The Authenticity and Significance of the Texts on the Rainbow and Probability

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

The Authenticity and Significance of the Texts on the Rainbow and Probability APPENDIX THE AUTHENTICITY AND SIGNIFICANCE OF THE TEXTS ON THE RAINBOW AND PROBABILITY A. SPINOZA'S CONTEMPORARIES The most concrete and clear-cut information concerning the development of Spinoza's ideas on theoretical optics is to be found in his correspondence. It is evident from the letters that it was probably during the mid-1660's, the four years following the publication of his book on the principles of Cartesianism, that he was most actively involved in exploring the theoretical foundations of his professional concern with the grinding of lenses and the construction of optical instruments. During these years he was co-operating with Jan Hudde (1628-1704) in the preparation of lenses for telescopes. Hudde also composed a small treatise on dioptrics, which if it had been preserved would have provided us with invaluable insight into the precise manner in which Spinoza was then thinking about light and optics. It is apparent from the surviving letters not only that he thought very highly of Hudde's expertise in dioptrics, but that as might have been expected, they were both approaching the problems it presented from a basically Cartesian standpoint. In the summer of 1666, for example, when Spinoza wrote asking for advice on the possible advantages of plano-convex lenses, he also took the trouble to re-state Hudde's geometrical presentation of spheri­ cal aberration in algebraic terms.! It was also during these years that JarigJelles (1619120-1683), a close friend of Spinoza's who had paid for the publication of the book on the principles of Cartesianism, wrote asking him to explain an apparent anomaly in Descartes' Dioptrics. After some delay, Spinoza replied in two letters, the second of which con- 1. See Spinoza, BrieJwlsselmg (ed. F. Akkerman, H.G. Hubbeling, A.G. Wester­ brink, Amsterdam, 1977), letters 34 (7 January 1666), 35 (10 April 1666), 36 Gune 1666). It used to be thought that these letters were written to Huygens. 91 APPENDIX tains a not too successful attempt at explaining the working of the human eye.2 During the 1650's, several members of this Amsterdam circle, together with their associates, had had close connections with the University of Leiden through the professor of mathematics there, Frans van Schoo ten (1615-1660). Hudde, together with Christiaan Huygens (1629-1695) and Jan de Witt (1625-1672), had studied mathematics privately at Leiden under van Schoo­ ten, who in 1649 had published an annotated Latin edition of Descartes' Geometry. This work had proved to be such a suc­ cess, that he was encouraged to prepare a second edition, in which he included a number of contributions by his pupils: articles by Hudde on the reduction of equations and the rule of extreme values, by Huygens on the intersections of a parabola with a circle and an improved method of constructing tangents to the conchoid, and by de Witt on conic sections.3 The pro­ fessor of philosophy at Leiden at this time was Adriaan Heere­ boord (1614-1661), also an enthusiastic Cartesian, and with an interest in introducing the new methods of enquiry into the natural sciences. Initially, he met with uncompromising opposi­ tion to this in the University, but in 1653 the curators appointed his pupil Joannes de Raey (1622-1702)to the chair of physics.4 Claes van der Meer (1594-1654), a Leiden financier and insur­ ance broker, was then treasurer of the University, and his son Jan van der Meer (1639-1686), who was corresponding with Spinoza on probability in 1666, and in 1678 was thought by Spinoza's friend the Amsterdam physician G.H. Schuller to be in business in Amsterdam, was evidently one of the links be­ tween Leiden and the Amsterdam circle during the 1660's.5 2. BriefwlSSeling, letters 39 (3 March 1667), 40 (25 March 1667). 3. Geometria, a Renato Des Cartes (2 vols., Amsterdam, 1659/61). Spinoza evi­ dently had both the first and the second edition of this work in his library. 4. H. De Dijn, 'Adriaan Heereboord en het Nederlands Cartesianisme', Algemeen Nederlands TiJdschrtft voor Wtjsbegeerte, vol. 75, no. 1 Qanuary 1983), pp. 56-69; E.G. Ruestow, Phystcs at seventeenth and etghteenth century Letden (The Hague, 1973), pp. 34-72. 5. Brtefwisseling, letter 38 (1 October 1666); J. Freudenthal, Dte Lebensgeschlchte Spinoza's (Leipzig, 1899), p. 207. There is no evidence that van der Meer was ever in business in Amsterdam, see K.O. Meinsma, Spmoza en ziJn krmg Cs-Gravenhage, 1896), p. 259, note 2. 92 THE AUTHENTICITY AND SIGNIFICANCE OF THE TEXTS In respect of the background to Spinoza's texts on the rain­ bow and probability, it is certainly worth noting that there is evidence that the dioptrics of the rainbow and the theory of probability were topics of general discussion in this circle during the 1650's. Huygens, for example, was investigating refraction with reference to Descartes' explanation of the rainbow as early as December 1652, and five years later published the Latin version of his work on the theory of probability, a copy of which was in Spinoza's library. Since Rene-Fran~ois de Sluse (1622-1685) is mentioned in the Treatise on the Rainbow, it is also worth noting that Huygens was corresponding with him in 1657. 6 As well as providing us with insight into the ways in which Spinoza's involvement in practical and theoretical optics led to his exchanging ideas with his fellow countrymen, the corre­ spondence also seems to indicate that prior to the publication of the Tractatus theologico-politicus in 1670, this involvement con­ stituted the main basis of his international reputation. It is certainly of significance that when Henry Oldenburg (c. 1620- 1677), secretary of the Royal Society, wanted to re-open his correspondence with him, he did so by informing him of the recent publication of Boyle's Experiments and Considerations concerning Colours and Hooke's Micrographia. What is more, when Spinoza returned the compliment, he did so by sending news of Huygens' activities and information concerning discov­ eries in astronomy being made by means of Campani's tele­ scopes. 7 When Leibniz was informed that it was Spinoza who had written the Tractatus theologico-politicus, he introduced himself to him not by commenting upon the work, but by indicating that he was aware of the importance of Hudde's dioptrical writings, and asking for Spinoza's opinion on his own recently-published Note on advanced optics. Spinoza replied 6. Huygens, CEuvres XIII, 1, pp. 146-153; letters 396-404 (II, pp. 39-53). Huygens' Tractatus de ratiOClnllS In aleae ludo was published in F. van Schooten's Exerclta­ tzonum mathematicarum (Leiden, 1657), which was in Spinoza's library: Freudenthal, op. cit., p. 161, no. (53). 7. Briefwlsseling, letters 25 (28 April 1665), 26 (May 1665); d. the enquiry and response concerning Huygens' DIOptrics in letters 29 (c. 20 September 1665) and 30 (c. 1 October 1665) 93 APPENDIX expressing doubts concerning what Leibniz called his 'pan­ dochal' lenses, and informing him that he had sent the second copy of the work on to Hudde, who had replied that he had had no time to look at it, but that he hoped he would be able to do so in a week or two.8 lt is not surprising, therefore, that the mention of a lost Treatise on the Rainbow in the preface to the collected works of Spinoza, published immediately after his death in 1677, should have aroused widespread curiosity abroad. When Jelles wrote to Spinoza enquiring about the apparent anomaly in Descartes' Dioptrics, only he and a small circle of friends in Amsterdam knew that something resembling the geometrical method then being used in dealing with light and colours was also being applied, in the re-drafting of the Ethics, to questions concerning nothing less than God and mind, the emotions and human servitude, the power of the intellect and human freedom. 9 Ten years later the full text of the Ethics was about to be presented to the world in both Latin and Dutch. Anyone who knew anything of Spinoza's interest in theoretical optics was bound to search the collected works for new light on the precise connection between the geometrical order of presentation employed in his philosophical masterpiece and the analytical geometry then being applied so successfully in the various branches of the exact sciences. Unfortunately, it was by no means apparent from the material included in the Opera posthuma what this connection might be. lt was J arig J elles who wrote the preface to the Dutch edition of the collected works, and he was evidently aware that this absence of any clear indication of what the connection might be between Spinoza's metaphysics and his mathematics was almost certain to give rise to disappointment. This probably accounts, 8. Briefwzsselmg, letters 45 (5 October 1671), 46 (9 November 1671); G.W. Leibniz, Sdmtliche Schnften und Bnefe, Zweiter Reihe, Erster Band (Darmstadt, 1926), pp. 155,184,185. Leibniz read the Tractatus soon after it was published and by the April of 1671 knew that it was by Spinoza: L. Stein, Leibmz und Spinoza (Berlin, 1890), pp. 32-34. His Notztia optzc£ promot£ was published at Frankfurt-on-Main in 1671. 9. In the draft as it existed in June 1665, the work was divided into three main sections, not five: Ethica (tr. and ed. N. and G. van Suchtelen, Amsterdam, 1979), pp. 7-8. Cf. F. Mignini's edition of the Korte Verhandeling, in Spinoza: Korte Geschriften (Amsterdam, 1982), pp. 221-436. 94 THE AUTHENTICITY AND SIGNIFICANCE OF THE TEXTS in part at least, for his statement that the Treatise on the Rain­ bow was the only manuscript of any significance that the editors had been unable to obtain a copy of: This is all the material, of any value, that we have been able to gather from the papers he left behind, and from certain copies, preserved by his friends and acquaintances.
Recommended publications
  • Newton.Indd | Sander Pinkse Boekproductie | 16-11-12 / 14:45 | Pag
    omslag Newton.indd | Sander Pinkse Boekproductie | 16-11-12 / 14:45 | Pag. 1 e Dutch Republic proved ‘A new light on several to be extremely receptive to major gures involved in the groundbreaking ideas of Newton Isaac Newton (–). the reception of Newton’s Dutch scholars such as Willem work.’ and the Netherlands Jacob ’s Gravesande and Petrus Prof. Bert Theunissen, Newton the Netherlands and van Musschenbroek played a Utrecht University crucial role in the adaption and How Isaac Newton was Fashioned dissemination of Newton’s work, ‘is book provides an in the Dutch Republic not only in the Netherlands important contribution to but also in the rest of Europe. EDITED BY ERIC JORINK In the course of the eighteenth the study of the European AND AD MAAS century, Newton’s ideas (in Enlightenment with new dierent guises and interpre- insights in the circulation tations) became a veritable hype in Dutch society. In Newton of knowledge.’ and the Netherlands Newton’s Prof. Frans van Lunteren, sudden success is analyzed in Leiden University great depth and put into a new perspective. Ad Maas is curator at the Museum Boerhaave, Leiden, the Netherlands. Eric Jorink is researcher at the Huygens Institute for Netherlands History (Royal Dutch Academy of Arts and Sciences). / www.lup.nl LUP Newton and the Netherlands.indd | Sander Pinkse Boekproductie | 16-11-12 / 16:47 | Pag. 1 Newton and the Netherlands Newton and the Netherlands.indd | Sander Pinkse Boekproductie | 16-11-12 / 16:47 | Pag. 2 Newton and the Netherlands.indd | Sander Pinkse Boekproductie | 16-11-12 / 16:47 | Pag.
    [Show full text]
  • The Actuality of Critical Theory in the Netherlands, 1931-1994 By
    The Actuality of Critical Theory in the Netherlands, 1931-1994 by Nicolaas Peter Barr Clingan A dissertation submitted in partial satisfaction of the requirements for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy in History in the Graduate Division of the University of California, Berkeley Committee in charge: Professor Martin E. Jay, Chair Professor John F. Connelly Professor Jeroen Dewulf Professor David W. Bates Spring 2012 Abstract The Actuality of Critical Theory in the Netherlands, 1931-1994 by Nicolaas Peter Barr Clingan Doctor of Philosophy in History University of California, Berkeley Professor Martin E. Jay, Chair This dissertation reconstructs the intellectual and political reception of Critical Theory, as first developed in Germany by the “Frankfurt School” at the Institute of Social Research and subsequently reformulated by Jürgen Habermas, in the Netherlands from the mid to late twentieth century. Although some studies have acknowledged the role played by Critical Theory in reshaping particular academic disciplines in the Netherlands, while others have mentioned the popularity of figures such as Herbert Marcuse during the upheavals of the 1960s, this study shows how Critical Theory was appropriated more widely to challenge the technocratic directions taken by the project of vernieuwing (renewal or modernization) after World War II. During the sweeping transformations of Dutch society in the postwar period, the demands for greater democratization—of the universities, of the political parties under the system of “pillarization,” and of
    [Show full text]
  • A “Calvinist” Theory of Matter? Burgersdijk and Descartes on Res Extensa
    Title Page A “Calvinist” Theory of Matter? Burgersdijk and Descartes on res extensa Giovanni Gellera ORCID IDENTIFIER 0000-0002-8403-3170 Section de philosophie, Université de Lausanne [email protected] The Version of Record of this manuscript has been published and is available in Intellectual History Review volume 28 (2018), issue 2. Published online 24 Novembre 2017. http://www.tandfonline.com/doi/full/10.1080/17496977.2017.1374058 Abstract In the Dutch debates on Cartesianism of the 1640s, a minority believed that some Cartesian views were in fact Calvinist ones. The paper argues that, among others, a likely precursor of this position is the Aristotelian Franco Burgersdijk (1590-1635), who held a reductionist view of accidents and of the essential extension of matter on Calvinist grounds. It seems unlikely that Descartes was unaware of these views. The claim is that Descartes had two aims in his Replies to Arnauld: to show the compatibility of res extensa and the Catholic transubstantiation but also to differentiate the res extensa from some views of matter explicitly defended by some Calvinists. The association with Calvinism will be eventually used polemically against Cartesianism, for example in France. The paper finally suggests that, notwithstanding the points of conflict, the affinities between the theologically relevant theories of accidents, matter and extension ultimately facilitated the dissemination of Cartesianism among the Calvinists. Keywords: Descartes, Burgersdijk, res extensa, accident, Calvinist scholasticism, eucharist 2 G. GELLERA A “Calvinist” Theory of Matter? Burgersdijk and Descartes on res extensa Giovanni Gellera University of Lausanne, Switzerland In 1651 Count Louis Henry of Nassau demanded that the Dutch universities issue public statements on Cartesian philosophy.
    [Show full text]
  • Research Review Philosophy 2012-2017
    RESEARCH REVIEW PHILOSOPHY 2012-2017 RESEARCH REVIEW – PHILOSOPHY De Onderzoekerij Vondellaan 58 2332 AH Leiden Phone: +31 6 24812176 Email: [email protected] Internet: www.onderzoekerij.nl Page 2/56 RESEARCH REVIEW – PHILOSOPHY Contents Preface ............................................................................................................................................... 6 1. Introduction ................................................................................................................................... 7 1.1 Terms of reference for the assessment ....................................................................................................................................................................................................... 7 1.2 The Review Committee ....................................................................................................................................................................................................................................................... 7 1.3 Procedures followed by the Committee ................................................................................................................................................................................................... 7 1.4 Application of the SEP scores ...................................................................................................................................................................................................................................
    [Show full text]
  • BCA Schedule
    A General philosophy AA8A A Rational enquiry, formal & abstract modes of enquiry Philosophy AA General philosophy * Studies in which reasoning is the fundamental instrument, History of philosophy in general AA7 whether or not combined with observation and experiment. * Add to AA7 letters A/V from Auxiliary Schedule 4B - e.g. * For the organization of knowledge and the relations epistemology in the 20th century (i.e. covering both between different disciplines, see Class 6. Western & Oriental studies) AAG R7R. A9 Philosophy & science * Alternative (not recommended) for libraries wishing to * Considered together. cite Branches & Viewpoints before broad traditions and historical `schools'. If this option is taken, assign notation as follows: AA Philosophy * | AA7 Periods * For history of ideas see Social sciences and humanities * | . * Add to AA7 as above from Schedule 4B. JZ9 Q. * | AA8 . Western philosophy in general AA2 . Common subdivisions * | . * Instead of AB. * Add to AA numbers 2/6 from Auxiliary Schedule 1 * | AA9 . By place with the slight modifications indicated at 6T/6Y. * | . * Instead of ADA. AA3 B . Dictionaries, glossaries * | . * Add to AA9 letters D/Z from G . Serials, periodicals * | . Schedule 2. AA5 . Organizations in philosophy * | AAB . By broad period & place R . Documents & libraries in philosophy * | . * Instead of ADB/ADX. AA6 A . Study & education in philosophy * | . * Add to AA letters B/X following AD * . Phase relations, interactions with other classes | . - e.g. AAR Renaissance. * | AAY . Individual Western philosophers A/Z * Use these instead of 9C/9K, if necessary. Most of the * | . * Instead of alternative at AE. relations occur as integral classes within the * | AB . Eastern philosophy philosophy schedule (e.g.
    [Show full text]
  • Chapter 18 Albert Borgmann and a Philosophy of Technology? I Begin
    Technè 10:2 Winter 2006 Special Issue: Durbin, In Search of Discourse Synthesis/168 Chapter 18 Albert Borgmann and a Philosophy of Technology? I begin this chapter with Higgs, Light, and Strong and their argument in Technology and the Good Life? (2000) in favor of the need for a new discipline: Broadening the scope of Philosophy of Technology “The set of questions a philosophy of technology should address in order to fulfill its promise are often at the intersection of it and other fields. In our opinion, philosophy of technology at its best should appeal to a very wide audience partly because it illuminates our shared, ordinary everyday life, such as with things and devices, and partly because the issues it probes cut across the full range of disciplines. Many of these issues are already vital matters of concern for these disciplines, such as ethics, social and political philosophy, aesthetics, art history, architecture, music, anthropology, religion, history, history of science and technology, cultural studies, sociology, political science, economics, linguistics, literary criticism, visual culture, and the hard sciences. For example, one of the interdisciplinary successes that philosophy of technology has had is with environmental ethics. Issues that join both fields are addressed in journals regularly, and numerous books have appeared. However, this kind of success should be occurring with other fields as well. What does philosophy of technology have to offer other disciplines? In the view of some of our contributors, traditional philosophical approaches may not be capable of questioning and challenging technology in a sufficiently radical manner. Nevertheless, we can show the kinds of questions a robust philosophy of technology can raise and address.
    [Show full text]
  • Frans Hemsterhuis
    r ! 55 MICHIEL WIELEMA, ERASMUS UNIVERSITY, ROTTERDAM Frans Hemsterhuis: A Philosopher's View of the History of the Dl;ltch Republic / In the English-speaking world, the Dutch record of philosophy in the Netherlands, both philosopher Frans Hemsterhuis (1721-1790) in a national and an international perspective. is still comparatively unknown. Despite the It is becoming clear that the Netherlands, fact that he was the most original Dutch especially in the seventeenth and eighteenth thinker of the eighteenth century, there is centuries, played an extremely important role only one book on him in English, together in the development and transmission of with a few articles. 1 At the moment, his ideas philosophical ideas. 5 Although Dutch are the subject of research both in the philosophers were part and parcel of general Netherlands itself and in Germany, France European movements of thought, their and Italy. In November and December 1990, contribution to philosophy was in many ways two international symposia were held to highly original. commemorate his death two centuries ago. Attention was focused on his philosophical In the case of Hemsterhuis, this contribution achievement as well as on the reception of his concerned such diverse topics as thought in the Netherlands and in Germany. mathematics, astronomy, optics, philosophy, The proceedings of these symposia will soon ethics, politics, history, aesthetics and be published. A Dutch translation of his religion. His ideas in these fields mark him complete works and of some hitherto as a thinker who has left behind naive unpublished letters (he wrote only in French) Enlightenment rationalism, and has opened is being prepared in three volumes.
    [Show full text]
  • Ankersmit's Dutch Writings and Their Audience
    journal of the philosophy of history 12 (2018) 450–471 brill.com/jph Ankersmit’s Dutch Writings and Their Audience Jacques Bos Universiteit van Amsterdam [email protected] Abstract This article analyses Frank Ankersmit’s Dutch-language writings in the context of Dutch debates on historical theory. In the 1970s and 1980s historical theory became a flourishing discipline in the Netherlands; it was a compulsory part of all history pro- grammes in the country, and all history departments employed one or more historical theorists. The Dutch theoretical debates of the 1970s and 1980s mainly dealt with the relation between history and the social sciences. In these debates Ankersmit defended the traditional historicist conception of historiography, while developing philosophi- cal views that would remain important in his later work. Especially relevant in this respect is his critique of linguistic transcendentalism. This view is already present in his earliest writings in the 1970s, but it also informs his work on historical representa- tion of the late 1980s and 1990s, and it is very important in his analysis of historical experience, which has its roots in his Dutch writings of the mid-1990s. Keywords Frank Ankersmit – Dutch philosophy of history – historicism – narrativism – historical experience – linguistic transcendentalism Frank Ankersmit has produced an impressive oeuvre, both in Dutch and in English. Of course, there is a significant overlap between Ankersmit’s Dutch and English writings. Many of his Dutch works were translated into English, and the other way round, and apart from that there is much thematic conver- gence between Ankersmit’s writings in Dutch and English; he did not produce two distinct oeuvres.
    [Show full text]
  • Research Guide to Philosophy
    Research Guide to Philosophy John M. Kelly Library University of St. Michael’s College MULTI-VOLUME ENCYCLOPEDIAS CONTENTS Routledge Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Edited by Edward Craig. London: Routledge, 1998. 10 volumes. Multi –Volume Encyclopedias 1 [Available online for UofT use: http://www.library.utoronto.ca] General Dictionaries and Handbooks 2 [Print version: St. Michael's 1st Floor Reference Area – B 51 .R68 1998] Branches of Philosophy - Dictionaries & Handbooks 3 The definitive English-language philosophy encyclopedia. Over 2,000 Summaries 5 articles – thematic, biographical, and national – ranging from 500 to Manuals 5 15,000 words in length, written by over 1,200 renowned authors from Finding Journal Articles 6 around the world. Bibliographies 6 Web Guides 7 The Encyclopedia of Philosophy. 2nd ed. Edited by Donald M. Borchert. Detroit: Macmillan Reference, 2006. 10 volumes. Associations 7 [Available online for UofT use: http://www.library.utoronto.ca] [Victoria Pratt and Trinity Graham, Reference Area – B 41 .E53 2006] Over 2100 lengthy articles with extensive bibliographies on every aspect of Eastern and Western philosophy, ancient, medieval, and modern. The Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy [Available online: http://www.iep.utm.edu] Almost 500 peer-reviewed articles contributed by professional philosophers or graduate students. Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy [Available online: http://plato.stanford.edu/] Peer-reviewed articles contributed by professional philosophers. New Catholic Encyclopedia. 2nd edition. Washington, DC: Gale, 2003. 15 volumes + annual supplements. [Available online for UofT use: http://www.library.utoronto.ca] [St. Michael’s 1st Floor Reference Area – BX 841 .N44 2003] The major English-language encyclopedia on Catholic topics. There is an article entitled “Philosophy, Articles on” which provides an overview of the encyclopedia’s philosophical content and identifies several hundred entries relating to philosophy.
    [Show full text]
  • Beth's Views Hâve Been Developed in Close Connection with His Intellectual Environment, As Is Shown, Notably in (Critical) Interaction with H.J
    PHILOSOPHIA SCIENTIÆ PAUL CORTOIS Science, culture, and the science of culture: Beth’s view Philosophia Scientiæ, tome 3, no 4 (1998-1999), p. 199-231 <http://www.numdam.org/item?id=PHSC_1998-1999__3_4_199_0> © Éditions Kimé, 1998-1999, tous droits réservés. L’accès aux archives de la revue « Philosophia Scientiæ » (http://poincare.univ-nancy2.fr/PhilosophiaScientiae/) implique l’accord avec les conditions générales d’utilisation (http://www. numdam.org/conditions). Toute utilisation commerciale ou im- pression systématique est constitutive d’une infraction pénale. Toute copie ou impression de ce fichier doit contenir la pré- sente mention de copyright. Article numérisé dans le cadre du programme Numérisation de documents anciens mathématiques http://www.numdam.org/ Science, Culture, and the Science of Culture: Bethfs View Paul CORTOIS KU Leuven/UFSIA Antwerp Abstract. In this article some less well-known aspects of Beth's gênerai philosophical ideas are reviewed and connected with each other, viz. his views on the perspectives for a new systematic philosophy, on the identity of the humanities, and on the rôle of philosophy and science with respect to culture and life. The resulting picture is that Beth did hâve a rather sophisticated vîew on the identity of the humanities. By means of a distinction between 'method' and 'mode of thought' (beschouwingswijze\ he defended their objectivity and, at the same time, the ineliminable rôle of an account in terms of intentions. Beth's 'scientific philosophy', on the other hand, has a double face: it is a philosophy of science and a scientific philosophy of life. The perspectives for a scientific philosophy of culture and life appear to be limited, however, as Beth came to recognize implicitly.
    [Show full text]
  • Few Modern Philosophers Have Determined Our Understanding of Early Modern Philosophy in the Way Hegel Has
    1 The Use of the Vernacular in Early Modern Philosophy Wiep van Bunge Hegel to Copleston Few modern philosophers have determined our understanding of early modern philosophy in the way Hegel has. More in particular, Hegel held highly influential views on the real significance of the language in which Philosophy came into its own after the Middle Ages. In his Lectures on the History of Philosophy Hegel introduced the issue in his paragraph on Luther, who completed his Reformation of Christianity, or so Hegel argued, by rendering the Bible into German, for according to Hegel philosophical self-consciousness can only be achieved in a native language, a language, that is, we can truly call our own. For, Hegel continued, only a language that is able to express our innermost concerns can serve as a vehicle for our subjectivity: In der Sprache ist der Mensch produzierend: es ist die erste Aüsserlichkeit, die der Mensch sich gibt durch die Sprache; es ist die erste, einfachste Form der Produktion, des Daseins, zu der er kommt im Bewusstsein; was der Mensch sich vorstellt, stellt er sich auch innerlich vor als gesprochen. Diese erste Form ist ein Gebrochenes, Fremdartiges, wenn der Mensch in einer fremden Sprache sich ausdrücken oder empfinden soll, was sein höchstes Interesse berührt. Dieser Bruch mit dem ersten Heraustreten in das Bewusstsein ist so aufgehoben; hier bei sich selbst in seinem Eigentum zu zein, in seiner Sprache zu sprechen, zu denken, gehört ebenso zur Form der Befreiung. Dies ist von unendlicher Wichtigkeit. Luther hätte nicht
    [Show full text]
  • Philosophy of Sport in Belgium and the Netherlands; History and Characteristics Van Hilvoorde, I.M.; Vorstenbosch, J.; Devisch, I
    VU Research Portal Philosophy of Sport in Belgium and the Netherlands; History and Characteristics van Hilvoorde, I.M.; Vorstenbosch, J.; Devisch, I. published in Journal of the Philosophy of Sport 2010 DOI (link to publisher) 10.1080/00948705.2010.9714778 document version Publisher's PDF, also known as Version of record Link to publication in VU Research Portal citation for published version (APA) van Hilvoorde, I. M., Vorstenbosch, J., & Devisch, I. (2010). Philosophy of Sport in Belgium and the Netherlands; History and Characteristics. Journal of the Philosophy of Sport, 37(2), 225-236. https://doi.org/10.1080/00948705.2010.9714778 General rights Copyright and moral rights for the publications made accessible in the public portal are retained by the authors and/or other copyright owners and it is a condition of accessing publications that users recognise and abide by the legal requirements associated with these rights. • Users may download and print one copy of any publication from the public portal for the purpose of private study or research. • You may not further distribute the material or use it for any profit-making activity or commercial gain • You may freely distribute the URL identifying the publication in the public portal ? Take down policy If you believe that this document breaches copyright please contact us providing details, and we will remove access to the work immediately and investigate your claim. E-mail address: [email protected] Download date: 01. Oct. 2021 Journal of the Philosophy of Sport, 2010, 37, 225-236 © 2010 Human Kinetics, Inc. Philosophy of Sport in Belgium and the Netherlands: History and Characteristics Ivo van Hilvoorde, Jan Vorstenbosch, and Ignaas Devisch For a few decades now, philosophy of sport has been an acknowledged area of philosophy.
    [Show full text]