Jun, Nathan. "Liberalism." Anarchism and Political Modernity. New York: Continuum, 2012

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Jun, Nathan. Jun, Nathan. "Liberalism." Anarchism and Political Modernity. New York: Continuum, 2012. 47–78. Contemporary Anarchist Studies. Bloomsbury Collections. Web. 23 Sep. 2021. <http:// dx.doi.org/10.5040/9781501306785.ch-003>. Downloaded from Bloomsbury Collections, www.bloomsburycollections.com, 23 September 2021, 18:07 UTC. Copyright © Nathan Jun 2012. You may share this work for non-commercial purposes only, provided you give attribution to the copyright holder and the publisher, and provide a link to the Creative Commons licence. 3 Liberalism Representationalism Ancient and medieval political theory, as we saw in the fi rst two chapters, was situated in an archic context that presupposed a natural cosmological order. To this extent it is best understood as a kind of ethical naturalism according to which the lives of human beings (ought to) refl ect or conform to the order of nature. Political relations and institutions, by extension, are described and/or justifi ed in relation to natural laws. For Aristotle, human beings are social creatures by nature, thus life in the polis is natural for human beings. Certain Stoics, while not necessarily disagreeing with the idea that human beings are social by nature, nonetheless deny that the polis (or at least certain of its key features, such as private property) is natural in the strict sense. In both cases, the concept of the individual person is at best secondary to the concept of the community, which is in turn secondary to the archic concept of natural order. Because human beings are essentially social, and because this essential sociability helps to defi ne the place of human beings within the broader cosmological order, sociopolitical relations within communities and among individual human beings are justifi ed to the extent that they are deemed “natural.” Political naturalism of this sort is better understood as a species of a wider genre which might be called “political holism.” This “holism,” as I understand it, rests on two crucial theses. The fi rst is that corporate entities such as communities, societies, cultures, and states have interests that transcend those of individual persons. 1 The second, according to Charles Taylor, is that “living in society is a necessary condition of the development of rationality, in some sense of this property, or of becoming a moral agent in the full sense of the term, or of becoming a fully responsible, autonomous being.” 2 If holism is essentially a descriptive or metaphysical doctrine, naturalism is an ethical doctrine; for the naturalist, after all, what matters is not just that human beings are social by nature, but that “naturalness” is 99781441140159_Ch03_Fpp_txt_prf.indd781441140159_Ch03_Fpp_txt_prf.indd 4477 99/2/2011/2/2011 66:33:06:33:06 PPMM 48 ANARCHISM AND POLITICAL MODERNITY the standard according to which political practices and institutions are to be ethically evaluated. Later holistic theories, such as those of Vico, Herder, Rousseau, and Hegel, do not necessarily ground ethical evaluation in an account of what is natural even though their accounts of the natural are similar to those which underwrite naturalistic theories. 3 Thus the concept of “nature” in general and “human nature” in particular did not vanish in the wake of modernity. On the contrary, questions such as “what does it means to be human?” or “what is the universal essence shared in common by all human beings?” remained centrally important for liberal and protoliberal philosophers, especially those of the so- called early modern era. One crucial difference is that for such philosophers, human beings are generally understood fi rst and foremost as individuals who are to be distinguished from each other as well from the natural world which they inhabit. This constitutes a rather signifi cant departure from the aforesaid ancient and medieval theories, which, while scarcely denying the existence of individuals, tended to analyze them in terms of their relationship to the community and, by extension, to nature as a whole. Liberalism tends to invert this priority by analyzing both the community and nature as a whole in terms of their relationship to individual human beings. From this we can adduce two distinctively “liberal” theses which serve to distinguish liberal and protoliberal theories from other theories. The fi rst, which Pettit calls “personalism,” claims that “whatever is good or bad about a set of institutions is something that is good or bad for the people whom they affect.” 4 In contrast to the fi rst thesis of holism mentioned above, personalism claims that there are no distinctly corporate interests or, to put it another way, that all corporate interests are reducible to individual interests. The second thesis, which Pettit calls “solipsism” or “social atomism,” holds that (a) “the solitary individual— the agent who is and always has been isolated from others— is nevertheless capable, in principle, of displaying all distinctive human capacities”; (b) that “any property that can serve as an ultimate political value, any property that can be regarded as a yardstick of political assessment has to be capable of instantiated by the socially isolated person, by the solitary individual”; and (c) “that the ultimate criteria of political judgment . are provided by non- social as distinct from social values.” 5 Taken together, these two theses basically turn political holism on its head. One way to explain this inversion has to do with the development of modern natural sciences in the late sixteenth and early seventeenth centuries. The scholastic natural philosophy of the Middle Ages, which these sciences eventually surpassed, was a bricolage of ideas drawn from Ptolemian cosmology, Galenic medicine, Aristotelian physics, and so on. Generally speaking, medieval science retained the Aristotelian emphasis on the empirical observation of material entities and the explanation of natural phenomena in terms of internal principles of change and causation (especially 99781441140159_Ch03_Fpp_txt_prf.indd781441140159_Ch03_Fpp_txt_prf.indd 4488 99/2/2011/2/2011 66:33:06:33:06 PPMM LIBERALISM 493 teleological principles, i.e., fi nal causes). Within this framework human beings, alongside all other material entities, belonged to a hierarchy whose elements were differentiated according to their natural functions and ends. (This way of thinking is captured vividly in the famous Tree of Porphyry and similar classifi catory schemes.) The starting point of philosophy, which was almost always regarded, with appropriate reverence, as the “handmaiden” ( ancilla ) of theology, was the natural world as given to the senses. The human mind or soul, while crucial for locating human beings within the natural order, was not regarded as theoretically foundational. Broadly construed, ancient and medieval philosophy was not concerned with the problem of individuating human beings vis- à- vis mental or spiritual categories, the concept of consciousness, or the question of whether sensory experience correspond authentically to any “external” reality. 6 For example, Aristotle’s De Anima , which is widely regarded as the magnum opus of premodern psychology, pertains chiefl y to the operation of the senses and other mental faculties. 7 Aristotle does not discuss individuation in psychological terms (this would later become important in debates surrounding the so- called problem of other minds) nor the relation between mind and world. In point of fact, correspondence between the senses and the material world was largely taken for granted by Aristotle and his scions. For a number of reasons, the new scientifi c and mathematical ideas articulated in the work of Copernicus, Galileo, and Kepler cast signifi cant doubt on the explanatory framework of medieval science. 8 Descartes, among others, sought to create a new philosophical methodology modeled on and capable of accommodating these developments. 9 His approach, which we will refer to as representationalism , involved nothing less than a comprehensive upheaval of prevailing philosophical wisdom (“rebuilding the house,” as Descartes put it). 10 Adopting a kind of tactical skepticism, Descartes rejected any ideas, concepts, or entities which could, within the limits of logic, be doubted. 11 As an immediate consequence, he could no longer take for granted that his perceptions faithfully corresponded to (“represented”) an external reality, or even that there was such a thing as external reality. 12 The best he could do, at least initially, was to establish, by means of the vaunted cogito , 13 that he himself existed as a thinking thing (res cogitans ). 14 In this way Cartesian philosophy introduces the critical modern notion of the subject —literally, “that which is thrown under.” 15 The human being is no longer defi ned in terms of its functions or attributes or fi nal causes— in short, its position within the Aristotelian cosmological order. 16 Rather, the human is defi ned as “that which is thrown under” (i.e., the subject of) conscious experiences, including thoughts, perceptions, and sensations. 17 It is the res of the res cogitans . The question becomes: what, if anything, exists apart from the thinking thing and its representations? Are there objects of knowledge before which stand the subject of consciousness and, if so, how do the former relate to the latter? 99781441140159_Ch03_Fpp_txt_prf.indd781441140159_Ch03_Fpp_txt_prf.indd 4499 99/2/2011/2/2011 66:33:06:33:06 PPMM 50 ANARCHISM AND POLITICAL MODERNITY Attempts to answer these questions,
Recommended publications
  • UCLA Electronic Theses and Dissertations
    UCLA UCLA Electronic Theses and Dissertations Title Between Anarchy and Leviathan: A Return to Voluntarist Political Obligation Permalink https://escholarship.org/uc/item/8pj296m6 Author Hallock, Emily Rachel Publication Date 2013 Peer reviewed|Thesis/dissertation eScholarship.org Powered by the California Digital Library University of California UNIVERSITY OF CALIFORNIA Los Angeles Between Anarchy and Leviathan: A Return to Voluntarist Political Obligation A dissertation submitted in partial satisfaction of the requirements for the degree Doctor of Philosophy in Political Science by Emily Rachel Hallock 2013 © Copyright by Emily Rachel Hallock 2013 ABSTRACT OF THE DISSERTATION Between Anarchy and Leviathan: A Return to Voluntarist Political Obligation by Emily Rachel Hallock Doctor of Philosophy in Political Science University of California, Los Angeles, 2013 Professor Carole Pateman, Chair No defense of the liberal-democratic state can do without political obligation, yet existing theories cannot provide a successful account of political obligation. Existing accounts of obligation cannot parry critiques from rival theories, nor refute philosophical anarchists’ formidable attack on obligation. To move discussion of obligation forward, this dissertation offers an alternative solution to what George Klosko has called the ‘voluntarist paradox’ of liberal-democratic political obligation. While liberal ideas about the individual require that any obligation to obey be assumed through a voluntary act, individuals do not voluntarily assume obligations frequently enough to support legitimacy claims. In response to this paradox, most scholars deploy non-voluntary justifications for a general obligation to obey, while philosophical anarchists deny that such an obligation exists at all. In contrast, I argue that overcoming the voluntarist paradox requires a radically different view of the aims and scope of political obligation.
    [Show full text]
  • The Contradiction of Classical Liberalism and Libertarianism
    The contradiction of classical liberalism and libertarianism blogs.lse.ac.uk/businessreview/2017/02/01/the-contradiction-of-classical-liberalism-and-libertarianism/ 2/1/2017 A standard assumption in policy analyses and political debates is that classical liberal or libertarian views represent a radical alternative to a progressive or egalitarian agenda. In the political arena, classical liberalism and libertarianism often inform the policy agenda of centre-right and far- right parties. They underpin laissez-faire policies and reject any redistributive action, including welfare state provisions and progressive taxation. This is motivated by a fundamental belief in the value of personal autonomy and protection from (unjustified) external interference, including from the state. It is difficult to overestimate the philosophical and political relevance of classical liberalism and libertarianism. President Trump’s proposal to repeal the “Affordable Care Act (Obamacare)”, for example, is clearly inspired by a libertarian philosophical outlook whereby “No person should be required to buy insurance unless he or she wants to” (Healthcare Reform to Make America Great Again ). More generally, in the last four decades the political consensus, and the spectrum of policy proposals and outcomes, has significantly moved in a less interventionist, more laissez faire direction. The centrality of classical liberal and libertarian views has been such that the historical period after the end of the 1970s – following the election of Margaret Thatcher in the UK and Ronald Reagan in the US – has come to be known as the “Neoliberal era”. Yet the very coherence of the classical liberal and libertarian view of society, and its consistency with the fundamental tenets of modern democracies, have been questioned.
    [Show full text]
  • Classical Liberalism and the Problem of Technological Change
    Classical Liberalism and the Problem of Technological Change Justin “Gus” Hurwitz & Geoffrey A. Manne ICLE Innovation & the New Economy Research Program White Paper 2018-1 ICLE | 2117 NE Oregon St. Ste 501 | Portland, OR 97232 | 503.770.0652 [email protected] | @laweconcenter | www.laweconcenter.org 2 13 Classical Liberalism and the Problem of Technological Change Justin (Gus) Hurwitz and Geoffrey A. Manne Introduction The relationship between classical liberalism and technology is surprisingly fraught. The common understanding is that technological advance is complementary to the principles of classical liberalism – especially in the case of contemporary, information-age technology.1 This is most clearly on display in Silicon Valley, with its oft-professed libertarian (classical liberalism’s kissing cousin) affinities. The analytical predicate for this complementarity is that classical liberalism values liberty-enhancing private ordering, and technological advance both is generally facially liberty-enhancing and facilitates private ordering. 1 This chapter focuses on “contemporary technology.” That is, generally, those technologies associated with the information revolution of the past generation: computers, the Internet, and related information communications and processing technologies. A treatment of the relationship between classical liberalism and a more generalized concept of technology is beyond the scope of this chapter. It is, however, the authors’ view that the discussion offered here is relevant to such a broader conceptualization. 3 This analysis, however, is incomplete. Classical liberalism recognizes that certain rules are necessary in a well-functioning polity.2 The classical liberal, for instance, recognizes the centrality of enforceable property rights, and the concomitant ability to seek recourse from a third party (the state) when those rights are compromised.
    [Show full text]
  • The Principles of Embedded Liberalism: Social Legitimacy and Global Capitalism Rawi Abdelal and John G
    chapter 7 The Principles of Embedded Liberalism: Social Legitimacy and Global Capitalism Rawi Abdelal and John G. Ruggie In this essay we revisit the principles of “embedded liberalism” and argue for their relevance to the contemporary global economy. The most essential principle is the need for markets to enjoy social legitimacy, because their politi- cal sustainability ultimately depends on it. From this principle we analyze three current sets of practices and institutions in which ongoing crises of legitimacy demonstrate the need for a renewal of embedded liberalism and a revitalization of global governance. They are: the activities of transnational corporations, particularly with regard to core standards in labor and human rights; the orga- nization of the international financial architecture; and the formal rules and informal norms of international organizations. Learning the Lessons of Embedded Liberalism The post-1945 world economy embodied a social bargain. In the aftermath of the political and economic chaos of 1920s, the Great Depression of the 1930s, and the Second World War—all of which together shattered the world order within the span of a single generation—policymakers sought to reorganize and rebuild the world economy by restoring open markets, promising to mitigate their adverse social consequences and thereby preempting societal demands, from both left and right, to replace markets altogether. The failure to strike such a compromise earlier had undermined international cooperation in trade and macroeconomic policy during the 1920s and 1930s, just as it had caused the collapse of the first era of globalization, circa 1870 to 1914. Influential scholars and policymakers began to make sense of how that first era of globalization had lost its way.
    [Show full text]
  • Planting Parliaments in Eurasia, 1850–1950
    Planting Parliaments in Eurasia, 1850–1950 Parliaments are often seen as Western European and North American institutions and their establishment in other parts of the world as a derivative and mostly defec- tive process. This book challenges such Eurocentric visions by retracing the evo- lution of modern institutions of collective decision-making in Eurasia. Breaching the divide between different area studies, the book provides nine case studies cov- ering the area between the eastern edge of Asia and Eastern Europe, including the former Russian, Ottoman, Qing, and Japanese Empires as well as their succes- sor states. In particular, it explores the appeals to concepts of parliamentarism, deliberative decision-making, and constitutionalism; historical practices related to parliamentarism; and political mythologies across Eurasia. It focuses on the historical and “reestablished” institutions of decision-making, which consciously hark back to indigenous traditions and adapt them to the changing circumstances in imperial and postimperial contexts. Thereby, the book explains how represent- ative institutions were needed for the establishment of modernized empires or postimperial states but at the same time offered a connection to the past. Ivan Sablin is a research group leader in the Department of History at Heidelberg University, Germany. Egas Moniz Bandeira is a researcher at the Max Planck Institute for Legal History and Legal Theory, Frankfurt am Main, Germany. Routledge Studies in the Modern History of Asia 152. Caste in Early Modern Japan Danzaemon and the Edo Outcaste Order Timothy D. Amos 153. Performing the Politics of Translation in Modern Japan Staging the Resistance Aragorn Quinn 154. Malaysia and the Cold War Era Edited by Ooi Keat Gin 155.
    [Show full text]
  • Capitalism in the Classical and High Liberal Traditions*
    CAPITALISM IN THE CLASSICAL AND HIGH LIBERAL TRADITIONS* By Samuel Freeman I. Essential Features of Liberalism Liberalism holds that there are certain individual liberties that are of fundamental political significance. These liberties are fundamental or basic in that they are preconditions on the pursuit of other social values, such as achieving economic efficiency, promoting the general welfare, and mod- erating the degree of inequality in the distribution of income and wealth. None of these liberties are absolute, but the reasons for limiting their exercise are to protect other basic liberties and maintain essential back- ground conditions for their effective exercise. For example, freedom of speech and expression can be limited when it imminently endangers others’ safety or the freedom of their person, but not because the ideas expressed are found to be offensive by vast majorities of people. Liberal basic liberties are also inalienable: they cannot be given up voluntarily or permanently transferred to anyone else, though some liberties are forfeit- able upon criminal conviction for serious crimes. No liberal government would enforce a contract in which a person sold himself into permanent servitude, or alienated his freedom to change religions, or legally bound himself to vote only as his employer insisted. An integral feature of a liberal constitution is the protection of the basic rights and liberties nec- essary to establish and maintain the equal civic status of citizens. What liberties do liberals generally find to have this extraordinary status? Liberals now would all agree that among the basic liberties are freedom of thought, expression, and inquiry, freedom of conscience and of association, freedom and security of the person, and free choice of occupation.
    [Show full text]
  • NATURAL LAW, LIBERALISM, and CHRISTIANITY Frank Van Dun*
    Journal of Libertarian Studies Volume 15, no. 3 (Summer 2001), pp. 1–36 Ó2001 Ludwig von Mises Institute www.mises.org NATURAL LAW, LIBERALISM, AND CHRISTIANITY Frank van Dun* Classical liberalism arose at a time when Christian orthodoxy was still vibrant.1 Liberalism and Christian orthodoxy, sharing a number of fundamental ideas about the nature of man and of inter- personal relations, presuppose the same moral ontology of natural law. The high tide of Christian orthodoxy and classical liberalism belongs to the era when natural law was the fundamental concept of all serious thought about the human world. Both classical liberalism and Christianity went into sharp de- cline from the later nineteenth century onward, and, by the begin- ning of the twentieth century, the concept of natural law was rap- *Professor of Philosophy of Law at the Universities of Ghent and Maas- tricht. An earlier version of this text was presented at the conference “The World Out of Balance?” (Gummersbach, Germany, November 5–7, 1999), held at the Theodor Heuss Akademie, and organized in cooperation with the Von Mises Institute (Ghent), Nova Civitas (Ghent), and The Centre for a New Europe (Brussels). The author wishes to thank the participants for their questions and comments. 1By “classical liberalism,” I mean the liberalism of those who postulate a necessary link between liberty and objective law and justice, i.e., respect for natural persons, their property, and contractual obligations. By “Chris- tian orthodoxy,” I mean the interpretation of the Bible that became au- thoritative within the main churches as a result of the efforts of Saint Augustine and other early church fathers.
    [Show full text]
  • Classical Liberalism and the Austrian School
    Classical Liberalism and the Austrian School Classical Liberalism and the Austrian School Ralph Raico Foreword by Jörg Guido Hülsmann Preface by David Gordon LvMI MISES INSTITUTE The cover design by Chad Parish shows the Neptune Fountain, at the Schönbrunn Palace, in Vienna. Copyright © 2012 by the Ludwig von Mises Institute. Permission to reprint in whole or in part is gladly granted, provided full credit is given. Ludwig von Mises Institute 518 West Magnolia Avenue Auburn, Alabama 36832 mises.org ISBN: 978-1-61016-003-2 Dedicated to the memory of the great Ludwig von Mises Table of Contents Foreword by Jörg Guido Hülsmann . ix Preface by David Gordon . xiii Introduction . .xxv 1. Classical Liberalism and the Austrian School . .1 2. Liberalism: True and False . .67 3. Intellectuals and the Marketplace. 111 4. Was Keynes a Liberal? . .149 5. The Conflict of Classes: Liberal vs. Marxist Theories. .183 6. The Centrality of French Liberalism . .219 7. Ludwig von Mises’s Liberalism on Fascism, Democracy, and Imperalism . .255 8. Eugen Richter and the End of German Liberalism. .301 9. Arthur Ekirch on American Militarism . .331 Index. .339 vii Foreword “History looks backward into the past, but the lesson it teaches concerns things to come. It does not teach indolent quietism; it rouses man to emulate the deeds of earlier generations.” Ludwig von Mises1 The present book contains a collection of essays written through- out the past twenty years. I read virtually all of them when they were first published. They have been a central part of my education in the history of liberalism and of the Austrian School of economics, and I consider myself privileged indeed to have encountered Professor Raico and his work early on in my intellectual development.
    [Show full text]
  • Kant and Contemporary Liberal Cosmopolitanism
    Preliminary Communication UDC 172.16:[1:329.12] Received November 30th, 2008 Rafał Wonicki Warsaw University, Institute of Philosophy, Krakowskie Przedmiescie 3, PL–00–047 Warsaw [email protected] Cosmopolitanism and Liberalism: Kant and Contemporary Liberal Cosmopolitanism Abstract The author of this paper compares Kant’s notion of cosmopolitan right with contemporary liberal cosmopolitanism of such theorists like James Bohman (Professor of Philosophy at Saint Louis University) and David Held (Professor at the London School of Economics and Political Science). These two theorists bring Kant’s cosmopolitan right and reshape it by taking into consideration the process of globalization and the fact of pluralism. It is neces- sary to investigate how far these authors have changed the insight into Kant’s cosmopolitan right and its implications as well as how deeply the authors reshape the classical liberal political vocabulary. Key words Immanuel Kant, David Held, James Bohman, cosmopolitanism, liberalism, democracy Introduction Currently, it is observed that the issues of political philosophy and political science concern not only the internal state relations but also the internation- al, trans- and supranational relations. The perspective of describing political phenomena shifted from the national and local to the global and cosmo- politan. Moreover, the language of political theories has changed. Numer- ous authors consider this situation to be the result of dwindling explanatory power of the classical political theories and their less adequate descriptions of virtual mutual relations of states and other political actors or entities. As a result, new social and political science theories have evolved. Numerous authors, Giddens, Beck, Held, and Bohman among them, formed theories which describe the “global” political reality and make it more comprehen- sible.
    [Show full text]
  • An Analysis of Classical- and Neo-Liberal Imperatives in the Immigration Policy and Ethnic Relations in New Zealand for a Cohesive Multi-Ethnic Civil Society
    Copyright is owned by the Author of the thesis. Permission is given for a copy to be downloaded by an individual for the purpose of research and private study only. The thesis may not be reproduced elsewhere without the permission of the Author. An Analysis of Classical- and Neo-liberal imperatives in the Immigration Policy and Ethnic Relations in New Zealand for a Cohesive Multi-ethnic Civil Society A thesis presented in partial fulfilment of the requirements for the degree of Master of Arts in Sociology At Massey University, Albany, New Zealand John (Jong Duk) Park 2014 Abstract The influence of classical- and neo-liberal imperatives in relation to immigration is not confined to the settlement processes of new immigrants. It seems to penetrate the whole procedure, including the formation of immigration policy, the selection of immigrants, their settlement, their residential and economic activities, and social experiences. Furthermore, it extends, on a national level, to the nation-building project of New Zealand for a cohesive multi-ethnic civil society. Current tensions and conflicts surrounding immigration in Western countries appear to be the immediate products of the collision between, on the one hand, ethnic immigrants who experience socio-economic discrimination in their search for social and economic spaces for them in the host society and, on the other, the existing inhabitants of the host society who might experience anxiety over the changed social space around them. The ultimate cause of these tensions and conflicts, however, seems to be the collision between, on the one hand, global and local capitalist imperatives to incorporate nation- states into the global capitalist system and, on the other, the social imperatives of nation- states to maintain a cohesive national society.
    [Show full text]
  • This Thesis Has Been Submitted in Fulfilment of the Requirements for a Postgraduate Degree (E.G
    This thesis has been submitted in fulfilment of the requirements for a postgraduate degree (e.g. PhD, MPhil, DClinPsychol) at the University of Edinburgh. Please note the following terms and conditions of use: This work is protected by copyright and other intellectual property rights, which are retained by the thesis author, unless otherwise stated. A copy can be downloaded for personal non-commercial research or study, without prior permission or charge. This thesis cannot be reproduced or quoted extensively from without first obtaining permission in writing from the author. The content must not be changed in any way or sold commercially in any format or medium without the formal permission of the author. When referring to this work, full bibliographic details including the author, title, awarding institution and date of the thesis must be given. Pro-slavery and the Classics in Antebellum America, 1840 – 1860: Thomas Cobb, Louisa McCord, George Frederick Holmes, George Fitzhugh, and James Henry Hammond under Scrutiny. Jared Jodoin Doctorate of Philosophy The University of Edinburgh March 2019 Signed Declaration I hereby declare that that this thesis is entirely my own composition and work. It contains no material previously submitted for the award of any other degree or professional degree. Jared A. Jodoin 2 Table of Contents Abstract / 4 Acknowledgments / 6 1 / Two Worlds Collided: Greco-Roman Antiquity and the Antebellum United States / 7 2 / The Pro-Slavery Argument / 36 3 / As the Greeks and Romans “Did”: Thomas R. Cobb’s Black Slaves
    [Show full text]
  • Classical Liberalism, Neoliberalism and Ordoliberalism1
    ELZBIETA MĄCZYNSKA PIOTR PYSZ CLASSICAL LIBERALISM, NEOLIBERALISM AND ORDOLIBERALISM1 The key to distinguishing between classical liberalism, neoliberalism and ordoliberalism is their approach to the freedom of the individual. In 1938, Walter Lippmann asserted that the main cause underlying all failures of economic liberalism was its focus on expanding the scope of individual freedom in the market. This was accompanied by a lack of understanding of the need to develop an economic system under which the freedom of the individual would serve not only a select few, but also promote the interests of the majority of society. Eighty years later, this criticism goes to the crux of the contemporary dilemmas, as the neoliberal doctrine is driven by “freedom without order.” To overcome the ongoing global economic crisis, characterized by disorder, chaos, and anarchy, it is imperative to guide economic policy towards thinking “in terms of order” (Max Weber). And such an approach is offered by ordoliberal thought, which is concerned with the issue of economic order. Its leading idea, which is critical for today’s world, is “freedom within order.” Keywords: classical liberalism; neoliberalism; ordoliberalizm; historical context; advantages; reform. UDC 330.837.1 ELŻBIETA MĄCZYŃSKA ([email protected] ), Professor, Head of the Scientifi c Research Institute of bankruptcies Business Finance and Investment Corporation in the College of Business of the Warsaw School of Economics. Warsaw School of Economics, al. Niepodległości 162, 02-554, Warsaw, Poland. +48 22 564 60 00; PIOTR PYSZ ([email protected]), Professor of the Higher School of Finance and Management in Bialystok (Poland), the College of Business and Technology (Vechta, Germany).
    [Show full text]