War Rights and Military Virtues: a Philosophical Re-Appraisal of Just War Theory

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

War Rights and Military Virtues: a Philosophical Re-Appraisal of Just War Theory The University of Notre Dame Australia ResearchOnline@ND Theses 2014 War rights and military virtues: A philosophical re-appraisal of Just War Theory Matthew T. Beard University of Notre Dame Australia Follow this and additional works at: https://researchonline.nd.edu.au/theses Part of the Philosophy Commons COMMONWEALTH OF AUSTRALIA Copyright Regulations 1969 WARNING The material in this communication may be subject to copyright under the Act. Any further copying or communication of this material by you may be the subject of copyright protection under the Act. Do not remove this notice. Publication Details Beard, M. T. (2014). War rights and military virtues: A philosophical re-appraisal of Just War Theory (Doctor of Philosophy (PhD)). University of Notre Dame Australia. https://researchonline.nd.edu.au/theses/96 This dissertation/thesis is brought to you by ResearchOnline@ND. It has been accepted for inclusion in Theses by an authorized administrator of ResearchOnline@ND. For more information, please contact [email protected]. War Rights and Military Virtues A Philosophical Re-appraisal of Just War Theory Doctoral Thesis Prepared by Matthew T. Beard School of Philosophy and Theology University of Notre Dame, Australia Supervised by Christian Enemark and Hayden Ramsay Supported by The Morris Research Scholarship Declaration I, Matthew Thomas Beard, declare that this PhD thesis, entitled War Rights and Military Virtues: A Philosophical Re-appraisal of Just War Theory is no more than 100,000 words exclusive of title pages, table of contents, acknowledgements, list of figures, reference list, and footnotes. The thesis is my own original work, prepared for the specific and unique purposes of this academic degree and has not been submitted in whole or part for the awarding of any other academic degree at any institution. Where work is not my own original contribution, it has been referenced appropriately. Matthew Thomas Beard 30/5/14 i Abstract The overwhelming majority of theorists addressing questions of the morality of war do so from within the moral framework provided by Just War Theory (JWT): a normative account of war that dates back over 1500 years in the Western Tradition. However, today’s iterations of Just War Theory are markedly different from those of its intellectual ancestors. Specifically, today’s accounts tend not to consider matters of moral virtue, personal excellence, moral psychology, or human flourishing – that is, aretaic matters – to be worthy subjects of discussion. Instead, they prefer to focus overtly on questions of law, justice, and human rights – deontological questions – as if they were the entire purview of a comprehensive morality of war. I explore some of the major theorists in the history of Western JWT, showing that the ancestors of today’s just war theories did consider aretaic matters – in particular the moral virtues – to be of central importance to the morality of war. I also show how and why it came to be that deontological and aretaic discussions became fragmented in contemporary JWT. In order to demonstrate how this fragmentation is problematic, I consider deontological ethics’ connection to aretaic ethics. I explain how contemporary JWT tends to conceptualise rights, emphasising the central place of intention in those theories. I show how aretaic ethics can enrich deontological appraisals of ongoing debates in military ethics. ii Finally, I make a positive case for aretaic ethics by identifying new questions that aretaic ethics reveals to JWT, those being: the complexity of the identity of soldiers, how moral character and identity can help prevent moral transgressions, and the moral and psychological trauma suffered by many soldiers and veterans. I argue that aretaic modes of thinking help to explain moral transgressions of soldiers and the psychological difficulties that veterans can experience post-war. Deontological and aretaic ethics also interact in the three professions most relevant to waging war: soldiers, commanders, and political leaders. I show how the virtues are necessary character traits in order to guarantee that warfighters and their political leaders can be relied on to fulfil their professional duties. Aretaic ethical analysis is also able to provide conceptual understanding of supererogatory actions. Contemporary just war theorists would be wise to re-integrate aretaic ethics into their considerations of the morality of war. Aretaic ethics can be combined seamlessly and productively with deontological ethics, yielding more robust and intelligible responses to the most pressing controversies facing military ethics today. Rights and deontology present crucial elements of the ethics war, but they can be ably complemented by insights from aretaic ethics; specifically, matters of character and the moral development of the agent. Furthermore, incorporating aretaic ethics into JWT enables theorists to utilise that framework to consider matters currently outside of its purview, but which are of growing relevance to military practice. iii Acknowledgements This thesis has been three-and-a-half years in the making, and I am not the same man today that I was when it began. I am, however, all the better for having written it. This thesis could not have been completed without the generous support of Mr. Karl Morris. Karl’s generosity led to the creation of the Morris Scholarship for Ethics, of which I was the inaugural recipient. I am extremely grateful for Karl’s financial support, but also for his interest in the progress of my thesis and the development of my ideas. I offer my thanks to my supervisors, Christian Enemark and Hayden Ramsay. Christian accepted the role of supervisor at the beginning of 2013 when my thoughts were at their least coherent. That I completed a thesis at all – irrespective of quality – is testament to Christian’s kindness, wisdom and professionalism. Thanks are also due for Christian’s continual efforts to ground my philosophical hand-wavings in the empirical realities of war and military practice: this thesis is much more grounded for the expertise and advice provided in marathon meetings in Canberra and over Skype! Hayden has been my mentor and friend since my philosophical studies began in 2008. He has been a source of constancy, stability and reason throughout the writing of this thesis. Most of all, his philosophical demeanour and spirit iv have been sources of inspiration and example that I have (perhaps embarrassingly) sought to replicate. To those who proof-read this thesis in part or in full, Elle Glynn, Nick Evans, and Jenn Edgar, thank you. My apologies if I was unable to make all the changes you recommended. My work is much stronger for your help. Academic support is only a small part of what it takes to complete a thesis. Immense thanks are due to my parents, Mark and Jane, and siblings, Bec, Andrew, Nathan, Rachel and Emily, for their love, support, hilarity and distraction for the duration of this. Thanks also to my future in-laws, Garth, Sandra and Michelle for their interest, love and support. To my colleagues at the Centre for Faith, Ethics & Society, Sandra Lynch and Elle Glynn, thank you for tolerating my occasional madness, providing wonderful sounding-boards for my ideas, and allowing me to balance the demands of my employment and scholarship. Without you both, the last shred of my sanity would be long gone. My life writing this thesis has been a paradox. Whilst my mind, readings and writings have been occupied with war, death and sorrow, I have enjoyed the most surreal peace I’ve ever known. To Jennifer Edgar – soon to be Jennifer Beard – who was a stranger when this thesis begun and will be my wife before it is awarded, I offer my deepest and most sincere thanks. You have been my Helen and my Andromache – my comfort and my compass, my motivation and my salvation, my peace and my joy – since the day I met you. Thank you for making this work the second most important project in my life, and v especially for helping me in the final week before submission, when I couldn’t help myself. In particular I acknowledge my late Grandfather, Leading Shipman Robert George McNamara, who served in the Royal Australian Navy from 1947-1970. Pop, like so many others, wore his duty with silent, stoic pride. The pride he took in his service and his country was matched only by the love he held for his family. Finally, I acknowledge those for whom this thesis actually promises to be of some assistance: those for whom war is a practical reality and for whom peace is far rarer than it has been for me. I hope that, in some way, my work may be of service. At my grandfather’s funeral, a member of the local RSL branch recited the following verses. The first speaks of peace, the second of safety. It seems to me that more can be done to provide both to soldiers, veterans, and all those responsible for decision-making in times of war. O valiant hearts who to your Eternal Father, strong to save, glory came Whose arm hath bound the restless Through dust of conflict and wave, through battle flame; Who bidd'st the mighty ocean deep Tranquil you lie, your knightly Its own appointed limits keep; virtue proved, Oh, hear us when we cry to Thee, Your memory hallowed in the For those in peril on the sea! land you loved. - Eternal Father, Strong to Save - Oh Valiant Hearts vi Table of Contents Chapter One – Introduction 1 1 Approaches to Moral Philosophy 3 2 Just War Theory 17 3 Thesis Rationale, Content and Purpose 34 4 Conclusion 40 Chapter Two – Just War
Recommended publications
  • Thinking, Relating and Choosing: Resolving the Issue of Faith, Ethics and the Existential Responsibility of the Individual
    Indo-Pacific Journal of Phenomenology, Volume 9, Edition 2 October 2009 Page 1 of 5 Personal Reflection Thinking, Relating and Choosing: Resolving the Issue of Faith, Ethics and the Existential Responsibility of the Individual by Neil Alan Soggie Abstract Which is worse: Doing evil or being evil? If we are free to define ourselves through our choices, as existentialism posits, then the latter is worse. This paper attempts to resolve the issue of the difference between religious (group) ethics and the ethics of a person of faith that embraces individuals with an existential understanding. In the existential view, the individual (whether the self or the other) is the primary concern, and so the issue of personal relational morality supersedes religious narratives, social morality and popular ethics (White, 2002). If we think and choose, there is the possibility that we may occasionally make a mistake and do evil. However, if we do not think about our choices, and if the conventions we hold happen to be flawed in some way, then we become defined by a continual cycle of mistakes. Existentialism teaches that we become who we are in the process of making choices; therefore the difference between doing evil and being evil can be found in the small but important flow of thinking, relating and choosing. I was visiting with friends recently, and their In fact, it has been my experience that many people observations and comments sparked angst within my who embrace existentialism (in one form or another) soul. For this reason, I am writing on this topic of the are people of faith (Evans, 1995; Tillich, 1990; Wong, ethical life, whatever that may mean, and in so far as 1989; Wong & Fry, 1998).
    [Show full text]
  • Professional Ethics: Responsible Practice in the Professions
    Society for Ethics Across the Curriculum 13th International Conference on Ethics Across the Curriculum Professional Ethics: Responsible Practice in the Professions Saint Louis, Missouri November 3 – 5, 2011 Directors Donna J. Werner (St. Louis Community College) Jeanne Sokolec (Loyola University Chicago) Society for Ethics Across the Curriculum The purpose of the Society for Ethics Across the Curriculum is to stimulate scholarship on ethics and the teaching of ethics in all academic disciplines and to afford an opportunity for the exchange of research. President Dan Wueste (Clemson University) Executive Committee: Doug Chismar (Ringling College of Art and Design) Deborah Mower (Youngstown State University) Lisa Newton (Fairfield University) Wade Robison (Rochester Institute of Technology) Stephen Satris (Clemson University) Stephen Scales (Towson University) Jeanne Sokolec (Loyola University Chicago) Kelly Smith (Clemson University) Secretary-Treasurer Donna Werner (St Louis Community College) Editors of Teaching Ethics Elaine Englehardt (Utah Valley University) & Michael Pritchard (Western Michigan University) Special thanks to the following institutions for their generous support of SEAC: Dr. James Dale Ethics Center, Youngstown State University Center for the Study of Ethics, Utah Valley University Ezra A. Hale Chair in Applied Ethics, Rochester Institute of Technology Robert J. Rutland Institute for Ethics, Clemson University Program in Applied Ethics, Fairfield University Center for the Study of Ethics in Society, Western Michigan University Young Harris College Georgia Military College Special thanks to the following individuals for their generous support of the 2011 conference: Ellen Harshman, Dean of the John Cook School of Business at Saint Louis University Donna Dare, Vice Chancellor for Academic and Student Affairs, St.
    [Show full text]
  • The National Association of Social Workers (NASW) Code of Ethics
    The National Association of Social Workers (NASW) The Code offers a set of values, principles, and standards to guide decision making and conduct when ethical issues arise. It does not provide a set of rules Code of Ethics that prescribe how social workers should act in all situations. Specific applications of the Code must take into account the context in which it is being considered and the possibility of conflicts among the Code’s values, principles, Preamble and standards. Ethical responsibilities flow from all human relationships, from the personal and familial to the social and professional. The primary mission of the social work profession is to enhance human well- being and help meet basic human needs of all people, with particular attention Further, the NASW Code of Ethics does not specify which values, principles, and to the needs and empowerment of people who are vulnerable, oppressed, and standards are most important and ought to outweigh others in instances when living in poverty. A historic and defining feature of social work is the they conflict. Reasonable differences of opinion can and do exist among social profession’s focus on individual well-being in a social context and the well- workers with respect to the ways in which values, ethical principles, and ethical being of society. Fundamental to social work is attention to the environmental standards should be rank ordered when they conflict. Ethical decision making in forces that create, contribute to, and address problems in living. a given situation must apply the informed judgment of the individual social worker and should also consider how the issues would be judged in a peer Social workers promote social justice and social change with and on behalf of review process where the ethical standards of the profession would be applied.
    [Show full text]
  • Altruism–Self-Interest Archetypes
    Altruism–Self-Interest Archetypes: A Paradigmatic Narrative of Counseling The Professional Counselor VolumeVolume 3, Issue 3, Issue 2, Pages 2, Pages 54–66 – Professionals http://tpcjournal.nbcc.org http://tpcjournal.nbcc.org © 2013 NBCC, Inc. and Affiliates doi:10.15241/svf.3.2.54 Stephen V. Flynn Linda L. Black The quality of the therapeutic relationship and the personal characteristics of professional counselors are key determinants of positive counseling outcomes and decision making, and they are believed to be influenced by conscious and unconscious processes. Beliefs about the unconscious nature of altruism and self-interest among 25 mental health professionals were examined through a paradigmatic narrative analysis. Data from 19 semi-structured individual interviews, one focus group, 19 artifacts and participant member checks were subjected to a secondary qualitative analysis. The results of the analysis generated three salient archetypes representative of the altruism–self-interest dynamic: exocentric altruist, endocentric altruist, and psychological egoist. Keywords: professional counselors, altruism, self-interest, archetype, qualitative, paradigmatic narrative analysis The constructs altruism and self-interest have long been described in dichotomous terms and as the sole motivators of human behavior (Holmes, Miller, & Lerner, 2002; Simpson, Irwin, & Lawrence, 2006). In 1851, Comte defined the term altruism as “self-sacrifice for the benefit of others” (1875/2001, p. 565). More than a century later, Sober (1993) defined self-interest as “the sole fixation on gaining pleasure and avoiding pain.” Because these two constructs typically have been associated with individuals’ actions and viewed through a polarized lens, there is a dearth of research examining the unified and unconscious nature of both altruism and self- interest (Bishop, 2000).
    [Show full text]
  • Deontological Ethics
    DEONTOLOGICAL ETHICS “FROM THE CROOKED TIMBER OF HUMANITY, NOTHING WHOLLY STRAIGHT CAN BE MADE.” – Immanuel Kant (1724-1804) [47] DUTY AND THE GOOD WILL Immanuel Kant (1724-1804) wrote prolifically on a wide range of subjects, most fa- mously on epistemology and the limits of human reason in his Critique of Pure Reason (1781). But he is also well known for his moral philosophy, and here he wants to ex- plain the feeling that many of us have that certain actions are required or prohibited of us absolutely, unconditionally, without exception. For instance, many people feel that they are absolutely prohibited from torturing or killing innocent human beings no matter what, even if the whole world depended upon it. Now, what could be the source of such an unyielding sense of obligation? It does not appear to be our desire for some consequence of our action or omission, for we find the action or omission to be right or wrong in itself, independent of the consequences. I simply see that it is wrong to take innocent life, and I avoid it not because I fear going to jail, nor because I fear public criticism, nor because I am merely disinclined to kill the innocent, but because it is morally wrong. One might think this obligation is nothing more than a strong, emotion-laden inclination resulting from previous conditioning and perhaps our biological nature. But Kant suggests it has instead to do with the nature of reason itself, that reason is the source of this obligation and feeling of duty. Kant discovers in our reason a moral principle called the Categorical Imperative, which he uses to discover more specific, lower-level moral laws or duties (also called “categorical imperatives” or “moral imperatives” or “impera- tives of duty”), and it becomes our self-imposed duty to follow these moral laws.
    [Show full text]
  • Classical Ethics in A/IS
    The IEEE Global Initiative on Ethics of Autonomous and Intelligent Systems Classical Ethics in A/IS We applied classical ethics methodologies to considerations of algorithmic design in autonomous and intelligent systems (A/IS) where machine learning may or may not reflect ethical outcomes that mimic human decision-making. To meet this goal, we drew from classical ethics theories and the disciplines of machine ethics, information ethics, and technology ethics. As direct control over tools becomes further removed, creators of autonomous systems must ask themselves how cultural and ethical presumptions bias artificially intelligent creations. Such introspection is more necessary than ever because the precise and deliberate design of algorithms in self-sustained digital systems will result in responses based on such design. By drawing from over two thousand years’ worth of classical ethics traditions, we explore established ethics systems, including both philosophical traditions (utilitarianism, virtue ethics, and deontological ethics) and religious and culture-based ethical systems (Buddhism, Confucianism, African Ubuntu traditions, and Japanese Shinto) and their stance on human morality in the digital age.1 In doing so, we critique assumptions around concepts such as good and evil, right and wrong, virtue and vice, and we attempt to carry these inquiries into artificial systems’ decision-making processes. Through reviewing the philosophical foundations that define autonomy and ontology, we address the potential for autonomous capacity of artificially intelligent systems, posing questions of morality in amoral systems and asking whether decisions made by amoral systems can have moral consequences. Ultimately, we address notions of responsibility and accountability for the decisions made by autonomous systems and other artificially intelligent technologies.
    [Show full text]
  • Ciceronian Business Ethics Owen Goldin Marquette University, [email protected]
    Marquette University e-Publications@Marquette Philosophy Faculty Research and Publications Philosophy, Department of 11-1-2006 Ciceronian Business Ethics Owen Goldin Marquette University, [email protected] Published version. Studies in the History of Ethics (November 2006). Publisher link. © 2006 HistoryofEthics.org. Used with permission. Studies in the History of Ethics Ciceronian Bu siness Ethics Owen Goldin (Mar quette University) The teaching and practice of business must resist ethical compartmentalization. One engaged in business ought not check moral principles at the door and say “business is business,” for this is to pretend that when one is engaged in business, one is no longer a human being, with the rational nature, emotional constitution, and social bonds that are at the root of our ethical nature. Ethical standards apply to business as they do all aspects of human life. Nonetheless, making money is the goal of business, and more often than not, one is trying to take money from another, at the least possible cost. Such action is necessarily self-centered, if not selfish, and requires acting in a way that we would not want to see people act in all of their dealings with others, especially in regard to family, friends, and others with whom they have special social bonds. Granting that business practices are not compartmentalized against all ethical considerations, the fact that business demands maximization of profit entails that special rules apply. Determining what these are, in what circumstances they are less demanding than the ethical principles of everyday life, and in what circumstances they are more demanding, is the domain of business ethics, as a special domain of ethical philosophy.
    [Show full text]
  • Deontological Ethics the Many”
    1st Asian Workshop on the Ethical Dimensions of the Radiological Protection System Daejeon, Korea 2013 August 27-28 Christopher Clement ICRP Scientific Secretary ICRP develops and maintains the system of radiological protection based on SCIENCE, VALUES and EXPERIENCE Scientific and philosophical understanding are fundamental, but as means not ends ICRP uses science and philosophy 2 “The unexamined life is not worth living” (Socrates, in Plato’s “Apology”) Perhaps extreme, but one cannot know if a life is worth living without examining it. The unexamined system of radiological protection is not worth using Examining the system of radiological protection we gain a deeper understanding, see if it is serving its intended purpose, and perhaps improve upon it. 3 A structured What is there? approach to Metaphysics asking and answering questions What is How should known or one behave? knowable? Ethics Epistemology 4 What is the true nature of existence? Can anything can really be known? Do we have free will? Are good and right fundamental properties, or social constructions? 5 — Value — Why are ethical values important? — What makes something good or bad, right or wrong? — Characteristics of values — Examples — CHALLENGE: A pragmatic way forward 6 Questions and Statements of Fact — 214Bi emits a 609 keV photon upon decay. — How does ionising radiation interact with the body? — Iodine collects principally in the thyroid. Questions and Statements of Value — Children should be protected more than adults. — What is an acceptable lifetime risk? — The environment should be protected. 7 Fact — What is — Questions of science — Descriptive statements Value — What ought to be — Ethical questions — Normative statements 8 The “is-ought” problem Described by Scottish philosopher David Hume (1711– 76) in “A Treatise of Human Nature” (1739) It is impossible to derive statements of value (what ought to be) from statements of fact (what is) 9 I have been bitten by a Doses of radiation above poisonous snake.
    [Show full text]
  • Professional Ethics 1.9
    CANDIDATE GUIDE PROFESSIONAL ETHICS OUTCOME 8 T ABLE OF CONTENTS PAGE NO. CANDIDATE INFORMATION 4 COMPETENCY STANDARD REQUIREMENTS 5 KEYS TO ICONS 6 GENERAL GUIDELINES 7 CANDIDATE SUPPORT 9 SECTION 1: AN INTRODUCTION TO THE CONCEPT OF ETHICS AND 10 ETHICAL BEHAVIOUR 1.1. What are Ethics? 1.2. Value Systems 1.3. A Brief History of Ethics 1.4. Ethics Definitions 1.5. Key Concepts 1.6. Ethics Alarms 1.7. Importance of Ethical Conduct in Business 1.8. Professional Ethics 1.9. Ethical Issues Facing Engineers 1.10. Code of Ethics 1.11. SAIMechE‟s Code of Conduct INITIAL TEST 2 SECTION 2: PRACTICAL ETHICAL DECISION MAKING MODEL AS 37 PER THE ASSESSMENT CRITERIA 2.1. Introduction 2.2. Steps in Ethical Decision Making STEP 1: Define the Ethical Problem STEP 2: Identify Affected Parties STEP 3: Explore Optional Solutions STEP 4: Evaluate Solutions STEP 5: Select and Justify a Solution ASSESSMENT TEST SECTION 3: GENERIC GUIDELINES: LEARNING OUTCOMES AND 57 ASSESSMENT CRITERIA ARE THE GUIDING PRINCIPLES OF PROFESSIONAL PRACTICE APPENDICES 59 REFERENCES 70 RECORDING OF REPORTS 73 ASSESSMENT PROCESS 74 3 CANDIDATE INFORMATION Details Please Complete details Name of candidate Name of supervisor Work Unit Name of mentor Date started Date of completion & Assessment 4 COMPETENCY STANDARD REQUIREMENTS (Direct extract from SAIMechE‟s Standard of Professional Competency (SPC)) LEARNING OUTCOME 8 Conduct his or her engineering activities ethically. Assessment Criteria: The candidate is expected to be sensitive to ethical issues and adopt a systematic approach to resolving these issues, typified by: 1. Identify the central ethical problem; 2.
    [Show full text]
  • When the Kingdom of God Became the Kingdom of Ends: Altruism’S Development Into a Normative Ideal
    When the Kingdom of God Became the Kingdom of Ends: Altruism’s Development into a Normative Ideal A Senior Honor Thesis Presented in partial fulfillment of the requirements for graduation with distinction in Political Science in the College of Social and Behavioral Sciences by Benjamin T. Jones The Ohio State University December 10, 2006 Project Advisors: John M. Parrish, Department of Political Science (Loyola Marymount University) Michael A. Neblo, Department of Political Science (The Ohio State University) Table of Contents Abstract ii Acknowledgements iii Introduction 1 The Paradox at the Heart of Altruism 4 Defining Altruism and Normativity 6 What Are We Looking For? 11 Roadmap of What’s to Come 14 Part I Towards a Problem: The Ancient Debate over Public Life 17 Eudaimonia and Ancient Ethics 18 Plato and Aristotle 24 Epicurus and the Stoics 40 A Solution from an Unlikely Source 47 Augustine’s Reconciliation of the Two Cities 55 Conclusion 63 Part II Self-Love’s Fall from Grace: How Normative Altruism Developed out of the Augustinian Tradition 65 Entangled in Self-love: Augustine’s Normative Argument 67 Augustine Goes Secular 75 Kant’s Problematic Solution 83 Reworking Kant—And Altruism 89 Conclusion 91 Part III The Problems with Normative Altruism 93 Two Conceptions of Altruism 93 Evidence for Altruism on a Descriptive Level 95 Motivational Barriers to Normative Altruism 113 Changing the Way We Talk About Altruism 121 Conclusion 126 Bibliography 131 i Abstract In contemporary moral philosophy, altruism holds a place of prominence. Although a complex idea, the term seeps into everyday discourse, by no means confined to the esoteric language of philosophers and psychologists.
    [Show full text]
  • Is Bioethics a Profession? Craig M
    Online Journal of Health Ethics Volume 5 | Issue 2 Article 6 Is Bioethics A Profession? Craig M. Klugman Ph.D. University of Nevada Reno, [email protected] Follow this and additional works at: http://aquila.usm.edu/ojhe Recommended Citation Klugman, C. M. (2008). Is Bioethics A Profession?. Online Journal of Health Ethics, 5(2). http://dx.doi.org/10.18785/ojhe.0502.06 This Article is brought to you for free and open access by The Aquila Digital Community. It has been accepted for inclusion in Online Journal of Health Ethics by an authorized administrator of The Aquila Digital Community. For more information, please contact [email protected]. Running head: BIOETHICS 1 Is Bioethics A Profession? Craig M. Klugman, Ph.D. Associate Professor of Bioethics and Medical Humanities University of Nevada Reno [email protected] Abstract The development of an occupation into a profession is an historical process that concerns power, jurisdiction, social contracts, and economic interests. Sociological theories of professionalization view these developments through perspectives of superior work, pay for performance, historical processes, jurisdictional disputes, struggles of social and economic power, and virtues. This essay explores these theories and examines the field of bioethics through each of these lenses looking at such issues amateur versus professional, education, professional organizations, specialized knowledge, code of ethics, jurisdiction, work sites, work focus, research, socialization, professional autonomy, licensure, legislation, and prestige. Bioethics is seen as falling in the middle of Goode’s “profession continuum.” While bioethics has adopted some of the necessary characteristics of a profession, having those elements is not a sufficient condition to being a profession.
    [Show full text]
  • Modern Moral Conscience
    Modern Moral Conscience Tom O’Shea Forthcoming in International Journal of Philosophical Studies Abstract: This article challenges the individualism and neutrality of modern moral conscience. It looks to the history of the concept to excavate an older tradition that takes conscience to be social and morally responsive, while arguing that dominant contemporary justifications of conscience in terms of integrity are inadequate without reintroducing these social and moral traits. This prompts a rethinking of the nature and value of conscience: first, by demonstrating that a morally-responsive conscience is neither a contradiction in terms nor a political absurdity; second, by suggesting how a morally-responsive conscience can be informed by the social world without being a mere proxy for social power or moribund tradition. 1. The idea of conscience underwent a gradual hollowing out during modernity. Our now- dominant conceptions of conscience have sundered it from both social relationships and ethical truths which outrun each individual’s convictions. We have yet to properly reckon with the implications of this shift towards an egocentric and normatively neutral understanding of conscience. My aim is to excavate an older tradition without these two traits and to ask what we may have lost by leaving it behind. While this will reveal a challenge to modern moral conscience, there remain formidable obstacles to returning to earlier understandings of it. I shall outline a social and normative conception of conscience which learns the lessons of this earlier tradition while showing how it must nevertheless adapt to modern conditions. What then is conscience? Among our oldest moral concepts – recognisable as early as the Greek playwrights of the 5th century BCE – it has long been understood as the self’s awareness of the moral dimension of its conduct (Sorabji 2014, 15).1 Conscience consists in a consciousness of moral demands upon the particular individual in their own specific circumstances rather than a merely abstract knowledge of right and wrong.
    [Show full text]