Metaethics and the Autonomy of Morality

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Metaethics and the Autonomy of Morality Philosophers’ volume8,no.6 july2008 Imprint 1. Introduction SincethepublicationofG.E.Moore’sPrincipia Ethicaithasbecome commonplace for philosophers to distinguish between questions in metaethics and those in normative ethics.1 A sympathetic character- Metaethics izationofthecenturyofself-consciouslymetaethicalresearchthatfol- lowedwouldemphasizetheextraordinarydevelopmentbothinour understandingofthecentralmetaethicalproblemsandinthesophis- ticationofthetheorieselaboratedtomeetthem.However,someare & notsosympathetic.Inthispaper,Iexamineonesourceofdistrustin metaethicalresearch:itsapparenttensionwiththenotionthatmoral- ityisautonomous. Tobegin,IbrieflysketchhowIamthinkingofmetaethics,ofthe the Autonomy of autonomyofmorality,andofthetensionthatcanappeartoexistbe- tweenthem.Onetraditionalconceptionofmetaethicstakesittocon- cern only the analysis of moral language.2 However, contemporary philosophers typically use the term more expansively.3 Here, I use Morality the term to pick out elements common to these contemporary dis- cussions.Thiscommoncoreencompassesmoralontologyandmoral psychologyaswellasmoralsemantics.Bycontrast,normativeethics (sometimesalsocalled‘substantiveethics’)concernsthestructureand contentofthecorrectmoralevaluationofagents,statesofaffairs,and actions.Normativeethicaltheoriestypicallyofferaccountsofmoral valueandmoralreasons,ofvirtuouscharactertraits,ofrightness,and Tristram McPherson oftherelationshipsbetweenthese. 1. The word ‘metaethics’ came into regular philosophical usage much later. University of Minnesota Duluth Moore’sdiscussionemphasizedthedistinctionbetweentwokindsofques- tionsaboutmorality,whichinturnencouragedthedevelopmentofindepen- dentresearchprogramsinwhatwouldlaterbecalled“metaethics”and“nor- mativeethics”. 2. ObviousworriesaboutthisconceptionarisefromQuineanconcernsabout analyticity.SuchworriesledZimmermantoargueforan“ontologicalturn”in metaethics(1980,653). © 2008 TristramMcPherson 3. VariousbroaderconceptionsofmetaethicsaresuggestedinDarwall,Gibbard, <www.philosophersimprint.org/008006/> andRailton(1997,7),Miller(2003,2),andSinnott-Armstrong(2006,6). tristrammcpherson Metaethics and the Autonomy of Morality AdomainofinquiryisautonomousinthesenseIintendifresultsin The apparent tension between metaethics and the autonomy of otherdomainsdonotcontributetothejustificationoftheoriesinthat morality derives from the plausibility of taking metaethical theoriz- domain.4Theautonomy of moralityisthustheclaimthat: ingtohavetwofeatures.First,metaethicscanseeminglybearonthe justificationofnormativeethicaltheories.ShellyKaganmakesanes- autonomy: Non-moral theses are irrelevant to the justifica- peciallystrongversionofthisclaimthatmetaethicsisrelevanttothe tionofnormativeethicaltheories. justificationofnormativetheory:“[I]nthecourseofdefendingagiven Iwillsometimesrefertothisastheautonomy thesis.5Theideathatnor- theoryaboutthefoundationsofnormativeethics,whenwetrytoex- mativeethicaltheorizingisautonomousmayappearintuitivelyattrac- plainwhyitisthatthevariousfeaturesofthattheoryshouldseemat- tive.Thus,itmayseemonreflectionthattheonlylegitimategrounds tractiveandplausible,inevitablytheclaimswemakewillthemselves for abandoning a basic moral principle will involve tension with simplybemetaethicalclaims”(1998,6).Kagan’sclaimiscontroversial. othermoralcommitments.6Further,theautonomythesispromisesto However,evenifitdoesnotseeminevitablethatmetaethicsplaysthis explaintheplausibilityofHume’sdictumthatonecannotderivean sortoffoundationalroleinnormativetheorizing,theideathatourbest ‘ought’froman‘is’:ifmoralityisautonomous,itwillalwaysbeanerror accountsofmoralpropertiesormoralconceptscouldn’tcountforor toderiveamoralconclusionfromstrictlynon-moralpremises. againstthejustifiabilityofanormativetheorymightseempuzzling. Becausemetaethicalclaimsarethemselvesclaimsaboutmorality, 4. My use of the term ‘autonomous’ here is inspired by Harman’s distinction this point does not by itself conflict with the autonomy thesis. The between“naturalism”and“autonomousethics”inmoraltheory(2000,79). apparentproblemarisesfromconjoiningthispointwithreflectionon However,Iuseittomakeaslightlydifferentdistinction.Harmansuggests thatanyapproachtoethicsnotdominatedbyaconcerntoplacevaluesin thetaskofmetaethicaltheory.Onaplausiblegloss,thecentraltaskof thenaturalworlddiscoveredbyscienceisautonomous(2000,79).Onmy metaethicsistoexplainhowmoralityfitswiththeotherelementsof gloss,scienceisonlyonedomainwithrespecttowhichmoralitymightbe autonomous.Forexample,Ialsotakedivinecommandtheorytobeincom- ourbroaderconceptionoftheworld.(Notethatthisdescriptionofthe patiblewiththeautonomyofmorality,asitwouldrenderevidenceofGod’s taskofmetaethicsisconsistentbothwithconceivingoftheseother willprobativefornormativeethicaltheory. elementsinexclusivelynaturalisticterms,andwiththinkingthatour 5. Therestrictionofthescopeoftheautonomythesistotheories,understood bestoverallconceptionoftheworldmustaugmentortranscendthe asconsistingoffundamentalprinciples,iscrucialtotheplausibilityofthe autonomythesis,becauseitisimplausiblethatevidencefromotherdomains scientificworldview.)Thissuggeststhatcoherencewithwell-justified isnotrelevanttothejustificationofderivativeprinciplesorofparticularmor- generalaccountsofontologyandsemanticscountsinfavorofame- aljudgments.Forexample,considerthemoralprinciple“Itiswrongtofire loadedgunsatinnocentpeople”andtheparticularmoralclaim“Lee’sfiring taethicaltheory.Hence,itseemsnaturalformetaethicaltheorizingto hisgunatJohniswrong.”Anaturalwaytojustifysuchclaimswouldappeal involveappealtonon-moralpremises. inparttomorebasicnormativeprinciples,andinparttothetypicalorpre- dictablecausalconsequencesoffiringloadedgunsatpeople.Theautonomy Together, these two apparent features of metaethical theorizing thesisshouldthusbeunderstoodascompatiblewitharolefornon-moral appeartoconflictwiththeautonomyofmorality.Thus,ifnon-moral thesesinexplainingwhyanormativemoralprincipleappliestoaparticular premisesarerelevanttothejustificationofaccountsofmoralseman- case,orsupportsaderivativeprinciple. ticsorontology,andtheseaccountsinturnplayaroleinjustifying 6. CompareHarman’sdescriptionoftheautonomousethicist’sreasoningabout acase:“[W]eshouldcontinuetobelieve[thatacriminalhassufficientreason foundationalnormative theories, then non-moral premises can play nottoharmhisorhervictims]unlesssuchcontinuedbeliefconflictswith anindirectroleinjustifyingnormativeethicaltheories.Thisconclu- generalizationsorothertheoreticalprinciplesinternaltoethicsthatwefind attractivebecausetheydoabetterjobatmakingsenseofmostofthethings sionappearstobeinconsistentwiththeautonomythesis. weoriginallybelieve”(2000,87). Ifoneissympathetictotheautonomythesis,thisapparenttension philosophers’imprint – 2 – vol.8,no.6(july2008) tristrammcpherson Metaethics and the Autonomy of Morality mightsuggestthatthereissomeerrorimplicitinmetaethicaltheoriz- implications. Thus, if metaethics was necessarily neutral between ing.Somephilosophershaverecentlyoffereddiagnosesofthisalleged normativetheories,thesensitivityofmetaethicaltheorytonon-moral error. Thus Christine Korsgaard suggests that the dialectic between considerations(thesecondapparentfeatureofmetaethicaltheories) metaethical realists and antirealists rests on a mistaken conception couldnotimpugntheautonomyofnormativeethicaltheorizing. ofthefunctionofmoralconcepts.Sheclaimsthatwhenourthinking Onecouldthinkoftheneutralitythesisineitheroftwoways.First, aboutthesubjectiscorrected,“wewillnotbeinclinedtothinkthat one could think of it as a hypothesis about metaethical theories, to there is a difference between doing ‘meta-ethics’ and doing ‘norma- beevaluatedbyexaminingsuchtheories.However,itiseasytofind tive’orpracticalethics”(2003,121n.44).RonaldDworkinalsofinds counterexamplestothisneutralityhypothesis,intheformofmetaethi- errorinmuchapparentlymetaethicaltheorizing,arguingthatitrests caltheorieswithdirectnormativeimplications.Considerasimpleex- onmistakingsubstantiveethicalclaimstobemetaphysicalor“philo- ample:theanalyticutilitarianismthatMoore(1903,17–18)attributes sophical”(1996,100). toJeremyBentham.Thissemantictheorystatesthattheword‘right’ Thispaperexaminesthreewaystoaddresstheapparenttension means“conducivetogeneralhappiness”.Analyticalutilitarianismisan betweenmetaethicsandtheautonomyofmorality.Insection2,Iex- accountofthesemanticsofacentralpieceofmoralvocabulary,and aminetheattempttoaddressthistensionbyrejectingtheclaimthat hence a paradigmatic metaethical theory. However, it also transpar- metaethics can be relevant to the justification of normative ethical entlyhasimplicationsforthecontentofthecorrectnormativetheory. theories.Ievaluatethisstrategyinpartbyexaminingthereasoning Theneutralitythesisthusseemsimplausibleifreadasahypothesis thatleadsDworkintothediagnosismentionedabove.Insection3,I concerningthepossiblecontentoftheoriesthatweintuitivelycount examinevariantsontheproposaltovindicatetheautonomyofmoral- asmetaethical. itybyappealingtoadeepcontrastbetweenpracticalandtheoretical Onecouldinsteadthinkoftheneutralitythesisasaconstrainton reason. Korsgaard’s diagnosis is best understood as following from atheory’scountingasmetaethical.Thinkingoftheneutralitythesis suchacommitment.Finally,insection4IsuggestwhatItaketobe asahypothesisrunsintotroublewhereseeminglyparadigmaticme- themostpromisingwaytoresolvetheapparenttensionbetweenme- taethicaltheorieshavenormativeimplications.Bycontrast,aneutral- taethicsandtheautonomyofmorality. ityconstraintwouldentailthatthesamedatashowedsuchtheories notreallytobemetaethical.Thus,acceptingsuchaconstraintmight 2.
Recommended publications
  • Defending Options Author(S): Shelly Kagan Source: Ethics, Vol. 104, No. 2 (Jan., 1994), Pp
    Defending Options Author(s): Shelly Kagan Source: Ethics, Vol. 104, No. 2 (Jan., 1994), pp. 333-351 Published by: The University of Chicago Press Stable URL: http://www.jstor.org/stable/2381581 Accessed: 13-08-2014 16:42 UTC Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of the Terms & Conditions of Use, available at http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide range of content in a trusted digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and facilitate new forms of scholarship. For more information about JSTOR, please contact [email protected]. The University of Chicago Press is collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend access to Ethics. http://www.jstor.org This content downloaded from 130.132.173.11 on Wed, 13 Aug 2014 16:42:57 UTC All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions Defending Options ShellyKagan Suppose some act would best promote the overall good, objectively speaking. Are we morallyrequired to do it? Not necessarily,says ordi- nary,commonsense morality: after all, the act in question mightviolate someone's rightsor run afoul of some otheragent-centered constraint. Well, then, are we at least morallyrequired to performthe act with the best resultsof those acts that are not otherwiseforbidden? Here, too, ordinarymorality says no: thereis no such general moral require- ment to promote the good (not even within the confines of moral constraints).Rather, ordinary morality claims that in a certainbroad, but not unlimited,range of cases, agents have moraloptions: although they are morallypermitted to performthe act with the best conse- quences overall,they are not morallyrequired to do so; on the contrary, they are also morallypermitted to performinstead acts that are less than optimal, such as pursuing theirown interests.
    [Show full text]
  • Scanlon on the Metaphysics of Reasons
    Against Quietist Normative Realism Forthcoming in Philosophical Studies Tristram McPherson University of Minnesota Duluth [email protected] Note: This is the author’s penultimate manuscript of this paper (ms. of March 1, 2010). The final publication is available at www.springerlink.com. Abstract: Recently, some philosophers have suggested that a form of robust realism about ethics, or normativity more generally, does not face a significant explanatory burden in metaphysics. I call this view metaphysically quietist normative realism. This paper argues that while this view can appear to constitute an attractive alternative to more traditional forms of normative realism, it cannot deliver on this promise. I examine T. M. Scanlon’s attempt to defend such a quietist realism, and argue that rather than silencing metaphysical questions about normative reasons, his defense at best succeeds only in shifting the focus of metaphysical enquiry. I then set aside the details of Scanlon’s view, and argue on general grounds that that the quietist realist cannot finesse a crucial metanormative task: to explain the contrast between the correct normative system and alternative putatively normative standards. Keywords: metaethics, metanormative quietism, metanormative realism, normativity, reasons, Scanlon McPherson Against quietist normative realism MS 1 Introduction Philosophers interested in normative domains such as ethics or epistemology face a persistent challenge: to understand how our practices of normative judgment and discourse fit within our best general account of the world. I will call this the metanormative project.1 (Contrast the more familiar metaethical project, which addresses similar questions about specifically moral or practical norms.) Roughly, metanormative realists think that normative claims are made true by their correspondence to the normative facts.2 Metanormative realists appear to face a daunting metaphysical challenge, which can be partially characterized by noting three central desiderata for a metanormative theory.
    [Show full text]
  • Shifting Liberal and Conservative Attitudes Using Moral Foundations
    PSPXXX10.1177/0146167214551152Personality and Social Psychology BulletinDay et al. 551152research-article2014 Article Personality and Social Psychology Bulletin Shifting Liberal and Conservative 1 –15 © 2014 by the Society for Personality and Social Psychology, Inc Attitudes Using Moral Reprints and permissions: sagepub.com/journalsPermissions.nav Foundations Theory DOI: 10.1177/0146167214551152 pspb.sagepub.com Martin V. Day1, Susan T. Fiske1, Emily L. Downing2, and Thomas E. Trail3 Abstract People’s social and political opinions are grounded in their moral concerns about right and wrong. We examine whether five moral foundations—harm, fairness, ingroup, authority, and purity—can influence political attitudes of liberals and conservatives across a variety of issues. Framing issues using moral foundations may change political attitudes in at least two possible ways: (a) Entrenching: Relevant moral foundations will strengthen existing political attitudes when framing pro-attitudinal issues (e.g., conservatives exposed to a free-market economic stance) and (b) Persuasion: Mere presence of relevant moral foundations may also alter political attitudes in counter-attitudinal directions (e.g., conservatives exposed to an economic regulation stance). Studies 1 and 2 support the entrenching hypothesis. Relevant moral foundation-based frames bolstered political attitudes for conservatives (Study 1) and liberals (Study 2). Only Study 2 partially supports the persuasion hypothesis. Conservative-relevant moral frames of liberal issues increased conservatives’ liberal attitudes. Keywords morality, moral foundations, ideology, attitudes, politics Received July 1, 2013; revision accepted August 19, 2014 Our daily lives are steeped in political content, including 2012). Understanding the effectiveness of morally based many attempts to alter our attitudes. These efforts stem from framing may be consequential not only for politics but also a variety of sources, such as political campaigns, presidential for better understanding of everyday shifts in other opinions.
    [Show full text]
  • Moral Theories Course Leader
    PHIL 101: Conceptual Foundations of Bioethics: Moral Theories Course Leader: Stavroula Tsinorema Semester: 1st (7 ECTS) Course Type: Required Objectives: The aims of this course unit are (a) to bring students in contact with the theoretical basis of Bioethics, through training in the methodologies and analytical tools of moral reasoning, (b) to provide them with the basic categories which show the conceptual links between the frameworks of moral philosophy and normative bioethical reasoning, (c) to equip them with the appropriate theoretical frameworks in order to be able to investigate critically and, where possible, to resolve specific moral problems deriving in biomedical research, its application in clinical contexts, health care and environmental policy. The overall aim is to enable students to develop core skills for the conduct of normative analysis and reasoning in Bioethics. Content: The normative resources for moral argument and justification in Bioethics are found in moral philosophy and philosophical theories of ethics. This course unit will survey some of the principle philosophical approaches in addressing a number of bioethical controversies and bring appropriate perspectives from ethical theories to bear on case studies in Bioethics. Topics include: 1) Philosophical ethics and its relation to Bioethics. 2) Classical approaches. Ethics and metaphysics. Ontological approaches to ethics. 3) Modern classical approaches to ethics. Theories of Scottish Enlightenment. Moral sentiments and the ethics of work: David Hume and Adam Smith. 4) Immanuel Kant: The ethics of form. 5) Jeremy Bentham and John Stuart Mill. Utilitarianism. 6) Contemporary moral theories: - Contractarian and constructivist theories. John Rawls, Jurgen Habermas, Onora O’ Neill Postgraduate Prospectus 17 - Virtue ethics, ethics of care, feminism, communitarianism 7) Theories of a deflatory kind and moral scepticism.
    [Show full text]
  • Moral Fallibility and Moral Smugness
    This is a repository copy of Gibbardian Humility: Moral Fallibility and Moral Smugness. White Rose Research Online URL for this paper: http://eprints.whiterose.ac.uk/93155/ Version: Accepted Version Article: Lenman, J.W. (2014) Gibbardian Humility: Moral Fallibility and Moral Smugness. Journal of Value Inquiry, 48 (2). 235 - 245. ISSN 0022-5363 https://doi.org/10.1007/s10790-014-9420-6 Reuse Unless indicated otherwise, fulltext items are protected by copyright with all rights reserved. The copyright exception in section 29 of the Copyright, Designs and Patents Act 1988 allows the making of a single copy solely for the purpose of non-commercial research or private study within the limits of fair dealing. The publisher or other rights-holder may allow further reproduction and re-use of this version - refer to the White Rose Research Online record for this item. Where records identify the publisher as the copyright holder, users can verify any specific terms of use on the publisher’s website. Takedown If you consider content in White Rose Research Online to be in breach of UK law, please notify us by emailing [email protected] including the URL of the record and the reason for the withdrawal request. [email protected] https://eprints.whiterose.ac.uk/ 1 1 Gibbardian Humility: Moral Fallibility and Moral Smugness This is my version of a paper published in The Journal of Value Inquiry 48, 2014, pp. 235-245. DOI 10.1007/s10790-014-9420-6. Please refer to the latter when quoting or citing Abstract Andy Egan objects to quasi-realism that quasi-realists are committed to a form of smugness: when confronted with cases of fundamental disagreement, the quasi-realist must see him/herself as immune to moral error in a way that others are not.
    [Show full text]
  • Sense and Sensibility
    Nils Franzén Sense and Sensibility Four Essays on Evaluative Discourse Dissertation presented at Uppsala University to be publicly examined in Geijersalen, Thunbergsvägen 3H, Uppsala, Thursday, 20 September 2018 at 15:00 for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy. The examination will be conducted in English. Faculty examiner: Professor Pekka Väyrynen (University of Leeds, Faculty of Arts, Humanities and Cultures ). Abstract Franzén, N. 2018. Sense and Sensibility. Four Essays on Evaluative Discourse. 37 pp. Uppsala: Department of Philosophy. ISBN 978-91-506-2717-6. The subject of this thesis is the nature of evaluative terms and concepts. It investigates various phenomena that distinguish evaluative discourse from other types of language use. Broadly, the thesis argues that these differences are best explained by the hypothesis that evaluative discourse serves to communicate that the speaker is in a particular emotional or affective state of mind. The first paper, “Aesthetic Evaluation and First-hand Experience”, examines the fact that it sounds strange to make evaluative aesthetic statements while at the same time denying that you have had first-hand experience with the object being discussed. It is proposed that a form of expressivism about aesthetic discourse best explains the data. The second paper, “Evaluative Discourse and Affective States of Mind”, discusses the problem of missing Moorean infelicity for expressivism. It is argued that evaluative discourse expresses states of mind attributed by sentences of the form “Nils finds it wrong to tell lies”. These states, the paper argues, are non-cognitive, and the observation therefore addresses the problem of missing infelicity. The third paper, “Sensibilism and Evaluative Supervenience”, argues that contemporary theories about why the moral supervenes on the non-moral have failed to account for the full extent of the phenomenon.
    [Show full text]
  • The Terrible, Horrible, No Good, Very Bad Truth About Morality and What to Do About It, Doctoral Dissertation of Joshua D
    9/03 Note to readers of The Terrible, Horrible, No Good, Very Bad Truth about Morality and What to Do About it, Doctoral Dissertation of Joshua D. Greene in the Department of Philosophy, Princeton University, June 2002. You are welcome to read this work, pass it on to others, and cite it. I only ask that if you pass on this work to someone else that it be passed on (1) in its entirety, (2) without modification, and (3) along with this note. I consider this a work in progress. It is currently under review in its present form at an academic press. I intend to revise and expand it substantially before publishing it as a book, so much so that the book and the dissertation will probably best be considered separate works. Comments are welcome. You can contact me by email ([email protected]) or by regular mail: Joshua Greene Department of Psychology Princeton University Princeton, NJ 08544 jdg THE TERRIBLE, HORRIBLE, NO GOOD, VERY BAD TRUTH ABOUT MORALITY AND WHAT TO DO ABOUT IT Joshua David Greene A DISSERTATION PRESENTED TO THE FACULTY OF PRINCETON UNIVERSITY IN CANDIDACY FOR THE DEGREE OF DOCTOR OF PHILOSOPHY RECOMMENDED FOR ACCEPTANCE BY THE DEPARTMENT OF PHILOSOPHY NOVEMBER 2002 © Copyright by Joshua David Greene, 2002. All rights reserved. ii Abstract In this essay I argue that ordinary moral thought and language is, while very natural, highly counterproductive and that as a result we would be wise to change the way we think and talk about moral matters. First, I argue on metaphysical grounds against moral realism, the view according to which there are first order moral truths.
    [Show full text]
  • 2014-PDF-Of-Philosophy-News
    UNIVERSITY OF TORONTO DEPARTMENT OF PHILOSO PHY FALL 2014 IAN HACKI NG WSEI E NPAGS E 3BALZAN PRIZ E! PRACT ICAL ETH ICS – SHEL LY KAG AN ON SPECIESISM By Ellen Roseman Shelly Kagan, the Clark Professor of Philosophy at Yale University, drew a capacity crowd to the Roseman Lecture in Practical Ethics last fall. He is an engaging, funny and whip- smart speaker. And he chose an intriguing topic, one that is not usually explored in mainstream philosophy courses. The title: What’s wrong with speciesism? In a bestselling 1975 book, Animal Liberation , Australian philosopher Peter Singer claimed that most of us Shelly Kagan with Ellen Roseman are “speciesists” in our attitude toward, and treatment of, animals. Singer, now a bioethics professor than persuasive. “People have rights. Animals don’t,” he tells Speciesism is supposed to be a kind at Princeton University, created me after the lecture. “There’s a of morally unjustified prejudice, akin a splash when he called for an huge crowd of people working to racism or sexism, Kagan said in animal rights movement. Kagan on this issue. I thought a lot of his notes for the lecture. “Although read the book while in graduate the arguments were weak.” I found that charge compelling for school. He became a vegetarian. years, I now find that I have my But in a second reading of the Kagan thinks the crucial concept doubts,” he explained. “It now seems book in 2011, while preparing is to define the meaning of a to me that most people are not actu - to give an animal ethics seminar “person.” Going back to British ally speciesists at all, but something to Yale students, Kagan found philosopher John Locke’s work rather different.” some of Singer’s arguments less ...continued on Page 2 We wish to thank the generous donors to the Department of Philosophy, without whom Philosophy News would not be possible.
    [Show full text]
  • The Moral Self: a Review and Integration of the Literature
    The IRIOP Annual Review Journal of Organizational Behavior, J. Organiz. Behav. 36, S104–S168 (2015) Published online 20 February 2014 in Wiley Online Library (wileyonlinelibrary.com) DOI: 10.1002/job.1919 The moral self: A review and integration of the literature PETER L. JENNINGS1*,†, MARIE S. MITCHELL2† AND SEAN T. HANNAH3 1Leavey School of Business, Santa Clara University, Santa Clara, California, U.S.A. 2Terry College of Business, University of Georgia, Athens, Georgia, U.S.A. 3School of Business, Wake Forest University, Winston-Salem, North Carolina, U.S.A. Summary The role of the self in moral functioning has gained considerable theoretical and empirical attention over the last 25 years. A general consensus has emerged that the self plays a vital role in individuals’ moral agency. This surge of research produced a proliferation of constructs related to the moral self, each grounded in diverse theoretical perspectives. Although this work has advanced our understanding of moral thought and behavior, there has also been a lack of clarity as to the nature and functioning of the moral self. We review and synthesize empirical research related to the moral self and provide an integrative framework to increase conceptual coherence among the various relevant constructs. We then discuss emerging opportunities and future directions for research on the moral self as well as implications for behavioral ethics in organizational contexts. Copyright © 2014 John Wiley & Sons, Ltd. Keywords: moral self; moral identity centrality; moral judgment disposition; self-conscious moral orientation; self-conscious moral emotions; moral strength; moral functioning The corruption and scandals that have plagued organizations in recent years have prompted significant interest in the study of ethical work behavior.
    [Show full text]
  • Gibbard, Allan
    ThinkingH ow to Live with Each Other ALLAN GibbARD The Tanner Lectures on Human Values Delivered at TheU niversity of California, Berkeley February 28–March 2, 2006 Allan Gibbard is Richard Brandt Distinguished University Professor of Philosophy at the University of Michigan. He graduated from Swarth- more College and received his Ph.D. from Harvard University. He taught at Achimota School in Ghana while in the Peace Corps, and at the Uni- versity of Chicago and the University of Pittsburgh. He has also been a visiting professor at Stanford University. He is a member of the American Philosophical Society and a fellow of the American Academy of Arts and Sciences. He has served as president of the Central Division of the Ameri- can Philosophical Society. His many publications include Manipulation of Voting Schemes: A General Result (1973); Wise Choices, Apt Feelings: A Theory of Normative Judgment (1990); Moral Discourse and Practice (co- editor with Stephen Darwall and Peter Railton, 1997); and ThinkingH ow to Live (2003). I. INSight, CONSISTENCY, AND PLANS FOR LiviNG Jonathan Haidt, the social psychologist, entitles a fascinating article “The Emotional Dog and Its Rational Tail.” His topic is moral judgment, and the emotional dog is what he calls “intuition.” Mostly, he argues, we don’t arrive at our moral conclusions by reasoning. We jump to them with emo- tional judgments, with “affectively valenced intuitions,” as he puts it. We will often be firmly convinced that our moral judgments rest on sound reasoning, and that unless others are driven by bias, they will appreciate the force of our arguments.
    [Show full text]
  • Ethics and the Future -- Assigned Readings
    Ethics and the Future -- Assigned Readings Note: This is a list of the readings that I assigned (or recommended) to the students (a mix of undergraduates and graduate students) for my seminar, “Ethics and the Future,” taught at Yale in Spring 2021. As the reading list was prepared only for the students in the course, I’m afraid I didn’t include links for any papers that I was including in the course pack, though I believe all of these readings can be easily found online, with the exception, of course, of Ord’s The Precipice, and Parfit’s Reasons and Persons. I am making the reading list publicly available at the request of Pablo Stafforini. In choosing suitable readings I was aided tremendously by the list of readings selected by William MacAskill and Christian Tarsney for their own seminar taught at Oxford in 2019, and especially by the potential syllabus that Joshua Monrad wrote up for my benefit. (Since it was Joshua who rightly insisted to me that this would make an interesting and important topic for a seminar, I am doubly in his debt.) The readings are organized by topic. We spent a week on each. --Shelly Kagan Background on Existential Risks: 1. Toby Ord, The Precipice, Chapters 3-6 and Appendices C and D (about 124 pages) The Basic Case for Longtermism: 1. Perhaps start with this very brief overview: Todd, “Future Generations and Their Moral Significance” (about 7 pages), which can be found online at: https://80000hours.org/articles/future-generations/ 2. Then look at the somewhat longer (but still breezy) exposition in Ord, The Precipice, Intro and Chapters 1-2, and Appendix E (65 pgs.) 3.
    [Show full text]
  • The Psychology of Moral Reasoning
    Judgment and Decision Making, Vol. 3, No. 2, February 2008, pp. 121–139 The psychology of moral reasoning Monica Bucciarelli∗ Centro di Scienza Cognitiva and Dipartimento di Psicologia University of Turin Sangeet Khemlani and P. N. Johnson-Laird Department of Psychology Princeton University Abstract This article presents a theory of reasoning about moral propositions that is based on four fundamental principles. First, no simple criterion picks out propositions about morality from within the larger set of deontic propositions con- cerning what is permissible and impermissible in social relations, the law, games, and manners. Second, the mechanisms underlying emotions and deontic evaluations are independent and operate in parallel, and so some scenarios elicit emo- tions prior to moral evaluations, some elicit moral evaluations prior to emotions, and some elicit them at the same time. Third, deontic evaluations depend on inferences, either unconscious intuitions or conscious reasoning. Fourth, human beliefs about what is, and isn’t, moral are neither complete nor consistent. The article marshals the evidence, which includes new studies, corroborating these principles, and discusses the relations between them and other current theories of moral reasoning. Keywords: moral reasoning; deontic reasoning; intuitions; inferences; moral dilemmas. 1 Introduction principal psychological theories of how individuals make moral evaluations. We then describe the new theory. We Is it morally wrong to take a paper-clip from your office? present the evidence corroborating it, including some new Is it morally wrong to steal money from your co-worker? experimental results. Finally, we consider the general na- Is it morally wrong to stab your employer? In the ab- ture of reasoning about moral propositions.
    [Show full text]