An Experiential Approach to Kant's Moral Philosophy: a Reply to Dogmatism, Formalism and Rigorism

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

An Experiential Approach to Kant's Moral Philosophy: a Reply to Dogmatism, Formalism and Rigorism Loyola University Chicago Loyola eCommons Dissertations Theses and Dissertations 2010 An Experiential Approach to Kant's Moral Philosophy: A Reply to Dogmatism, Formalism and Rigorism Chris McTavish Loyola University Chicago Follow this and additional works at: https://ecommons.luc.edu/luc_diss Part of the Ethics and Political Philosophy Commons Recommended Citation McTavish, Chris, "An Experiential Approach to Kant's Moral Philosophy: A Reply to Dogmatism, Formalism and Rigorism" (2010). Dissertations. 215. https://ecommons.luc.edu/luc_diss/215 This Dissertation is brought to you for free and open access by the Theses and Dissertations at Loyola eCommons. It has been accepted for inclusion in Dissertations by an authorized administrator of Loyola eCommons. For more information, please contact [email protected]. This work is licensed under a Creative Commons Attribution-Noncommercial-No Derivative Works 3.0 License. Copyright © 2010 Chris McTavish LOYOLA UNIVERSITY OF CHICAGO AN EXPERIENTIAL APPROACH TO KANT’S MORAL PHILOSOPHY: A REPLY TO DOGMATISM, FORMALISM AND RIGORISM A DISSERTATION SUBMITTED TO THE FACULTY OF THE GRADUATE SCHOOL IN CANDIDACY FOR THE DEGREE OF DOCTOR OF PHILOSOPHY PROGRAM IN PHILOSOPHY BY CHRISTOPHER HENRY MCTAVISH CHICAGO, ILLINOIS DECEMBER 2010 Copyright by Christopher Henry McTavish, 2010 All rights reserved. ACKNOWLEDGEMENTS This dissertation would not have been possible without the support, patience, wisdom and love of many others. I would like to begin by acknowledging those professors in Loyola’s Department of Philosophy who helped me through this giant adventure. I would like to thank Dr. Adriaan Peperzak for his generous time during the formative years of this project, and for showing me that genuine philosophical thought often requires one to step outside of the comfortable boundaries of strictly academic prescriptions. Dr. Thomas Carson helped me to see how there are good ideas to be uncovered on both sides of the analytic / continental border. Dr. Andrew Cutrofello was, as he is to many of Loyola’s graduate students, a pillar of endless support and friendship. There is not enough space in this section to list all of those instances in which he helped me though challenging times. And to my supervisor, Dr. Victoria Wike, whose advice, direction and, most of all, belief in me, enabled this study to finally see the light of day. My thanks to her will be never ending. I would also like to thank Loyola University of Chicago for providing me with funds for my research and writing. A five year Graduate Tuition Scholarship allowed me to make discernable progress on my research, while an Arthur J. Schmidt Dissertation Fellowship allowed me to focus my attention upon the writing process. I would also like to thank the Social Sciences and Humanities Research Council of Canada for three years of generous funding. Without that funding, I would not have been able to even consider iii embarking upon this great journey across the border. I sincerely hope that the Government of Canada will continue its invaluable support of graduate scholarship in the social sciences and humanities. My wonderful friends have each provided me with endless support, patience, sympathy and (necessary) distractions during which I was able to regroup and come back to my project refreshed and ready to confront it with confidence over and over again. The list of names is much too lengthy, but I would like to especially thank: Joe Linn, James Twine, Justin Harrison, Chris Anderson, Alonso Villaran, Nicholas Mowad, Brendan Alexander, Gabriel Buzzi, Nicoletta Ruane, Thane Montaner, Brain Lisle, Jeff Courtright, Drew Pierce, Lutz Keferstein, Blaine Swen, Stacy Bautista, Michael Burke, Maria Kulp, Doug Boyd, Mike Ward, Chris Everson, Dan Hinderer, Steven Blum, Alain Beauclair, Yasir Syed, Andreas Morse, Ian Drummond, Adam Smith, Robert Burch, Robbie McTavish, Laura MacPherson and Elizabeth Panasiuk. With friends like these no man can fall. A very special and sincere thank-you goes to my loving family. In particular, to my parents, Angela and Gordon, whose trust and love has never swayed, to my sister, Erin, whose good humor and well-timed visits helped to remind me of the important things in life, and to both sets of grandparents, Allan and Dougie and Maria and Henry, who have each supported me with endless love to which I will never be able to fully repay. I can only ever hope to approximate the kind of person that my family continues to believe that I can be. iv And finally, I would like to thank the love of my life and my best friend, Pam McTavish. Through all of the dark times she was the light. Without her support, patience and love this project would have never been completed. Thank you, Pam, for your unfailing trust and belief in me. v For my grandpa, Henry Huff TABLE OF CONTENTS ACKNOWLEDGEMENTS iii LIST OF ABBREVIATIONS ix INTRODUCTION 1 CHAPTER ONE: KANT’S MORAL PHILOSOPHY AND THREE COMMON CRITICISMS 3 I. Kant’s Early Influences in Moral Philosophy 4 (a) Wolff, Hutcheson and Rousseau 4 (b) Reason and Kant’s Departure from the Brits 10 II. Kant’s Groundwork for the Metaphysics of Morals 11 (a) Groundwork Section I – Good Will and Duty 12 (b) Groundwork Section II – The Categorical Imperative 17 (c) Groundwork Section III – A Deduction of Morality? 23 III. Kant’s Doctrine of a “Fact of Pure Reason” 27 (a) Kant’s “Fact of Pure Reason” 28 (b) Questions Concerning Kant’s “Fact” 31 IV. Three Common Criticisms of Kant’s Moral Philosophy 33 (a) Dogmatism 35 (b) Formalism 36 (c) Rigorism 39 (d) The Three Common Criticisms and Existential Veracity 40 V. An Experiential Approach to Kant’s Moral Philosophy 40 VI. Conclusion 43 CHAPTER TWO: AN EXPERIENTIAL APPROACH TO KANT’S MORAL PHILOSOPHY: HAPPINESS AND MORAL FEELING 45 I. Happiness 49 II. Moral Feeling 54 III. Summary Results of this Experiential Account 73 (a) Summary 73 (b) A Response to the Three Criticisms? 76 IV. Conclusion 80 CHAPTER THREE: KANT’S DOCTRINE OF VIRTUE 81 I. Kant’s Doctrine of Virtue 85 (a) Doctrine of Virtue 85 (b) Ends That are Duties 88 (c) Kant’s Derivation of Ethical Duties 92 (d) Summary of Some Key Conclusions from Kant’s Doctrine of Virtue 94 vii II. An Experiential Approach to Kant’s Doctrine of Virtue 97 (a) A Picture of Kantian Moral Life 97 (b) Self-Other Asymmetry 102 (c) Kantian Moral Life 108 III. Conclusion 113 CHAPTER FOUR: A REPLY TO DOGMATISM, FORMALISM AND RIGORISM 115 I. An Experiential Reply to Dogmatism, Formalism and Rigorism 118 (a) Dogmatism 118 (b) Formalism 121 (c) Rigorism 128 (d) Summary of the Experiential Reply to Dogmatism, Formalism and Rigorism 136 CHAPTER FIVE: TWO APPLICATIONS OF THE EXPERIENTIAL APPROACH TO KANT’S MORAL PHILOSOPHY 140 I. Teaching Kant’s Moral Philosophy 140 II. Critical Comparison with Emmanuel Levinas 143 (a) Kant and Levinas on Moral Feeling and Happiness 150 CONCLUSION 167 BIBLIOGRAPHY 169 VITA 184 viii LIST OF ABBREVIATIONS Works by Kant : All page references to Kant’s works are to the Royal Prussian Academy Edition of Kants Gesammelte Schriften . The abbreviations for the English translations are as follows: B Observations on the Feeling of the Beautiful and Sublime , translated by J. Goldthwait (Berkeley: University of California Press, 1960) C Correspondence , translated and edited by A. Zweig (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1999) G “Groundwork of the Metaphysics of Morals,” translated by M.J. Gregor in Practical Philosophy (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1996) pp. 43-108 KPV Critique of Practical Reason , translated by M.J. Gregor (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1996) KRV Critique of Pure Reason , translated by P. Guyer and A. Wood (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1997) KU Critique of the Power of Judgment , translated by P. Guyer and E. Matthews (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2000) LE Lectures on Ethics , translated by Louis Infield (New York: Harper, 1963) MS “Metaphysics of Morals,” translated by M.J. Gregor in Practical Philosophy (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1996) pp. 365-603 P “Inquiry Concerning the Distinctness of the Principles of Natural Theology and Morals,” translated by L.W. Beck in Kant: Selections (New York: MacMillan Publishing, 1988) pp. 5-9 R Religion Within the Limits of Reason Alone , translated by T. Greene and H. Hudson (New York: Harper Row, 1960) TP “On the Common Saying: That May Be True In Theory, But It Is Of No Use In Practice,” translated by M.J. Gregor in Practical Philosophy (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1996) pp. 279-309 ix Works by Other Authors KE Wood, Allen. Kantian Ethics (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2008) OBE Lévinas, Emmanuel. Otherwise Than Being or Beyond Essence , translated by A. Lingis (The Hague: Martinus Nijhoff, 1981) TH Lévinas, Emmanuel. “Transcendence and Height” in Emmanuel Levinas: Basic Philosophical Writings , translated by T. Chanter, S. Critchley, N. Walker and A. Peperzak, edited by A. Peperzak, S. Critchley, and R. Bernasconi (Bloomington: Indiana University Press, 1996) pp. 11-32 TeI / Lévinas, Emmanuel. Totality and Infinity: an Essay on Exteriority , translated by TaI A. Lingis (The Hague: Martinus Nijhoff, 1979). French : Totalité et Infini: Essai sur l’exteriorité (Hague: Martinus Nijhoff, 1971 x INTRODUCTION Many of Kant’s commentators and critics interpret his moral philosophy solely in terms of the cognitive dimension of his categorical imperative. Such a predominant manner of reading Kant gives rise to the criticism that his moral philosophy is too far removed from the actual way in which human beings orient themselves as moral persons in the world. In response to this general tendency in Kant interpretation, my dissertation proposes to offer an experiential approach to Kant’s ethics. By the expression experiential I mean an approach to Kant’s thinking that attends to the living sense in which we experience the phenomena and realities that his moral philosophy presents.
Recommended publications
  • Thinking, Relating and Choosing: Resolving the Issue of Faith, Ethics and the Existential Responsibility of the Individual
    Indo-Pacific Journal of Phenomenology, Volume 9, Edition 2 October 2009 Page 1 of 5 Personal Reflection Thinking, Relating and Choosing: Resolving the Issue of Faith, Ethics and the Existential Responsibility of the Individual by Neil Alan Soggie Abstract Which is worse: Doing evil or being evil? If we are free to define ourselves through our choices, as existentialism posits, then the latter is worse. This paper attempts to resolve the issue of the difference between religious (group) ethics and the ethics of a person of faith that embraces individuals with an existential understanding. In the existential view, the individual (whether the self or the other) is the primary concern, and so the issue of personal relational morality supersedes religious narratives, social morality and popular ethics (White, 2002). If we think and choose, there is the possibility that we may occasionally make a mistake and do evil. However, if we do not think about our choices, and if the conventions we hold happen to be flawed in some way, then we become defined by a continual cycle of mistakes. Existentialism teaches that we become who we are in the process of making choices; therefore the difference between doing evil and being evil can be found in the small but important flow of thinking, relating and choosing. I was visiting with friends recently, and their In fact, it has been my experience that many people observations and comments sparked angst within my who embrace existentialism (in one form or another) soul. For this reason, I am writing on this topic of the are people of faith (Evans, 1995; Tillich, 1990; Wong, ethical life, whatever that may mean, and in so far as 1989; Wong & Fry, 1998).
    [Show full text]
  • War Rights and Military Virtues: a Philosophical Re-Appraisal of Just War Theory
    The University of Notre Dame Australia ResearchOnline@ND Theses 2014 War rights and military virtues: A philosophical re-appraisal of Just War Theory Matthew T. Beard University of Notre Dame Australia Follow this and additional works at: https://researchonline.nd.edu.au/theses Part of the Philosophy Commons COMMONWEALTH OF AUSTRALIA Copyright Regulations 1969 WARNING The material in this communication may be subject to copyright under the Act. Any further copying or communication of this material by you may be the subject of copyright protection under the Act. Do not remove this notice. Publication Details Beard, M. T. (2014). War rights and military virtues: A philosophical re-appraisal of Just War Theory (Doctor of Philosophy (PhD)). University of Notre Dame Australia. https://researchonline.nd.edu.au/theses/96 This dissertation/thesis is brought to you by ResearchOnline@ND. It has been accepted for inclusion in Theses by an authorized administrator of ResearchOnline@ND. For more information, please contact [email protected]. War Rights and Military Virtues A Philosophical Re-appraisal of Just War Theory Doctoral Thesis Prepared by Matthew T. Beard School of Philosophy and Theology University of Notre Dame, Australia Supervised by Christian Enemark and Hayden Ramsay Supported by The Morris Research Scholarship Declaration I, Matthew Thomas Beard, declare that this PhD thesis, entitled War Rights and Military Virtues: A Philosophical Re-appraisal of Just War Theory is no more than 100,000 words exclusive of title pages, table of contents, acknowledgements, list of figures, reference list, and footnotes. The thesis is my own original work, prepared for the specific and unique purposes of this academic degree and has not been submitted in whole or part for the awarding of any other academic degree at any institution.
    [Show full text]
  • Kant's Theory of Knowledge and Hegel's Criticism
    U.Ü. FEN-EDEBİYAT FAKÜLTESİ SOSYAL BİLİMLER DERGİSİ Yıl: 2, Sayı: 2, 2000-2001 KANT’S THEORY OF KNOWLEDGE AND HEGEL’S CRITICISM A. Kadir ÇÜÇEN* ABSTRACT Kant inquires into the possibility, sources, conditions and limits of knowledge in the tradition of modern philosophy. Before knowing God, being and reality, Kant, who aims to question what knowledge is, explains the content of pure reason. He formalates a theory of knowledge but his theory is neither a rationalist nor an empiricist theory of knowledge. He investigates the structure of knowledge, the possible conditions of experience and a priori concepts and categories of pure reason; so he makes a revolution like that of Copernicus . Hegel, who is one of proponents of the German idealism, criticizes the Kantian theory of knowledge for “wanting to know before one knows”. For Hegel, Kant’s a priori concepts and categories are meaningless and empty. He claims that the unity of subject and object has been explained in that of the “Absolute”. Therefore, the theory of knowledge goes beyond the dogmatism of the “thing-in- itself” and the foundations of mathematics and natural sciences; and reaches the domain of absolute knowledge. Hegel’s criticism of Kantian theory of knowledge opens new possibilities for the theory of knowledge in our age. ÖZET Kant’ın Bilgi Kuramı ve Hegel’in Eleştirisi Modern felsefe geleneği çerçevesinde Kant, bilginin imkânını, kaynağını, kapsamını ve ölçütlerini ele alarak, doğru bilginin sınırlarını irdelemiştir. Tanrı’yı, varlığı ve gerçekliği bilmeden önce, bilginin neliğini sorgulamayı kendine amaç edinen Kant, saf aklın içeriğini incelemiştir. Saf aklın a priori kavram ve kategorilerini, deneyin görüsünü ve bilgi yapısını veren, fakat ne usçu ne de deneyci * Uludag University, Faculty of Sciences and Letters, Dept.
    [Show full text]
  • Shifting Liberal and Conservative Attitudes Using Moral Foundations
    PSPXXX10.1177/0146167214551152Personality and Social Psychology BulletinDay et al. 551152research-article2014 Article Personality and Social Psychology Bulletin Shifting Liberal and Conservative 1 –15 © 2014 by the Society for Personality and Social Psychology, Inc Attitudes Using Moral Reprints and permissions: sagepub.com/journalsPermissions.nav Foundations Theory DOI: 10.1177/0146167214551152 pspb.sagepub.com Martin V. Day1, Susan T. Fiske1, Emily L. Downing2, and Thomas E. Trail3 Abstract People’s social and political opinions are grounded in their moral concerns about right and wrong. We examine whether five moral foundations—harm, fairness, ingroup, authority, and purity—can influence political attitudes of liberals and conservatives across a variety of issues. Framing issues using moral foundations may change political attitudes in at least two possible ways: (a) Entrenching: Relevant moral foundations will strengthen existing political attitudes when framing pro-attitudinal issues (e.g., conservatives exposed to a free-market economic stance) and (b) Persuasion: Mere presence of relevant moral foundations may also alter political attitudes in counter-attitudinal directions (e.g., conservatives exposed to an economic regulation stance). Studies 1 and 2 support the entrenching hypothesis. Relevant moral foundation-based frames bolstered political attitudes for conservatives (Study 1) and liberals (Study 2). Only Study 2 partially supports the persuasion hypothesis. Conservative-relevant moral frames of liberal issues increased conservatives’ liberal attitudes. Keywords morality, moral foundations, ideology, attitudes, politics Received July 1, 2013; revision accepted August 19, 2014 Our daily lives are steeped in political content, including 2012). Understanding the effectiveness of morally based many attempts to alter our attitudes. These efforts stem from framing may be consequential not only for politics but also a variety of sources, such as political campaigns, presidential for better understanding of everyday shifts in other opinions.
    [Show full text]
  • Kant's Critique of Judgment and the Scientific Investigation of Matter
    Kant’s Critique of Judgment and the Scientific Investigation of Matter Daniel Rothbart, Irmgard Scherer Abstract: Kant’s theory of judgment establishes the conceptual framework for understanding the subtle relationships between the experimental scientist, the modern instrument, and nature’s atomic particles. The principle of purposive- ness which governs judgment has also a role in implicitly guiding modern experimental science. In Part 1 we explore Kant’s philosophy of science as he shows how knowledge of material nature and unobservable entities is possible. In Part 2 we examine the way in which Kant’s treatment of judgment, with its operating principle of purposiveness, enters into his critical project and under- lies the possibility of rational science. In Part 3 we show that the centrality given to judgment in Kant’s conception of science provides philosophical in- sight into the investigation of atomic substances in modern chemistry. Keywords : Kant , judgment , purposiveness , experimentation , investigation of matter . Introduction Kant’s philosophy of science centers on the problem of how it is possible to acquire genuine knowledge of unobservable entities, such as atoms and molecules. “What and how much can the understanding and reason know apart from all experience?” ( CPuR , Axvii). This raises the question of the role of experiments in the knowability ( Erkennbarkeit ) and the experientiality (Erfahrbarkeit ) of nature. Kant’s insights into the character of scientific experimentation are not given the hearing they deserve. We argue that Kant’s theory of judgment establishes the conceptual framework for understanding the subtle inter- actions between the experimental chemist, the modern chemical instrument, and molecular substance.
    [Show full text]
  • Introduction: Towards a Reconsideration of Neo-Kantianism Nicolas De Warren and Andrea Staiti
    Cambridge University Press 978-1-107-03257-6 - New Approaches to Neo-Kantianism Edited by Nicolas De Warren and Andrea Staiti Excerpt More information Introduction: towards a reconsideration of Neo-Kantianism Nicolas de Warren and Andrea Staiti In the summer of 1914, T. S. Eliot arrived in Marburg from Harvard University to attend a summer course in philosophy before taking up residency at Merton College, Oxford, for a year of study with Harold Joachim, F. H. Bradley’s successor. At the University of Marburg, Eliot met Paul Natorp, who assisted him in finding affordable accommodation and lectured in his course on philosophy. The outbreak of the First World War would cut short Eliot’s stay in Marburg, but not before he had the chance to sketch a portrait of the venerable Neo-Kantian Professor. Natorp strikes a professorial pose, one arm tucked behind his back, the other slung across his waist. With elven ears and bald cranium, the philosopher appears endearing in his otherworldliness. Natorp’s face is hidden behind oval glasses, so large that they seem to constitute a hindrance rather than an aid to seeing reality. Eliot’s sketch can be seen as a visual epitome for how Neo-Kantianism appeared to a younger generation of intellectuals and philosophers who would come of age in the aftermath of a Europe laid waste through the cataclysm of the Great War. Eliot’s amusing sketch is an apt illustration for what Hans-Georg Gadamer, who wrote his PhD dissertation on Plato under Natorp in 1922, characterized as the Neo-Kantian “calm and 1 confident aloofness” engrossed in “complacent system-building.” With slightly more bite, Hannah Arendt charged Neo-Kantianism with drown- ing philosophy “in a sea of boredom,” thereby offering a softer version of the same hostility that spirited Martin Heidegger’s confrontation with 2 Ernst Cassirer at Davos in 1929.
    [Show full text]
  • Ciceronian Business Ethics Owen Goldin Marquette University, [email protected]
    Marquette University e-Publications@Marquette Philosophy Faculty Research and Publications Philosophy, Department of 11-1-2006 Ciceronian Business Ethics Owen Goldin Marquette University, [email protected] Published version. Studies in the History of Ethics (November 2006). Publisher link. © 2006 HistoryofEthics.org. Used with permission. Studies in the History of Ethics Ciceronian Bu siness Ethics Owen Goldin (Mar quette University) The teaching and practice of business must resist ethical compartmentalization. One engaged in business ought not check moral principles at the door and say “business is business,” for this is to pretend that when one is engaged in business, one is no longer a human being, with the rational nature, emotional constitution, and social bonds that are at the root of our ethical nature. Ethical standards apply to business as they do all aspects of human life. Nonetheless, making money is the goal of business, and more often than not, one is trying to take money from another, at the least possible cost. Such action is necessarily self-centered, if not selfish, and requires acting in a way that we would not want to see people act in all of their dealings with others, especially in regard to family, friends, and others with whom they have special social bonds. Granting that business practices are not compartmentalized against all ethical considerations, the fact that business demands maximization of profit entails that special rules apply. Determining what these are, in what circumstances they are less demanding than the ethical principles of everyday life, and in what circumstances they are more demanding, is the domain of business ethics, as a special domain of ethical philosophy.
    [Show full text]
  • The Terrible, Horrible, No Good, Very Bad Truth About Morality and What to Do About It, Doctoral Dissertation of Joshua D
    9/03 Note to readers of The Terrible, Horrible, No Good, Very Bad Truth about Morality and What to Do About it, Doctoral Dissertation of Joshua D. Greene in the Department of Philosophy, Princeton University, June 2002. You are welcome to read this work, pass it on to others, and cite it. I only ask that if you pass on this work to someone else that it be passed on (1) in its entirety, (2) without modification, and (3) along with this note. I consider this a work in progress. It is currently under review in its present form at an academic press. I intend to revise and expand it substantially before publishing it as a book, so much so that the book and the dissertation will probably best be considered separate works. Comments are welcome. You can contact me by email ([email protected]) or by regular mail: Joshua Greene Department of Psychology Princeton University Princeton, NJ 08544 jdg THE TERRIBLE, HORRIBLE, NO GOOD, VERY BAD TRUTH ABOUT MORALITY AND WHAT TO DO ABOUT IT Joshua David Greene A DISSERTATION PRESENTED TO THE FACULTY OF PRINCETON UNIVERSITY IN CANDIDACY FOR THE DEGREE OF DOCTOR OF PHILOSOPHY RECOMMENDED FOR ACCEPTANCE BY THE DEPARTMENT OF PHILOSOPHY NOVEMBER 2002 © Copyright by Joshua David Greene, 2002. All rights reserved. ii Abstract In this essay I argue that ordinary moral thought and language is, while very natural, highly counterproductive and that as a result we would be wise to change the way we think and talk about moral matters. First, I argue on metaphysical grounds against moral realism, the view according to which there are first order moral truths.
    [Show full text]
  • When the Kingdom of God Became the Kingdom of Ends: Altruism’S Development Into a Normative Ideal
    When the Kingdom of God Became the Kingdom of Ends: Altruism’s Development into a Normative Ideal A Senior Honor Thesis Presented in partial fulfillment of the requirements for graduation with distinction in Political Science in the College of Social and Behavioral Sciences by Benjamin T. Jones The Ohio State University December 10, 2006 Project Advisors: John M. Parrish, Department of Political Science (Loyola Marymount University) Michael A. Neblo, Department of Political Science (The Ohio State University) Table of Contents Abstract ii Acknowledgements iii Introduction 1 The Paradox at the Heart of Altruism 4 Defining Altruism and Normativity 6 What Are We Looking For? 11 Roadmap of What’s to Come 14 Part I Towards a Problem: The Ancient Debate over Public Life 17 Eudaimonia and Ancient Ethics 18 Plato and Aristotle 24 Epicurus and the Stoics 40 A Solution from an Unlikely Source 47 Augustine’s Reconciliation of the Two Cities 55 Conclusion 63 Part II Self-Love’s Fall from Grace: How Normative Altruism Developed out of the Augustinian Tradition 65 Entangled in Self-love: Augustine’s Normative Argument 67 Augustine Goes Secular 75 Kant’s Problematic Solution 83 Reworking Kant—And Altruism 89 Conclusion 91 Part III The Problems with Normative Altruism 93 Two Conceptions of Altruism 93 Evidence for Altruism on a Descriptive Level 95 Motivational Barriers to Normative Altruism 113 Changing the Way We Talk About Altruism 121 Conclusion 126 Bibliography 131 i Abstract In contemporary moral philosophy, altruism holds a place of prominence. Although a complex idea, the term seeps into everyday discourse, by no means confined to the esoteric language of philosophers and psychologists.
    [Show full text]
  • Modern Moral Conscience
    Modern Moral Conscience Tom O’Shea Forthcoming in International Journal of Philosophical Studies Abstract: This article challenges the individualism and neutrality of modern moral conscience. It looks to the history of the concept to excavate an older tradition that takes conscience to be social and morally responsive, while arguing that dominant contemporary justifications of conscience in terms of integrity are inadequate without reintroducing these social and moral traits. This prompts a rethinking of the nature and value of conscience: first, by demonstrating that a morally-responsive conscience is neither a contradiction in terms nor a political absurdity; second, by suggesting how a morally-responsive conscience can be informed by the social world without being a mere proxy for social power or moribund tradition. 1. The idea of conscience underwent a gradual hollowing out during modernity. Our now- dominant conceptions of conscience have sundered it from both social relationships and ethical truths which outrun each individual’s convictions. We have yet to properly reckon with the implications of this shift towards an egocentric and normatively neutral understanding of conscience. My aim is to excavate an older tradition without these two traits and to ask what we may have lost by leaving it behind. While this will reveal a challenge to modern moral conscience, there remain formidable obstacles to returning to earlier understandings of it. I shall outline a social and normative conception of conscience which learns the lessons of this earlier tradition while showing how it must nevertheless adapt to modern conditions. What then is conscience? Among our oldest moral concepts – recognisable as early as the Greek playwrights of the 5th century BCE – it has long been understood as the self’s awareness of the moral dimension of its conduct (Sorabji 2014, 15).1 Conscience consists in a consciousness of moral demands upon the particular individual in their own specific circumstances rather than a merely abstract knowledge of right and wrong.
    [Show full text]
  • Moral Sense Theory and the Development of Kant's Ethics
    View metadata, citation and similar papers at core.ac.uk brought to you by CORE provided by Scholarship@Western Western University Scholarship@Western Electronic Thesis and Dissertation Repository 12-15-2015 12:00 AM Moral Sense Theory and the Development of Kant's Ethics Michael H. Walschots The University of Western Ontario Supervisor Corey Dyck The University of Western Ontario Graduate Program in Philosophy A thesis submitted in partial fulfillment of the equirr ements for the degree in Doctor of Philosophy © Michael H. Walschots 2015 Follow this and additional works at: https://ir.lib.uwo.ca/etd Part of the History of Philosophy Commons Recommended Citation Walschots, Michael H., "Moral Sense Theory and the Development of Kant's Ethics" (2015). Electronic Thesis and Dissertation Repository. 3383. https://ir.lib.uwo.ca/etd/3383 This Dissertation/Thesis is brought to you for free and open access by Scholarship@Western. It has been accepted for inclusion in Electronic Thesis and Dissertation Repository by an authorized administrator of Scholarship@Western. For more information, please contact [email protected]. MORAL SENSE THEORY AND THE DEVELOPMENT OF KANT’S ETHICS (Thesis format: Monograph) by Michael H. Walschots Graduate Program in Philosophy A thesis submitted in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy The School of Graduate and Postdoctoral Studies The University of Western Ontario London, Ontario, Canada © Michael H. Walschots 2015 Abstract This dissertation investigates a number of ways in which an eighteenth century British philosophical movement known as “moral sense theory” influenced the development of German philosopher Immanuel Kant’s (1724-1804) moral theory.
    [Show full text]
  • Ethical Realism/Moral Realism Ethical Propositions That Refer to Objective Features May Be True If They Are Free of Subjectivis
    Metaethics: Cognitivism Metaethics: What is morality, or “right”? Normative (prescriptive) ethics: How should people act? Descriptive ethics: What do people think is right? Applied ethics: Putting moral ideas into practice Thin moral concepts Thick moral concepts more general: good, bad, right, and wrong more specic: courageous, inequitable, just, or dishonest Centralism- thin concepts are antecedent to the thick ones Non-centralism- thick concepts are a sucient starting point for understanding thin ones because thin and thick concepts are equal. Normativity is a non-excisable aspect of language and there is no way of analyzing thick moral concepts into a purely descriptive element attached to a thin moral evaluation, thus undermining any fundamental division between facts and norms. Cognitivism ethical propositions are truth-apt (can be true or false), unlike questions or commands Ethical subjectivism/moral anti-realism Ethical realism/moral realism True ethical propositions are a function of subjective features Ethical propositions that refer to objective features may be true if they are free of subjectivism Moral relativism Moral universalism/ Robust and Minimal Robust moral objectivism/ nobody is objectively right or wrong universal morality 1. Semantic thesis: moral predicates 3. Metaphysical thesis: the facts in regards to diagreements about are to refer to moral properties so and properties of #1 are robust-- moral questions a system of ethics, or a universal ethic, moral statements represent moral their metaphysical status is not applies universally to "all" facts, and express propositions that relevantly dierent from ordinary are true or false non-moral facts and properties Cultural relativism not all forms of moral universalism 2.
    [Show full text]