Theme’ in English: Their Syntax, Semantics and Discourse Functions

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Theme’ in English: Their Syntax, Semantics and Discourse Functions The Many Types of ‘Theme’ in English: their Syntax, Semantics and Discourse Functions Robin P. Fawcett The Many Types of ‘Theme’ in English: their Syntax, Semantics and Discourse Functions Robin P. Fawcett Emeritus Professor of Linguistics Cardiff University This book is being worked on, intermittently, so please forgive any inconsistencies of numbering, etc. I would be very grateful if you felt able to send me your comments and suggestions for improvements, including improvements in clarity. However, plans for publishing this work in this form in the near future have been shelved, as a result of the decision to focus on three other books: Fawcett forthcoming 2009a, forthcoming 2009b and forthcoming 2010 (for which see the References). The last of these will include material from the descriptive portion of the present work. I still intend to bring this work up to book- publishing standard at some point in the near future. Meanwhile I am happy for it to be used and cited, if you wish. CHANGES TO BE MADE Networks derived from Figure 2 will be added at appropriate points throughout. The figure numbers will be changed to start anew for each chapter. Notes comparing this approach with the networks in Halliday and Matthiessen 2004 and Thompson 2004 will be added (noting Thompson’s use of our term ‘enhanced’). Other possible changes (marked by XXX) will be considered. Perhaps I shall add the ‘fact’ that the word beginning with ‘t’ that was looked up most frequently on dictionary.com in 2005 was ‘theme’! Contents Preface 1 Introduction 1.1 Three perspectives on ‘theme’ 1.2 The components of a Systemic Functional Grammar 1.3 Functional syntax: the systems for ‘theme’ viewed ‘from below’ 1.4 Discourse functions: the systems for ‘theme’ viewed ‘from above’ 1.5 The systems for ‘theme’ viewed ‘at their own level’ 1.6 Is there a unified concept of ’theme’? 1.7 The goals of this book 1.8 The role of Figure 2 in this book 2 A selective overview of the literature on ‘theme’ 2.1 The topics to be covered in this overview 2.2 The literature of ‘thematic progression’: a critical survey 2.3 The literature concerning the structures that realize ‘thematic’ meanings 2.4 The literature concerning the discourse purposes expressed in ‘thematic’ meanings and structures 2.5 The literature concerning the semantic systems for ‘thematic’ meanings 3 The many systems for SUBJECT THEME 3.1 The structure of this chapter 3.2 Criteria in assessing system networks 3.3 How many systems are there for SUBJECT THEME? 3.4 Probabilities in systems 3.5 Form and meaning 3.6 The explicit representation of meaning - i.e. semantic features 3.7 The Performer’s discourse purpose in making a Participant Role a Subject Theme 3.8 Some TRANSITIVITY system networks that do not enter the SUBJECT THEME system 4 The many systems for MARKED PARTICIPANT ROLE THEME 4.1 Form and meaning 4.2 More on probabilities on features in systems 4.3 Changing the probabilities in systems 4.4 The units that fill Marked PR Themes 4.5 The Performer’s discourse purposes in making a Participant Role a Marked PR Theme 4.6 Marked PR Themes of Location and Direction: a variant of the construction 5 The thematization of Adjuncts, Vocatives and Main Verb Extensions 5.1 Adjuncts in general 5.2 The form and meaning of a typical circumstantial Adjunct 5.3 The units that fill Adjuncts and the items that expound them 5.4 The many discourse purposes of Adjuncts 5.5 The ‘Respect’ and ‘Topic-marking’ Adjuncts 5.6 The Vocative 5.7 The Main Verb Extension 6 Multiple ‘themes’ 6.1 Halliday’s position on ‘multiple themes’ 6.2 An alternative position 6.3 The problem of the claim that there can be only one ‘experiential’ Theme 6.4 The problem of the claim that initial well and but are Themes 6.5 Summary so far 6.6 The three main sources of ‘multiple themes’ 6.7 From ‘simple Themes’ to ‘thematic structures’ 7 Existential Enhanced Theme 7.1 Form and meaning: a first account 7.2 A variant of the construction 7.3 Form and meaning: a fuller account 7.4 The Performer’s discourse purpose 8 ‘Referent as role in event’ as Subject Theme 8.1 The relationship between this construction and some others 8.2 The form and meaning of the construction: a first account 8.3 Where this construction occurs (1) systemically and (2) structurally 8.4 The problems caused by the established name for this construction 8.5 The form and meaning of the ‘referent as role in event’ construction: a fuller account 8.6 The Performer’s discourse purposes 9 Experiential Enhanced Theme 9.1 The high frequency of this construction 9.2 The problems caused by the established name for this construction 9.3 Form and meaning 9.4 The two basic types 9.5 Three combinations of an experiential enhanced theme and another type of ‘theme’ 9.6 The frequency of ellipted forms of this construction 9.7 The Performer’s discourse purposes 10 Evaluative Enhanced Theme 10.1 Introduction: its place in the system network 10.2 The problems caused by the established name for this construction 10.3 Form and meaning 10.4 An alternative functional explanation of the construction 10.5 Some problematical examples: the case of the case etc. 10.6 The combination of an evaluative experiential enhanced theme with other types of ‘theme’ 10.7 The Performer’s discourse purposes 10.8 Testing the model: variants in the form of the evaluative enhanced theme construction 10.9 Testing the model: variants in the range of ‘evaluative’ meanings in the construction 10.10 Three final possible counter-examples 10.11 Summary 11 Event-relating Enhanced Theme 11.1 Introducing the ‘event-relating’ class of Process 11.2 Form and meaning 11.3 A second type of enhanced theme construction that occurs with ‘event-relating’ Processes 11.4 The Performer’s discourse purposes 12 The four types of Enhanced Theme construction compared 13 A thematized Process and its dependent roles 13.1 Form and meaning 13.2 The Performer’s discourse purposes 14 Cases which some scholars treat as ‘theme’ but which are not 14.1 The basic principle: meaning implies choice 14.2 Elements that ALWAYS come early in the clause: Linkers and Binders 14.3 Elements that ALWAYS come early in the clause: Mood-marking elements 14.4 Elements that ALWAYS come early in the clause: ‘relating out’ expressions 14.5 A Respect Adjunct or a ‘Preposed Theme’? 14.6 Reporting Processes as ‘Marked Themes’? 14.7 Reported texts with direct quotations as ‘Marked PR Themes’? 14.8 Summary 15 Overt and covert Subject Themes 15.1 Two types of covert Subject Theme 15.2 Covertness arising from non-realization 15.3 Covertness arising from ellipsis 15.4 Summary: the importance of this concept 16 Summary: the many types of ‘theme’ Preface Let me begin with two statements, each of which is likely to appear controversial to at least some readers. The first is that the linguist who has made the greatest contribution to our understanding of the nature of language in the last century is Michael Halliday. And the second is that no one - not even Halliday! - should be expected to get everything ‘right’ in the description of a complex phenomenon such as human language at the first attempt - or even to get virtually everything right. Yet this is precisely what many people seem to believe that Halliday has achieved. Indeed, you need to believe this - or something close to it - if you are using the description of English in the second or third edition of IFG (Halliday 1994, Halliday & Matthiessen 2004) as your guide to analyzing texts. The reason is that, if you make a careful, page-by-page comparison between the 1994 edition of IFG and the 2004 edition (as I have done), you will find that the overwhelming majority of the substantive sections of description (as opposed to the examples) are, word for word and paragraph after paragraph, virtually unchanged from the 1994 edition. Moreover, the same relationship holds between the description of English given in the 1994 edition and that in the first edition, which was published over two decades ago, in 1985. So the substantive portions of the third edition are virtually unchanged from the first . One doesn’t expect a completely new grammar from a new edition of a book, of course, but one would normally expect at least SOME significant changes, including changes derived from the work of other scholars working in the same framework. 1 But this general pattern of ‘minimal change’ goes back even further. The first edition of IFG in turn reflects quite closely Halliday’s unpublished An Outlook on Modern English (e.g. as cited in Berry 1975), which was circulating informally in the early 1970s. And Outlook in turn resembles extremely closely the description of English that Halliday was presenting in his lectures in 1970 (e.g. those at University College London, which I attended when working there on my PhD). Thus most of Halliday’s current description of the lexicogrammar of English is essentially as it was in the late 1960s. What are we to infer from this? It is surely that we have here a situation that is either extremely worrying or approaching the miraculous. But which? What makes the fact that Halliday’s description of English has changed so little particularly surprising is the set of three revolutionary changes in his theory of language that he made in the 1970s.
Recommended publications
  • II Levels of Language
    II Levels of language 1 Phonetics and phonology 1.1 Characterising articulations 1.1.1 Consonants 1.1.2 Vowels 1.2 Phonotactics 1.3 Syllable structure 1.4 Prosody 1.5 Writing and sound 2 Morphology 2.1 Word, morpheme and allomorph 2.1.1 Various types of morphemes 2.2 Word classes 2.3 Inflectional morphology 2.3.1 Other types of inflection 2.3.2 Status of inflectional morphology 2.4 Derivational morphology 2.4.1 Types of word formation 2.4.2 Further issues in word formation 2.4.3 The mixed lexicon 2.4.4 Phonological processes in word formation 3 Lexicology 3.1 Awareness of the lexicon 3.2 Terms and distinctions 3.3 Word fields 3.4 Lexicological processes in English 3.5 Questions of style 4 Syntax 4.1 The nature of linguistic theory 4.2 Why analyse sentence structure? 4.2.1 Acquisition of syntax 4.2.2 Sentence production 4.3 The structure of clauses and sentences 4.3.1 Form and function 4.3.2 Arguments and complements 4.3.3 Thematic roles in sentences 4.3.4 Traces 4.3.5 Empty categories 4.3.6 Similarities in patterning Raymond Hickey Levels of language Page 2 of 115 4.4 Sentence analysis 4.4.1 Phrase structure grammar 4.4.2 The concept of ‘generation’ 4.4.3 Surface ambiguity 4.4.4 Impossible sentences 4.5 The study of syntax 4.5.1 The early model of generative grammar 4.5.2 The standard theory 4.5.3 EST and REST 4.5.4 X-bar theory 4.5.5 Government and binding theory 4.5.6 Universal grammar 4.5.7 Modular organisation of language 4.5.8 The minimalist program 5 Semantics 5.1 The meaning of ‘meaning’ 5.1.1 Presupposition and entailment 5.2
    [Show full text]
  • Equative Constructions in World-Wide Perspective
    View metadata, citation and similar papers at core.ac.uk brought to you by CORE provided by ZENODO 1 Equative constructions in world-wide perspective Martin Haspelmath & the Leipzig Equative Constructions Team1 Abstract: In this paper, we report on a world-wide study of equative constructions (‘A is as big as B’) in a convenience sample of 119 languages. From earlier work, it has been known that European languages often have equative constructions based on adverbial relative pronouns that otherwise express degree or manner (‘how’, ‘as’), but we find that this type is rare outside Europe. We divide the constructions that we found into six primary types, four of which have closely corresponding types of comparative constructions (‘A is bigger than B’). An equative construction often consists of five components: a comparee (‘A’), a degree-marker (‘as’), a parameter (‘is big’), a standard-marker (‘as’), and a standard (‘B’). Most frequently, the parameter is the main predicate and the equative sense is expressed by a special standard-marker. But many languages also have a degree-marker, so that we get a construction of the English and French type. Another possibility is for the equality sense to be expressed by a transitive ‘equal’ (or ‘reach’) verb, which may be the main predicate or a secondary predicate. And finally, since the equative construction is semantically symmetrical, it is also possible to “unify” the parameter and the standard in the subject position (‘A and B are equally tall’, or ‘A and B are equal in height’). But no language has only a degree-marker, leaving the standard unmarked.
    [Show full text]
  • The Origin of the Celtic Comparative Type Oir Tressa, MW
    170 R. Schmitt 16: offenbar noch nicht erschienen 14. 17: Het'owm Patmic', Patmowt'iwn T'at'arac' [Hethum der Histori­ ker Geschichte der Tataren] / Getum Patmic, Istorija Tatar / Hetum Patmich, History of Tatars, 4°, 1981, [Vlj, 704 S. (T: Ven~tik 1842; ]3: The Origin of the Celtic Comparative Type Olr. tressa, Bambis Asoti Eganyan; 642-691 Wortliste, Namen und Datlerungen em­ MW Jrech 'stronger' scblieBend; 692-702 Namenliste). 18/1-2: Step'anos Taronec'i Asolik, Patmowt'iwn Tiezerakan [Stepha­ The comparison of adjectives in Celtic presents many interesting fea­ nos von Taraun Asolik, Universalgeschichte] / Stepanos TaroneCl AsohIi<, tures 1, Some of these are structural and grammatical, such as the restric­ Obscaja Istorija / Stepanos Taronetsi Asoghik, General History, 8', 1: tion of the comparative to predicative position and the introdnction of a A-E, 1987 15, [IV], 707 S.; 2: m:-M, 1987 15 , [IV], 683 S. (T: S. Peterburg fourth degree of comparison, the equative, beside the usual positive, 1885; B: Valarsak Arzowmani K 'osyan; I 658-666, II 638-645 Namenhste; comparative and superlative. But there are purely formal peculiarities as 1667-706, II 646--682 Wortliste)15. well. Irregularly compared adjectives are synchronically very conspicuous 19/1-2: Frik, Banastelcowt'yownner [Frik, Gedichte] / Frik, Stihotvo­ in Old Irish and Middle Welsh, and many of the individual irregularities renija / Frik, Poems, 8°,1: A-K, 1986, [IV], 598 S.; 2: H-F, 1987,482 S. that they display are also puzzling from a diachronic point of view. A case (T: Erevan 1941; B: DSxowhi Sowreni Movsisyan; R: Alek'sandr S~mom in point is the Old Irish comparative ending in -a, the origin of which has Margaryan; I 563, II 449 Namenliste; I 564-597, II 450-481 Worthste).
    [Show full text]
  • The Meaning of German Wie in Equative Comparison (Follow-Up of the Project Expressing Similarity, UM 100/1-1)
    Beschreibung des Vorhabens / Project Description The meaning of German wie in equative comparison (follow-up of the project Expressing similarity, UM 100/1-1) Carla Umbach Zentrum für Allgemeine Sprachwissenschaft (ZAS), Berlin Institut für deutsche Sprache und Literatur (ISDL I), Universität Köln Februar 2016 1 State of the art and preliminary work1 Introduction The topic of this proposal is the meaning of German wie in equative comparison including scalar as well as non-scalar cases, cf. (1). The semantics of equatives has up to now been studied nearly exclusively from the perspective of the comparative, excluding non-scalar equatives from the analysis. Moreover, the semantics of equatives has been studied nearly exclusively from the perspective of English, which does not suggest a uniform analysis of scalar and non-scalar cases due to their different forms. In German, both scalar and non-scalar equatives are based on wie-clauses thus calling for a uniform analysis. (1) a. Anna ist so groß wie Berta. 'Anna is as tall as Berta.' b. Anna hat so eine Tasse wie Berta. 'Anna has a mug like Berta's. c. Anna hat so getanzt wie Berta. 'Anna danced like Berta.' In this project, a generalized account of German equatives will be developed including scalar as well as non-scalar cases. The core piece of this account is (i) the idea that equatives express similarity, that is, indistinguishability with respect to a given set of features and (ii) that this results from the meaning of the standard marker wie, which is not semantically empty (as assumed in standard degree semantics) but has a meaning of its own.
    [Show full text]
  • Similatives and the Argument Structure of Verbs∗
    Similatives and the argument structure of verbs∗ Jessica Rett May 2012 Abstract I begin with the observation in Haspelmath and Buchholz (1998) that languages tend to use the same morpheme to mark the standard of comparison across equation constructions. In English, it is the morpheme as, in similatives like John danced as Sue (did) and equatives like John is as tall as Sue (is). The first goal of this paper is to provide an analysis of as that accounts for its distribution across these constructions. The second goal of this paper is to provide an account of Haspelmath and Buchholz's second observation, which is that while languages can form equatives with parameter markers (the first as in John is as tall as Sue (is)), languages generally do not form similatives with parameter markers. I suggest that equation constructions are a test for lexicalized argumenthood, i.e. that the equation of a non-lexicalized argument prohibits the presence of a PM, and, for English, vice-versa. This leads to the conclusion that, contrary to recent claims (Pi~n´on2008, Bochnak forthcoming), verbs, unlike adjectives, generally do not lexicalize degree arguments. 1 Introduction This paper has a narrow empirical goal and a broader theoretical goal. The former has to do with several con- structions which form a natural morphological and semantic class across languages: equation constructions, exemplified in (1) and (2) in English. (1) a. John read the same book as Sue. same/different construction b. John is as tall as Sue. equative (2) a. John danced as Sue did. (manner) similative b.
    [Show full text]
  • Kambari Orthography Design
    Kambari Orthography Design Janie P. Stark S+L +nternational 2010 ii S+L e-Books 16 ©2010 S+L +nternational +SBN: 978-1-55671-245-6 +SSN: 1934-2470 Fair Use Policy Books published in the S+L e-Books (S+LEB) series are intended for scholarly research and educational use. You may make copies of these publications for research or instructional purposes free of charge (within fair use guidelines) and without further permission. Republication or commercial use of S+LEB or the documents contained therein is expressly prohibited without the written consent of the copyright holder(s). Series Editor George Huttar Volume Editor Mary Huttar Managing Editor Bonnie Brown Compositor Karoline Fisher iii DED+CAT+ON To My husband, John, without whom + wouldn’t have finished this book. iv Editor’s Note This work is a slightly revised version of the author’s 2000 Ph.D. dissertation, University of +lorin, Nigeria. Since the initial version of this book was written, many important works on orthography design have appeared (e.g., Handbook of Orthography and Literacy, ed. by R. Malatesha Joshi and P.G. Aaron, Routledge, 2005). Due to circumstances beyond the author’s control none of these recent works are included in the references. The reader should keep in mind that this work describes only one case of writing system development. Several principles of orthography design are discussed in detail. One principle which is left implicit is that community participation is a key factor in the development of an acceptable writing system. v FOREWORD This study deals with designing writing systems: it goes beyond basic principles of orthography development to develop a series of principles intended to guide orthography decisions in situations where the basic principles fall short.
    [Show full text]
  • The Study of Language and Language Acquisition
    1 The Study of Language and Language Acquisition We may regard language as a natural phenomenon—an aspect of his biological nature, to be studied in the same manner as, for instance, his anatomy. Eric H. Lenneberg, Biological Foundations of Language (), p. vii 1.1 The naturalistic approach to language Fundamental to modern linguistics is the view that human language is a natural object: our species-specific ability to acquire a language, our tacit knowledge of the enormous complexity of language, and our capacity to use language in free, appropriate, and infinite ways are attributed to a property of the natural world, our brain. This position needs no defense, if one considers the study of language is an empirical inquiry. It follows, then, as in the study of biological sciences, linguistics aims to identify the abstract properties of the biological object under study—human language—and the mechanisms that govern its organization. This has the goal set in the earliest state- ments on modern linguistics, Chomsky’s The Logical Structure of Linguistic Theory (). Consider the famous duo: () a. Colorless green ideas sleep furiously. b. *Furiously sleep ideas green colorless. Neither sentence has even a remote chance of being encountered in natural discourse, yet every speaker of English can perceive their differences: while they are both meaningless, (a) is grammatically Language Acquisition well formed, whereas (b) is not. To understand what precisely this difference is is to give ‘a rational account of this behavior, i.e., a theory of the speaker’s linguistic intuition . the goal of linguistic theory’ (Chomsky /: )—in other words, a psychology, and ultimately, biology of human language.
    [Show full text]
  • Diachronic Generative Syntax Conference
    DiGS14 14th DIACHRONIC GENERATIVE SYNTAX CONFERENCE http://digs14.clul.ul.pt/ Universidade de Lisboa 4-6 July 2012 [email protected] | Instituto para a Investigação Interdisciplinar | Av. Prof. Gama Pinto, 2 DiGS 14 14th Diachronic Generative Syntax Conference Lisbon, 4-6 July 2012 CLUL Centro de Linguística da Universidade de Lisboa center of linguistics of-the university of Lisbon ‘Linguistic Center of the University of Lisbon’ Table of contents Organizing Committee 2 Scientific Committee 3 Invited Speakers 4 Authors & emails 5 Program 6 Abstracts by author’s last name alphabetical order 9 Organizing Committee ∙ Adriana Cardoso ∙ Juliana Costa Moreira ∙ Rita Marquilhas ∙ Luís Graça ∙ Ana Maria Martins ∙ Sílvia Pereira (∙) Grupo de Dialectologia e Diacronia do CLUL group of dialectology and diachrony of-the CLUL ‘Dialectology and Diachrony Research Group of CLUL’ 2 Scientific Committee Adam Ledgeway Ioanna Sitaridou Adriana Cardoso Joel Wallenberg Ana Maria Brito John Sundquist Ana Maria Martins John Whitman Ann Taylor Judy Bernstein Ans van Kemenade Katalin Kiss Anna Bartra Kaufmann Lobke Aelbrecht Anne Breitbarth Marcel den Dikken Anthony Kroch Maria Francisca Xavier Beatrice Santorini Maria Lobo Caroline Heycock Marie Labelle Charlotte Galves Maria Llüisa Hernanz Chiara Gianollo Marit Julien Chris Reintges Mary Kato Dalina Kallulli Montse Batllori David Lightfoot Paola Crisma David Willis Paul Hirschbühler Edith Aldridge Roland Hinterhölz Elly van Gelderen Sonia Cyrino Eric Haeberli Susan Pintzuk Esther Rinke Susann Fischer Gertjan
    [Show full text]
  • A Term Used in Government-Binding Theory for a Feature [+Gamma] Which Is Assigned to Empty Categories That Are Properly Governed
    G gamma-marking (n.) A term used in government-binding theory for a feature [+gamma] which is assigned to empty categories that are properly governed. Empty cateogries that are not properly governed are assigned [–gamma]. gap (n.) (1) A term used in linguistics to refer to the absence of a linguistic unit at a place in a pattern of relationships where one might have been expected; also called an accidental gap or hole in the pattern. The term occurs especially in semantics, where a lexical gap can be illustrated by the absence of a male v. female distinction within the term cousin (cf. brother/sister, uncle/aunt, etc.). An example of a phonological gap would be seen in a language where the phonemic contrasts /p/, /b/ and /t/, /d/ were not matched by a corresponding velar pair, only /k/ being found. A morphological gap can be illustrated by a deverbal noun which does not take the usual -al suffix: *devisal alongside refusal, perusal, proposal, etc. (2) The term is also used in syntax: an example of a syntactic gap would be the underlying direct object position in Who did you invite –?. Gaps are often assumed to contain phonologically empty categories (symbolized as e). A parasitic gap is postulated when the presence of a syntactic gap depends on the prior existence of another gap in the structure of the sentence. See also pattern. gapping (n.) A term proposed in generative grammar to refer to the absence of a repeated verb in clauses which have been conjoined – a ‘gap’ appears in the reduced clause, e.g.
    [Show full text]
  • Processing Prescriptively Incorrect Comparative Particles: Evidence from Sentence-Matching and Eye-Tracking
    fpsyg-11-00186 February 13, 2020 Time: 18:19 # 1 ORIGINAL RESEARCH published: 14 February 2020 doi: 10.3389/fpsyg.2020.00186 Processing Prescriptively Incorrect Comparative Particles: Evidence From Sentence-Matching and Eye-Tracking Ferdy Hubers1†, Theresa Redl1,2*†, Hugo de Vos3, Lukas Reinarz4 and Helen de Hoop1 1 Centre for Language Studies, Radboud University Nijmegen, Nijmegen, Netherlands, 2 Max Planck Institute for Psycholinguistics, Nijmegen, Netherlands, 3 Institute of Public Administration, Leiden University, Leiden, Netherlands, 4 Department of Physics, University of Bonn, Bonn, Germany Speakers of a language sometimes use particular constructions which violate prescriptive grammar rules. Despite their prescriptive ungrammaticality, they can occur rather frequently. One such example is the comparative construction in Dutch and similarly in German, where the equative particle is used in comparative constructions instead of the prescriptively correct comparative particle (Dutch beter als Jan and German besser wie Jan “lit. better as John”). In a series of three experiments Edited by: using sentence-matching and eye-tracking methodology, we investigated whether M. Teresa Espinal, Autonomous University of Barcelona, this grammatical norm violation is processed as grammatical, as ungrammatical, or Spain whether it falls in between these two. We hypothesized that the latter would be the Reviewed by: case. We analyzed our data using linear mixed effects models in order to capture Gosse Bouma, University of Groningen, Netherlands possible individual differences. The results of the sentence-matching experiments, which Katharina Spalek, were conducted in both Dutch and German, showed that the grammatical norm Humboldt University of Berlin, violation patterns with ungrammatical sentences in both languages. Our hypothesis Germany was therefore not borne out.
    [Show full text]
  • The Possessive Equative Sentence in Mandarin: Its Relation to Possession and Existence
    The Possessive Equative Sentence in Mandarin: Its Relation to Possession and Existence Zhiguo Xie The Ohio State University Introduction : In addition to denoting possession and existence ((1) and (2)) and several other concepts, the Mandarin verb you can appear in the “X + you + Y + (zheme “this” or name “that”) + A(djective)” construction to express comparison between two individuals X and Y with respect to the property denoted by A (3). The nature of comparison the construction expresses is prima facie an equative one. On an intuitive level, the construction asserts that X is identical (or similar) to Y as far as the property denoted by A is concerned (Lü, 1980; Liu, 2004). This paper, ipso facto , calls it the possessive equative construction. Some descriptive works (Lü, 1980; Zhu, 1982; among others) treated the various uses of you as being separate from each other, and some others (e.g. Liu, 2004) considered them related in some way, yet without specifying how. On the other hand, formal semanticists have yet to offer a unified treatment of them. As an initial attempt, in this paper I offer a formal semantic analysis of the possessive equative construction and its relationship to the other uses of you . Equative you , in effect, functions as an abstractor over a variable in its object, which is consistently a small clause, overt or covert. The variable bears an index coming from the subject. The possessive equative construction can be analyzed as involving a subset relation between degrees, which are modeled as intervals on a scale (Kennedy, 2001; among others).
    [Show full text]
  • Berkeley Linguistics Society 36Th Annual Meeting February 6 & 7
    Berkeley Linguistics Society 36th Annual Meeting February 6 & 7, 2010 Berkeley, California Berkeley Linguistics Society 36 Contents MARK DINGEMANSE ...................... 17 Acknowledgements ......................... 1 How to do things with ideophones: Schedule ................................... 2 Towards a social interactional approach Conference Venue .......................... 6 YOUNG AH DO ............................ 17 Nearby Restaurants ........................ 7 Satisfying output-output faithfulness with Copy Shops ................................ 8 excessive morphology: Evidence from Korean Bookstores ................................. 8 acquisition ANDREW DOMBROWSKI ................... 18 Invited Speakers When is orthography not just orthography? The case of the Novgorod birchbark letters LYLE CAMPBELL ........................... 9 TERESA ELMS ............................. 18 Language isolates and their history, or, Gesture-to-speech mismatch in the What’s weird, anyway? construction of problem-solving insight PETER T. DANIELS ........................ 10 CALEB EVERETT .......................... 18 Writing in the world and linguistics Semantically-oriented vowel reduction in an JEAN-MARIE HOMBERT ................... 11 Amazonian language Language isolates and linguistic diversity: JOHNNY GEORGE ..........................19 A case for a mosaic approach to language Universals in the visual-kinesthetic modality: emergence Politeness marking features in Japanese Sign JOHN MCCARTHY ......................... 12 Language (JSL) Harmonic
    [Show full text]