Ankersmit's Dutch Writings and Their Audience

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Ankersmit's Dutch Writings and Their Audience journal of the philosophy of history 12 (2018) 450–471 brill.com/jph Ankersmit’s Dutch Writings and Their Audience Jacques Bos Universiteit van Amsterdam [email protected] Abstract This article analyses Frank Ankersmit’s Dutch-language writings in the context of Dutch debates on historical theory. In the 1970s and 1980s historical theory became a flourishing discipline in the Netherlands; it was a compulsory part of all history pro- grammes in the country, and all history departments employed one or more historical theorists. The Dutch theoretical debates of the 1970s and 1980s mainly dealt with the relation between history and the social sciences. In these debates Ankersmit defended the traditional historicist conception of historiography, while developing philosophi- cal views that would remain important in his later work. Especially relevant in this respect is his critique of linguistic transcendentalism. This view is already present in his earliest writings in the 1970s, but it also informs his work on historical representa- tion of the late 1980s and 1990s, and it is very important in his analysis of historical experience, which has its roots in his Dutch writings of the mid-1990s. Keywords Frank Ankersmit – Dutch philosophy of history – historicism – narrativism – historical experience – linguistic transcendentalism Frank Ankersmit has produced an impressive oeuvre, both in Dutch and in English. Of course, there is a significant overlap between Ankersmit’s Dutch and English writings. Many of his Dutch works were translated into English, and the other way round, and apart from that there is much thematic conver- gence between Ankersmit’s writings in Dutch and English; he did not produce two distinct oeuvres. This paper will discuss Ankersmit’s Dutch writings by relating them to the Dutch context in which they were published. This might provide Ankersmit’s international readers, who don’t know this Dutch context, © koninklijke brill nv, leiden, 2018 | doi:10.1163/18722636-12341407Downloaded from Brill.com09/27/2021 02:16:50PM via free access Ankersmit’s Dutch Writings and Their Audience 451 with a more complete and richer view of his work. Recently, Herman Paul and Adriaan van Veldhuizen addressed the Dutch context of Ankersmit’s work by emphasising the way in which he draws on the German historicist tradi- tion in the vein of Friedrich Meinecke. According to Paul and Van Veldhuizen, the influence of Ernst Kossmann, Ankersmit’s teacher at the University of Groningen, was especially important in shaping this position.1 The analysis by Paul and Van Veldhuizen is definitely very helpful in deepening our under- standing of the intellectual origins of Ankersmit’s work. Yet, as is inevitably the case in every contextualising interpretation, some aspects of the context could have been given more weight. The aspect that is, in my opinion, under- represented in the picture sketched by Paul and Van Veldhuizen is the context of Dutch historical theory, which strongly flourished from the 1980s onwards, mainly due to an internationally exceptional institutional position. This essay will mainly focus on this dimension of the Dutch context of Ankersmit’s work. In the first part of the text I shall position Ankersmit in the debates in Dutch historical theory in the 1980s, which were not just specialist discussions, but exchanges with a wider impact in the Dutch historical community. Ankersmit and his fellow theorists discussed topics such as historical explanation and postmodernism in general historical journals and wrote textbooks that were used by large groups of students. From the 1990s onwards, theoretical debates lost some of their prominent presence in the Dutch historical world, perhaps because their main protagonists, such as Ankersmit and Chris Lorenz, turned their attention towards the international scene. Illustrative of this tendency is the fact that Ankersmit’s Sublime Historical Experience, in preparation since the 1990s, first appeared in English in 2005, and two years later in Dutch, in a somewhat revised version. Whereas in the 1980s Dutch historical theorists developed their ideas in Dutch debates and later presented them in an inter- national context, after about 1990, and certainly after 2000, the order of Dutch and English seems to have reversed, at least in Ankersmit’s case. The reading of Ankersmit’s work presented here is a contextualising in- terpretation. This might deserve some explication. What I intend to do is to connect some of Ankersmit’s Dutch writings to their Dutch context and to other texts in that context. This does not necessarily unveil the “true” or “real” intentions behind Ankersmit’s writings. In the end, if these can be known at all, it is only by the author himself, and I have made no effort to reconstruct Ankersmit’s motives in writing certain texts by, for instance, analysing his state- ments in interviews. The aim of my contextual reading of Ankersmit’s Dutch 1 H. Paul and A. van Veldhuizen, “A Retrieval of Historicism: Frank Ankersmit’s Philosophy of History and Politics,” History and Theory, 57 (2018), 33–55. journal of the philosophy of history 12 (2018) 450–471Downloaded from Brill.com09/27/2021 02:16:50PM via free access 452 Bos work is to draw attention to certain connections and contrasts that might shed a new light on his oeuvre for an international audience. One point that will emerge from this analysis is that there is a remarkable continuity between Ankersmit’s earliest Dutch writings and his later work. An important theme in Sublime Historical Experience is the radical rejection of linguistic transcendentalism, the idea that our knowledge and experience are shaped by language. This point of view might seem novel, emerging as a result of Ankersmit’s search for a direct experience of the past. This search had already begun in Dutch in his 1993 inaugural lecture on historical experience. Ankersmit’s criticism of linguistic transcendentalism is even older, though. In his Dutch writings of the 1970s and 1980s he is already very explicit about this topic, and an important ambition in his turn to the concept of representation in the 1990s is to rethink the relation between language and reality in such a way that the pitfalls of linguistic transcendentalism can be avoided. 1 History and the Social Sciences In the 1980s, historical theory became a flourishing discipline in the Netherlands. In all history departments in the country one or more theorists worked with the explicit task of teaching philosophy of history and historiog- raphy and doing research in the field. This exceptional situation was codified in the revision of the so-called Academisch Statuut in 1982, which prescribed that every history student in the Netherlands should take at least one course in historiography, methodology and philosophy of history.2 As Chris Lorenz has recently shown, the revision of the Academisch Statuut was not the be- ginning of the rise of historical theory in the Netherlands but rather a formal affirmation of a development that had taken place during the previous de- cade. According to Lorenz, the institutionalisation of historical theory in the Netherlands had already started in the 1970s, as a result of, on the one hand, international developments within the historical discipline, and, on the other hand, Dutch university politics and student activism. In the 1970s the most 2 For an overview of Dutch philosophy of history in the 1980s, see J. Tollebeek, “De ekster en de kooi. Over het (bedrieglijke) succes van de theoretische geschiedenis in Nederland,” Bijdragen en Mededelingen betreffende de Geschiedenis der Nederlanden, 110 (1995), 52–72, and L. J. Dorsman, “Geschiedfilosofie in Nederland na 1945. Een overzicht,” in J. W. ter Avest et al. (eds.), Over nut en nadeel van geschiedtheorie voor de historicus (Leiden: Stichting Leidschrift, 1988), 99–116. A broader perspective on the success of Dutch philosophy of history in the 1980s is developed in the essays in J. Bos, H. Paul and K. Thijs (eds.), Geschiedfilosofie in Nederland, 1860–2000, Tijdschrift voor Geschiedenis, 129 (2016). journal of the philosophy of historyDownloaded 12from (2018) Brill.com09/27/2021 450–471 02:16:50PM via free access Ankersmit’s Dutch Writings and Their Audience 453 important theoretical debate within academic historiography was between proponents of social scientific methods and approaches and those defend- ing more traditional historical methods. Critical students tended to identify with the former party in this debate, and in the Dutch context of the 1970s they had a strong say in their programmes of study. Although the Dutch stu- dent protests of the late 1960s had been relatively peaceful in comparison with other European countries, the result was a very far-reaching democratisation of university governance, with students and university staff below the rank of full professor acquiring a significant influence in the newly established uni- versity and faculty councils. Furthermore, students also got seats in the uni- versity delegations to the Academische Raad, which was responsible for the Academisch Statuut and thus for the national regulation of the curricula of the various degree programmes. In the subcommittee for history in 1977, stu- dents and non-professorial staff managed to add historiography, methodology and philosophy of history to a proposal to amend the Academisch Statuut. Yet, according to Lorenz, even this early political step should be seen as a confir- mation of changes that were already taking place. In a situation of expanding student numbers and growing government budgets, the history departments in the country had started to create teaching positions for historical theory in order to meet the demand – driven by both developments in the historical dis- cipline and students’ wishes – for expertise in this field.3 In this context Frank Ankersmit was appointed at the University of Groningen in 1974, as one of the first of a group of academics that would shape the Dutch debates on historical theory in the 1980s.
Recommended publications
  • Newton.Indd | Sander Pinkse Boekproductie | 16-11-12 / 14:45 | Pag
    omslag Newton.indd | Sander Pinkse Boekproductie | 16-11-12 / 14:45 | Pag. 1 e Dutch Republic proved ‘A new light on several to be extremely receptive to major gures involved in the groundbreaking ideas of Newton Isaac Newton (–). the reception of Newton’s Dutch scholars such as Willem work.’ and the Netherlands Jacob ’s Gravesande and Petrus Prof. Bert Theunissen, Newton the Netherlands and van Musschenbroek played a Utrecht University crucial role in the adaption and How Isaac Newton was Fashioned dissemination of Newton’s work, ‘is book provides an in the Dutch Republic not only in the Netherlands important contribution to but also in the rest of Europe. EDITED BY ERIC JORINK In the course of the eighteenth the study of the European AND AD MAAS century, Newton’s ideas (in Enlightenment with new dierent guises and interpre- insights in the circulation tations) became a veritable hype in Dutch society. In Newton of knowledge.’ and the Netherlands Newton’s Prof. Frans van Lunteren, sudden success is analyzed in Leiden University great depth and put into a new perspective. Ad Maas is curator at the Museum Boerhaave, Leiden, the Netherlands. Eric Jorink is researcher at the Huygens Institute for Netherlands History (Royal Dutch Academy of Arts and Sciences). / www.lup.nl LUP Newton and the Netherlands.indd | Sander Pinkse Boekproductie | 16-11-12 / 16:47 | Pag. 1 Newton and the Netherlands Newton and the Netherlands.indd | Sander Pinkse Boekproductie | 16-11-12 / 16:47 | Pag. 2 Newton and the Netherlands.indd | Sander Pinkse Boekproductie | 16-11-12 / 16:47 | Pag.
    [Show full text]
  • The Actuality of Critical Theory in the Netherlands, 1931-1994 By
    The Actuality of Critical Theory in the Netherlands, 1931-1994 by Nicolaas Peter Barr Clingan A dissertation submitted in partial satisfaction of the requirements for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy in History in the Graduate Division of the University of California, Berkeley Committee in charge: Professor Martin E. Jay, Chair Professor John F. Connelly Professor Jeroen Dewulf Professor David W. Bates Spring 2012 Abstract The Actuality of Critical Theory in the Netherlands, 1931-1994 by Nicolaas Peter Barr Clingan Doctor of Philosophy in History University of California, Berkeley Professor Martin E. Jay, Chair This dissertation reconstructs the intellectual and political reception of Critical Theory, as first developed in Germany by the “Frankfurt School” at the Institute of Social Research and subsequently reformulated by Jürgen Habermas, in the Netherlands from the mid to late twentieth century. Although some studies have acknowledged the role played by Critical Theory in reshaping particular academic disciplines in the Netherlands, while others have mentioned the popularity of figures such as Herbert Marcuse during the upheavals of the 1960s, this study shows how Critical Theory was appropriated more widely to challenge the technocratic directions taken by the project of vernieuwing (renewal or modernization) after World War II. During the sweeping transformations of Dutch society in the postwar period, the demands for greater democratization—of the universities, of the political parties under the system of “pillarization,” and of
    [Show full text]
  • A “Calvinist” Theory of Matter? Burgersdijk and Descartes on Res Extensa
    Title Page A “Calvinist” Theory of Matter? Burgersdijk and Descartes on res extensa Giovanni Gellera ORCID IDENTIFIER 0000-0002-8403-3170 Section de philosophie, Université de Lausanne [email protected] The Version of Record of this manuscript has been published and is available in Intellectual History Review volume 28 (2018), issue 2. Published online 24 Novembre 2017. http://www.tandfonline.com/doi/full/10.1080/17496977.2017.1374058 Abstract In the Dutch debates on Cartesianism of the 1640s, a minority believed that some Cartesian views were in fact Calvinist ones. The paper argues that, among others, a likely precursor of this position is the Aristotelian Franco Burgersdijk (1590-1635), who held a reductionist view of accidents and of the essential extension of matter on Calvinist grounds. It seems unlikely that Descartes was unaware of these views. The claim is that Descartes had two aims in his Replies to Arnauld: to show the compatibility of res extensa and the Catholic transubstantiation but also to differentiate the res extensa from some views of matter explicitly defended by some Calvinists. The association with Calvinism will be eventually used polemically against Cartesianism, for example in France. The paper finally suggests that, notwithstanding the points of conflict, the affinities between the theologically relevant theories of accidents, matter and extension ultimately facilitated the dissemination of Cartesianism among the Calvinists. Keywords: Descartes, Burgersdijk, res extensa, accident, Calvinist scholasticism, eucharist 2 G. GELLERA A “Calvinist” Theory of Matter? Burgersdijk and Descartes on res extensa Giovanni Gellera University of Lausanne, Switzerland In 1651 Count Louis Henry of Nassau demanded that the Dutch universities issue public statements on Cartesian philosophy.
    [Show full text]
  • Research Review Philosophy 2012-2017
    RESEARCH REVIEW PHILOSOPHY 2012-2017 RESEARCH REVIEW – PHILOSOPHY De Onderzoekerij Vondellaan 58 2332 AH Leiden Phone: +31 6 24812176 Email: [email protected] Internet: www.onderzoekerij.nl Page 2/56 RESEARCH REVIEW – PHILOSOPHY Contents Preface ............................................................................................................................................... 6 1. Introduction ................................................................................................................................... 7 1.1 Terms of reference for the assessment ....................................................................................................................................................................................................... 7 1.2 The Review Committee ....................................................................................................................................................................................................................................................... 7 1.3 Procedures followed by the Committee ................................................................................................................................................................................................... 7 1.4 Application of the SEP scores ...................................................................................................................................................................................................................................
    [Show full text]
  • BCA Schedule
    A General philosophy AA8A A Rational enquiry, formal & abstract modes of enquiry Philosophy AA General philosophy * Studies in which reasoning is the fundamental instrument, History of philosophy in general AA7 whether or not combined with observation and experiment. * Add to AA7 letters A/V from Auxiliary Schedule 4B - e.g. * For the organization of knowledge and the relations epistemology in the 20th century (i.e. covering both between different disciplines, see Class 6. Western & Oriental studies) AAG R7R. A9 Philosophy & science * Alternative (not recommended) for libraries wishing to * Considered together. cite Branches & Viewpoints before broad traditions and historical `schools'. If this option is taken, assign notation as follows: AA Philosophy * | AA7 Periods * For history of ideas see Social sciences and humanities * | . * Add to AA7 as above from Schedule 4B. JZ9 Q. * | AA8 . Western philosophy in general AA2 . Common subdivisions * | . * Instead of AB. * Add to AA numbers 2/6 from Auxiliary Schedule 1 * | AA9 . By place with the slight modifications indicated at 6T/6Y. * | . * Instead of ADA. AA3 B . Dictionaries, glossaries * | . * Add to AA9 letters D/Z from G . Serials, periodicals * | . Schedule 2. AA5 . Organizations in philosophy * | AAB . By broad period & place R . Documents & libraries in philosophy * | . * Instead of ADB/ADX. AA6 A . Study & education in philosophy * | . * Add to AA letters B/X following AD * . Phase relations, interactions with other classes | . - e.g. AAR Renaissance. * | AAY . Individual Western philosophers A/Z * Use these instead of 9C/9K, if necessary. Most of the * | . * Instead of alternative at AE. relations occur as integral classes within the * | AB . Eastern philosophy philosophy schedule (e.g.
    [Show full text]
  • Chapter 18 Albert Borgmann and a Philosophy of Technology? I Begin
    Technè 10:2 Winter 2006 Special Issue: Durbin, In Search of Discourse Synthesis/168 Chapter 18 Albert Borgmann and a Philosophy of Technology? I begin this chapter with Higgs, Light, and Strong and their argument in Technology and the Good Life? (2000) in favor of the need for a new discipline: Broadening the scope of Philosophy of Technology “The set of questions a philosophy of technology should address in order to fulfill its promise are often at the intersection of it and other fields. In our opinion, philosophy of technology at its best should appeal to a very wide audience partly because it illuminates our shared, ordinary everyday life, such as with things and devices, and partly because the issues it probes cut across the full range of disciplines. Many of these issues are already vital matters of concern for these disciplines, such as ethics, social and political philosophy, aesthetics, art history, architecture, music, anthropology, religion, history, history of science and technology, cultural studies, sociology, political science, economics, linguistics, literary criticism, visual culture, and the hard sciences. For example, one of the interdisciplinary successes that philosophy of technology has had is with environmental ethics. Issues that join both fields are addressed in journals regularly, and numerous books have appeared. However, this kind of success should be occurring with other fields as well. What does philosophy of technology have to offer other disciplines? In the view of some of our contributors, traditional philosophical approaches may not be capable of questioning and challenging technology in a sufficiently radical manner. Nevertheless, we can show the kinds of questions a robust philosophy of technology can raise and address.
    [Show full text]
  • Frans Hemsterhuis
    r ! 55 MICHIEL WIELEMA, ERASMUS UNIVERSITY, ROTTERDAM Frans Hemsterhuis: A Philosopher's View of the History of the Dl;ltch Republic / In the English-speaking world, the Dutch record of philosophy in the Netherlands, both philosopher Frans Hemsterhuis (1721-1790) in a national and an international perspective. is still comparatively unknown. Despite the It is becoming clear that the Netherlands, fact that he was the most original Dutch especially in the seventeenth and eighteenth thinker of the eighteenth century, there is centuries, played an extremely important role only one book on him in English, together in the development and transmission of with a few articles. 1 At the moment, his ideas philosophical ideas. 5 Although Dutch are the subject of research both in the philosophers were part and parcel of general Netherlands itself and in Germany, France European movements of thought, their and Italy. In November and December 1990, contribution to philosophy was in many ways two international symposia were held to highly original. commemorate his death two centuries ago. Attention was focused on his philosophical In the case of Hemsterhuis, this contribution achievement as well as on the reception of his concerned such diverse topics as thought in the Netherlands and in Germany. mathematics, astronomy, optics, philosophy, The proceedings of these symposia will soon ethics, politics, history, aesthetics and be published. A Dutch translation of his religion. His ideas in these fields mark him complete works and of some hitherto as a thinker who has left behind naive unpublished letters (he wrote only in French) Enlightenment rationalism, and has opened is being prepared in three volumes.
    [Show full text]
  • Research Guide to Philosophy
    Research Guide to Philosophy John M. Kelly Library University of St. Michael’s College MULTI-VOLUME ENCYCLOPEDIAS CONTENTS Routledge Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Edited by Edward Craig. London: Routledge, 1998. 10 volumes. Multi –Volume Encyclopedias 1 [Available online for UofT use: http://www.library.utoronto.ca] General Dictionaries and Handbooks 2 [Print version: St. Michael's 1st Floor Reference Area – B 51 .R68 1998] Branches of Philosophy - Dictionaries & Handbooks 3 The definitive English-language philosophy encyclopedia. Over 2,000 Summaries 5 articles – thematic, biographical, and national – ranging from 500 to Manuals 5 15,000 words in length, written by over 1,200 renowned authors from Finding Journal Articles 6 around the world. Bibliographies 6 Web Guides 7 The Encyclopedia of Philosophy. 2nd ed. Edited by Donald M. Borchert. Detroit: Macmillan Reference, 2006. 10 volumes. Associations 7 [Available online for UofT use: http://www.library.utoronto.ca] [Victoria Pratt and Trinity Graham, Reference Area – B 41 .E53 2006] Over 2100 lengthy articles with extensive bibliographies on every aspect of Eastern and Western philosophy, ancient, medieval, and modern. The Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy [Available online: http://www.iep.utm.edu] Almost 500 peer-reviewed articles contributed by professional philosophers or graduate students. Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy [Available online: http://plato.stanford.edu/] Peer-reviewed articles contributed by professional philosophers. New Catholic Encyclopedia. 2nd edition. Washington, DC: Gale, 2003. 15 volumes + annual supplements. [Available online for UofT use: http://www.library.utoronto.ca] [St. Michael’s 1st Floor Reference Area – BX 841 .N44 2003] The major English-language encyclopedia on Catholic topics. There is an article entitled “Philosophy, Articles on” which provides an overview of the encyclopedia’s philosophical content and identifies several hundred entries relating to philosophy.
    [Show full text]
  • Beth's Views Hâve Been Developed in Close Connection with His Intellectual Environment, As Is Shown, Notably in (Critical) Interaction with H.J
    PHILOSOPHIA SCIENTIÆ PAUL CORTOIS Science, culture, and the science of culture: Beth’s view Philosophia Scientiæ, tome 3, no 4 (1998-1999), p. 199-231 <http://www.numdam.org/item?id=PHSC_1998-1999__3_4_199_0> © Éditions Kimé, 1998-1999, tous droits réservés. L’accès aux archives de la revue « Philosophia Scientiæ » (http://poincare.univ-nancy2.fr/PhilosophiaScientiae/) implique l’accord avec les conditions générales d’utilisation (http://www. numdam.org/conditions). Toute utilisation commerciale ou im- pression systématique est constitutive d’une infraction pénale. Toute copie ou impression de ce fichier doit contenir la pré- sente mention de copyright. Article numérisé dans le cadre du programme Numérisation de documents anciens mathématiques http://www.numdam.org/ Science, Culture, and the Science of Culture: Bethfs View Paul CORTOIS KU Leuven/UFSIA Antwerp Abstract. In this article some less well-known aspects of Beth's gênerai philosophical ideas are reviewed and connected with each other, viz. his views on the perspectives for a new systematic philosophy, on the identity of the humanities, and on the rôle of philosophy and science with respect to culture and life. The resulting picture is that Beth did hâve a rather sophisticated vîew on the identity of the humanities. By means of a distinction between 'method' and 'mode of thought' (beschouwingswijze\ he defended their objectivity and, at the same time, the ineliminable rôle of an account in terms of intentions. Beth's 'scientific philosophy', on the other hand, has a double face: it is a philosophy of science and a scientific philosophy of life. The perspectives for a scientific philosophy of culture and life appear to be limited, however, as Beth came to recognize implicitly.
    [Show full text]
  • Few Modern Philosophers Have Determined Our Understanding of Early Modern Philosophy in the Way Hegel Has
    1 The Use of the Vernacular in Early Modern Philosophy Wiep van Bunge Hegel to Copleston Few modern philosophers have determined our understanding of early modern philosophy in the way Hegel has. More in particular, Hegel held highly influential views on the real significance of the language in which Philosophy came into its own after the Middle Ages. In his Lectures on the History of Philosophy Hegel introduced the issue in his paragraph on Luther, who completed his Reformation of Christianity, or so Hegel argued, by rendering the Bible into German, for according to Hegel philosophical self-consciousness can only be achieved in a native language, a language, that is, we can truly call our own. For, Hegel continued, only a language that is able to express our innermost concerns can serve as a vehicle for our subjectivity: In der Sprache ist der Mensch produzierend: es ist die erste Aüsserlichkeit, die der Mensch sich gibt durch die Sprache; es ist die erste, einfachste Form der Produktion, des Daseins, zu der er kommt im Bewusstsein; was der Mensch sich vorstellt, stellt er sich auch innerlich vor als gesprochen. Diese erste Form ist ein Gebrochenes, Fremdartiges, wenn der Mensch in einer fremden Sprache sich ausdrücken oder empfinden soll, was sein höchstes Interesse berührt. Dieser Bruch mit dem ersten Heraustreten in das Bewusstsein ist so aufgehoben; hier bei sich selbst in seinem Eigentum zu zein, in seiner Sprache zu sprechen, zu denken, gehört ebenso zur Form der Befreiung. Dies ist von unendlicher Wichtigkeit. Luther hätte nicht
    [Show full text]
  • Philosophy of Sport in Belgium and the Netherlands; History and Characteristics Van Hilvoorde, I.M.; Vorstenbosch, J.; Devisch, I
    VU Research Portal Philosophy of Sport in Belgium and the Netherlands; History and Characteristics van Hilvoorde, I.M.; Vorstenbosch, J.; Devisch, I. published in Journal of the Philosophy of Sport 2010 DOI (link to publisher) 10.1080/00948705.2010.9714778 document version Publisher's PDF, also known as Version of record Link to publication in VU Research Portal citation for published version (APA) van Hilvoorde, I. M., Vorstenbosch, J., & Devisch, I. (2010). Philosophy of Sport in Belgium and the Netherlands; History and Characteristics. Journal of the Philosophy of Sport, 37(2), 225-236. https://doi.org/10.1080/00948705.2010.9714778 General rights Copyright and moral rights for the publications made accessible in the public portal are retained by the authors and/or other copyright owners and it is a condition of accessing publications that users recognise and abide by the legal requirements associated with these rights. • Users may download and print one copy of any publication from the public portal for the purpose of private study or research. • You may not further distribute the material or use it for any profit-making activity or commercial gain • You may freely distribute the URL identifying the publication in the public portal ? Take down policy If you believe that this document breaches copyright please contact us providing details, and we will remove access to the work immediately and investigate your claim. E-mail address: [email protected] Download date: 01. Oct. 2021 Journal of the Philosophy of Sport, 2010, 37, 225-236 © 2010 Human Kinetics, Inc. Philosophy of Sport in Belgium and the Netherlands: History and Characteristics Ivo van Hilvoorde, Jan Vorstenbosch, and Ignaas Devisch For a few decades now, philosophy of sport has been an acknowledged area of philosophy.
    [Show full text]
  • The Authenticity and Significance of the Texts on the Rainbow and Probability
    APPENDIX THE AUTHENTICITY AND SIGNIFICANCE OF THE TEXTS ON THE RAINBOW AND PROBABILITY A. SPINOZA'S CONTEMPORARIES The most concrete and clear-cut information concerning the development of Spinoza's ideas on theoretical optics is to be found in his correspondence. It is evident from the letters that it was probably during the mid-1660's, the four years following the publication of his book on the principles of Cartesianism, that he was most actively involved in exploring the theoretical foundations of his professional concern with the grinding of lenses and the construction of optical instruments. During these years he was co-operating with Jan Hudde (1628-1704) in the preparation of lenses for telescopes. Hudde also composed a small treatise on dioptrics, which if it had been preserved would have provided us with invaluable insight into the precise manner in which Spinoza was then thinking about light and optics. It is apparent from the surviving letters not only that he thought very highly of Hudde's expertise in dioptrics, but that as might have been expected, they were both approaching the problems it presented from a basically Cartesian standpoint. In the summer of 1666, for example, when Spinoza wrote asking for advice on the possible advantages of plano-convex lenses, he also took the trouble to re-state Hudde's geometrical presentation of spheri­ cal aberration in algebraic terms.! It was also during these years that JarigJelles (1619120-1683), a close friend of Spinoza's who had paid for the publication of the book on the principles of Cartesianism, wrote asking him to explain an apparent anomaly in Descartes' Dioptrics.
    [Show full text]