson The Sceptics R.J.Hankinson Socrates Gerasimos Xenophon Santas Berkeley George Pitcher Descartes Margaret Dauler Wilson Hobbes Tom Sorell Locke Michael Ayers Spinoza R.J.Delahunty Bentham Ross Harrison Hume Barry Stroud Butler Terence Penelhum John Stuart Mill John Skorupski Thomas Reid Keith Lehrer Kant Ralph C.S.Walker Hegel M.J.Inwood Schopenhauer D.W.Hamlyn Kierkegaard Alastair Hannay Nietzsche Richard Schacht Karl Marx Allen W.Wood Gottlob Frege Hans D.Sluga Meinong Reinhardt Grossmann Husserl David Bell G.E.Moore Thomas Baldwin Wittgenstein Robert J.Fogelin Russell Mark Sainsbury William James Graham Bird Peirce Christopher Hookway Santayana Timothy L.S.Sprigge Dewey J.E.Tiles Bergson A.R.Lacey J.L.Austin G.J.Warnock Karl Popper Anthony O’Hear Ayer John Foster Sartre Peter Caws THE SCEPTICS The Arguments of the Philosophers R.J.Hankinson London and New York For Myles Burnyeat First published 1995 by Routledge First published in paperback 1998 Simultaneously published in the USA and Canada by Routledge 29 West 35th Street, New York, NY 10001 Routledge is an imprint of the Taylor & Francis Group This edition published in the Taylor & Francis e-Library, 2005. “To purchase your own copy of this or any of Taylor & Francis or Routledge’s collection of thousands of eBooks please go to www.eBookstore.tandf.co.uk.” © 1995 R.J.Hankinson All rights reserved.
    [Show full text]
  • Philosophy) 15 2.1 References
    Necessity and sufficiency From Wikipedia, the free encyclopedia Contents 1 Abductive reasoning 1 1.1 History ................................................. 1 1.2 Deduction, induction, and abduction ................................. 1 1.3 Formalizations of abduction ...................................... 2 1.3.1 Logic-based abduction .................................... 2 1.3.2 Set-cover abduction ...................................... 2 1.3.3 Abductive validation ..................................... 3 1.3.4 Probabilistic abduction .................................... 3 1.3.5 Subjective logic abduction .................................. 4 1.4 History ................................................. 4 1.4.1 1867 ............................................. 6 1.4.2 1878 ............................................. 6 1.4.3 1883 ............................................. 6 1.4.4 1902 and after ......................................... 6 1.4.5 Pragmatism .......................................... 7 1.4.6 Three levels of logic about abduction ............................. 7 1.4.7 Other writers ......................................... 8 1.5 Applications .............................................. 8 1.6 See also ................................................ 9 1.7 References ............................................... 10 1.8 Notes ................................................. 11 1.9 External links ............................................. 14 2 Condition (philosophy) 15 2.1 References ..............................................
    [Show full text]
  • Cause and Explanation in Ancient Greek Thought Hankinson, R
    Cause and Explanation in Ancient Greek Thought Hankinson, R. J, University of Texas, Austin Abstract: In this book, R. J. Hankinson traces the history of investigation into the nature of cause and explanation, from the beginnings of Ancient Greek philosophy in 600 bc, through the Graeco-Roman world, to the end of pagan antiquity in c.500 ad The book consists of chapter-length studies of the Presocratics, Plato, Aristotle (two chapters), Atomism, Stoicism, Scepticism, and Neoplatonism, as well as the Sophistic movement, and Ancient Medicine. Hankinson is principally concerned with the following questions: ‘What did the Greeks understand by a cause?’, and ‘How did the Greeks conceive adequacy in explanation?’. The Ancient Greeks (excepting the Sceptics) are united in their belief that the world and at least some of its process can be rendered intelligible, and that this can be rendered by an inquiry into the nature of things, with reasoned argument as the appropriate method of exhibiting the real structure of the world. Thus, the Greek thinkers set the standards for science, because they are guided by logic and observation in their analysis of causation; but one can also recognize the growth of interest among the Greeks in the nature of explanation itself. The question that becomes central to the development of Greek philosophical science is whether nature can be understood in terms of teleology, or solely in terms of mechanical laws. Hankinson is interested in how the concepts of cause and explanation function in a properly scientific context; but he extends his investigation of these concepts to questions of freedom and responsibility, and fate and astrology, and also the treatment of disease.
    [Show full text]
  • Epistemological Perspectives in Late
    EPISTEMOLOGICAL PERSPECTIVES IN LATE ANTIQUITY – A DIALOG BETWEEN RATIONALISM AND EMPIRICISM IN THE SCIENTIFIC WRITINGS1 Adrian MURARU ABSTRACT: Given the particular character of Ancient Literature, I considered it useful to approach the issue from the perspective of the Philosophy of Science: Epistemology and the Philosophy of Science stem from the same source, and this aspect is all the more patent for Antiquity. In fact, the two perspectives that I mentioned in the subtitle, Empiricism and Rationalism, both represent epistemological choices and approaches specific to the Sciences, as well as to the Philosophy of Science, in the manner that they were practiced in Antiquity. This present study argues that Empiricism noticeably distinguishes itself from Rationalism, not merely in the philosophical works of the above-mentioned period, but also in its non-philosophical literature, especially the one pertaining to Science. Consequently, this study aims to indicate the major lines of thought in the Ancient Philosophy of Science, which reflect themselves in Epistemology in an unmediated manner. KEYWORDS: Late Antiquity’s epistemology, philosophy of science, Galen, rationalists, empiricists 1. Sources As one might rightly presume, the primary sources for this research consist of documents composed at that time, and successfully preserved onto this very day. They pertain to various disciplines, from Religion to Science, from Theology to sheer Literature. In my previous papers on the subject,2 I have tried to at least partially indicate how the epistemological endeavors of Late Antiquity were structured, and I mainly focused on the science of the period. Nevertheless, as 1 This paper was elaborated within the POSDRU/89/1.5/S/56815 project Knowledge – Based Society – research, debates, perspectives, co-financed by the European Union and the Romanian Government from the Social European Fund, through the Operational Sector Program for the Development of Human Resources 2007-2013.
    [Show full text]
  • Medical History from the Earliest Times
    June 25, 1892. THE HOSPITAL 195 Medical History from the Earliest Times. By E. T. Withington, M.A., M.B. Oxon. " xiy. heraclides and the empiric Cosmetics," and On Diet in Health" (Symposium), SCHOOL. are attributed to Heraclides, both, of which are said to been the first Some readers may have found the name Heraclides, have of their kind. From the former " mentioned among typical Greek physicians in a preced- Galen has extracted two recipes for making the hair ing article, rather strange to them, but in Heraclides of stick together," the first consisting of wax, pitch, glue, Tarentum, Heraclides the Empiric (B.C. 230), we may, and gum-mastich, equal parts, to be warmed before I think, find an almost forgotten hero of medicine, using. Did the ancient Greeks wax their moustaches ? some of whose claims to remembrance shall here he For incipient baldness, Heraclides recommends a briefly repeated. His works have perished?our relics pomade of anemones rubbed up in oil, which he says ?of ancient literature are by no means survivals of all will also darken the hair. Among the scanty extracts the fittest?and what we know of him is gathered from which survive from the Symposium, we may notice the " scattered notices in later writers. Galen calls him a assertion that sheep's trotters, snails, and other if most excellent physician," giving him the high praise glutinous substances cause indigestion taken in well to eat a little before that he never preferred his party to the truth, and excess, and that it is always wrote com- Soranus considered him the only Empiric worth re- drinking.
    [Show full text]
  • Aristotle's Empiricist Theory of Doxastic Knowledge
    Aristotle’s Empiricist Theory of Doxastic Knowledge Hendrik Lorenz and Benjamin Morison Introduction As is well known, Aristotle divides the human power of reason into two distinct powers: one of them is responsible for grasping things whose principles are necessary, the other is responsible for grasping contingent things. He refers to the latter power as the part of reason that is responsible for reasoning or calculating (logistikon, 1139a12) and also as that which is responsible for opinion (doxastikon, 1140b26 and 1144b14). Practical wisdom (phronêsis) and arts or crafts such as medicine are virtues of the doxastikon. In this paper, we suggest that these virtues are best thought of as forms of knowledge. They are acquired states of cognition that equip their bearers reliably to form true opinions about matters in their respective domains. (We are not claiming that they are exhausted by such states of cognition.) We argue that Aristotle’s conception of the forms of knowledge for which the doxastikon is responsible (in short, his conception of doxastic knowledge) is distinctive, and that it can usefully be thought of as Empiricist in a sense of the term familiar to students of ancient medicine. For our purposes, two features of Empiricist epistemology stand out: the ancient Empiricists held that knowledge does not rest on grasping logical relations that hold among relevant propositions; and that knowledge does not rest on grasping unobservable natures or essences of things. While grasping both logical relations and intelligible essences of things is absolutely central to Aristotle’s epistemology of theoretical understanding, neither of these cognitive accomplishments, we argue, is part of acquiring, having, or exercising doxastic knowledge.
    [Show full text]
  • Copyright by Joseph Benjamin Bullock 2015
    Copyright by Joseph Benjamin Bullock 2015 The Dissertation Committee for Joseph Benjamin Bullock certifies that this is the approved version of the following dissertation: Skeptical Science The Pyrrhonian critique of technai in Against the Professors (M I-VI) Committee: ____________________________________ Robert J. Hankinson, Supervisor ____________________________________ Stephen A. White, Co-Supervisor ____________________________________ Richard Bett ____________________________________ Matthew L. Evans ____________________________________ Robert C. Koons ____________________________________ Paul B. Woodruff Skeptical Science The Pyrrhonian critique of technai in Against the Professors (M I-VI) by Joseph Benjamin Bullock, B.S.; M. Theological Stds.; M.A. Dissertation Presented to the Faculty of the Graduate School of the University of Texas at Austin in Partial Fulfillment of the Requirements for the Degree of Doctor of Philosophy The University of Texas at Austin May 2015 Acknowledgements Jim Hankinson is, in a sense, one of the archai of this dissertation because I began working on the concept of technē in Against the Professors (M I-VI) after he suggested that I write about Sextus' least appreciated treatise. It is difficult to express everything that I owe to Jim. He has been my mentor throughout my time at UT, and he has been the greatest influence on my thinking about ancient skepticism and science. I thank him for always being available to talk through my ideas, or to read and discuss some ancient text. I owe similar thanks to Steve White. I literally could not have finished the dissertation without Steve's help, and I am deeply grateful to him for stepping in at the eleventh hour to become co-supervisor.
    [Show full text]
  • General Philosophy of Science and Its Significance
    Having Science in View: General Philosophy of Science and its Significance Stathis Psillos University of Athens & University of Western Ontario Quid tandem harmonia? Similitudo in varietate, seu diversitas identitate compensate. ‘The Confession of a Philosopher’, G W Leibniz 1672-73 1. Preamble General philosophy of science (GPoS) is the part of conceptual space where philosophy and science meet and interact. More specifically, it is the space in which the scientific image of the world is synthesised and in which the general and abstract structure of science becomes the object of theoretical investigation. Yet, there is some scepticism in the profession concerning the prospects of GPoS. In a seminal piece, Philip Kitcher (2013) noted that the task of GPoS, as conceived by Carl Hempel and many who followed him, was to offer explications of major meta- scientific concepts such as confirmation, theory, explanation, simplicity etc. These explications were supposed “to provide general accounts of them by specifying the necessary conditions for their application across the entire range of possible cases” (2013, 187). Yet, Kitcher notes, “Sixty years on, it should be clear that the program has failed. We have no general accounts of confirmation, theory, explanation, law, reduction, or causation that will apply across the diversity of scientific fields or across different periods of time” (2013, 188). The chief reasons for this alleged failure are two. The first relates to the diversity of scientific practice: the methods employed by the various fields of natural science are very diverse and field-specific. As Kitcher notes “Perhaps there is a ‘thin’ general conception that picks out what is common to the diversity of fields, but that turns out to be too attenuated to be of any great use”.
    [Show full text]
  • Antifragility Feb 20
    49 formalizable, theoretizable, codifiable, Sovietizable, bureaucratizable, Chapter 7. A Second Lesson in Harvardifiable, provable, etc. Epistemology from Fat Tony: The Soviet- To make things simple, just look at the second type of knowledge as something so stripped of ambiguity that an autistic Harvard Illusion, or How to Out-Argue person (a high functioning autistic person, that is) can easily Socrates understand it. So could a computer. The error of rationalism is, simply, overestimating the role and necessity of the second type, the academic knowledge, in human Birds rarely write more than ornithologists – Piety for the affairs --and degrading the uncodifiable, more complex, intuitive or impious –Fat Tony does not drink milk – Why not Harvardify? experience-based type. It is a severe error because not only a large –Can Socrates out-argue FT ? -- Mystagogue philosophaster share of our knowledge is not explainable, academizable, rationalizable, formalizable, theoretizable, codifiable, Sovietizable, bureaucratizable, Harvardifiable, etc., but, further, that the role such explainable knowledge plays in life is so minor that it is not even I said earlier that, because of complexity, life and the world are funny. not command-and-control style, but that we tended somehow to think so on the occasion, the wrong occasion. Hence, of course, we We are very likely to believe that skills and ideas that we actually fragilize and stifle antifragilities. Let us call it the error of acquired by doing, or that came naturally to us (as we already knew rationalism. I will outline it in this chapter and the next one will by our innate biological instinct) came from books, ideas, and show its application to the history of medicine.
    [Show full text]
  • Logic A-Z from Wikipedia, the Free Encyclopedia Chapter 1
    Logic A-Z From Wikipedia, the free encyclopedia Chapter 1 Antepredicament Antepredicaments, in logic, are certain previous matters requisite to a more easy and clear apprehension of the doctrine of predicaments or categories. Such are definitions of common terms, as equivocals, univocals, etc., with divisions of things, their differences, etc. They are thus called because Aristotle treated them before the predicaments, hoping that the thread of discourse might not afterwards be interrupted. 1.1 References • This article incorporates text from a publication now in the public domain: Chambers, Ephraim, ed. (1728). "*article name needed". Cyclopædia, or an Universal Dictionary of Arts and Sciences (first ed.). James and John Knapton, et al. 2 Chapter 2 Apophasis Not to be confused with Apophysis (disambiguation), Apoptosis, or Apophis (disambiguation). Apophasis is a rhetorical device wherein the speaker or writer brings up a subject by either denying it, or denying that it should be brought up.*[1] Accordingly, it can be seen as a rhetorical relative of irony. Also called paralipsis (παράλειψις) – also spelled paraleipsis or paralepsis –, or occupatio,*[2]*[3]*[4]*[5] and known also as prae- teritio, preterition, antiphrasis (ἀντίφρασις), or parasiopesis (παρασιώπησις), apophasis is usually employed to make a subversive ad hominem attack, which makes it a frequently used tactic in political speeches to make an attack on one's opponent. Using apophasis in this way is often considered to be bad form. The device is typically used to distance
    [Show full text]
  • SKEPTICISM Also Available from Bloomsbury
    SKEPTICISM Also available from Bloomsbury The Bloomsbury Companion to Analytic Philosophy, edited by Barry Dainton and Howard Robinson The Bloomsbury Companion to Epistemology, edited by Andrew Cullison A Critical Introduction to Skepticism, Allan Hazlett SKEPTICISM FROM ANTIQUITY TO THE PRESENT Edited by Diego E. Machuca and Baron Reed Bloomsbury Academic An imprint of Bloomsbury Publishing Plc LONDON • OXFORD • NEW YORK • NEW DELHI • SYDNEY Bloomsbury Academic An imprint of Bloomsbury Publishing Plc 50 Bedford Square 1385 Broadway London New York WC1B 3DP NY 10018 UK USA www.bloomsbury.com BLOOMSBURY and the Diana logo are trademarks of Bloomsbury Publishing Plc First published 2018 © Diego Machuca and Baron Reed, 2018 Diego Machuca and Baron Reed have asserted their right under the Copyright, Designs and Patents Act, 1988, to be identified as the Editors of this work. All rights reserved. No part of this publication may be reproduced or transmitted in any form or by any means, electronic or mechanical, including photocopying, recording, or any information storage or retrieval system, without prior permission in writing from the publishers. No responsibility for loss caused to any individual or organization acting on or refraining from action as a result of the material in this publication can be accepted by Bloomsbury or the editors. British Library Cataloguing-in-Publication Data A catalogue record for this book is available from the British Library. ISBN: HB: 978-1-4725-0771-6 ePDF: 978-1-4725-1436-3 ePub: 978-1-4725-1149-2 Library of Congress Cataloging-in-Publication Data Names: Machuca, Diego E., editor. Title: Skepticism: from antiquity to the present / [edited by] Diego Machuca and Baron Reed.
    [Show full text]