Susan Stebbing's Role in Early Analytic

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Susan Stebbing's Role in Early Analytic SUSAN STEBBING ON INCOMPLETE SYMBOLS AND ANALYSIS FREDERIQUE JANSSEN-LAURET 1. Introduction: Susan Stebbing's Role in Early Analytic Philosophy Susan Stebbing (1885-1943) was a pivotal figure in early analytic philosophy. She made vital contributions to philosophical logic, metaphysics, the philosophy of physics, critical thinking, and applied philosophy. Yet she has thus far largely been overlooked by historians of analytic philosophy. Although a handful of good historical publications on Stebbing have recently appeared, they are either primarily biographical (Chapman 2013) or tend to concentrate on her criticisms of more central canonical figures (Beaney 2003; Milkov 2003; Beaney 2016). In particular, most of these works tend to describe Stebbing as a follower of G.E. Moore. In this paper I present a short version of the argument of Janssen- Lauret 2017, Janssen-Lauret forthcoming-a, and Janssen-Lauret forthcoming-b, uncovering Stebbing's positive and original contributions to those fields and to the development of analytic philosophy. My focus in this paper will be on Stebbing's distinctive contributions to incomplete symbol theory and her views on philosophical analysis. I show that she made a significant advance on Russell and Moore, presenting a solution to what was later to be called `the paradox of analysis' in 1932. 2. Susan Stebbing: Life and Works Susan Stebbing was born in London in 1885 and orphaned as a young girl. Her early ed- ucation was rather neglected because of her disability, M´eni`ere'sdisease, which caused fre- quent attacks of vertigo, dizziness and nausea. She studied at Girton College, Cambridge, a woman's college whose Mistress was the logician E.E.C. Jones (for Jones's contributions to logic, see Janssen-Lauret 2021). She studied History, followed by Moral Sciences (Philoso- phy). Stebbing's main philosophy tutor was W.E. Johnson, and initially took to the idealist philosophy of McTaggart and Bradley. As Cambridge allowed women to sit exams, but not to actually graduate with their degrees, in the early 1910s Stebbing moved to the Univer- sity of London for her MA. Stebbing completed her thesis in 1912 and regularly spoke at the Aristotelian Society and published papers in its Proceedings, while teaching for Girton on a casual basis. In London she met Moore, Russell, and Whitehead, who were to become her main philosophical interlocutors, although she remained wedded to idealism for a few more years (Stebbing 1916-17, 1917-18). Around this time Stebbing, who had always re- gretted her lack of early education in science due to her disability, also began a programme of self-education in physics and its philosophy. She began by publishing on Whitehead's philosophy of science (Stebbing 1924, 1924-25, 1926). Having taking up a lecturing post in 1 2 FREDERIQUE JANSSEN-LAURET 1920 at Bedford College, a women's college in London, she enjoyed great success there, ris- ing through the ranks to become the UK's first female professor of philosophy in 1933. She published primarily on philosophy of science, formal and philosophical logic, metaphysics, and language, including the first accessible book on the new polyadic logic (Stebbing 1930), and important rebuttals of idealist interpretations of physics (Stebbing 1937). Stebbing continued to suffer severe attacks of M´eni`ere'sdisease, but used these periods of illness to read books in English, French, and German, often publishing her thoughts as a book review. As a result of her extensive reading and trilingualism, Stebbing was one of the first outside continental Europe to see the significance of logical positivism. Her publications on the movement did much to introduce it to the British philosophical scene (Stebbing 1933b; also see Janssen-Lauret forthcoming-b). In the late 1930s, Stebbing, increasingly alarmed by the rise of fascism, began to write on the application of critical thinking to ethics and politics, and also worked with Jewish refugees, work which she continued until her death in 1943. 3. Against the `Moorean' Interpretation of Stebbing Stebbing took philosophical and scientific investigation to rest on a basis of ordinary- language truths|such as `I am perceiving some paper' and `Other people have seen this paper before me' (1929: 174)|and emphasised that to know a truth is by no means the same as to know its analysis. As a result, it has become de rigueur to portray her as, in Ayer's words, `very much a disciple of [G.E.] Moore' (Ayer 1977: 71). Twenty-first century commentators still largely describe Stebbing as engaging in Moorean common-sense philosophy or Moorean analysis (Milkov 2003: 354; Beaney 2016: 249-250). Even those who consider Stebbing an original thinker in her own right, like Beaney and Chapman, still describe her as `a committed Moorean' with respect to analysis and common-sense truths (Beaney and Chapman 2018: xx3-4). My interpretation of Stebbing is a different one. I argue that the resemblance between Stebbing's method and Moore's are more superficial than they appear at first sight. Steb- bing's ordinary-language truths, such as `I am perceiving some paper' and `Other people have seen this paper before me' (1929: 174), which she describes as jointly comprising `real- ism' rather than `common sense', are different from Moore's both in their content and in the purpose for which they are used. Moore mentioned as paradigm examples of common-sense truths such ordinary English statements as `There exists at present a living human body, which is my body', and `The earth has existed for many years past'. Stebbing's truths have a narrower focus, on perceptual content shared between the minds of different perceivers. And she is explicit that these `realist' truths make up a basis for both philosophical and scientific investigation, which she connects to her extensive work in philosophy of physics. What's more, I will show that Stebbing's careful work on incomplete symbol theory and metaphysical analysis, which was in part motivated by, and applied to, her opposition to idealist analyses of modern physics, yielded a solution to the paradox of analysis ten years before Langford first formulated this paradox as a problem for Moore. I conclude that we ought to regard Stebbing as the originator of a distinctive position of her own, grown out SUSAN STEBBING ON INCOMPLETE SYMBOLS AND ANALYSIS 3 of dialogue with Russell and Whitehead as well as Moore, rather than as an exponent of Moorean common-sense philosophy. Historians have so far overlooked or minimised Stebbing's originality because they take Stebbing's respectful tone towards Moore and her (perhaps gendered) humility in describing her own achievements at face value, and because there has been relatively little investigation into Stebbing's philosophy of physics. Historians (e.g. Beaney and Chapman 2018 x3) correctly note that Stebbing|who had begun her philosophical career working in a spirit sympathetic to idealism (e.g. Stebbing 1916-17)|credited her original conversion to the Cambridge School of philosophy to Moore's mentorship (Stebbing 1942). But Stebbing had intended the paper in which she claimed this as an homage to Moore. Given that context, she naturally concentrated on the influence of Moore rather than her other influences or her own originality, but this does not imply that she had few other influences or original views. Stebbing also allied herself with Moore, and self-identified as a member of the `Cambridge School', while discussing logical atomism (Stebbing 1933b: 5). But, there, too, further context must be taken into account. Her goal in that discussion was to draw a contrast between the Cambridge School and logical positivism with respect to their views on analysis. Stebbing placed herself on the same side of the divide as Moore specifically in the context of a quotation from Wisdom which set up Moore, representing the Cambridge School, in opposition to Wittgenstein, whose approach to analysis Stebbing tentatively classes with the positivists'. Wisdom describes a prevailing kind of Moore-Wittgenstein rivalry in 1930s UK analytic philosophy. I note that several well-known early and mid- analytic philosophers were influenced by Moore or declared themselves to be on Moore's side rather than Wittgenstein's. Besides Wisdom, we might mention Austin, and Ryle, and even David Lewis and D.M. Armstrong. Grice, for example, quotes Austin saying, ` Some like Witters, but Moore is my man' (Grice 1989: 381). Yet these male philosophers are rarely if ever described as `Mooreans' tout court. Their original views are never prefaced with `Moorean'; but, as I will show, this certainly happens to Stebbing's original views. There is a gendered trap here which historians of philosophy should avoid falling into. If cited in isolation, Stebbing 1942 and Stebbing 1933b may well provide a misleading impression about Stebbings originality and the breadth of her expertise. Her areas of specialisation, unlike Moores, included philosophy of science. Moore's philosophy had grown out of interaction with ancient philosophy during his Classics degree on the one hand, and with Kant on the other hand. He never made any serious venture into the philosophy of science. Stebbing saw the importance of a scientifically informed philosophy fit for the new science and mathematics of the age. In this respect she resembled Russell and Whitehead more than Moore. As a woman with a disability born in the Victorian era, Stebbing had not been offered the kind of deep immersion into physics and mathematics from which the young, able-bodied men Russell and Whitehead had benefited.3 After her move to London and her discovery of analytic philosophy, Stebbing embarked on a programme of self-education in the philosophy of physics. In the early 1920s, she began by writing on Whitehead (Stebbing 1924, 1924-25, 1926b) on whose views she wrote more papers than on Moores.
Recommended publications
  • Susan Stebbing and the Vienna Circle on Moral Philosophy I Introduction
    Susan Stebbing and the Vienna Circle on Moral Philosophy Anne Siegetsleitner SWIP UK Panel at the Joint Session of the Mind Association and Aristotelian Society, University of Warwick, UK, July 11, 2015 Abstract: Susan Stebbing, who is rarely mentioned in the history of analytic philosophy, was a prominent figure in the Unity of Science movement and maintained relationships with leading members of the Vienna Circle. This paper compares Stebbing’s conception of moral philosophy to those of Carnap, Neurath, and Schlick. At first glance, the conceptions of moral philosophy held by Stebbing and the Vienna Circle differ widely, as Stebbing rejects the logical empiricist standard view of moral philosophy generally ascribed to the Vienna Circle. What we now call normative or substantial ethics – and what is ruled out by the standard view – is an essential part of moral philosophy in Stebbing’s conception. A closer look reveals, however, that Schlick shares this view. He practiced normative and applied ethics on a eudaimonistic basis. The discrepancies further diminish once more general questions are addressed. Stebbing, Carnap, Neurath and Schlick endorse the perspective of scientific humanism. They are convinced that it is the task of humanity itself to improve human life conditions and that science is one of the most valuable means to this improvement. Therefore, Stebbing is close to the Vienna Circle in her conception of moral philosophy once the Vienna Circle is no longer reduced to a general rejection of normative ethics, and scientific humanism is taken into account. New insights may be gained by reconsidering the Ethical Movement. I Introduction Susan Stebbing (1885–1943) was the first female professor of philosophy in Great Britain, a leading figure of the so-called Cambridge School of Analysis, co-founder of the journal Analysis, and president of the Mind Association as well as of the Aristotelian Society.
    [Show full text]
  • Bergsonism and the History of Analytic Philosophy
    palgrave.com Andreas Vrahimis 1st ed. 2022, Approx. 335 p. Bergsonism and the History Printed book Hardcover Ca. 109,99 € | Ca. £99.99 | Ca. of Analytic Philosophy $139.99 [1]Ca. 117,69 € (D) | Ca. 120,99 € (A) Series: History of Analytic Philosophy | Ca. CHF 130,00 Recovers work by women in the history of philosophy, namely L. Susan eBook Stebbing and Karin Costelloe-Stephen Available from your library or Examines the importance of responses to Bergsonism for the development of springer.com/shop the history of analytic philosophy MyCopy [3] Traces the Vienna Circle’s project of overcoming metaphysics back to earlier Printed eBook for just criticisms of Bergsonian intuition € | $ 24.99 During the first quarter of the twentieth century, the French philosopher Henri Bergson became springer.com/mycopy an international celebrity, profoundly influencing contemporary intellectual and artistic currents. Error[en_EN | Export.Bookseller. While Bergsonism was fashionable, L. Susan Stebbing, Bertrand Russell, Moritz Schlick, and MediumType | SE] Rudolf Carnap launched different critical attacks against some of Bergson’s views. This book examines this series of critical responses to Bergsonism early in the history of analytic philosophy. Analytic criticisms of Bergsonism were influenced by William James, who saw Bergson as an ‘anti-intellectualist’ ally of American Pragmatism, and Max Scheler, who saw him as a prophet of Lebensphilosophie. Some of the main analytic objections to Bergson are answered in the work of Karin Costelloe-Stephen. Analytic anti-Bergsonism accompanied the earlier refutations of idealism by Russell and Moore, and later influenced the Vienna Circle’s critique of metaphysics. It eventually contributed to the formation of the view that ‘analytic’ philosophy is divided from its ‘continental’ counterpart.
    [Show full text]
  • Susan Stebbing, Incomplete Symbols, and Foundherentist Meta-Ontology Volume 5, Number 2 Frederique Janssen-Lauret Editor in Chief Kevin C
    JOURNAL FOR THE HISTORY OF ANALYTICAL PHILOSOPHY SUSAN STEBBING, INCOMPLETE SYMBOLS, AND FOUNDHERENTIST METa-ONTOLOGY VOLUME 5, NUMBER 2 FREDERIQUE JANSSEN-LAURET EDITOR IN CHIEF KEVIN C. KLEMENt, UnIVERSITY OF MASSACHUSETTS Susan Stebbing’s work on incomplete symbols and analysis EDITORIAL BOARD was instrumental in clarifying, sharpening, and improving the ANNALISA COLIVA, UnIVERSITY OF MODENA AND UC IRVINE project of logical constructions which was pivotal to early ana- GaRY EBBS, INDIANA UnIVERSITY BLOOMINGTON lytic philosophy. She dispelled use-mention confusions by re- GrEG FROSt-ARNOLD, HOBART AND WILLIAM SMITH COLLEGES stricting the term ‘incomplete symbol’ to expressions eliminable HENRY JACKMAN, YORK UnIVERSITY through analysis, rather than those expressions’ purported ref- SANDRA LaPOINte, MCMASTER UnIVERSITY erents, and distinguished linguistic analysis from analysis of CONSUELO PRETI, THE COLLEGE OF NEW JERSEY facts. In this paper I explore Stebbing’s role in analytic philos- MARCUS ROSSBERG, UnIVERSITY OF CONNECTICUT ophy’s development from anti-holism, presupposing that anal- ANTHONY SKELTON, WESTERN UnIVERSITY ysis terminates in simples, to the more holist or foundherentist MARK TEXTOR, KING’S COLLEGE LonDON analytic philosophy of the later 20th century. I read Stebbing AUDREY YAP, UnIVERSITY OF VICTORIA as a transitional figure who made room for more holist analytic RICHARD ZACH, UnIVERSITY OF CALGARY movements, e.g., applications of incomplete symbol theory to Quinean ontological commitment. Stebbing, I argue, is part of REVIEW EDITORS a historical narrative which starts with the holism of Bradley, JULIET FLOYD, BOSTON UnIVERSITY an early influence on her, to which Moore and Russell’s logi- CHRIS PINCOCK, OHIO STATE UnIVERSITY cal analysis was a response.
    [Show full text]
  • Introduction 1 the Analyst in Training
    Notes Introduction 1. Herbert (1935: 4) 2. Mitford (1956) 3. Jepson (1937) and Thouless (1930) 4. Sayers (1971: 53, 58) 5. Woolf (1942) 6. Orwell (2000) 7. Penguin Books company website (http://www.penguin.co.uk/static/cs/uk/0 /aboutus/aboutpenguin_companyhistory.html), accessed 16th February 2012. 8. Waithe (1995: xl–xli) 9. Witt (2004: 9) 10. A. E. Heath in his Introduction to the Thinker’s Library edition of II, 1948. 11. See, for instance, Witt (2004: 1) 12. See, for instance, Rorty (1991) 13. Barth (1992: 1) 14. Warnock (1996: xxxiv) 15. Stebbing (1942a: 518) 16. Peggy Pyke-Lees, personal communication 17. Annotation on a letter from Stebbing to Ursula Roberts, 22 October 1922, Stanford University Libraries. 18. Obituary, Manchester Guardian, 13 September 1943. 19. Stebbing (1928b: 237) 20. Russell (1946: 864) 21. Gallie (1952: 32) 22. Floyd (2009: 162) 1 The Analyst in Training 1. Wisdom (1943) 2. Peggy Pyke-Lees, personal communication 3. Ibid. 4. Letter to Miss Jebb, 31 October 1943, RHC BC AR 150/D381 Archives, Royal Holloway, University of London 5. Wisdom (1943: 1) 6. Hamann and Arnold (1999: 139) 7. See, for instance, Robinson (2009: 69–75) 8. MacDonald (1943: 15) 9. See, for instance, Megson and Lonsay (1961: 49) 10. Bradbrook (1969: 56) 11. Oakeley (1948: 39) 187 188 Notes 12. Bradley (1893: 550) 13. Moore (1942: 18) 14. Ducasse (1942: 225) 15. Moore (1903a: 433) 16. Moore (1903a: 444) 17. Moore 1903a: 445) 18. Soames (2003 :12) 19. Moore (1939: 146) 20. Ibid. 21. Moore (1939: 150) 22. Moore (1925: 33) 23.
    [Show full text]
  • 2021 APA Eastern Division Meeting Program
    The American Philosophical Association EASTERN DIVISION ONE HUNDRED SEVENTEENTH ANNUAL MEETING PROGRAM VIRTUAL MEETING JANUARY 7 – 9, 2021 AND JANUARY 14 – 16, 2021 Use Coupon Code ZAPE21 to Save 30% (PB)/50% (HC) THROUGH FEBRUARY 16, 2021 ORDER ONLINE AT WWW.SUNYPRESS.EDU Critique in German Philosophy The Aesthetic Clinic From Kant to Critical Theory Feminine Sublimation in Contemporary María del Rosario Acosta López and Writing, Psychoanalysis, and Art J. Colin McQuillan, editors Fernanda Negrete The Primary Way The Disintegration of Community Philosophy of Yijing On Jorge Portilla’s Social and Political Chung-ying Cheng Philosophy, With Translations Foreword by Robert Cummings Neville of Selected Essays Carlos Alberto Sánchez and Jouissance Francisco Gallegos, editors A Lacanian Concept Néstor A. Braunstein Endangered Excellence Translation and Introduction by On the Political Philosophy of Aristotle Silvia Rosman Pierre Pellegrin Translated by Anthony Preus Epistemic Responsibility Lorraine Code A World Not Made for Us Topics in Critical Environmental Philosophy Manufactured Uncertainty Keith R. Peterson Implications for Climate Change Skepticism Recovering the Liberal Spirit Lorraine Code Nietzsche, Individuality, and Spiritual Freedom On Metaphysical Necessity Steven F. Pittz Essays on God, the World, Morality, and Democracy Adult Life Franklin I. Gamwell Aging, Responsibility, and the Pursuit of Happiness Carl Schmitt between John Russon Technological Rationality and Theology Modernity as Exception The Position and Meaning and Miracle
    [Show full text]
  • Susan Stebbing's Metaphysics and the Status Of
    The University of Manchester Research Susan Stebbing’s Metaphysics and the Status of Common- Sense Truths Document Version Accepted author manuscript Link to publication record in Manchester Research Explorer Citation for published version (APA): Janssen-Lauret, F. (Accepted/In press). Susan Stebbing’s Metaphysics and the Status of Common-Sense Truths. In J. Peijnenburg, & S. Verhaegh (Eds.), Women in the History of Analytic Philosophy Springer Nature. Published in: Women in the History of Analytic Philosophy Citing this paper Please note that where the full-text provided on Manchester Research Explorer is the Author Accepted Manuscript or Proof version this may differ from the final Published version. If citing, it is advised that you check and use the publisher's definitive version. General rights Copyright and moral rights for the publications made accessible in the Research Explorer are retained by the authors and/or other copyright owners and it is a condition of accessing publications that users recognise and abide by the legal requirements associated with these rights. Takedown policy If you believe that this document breaches copyright please refer to the University of Manchester’s Takedown Procedures [http://man.ac.uk/04Y6Bo] or contact [email protected] providing relevant details, so we can investigate your claim. Download date:28. Sep. 2021 Susan Stebbing (1885-1943) !1 Brief Biography Susan Stebbing was born in London in 1885. She studied History and Moral Sciences at Girton College, Cambridge, whose Mistress was the logician E.E.C. Jones. Stebbing's main philosophy tutor was W.E. Johnson. She always regretted that she had been unable to pursue a science degree due to her disability, Ménière's disease, which caused frequent attacks of vertigo, dizziness and nausea.
    [Show full text]
  • L. Susan Stebbing, CEM Joad, and Philipp Frank on the Philosophy Of
    Knowledge Missemination: L. Susan Stebbing, C.E.M. Joad, and Philipp Frank on the Philosophy of the Physicists Adam Tamas Tuboly Institute of Philosophy, Hungarian Academy of Sciences; Institute of Transdisciplinary Discoveries, University of Pecs Science popularization might take different forms. In the early twentieth cen- tury, Sir James Jeans and Sir Arthur Eddington presented the most successful endeavors. Philosophers were highly unimpressed and disturbed by these pop- ular works and various authors declared their disagreement with the physi- cists’ philosophical books against their own philosophical background. I will discuss three different philosophers, L. Susan Stebbing, C. E. M. Joad, and Philipp Frank, whose three lines of criticism represent three different forms of philosophy, social engagement, and scientific outlook. What is interesting is that there was a point when the most diverse philosophers (of science) agreed in contrast of their common enemy, namely, those popularizing scientists that have their reputation and use it to propagate false, or at least misleading views about science, culture, and values. What we shall see is how far this agreement went among these figures and how the divergent strategies culminated in very similar results regarding knowledge dissemination. Keywords: Susan Stebbing, Arthur Eddington, James Jeans, philosophy of physics, popularization of science, C.E.M. Joad, Philipp Frank, logical empiricism The paper was first presented at the Matter and Life: Historico-logical Issues in Post-1800 Physics and Biology workshop (Sarton Centre for History of Science, Ghent University, 27. 08. 2018). I am indebted to Bohang Chen, Maarten van Dyck and Charles T. Wolfe. I am also grateful to George Reisch for the many discussions on Frank’s philosophy, the two anonymous reviewers of the journal and to Alexander Levine and Michael Whitworth for their kindness and help.
    [Show full text]
  • Sir Karl Raimund Popper Papers, 1928-1995
    http://oac.cdlib.org/findaid/ark:/13030/tf8c60064j No online items Register of the Sir Karl Raimund Popper Papers, 1928-1995 Finding aid prepared by Hoover Institution staff and David Jacobs Hoover Institution Archives Stanford, CA, 94305-6010 (650) 723-3563 © 1998 Register of the Sir Karl Raimund 86039 1 Popper Papers, 1928-1995 Title: Sir Karl Raimund Popper papers Collection Number: 86039 Contributing Institution: Hoover Institution Archives Language of Material: In English Date (inclusive): 1928-1995 Abstract: Speeches and writings, correspondence, notes, printed matter, phonotapes, phonorecords, and photographs, relating to philosophy, the nature of knowledge, the philosophy of culture, the philosophy and methodology of science, and the philosophy of history and the social sciences. Deacribed in two groups, original collection (boxes 1-463) and the incremental materials acquired at a later date (boxes 464-583). Physical location: Hoover Institution Archives Collection Size: 575 manuscript boxes, 6 oversize boxes, 2 card file boxes, 28 envelopes, 47 phonotape reels, 4 phonotape cassettes, 11 phonorecords (248 linear feet) Creator: Popper, Karl Raimund, Sir, 1902- Access The collection is open for research. Use copies of sound recordings are available for immediate use. Publication Rights For copyright status, please contact the Hoover Institution Archives Acquisition Information Acquired by the Hoover Institution Archives in 1986 with increments added at a later date. Accruals Materials may have been added to the collection since this finding aid was prepared. To determine if this has occurred, find the collection in Stanford University's online catalog Socrates at http://library.stanford.edu/webcat . Materials have been added to the collection if the number of boxes listed in Socrates is larger than the number of boxes listed in this finding aid.
    [Show full text]
  • Knowledge Organization for a Global Learning Society
    Knowledge Organization for a Global Learning Society Advances in Knowledge Organization, Vol. 10 (2006) Knowledge Organization for a Global Learning Society Proceedings of the Ninth International ISKO Conference 4-7 July 2006 Vienna, Austria Edited by Gerhard Budin Christian Swertz Konstantin Mitgutsch ERGON VERLAG Predocumentation The volume contains: Introduction – Information Systems and Learning in a Global Society: Concepts, Design and Implementation – Global Society and Learning in Theories of Knowledge and Knowledge Organization – Multilingual problems of information retrieval – Representations of Educational and didactical knowledge – Theoretical basis of knowledge organization: universal vs. local solutions – Users and uses of knowledge organization – Ontologies – KO for non print multimedia – Linguistic and cultural approaches Bibliografische Information der Deutschen Bibliothek Die Deutsche Bibliothek verzeichnet diese Publikation in der Deutschen Nationalbibliografie; detaillierte bibliografische Daten sind im Internet über http://dnb.ddb.de abrufbar. 2006 ERGON Verlag · Dr. H.-J. Dietrich, D-97080 Würzburg This work is subject to copyright. All rights are reserved, whether the whole or part of the material is concerned, specifically the rights of translation, reprinting, reuse of illustrations, recitation, broadcasting, reproduction on microfilms or in other ways and storage in databanks. Duplication of this publication or parts thereof is only permitted under the provisions of the German Copyright Law, a copyright fee must always be paid. Cover Design : Jan von Hugo www.ergon-verlag.de Printed in Germany ISBN-10 3-89913-523-7 ISBN-13 978-3-89913-523-7 ISSN 0938-5495 Contents Introduction ..................................................................................................................... 9-10 1 Information Systems and Learning in a Global Society: Concepts, Design and Implementation Claudio Gnoli The meaning of facets in non-disciplinary classifications............................................
    [Show full text]
  • Susan Stebbing, Incomplete Symbols, and Foundherentist Meta-Ontology
    The University of Manchester Research Susan Stebbing, Incomplete Symbols, and Foundherentist Meta-Ontology DOI: 10.15173/jhap.v5i2.2928 Document Version Accepted author manuscript Link to publication record in Manchester Research Explorer Citation for published version (APA): Janssen-Lauret, F. (2017). Susan Stebbing, Incomplete Symbols, and Foundherentist Meta-Ontology. Journal for the History of Analytical Philosophy, 5(2), 1-12. https://doi.org/10.15173/jhap.v5i2.2928 Published in: Journal for the History of Analytical Philosophy Citing this paper Please note that where the full-text provided on Manchester Research Explorer is the Author Accepted Manuscript or Proof version this may differ from the final Published version. If citing, it is advised that you check and use the publisher's definitive version. General rights Copyright and moral rights for the publications made accessible in the Research Explorer are retained by the authors and/or other copyright owners and it is a condition of accessing publications that users recognise and abide by the legal requirements associated with these rights. Takedown policy If you believe that this document breaches copyright please refer to the University of Manchester’s Takedown Procedures [http://man.ac.uk/04Y6Bo] or contact [email protected] providing relevant details, so we can investigate your claim. Download date:26. Sep. 2021 SUSAN STEBBING, INCOMPLETE SYMBOLS, AND FOUNDHERENTIST META-ONTOLOGY FREDERIQUE JANSSEN-LAURET//PRE-PUBLICATION DRAFT. FORTHCOMING IN THE JOURNAL FOR THE HISTORY OF ANALYTICAL PHILOSOPHY. Abstract. Susan Stebbing's work on incomplete symbols and analysis was instrumental in clarifying, sharpening, and improving the project of logical constructions which was pivotal to early analytic philosophy.
    [Show full text]
  • 1 History of Analytic Philosophy Honours Course 2016-7 Lecture
    History of Analytic Philosophy Honours Course 2016-7 Lecture: Time: Monday 12.10-13.00 Honours Tutorial: Tutorial 1: Monday 14.10-15.00 Tutorial 2: Monday 15.10-16.00 Instructor: Bryan Pickel Office: Room 4.04b, Dugald Stewart Building Office-hours: Wednesday 3-5 Course Description: Towards the beginning of the twentieth century, a rich and influential tradition known as Analytic Philosophy emerged, which became predominate style of philosophy in the English speaking world. In this course, we will look at the early history of this movement, as reflected in the works of Frege, Russell, and Moore. This tradition emerged from two trends. One trend was a rejection of the idealism that had become popular in philosophy in the 19th century. Idealism holds that the world is somehow dependent on our conception of it. Frege, Russell, and Moore each developed frameworks according which the world is objective, and is not altered by what we think about it. The other major trend was that philosophers sought to apply developments in logic and the study of language to traditional philosophical problems. Difficulties in understanding the foundations of mathematics led Frege and Russell to develop rigorous new ways of thinking about logic and language. These tools form the foundation of many developments in contemporary logic and linguistics. But Frege and Russell went beyond the investigation of logic, mathematics, and language. We will see how these tools were put to use in understanding the structure of human thought and the world it represents, and in resolving scientific puzzles. Course Summary: This course will cover the philosophical climate in which Frege, Moore, and Russell developed, their views on traditional philosophical issues, and the distinctive debates that arose within the emerging tradition.
    [Show full text]
  • Monthly Record March, 1939
    SOUTH PLACE ETHICAL SOCIETY CONWAY HALL, RED LION SQUARE, LONDON, W.C.I. THE MONTHLY RECORD MARCH, 1939 SUNDAY MORNINGS AT ELEVEN February 26.—J. McCABE—The Subtle Tyranny of the Press. Pianoforte Solo: Rondo in C, Op. 51, No. 1 Beethoven MR. WILLIAM Buscu Hymns: Nos. 41 and 68 March 5. W. B. CURRY, M.A., B.Sc.—If War Comes. Soprano Solo: On Mighty Pens .. .. Haydn MISS HEBE SIMPSON Bass Solo: When the King went forth to war Koeneman MR. G. C. DOWMAN Hymns: Nos. 141 and 12. March 12. Professor T. H. PEAR, M.A., B.Sc.—The Social Psychology of Everyday Life Pianoforte Solo: Impromptu in B flat, Op. 142, Theme and Variations .. Schubert MR. WILLIAM BUSCH Hymns: Nos. 45 and 64 March 19. Dr. C. E. M. JOAD, M.A.—The Twilight of the Gods. Bass Solo: Myself when young .. Liza Lehmann MR. G. C. DOWMAN Soprano Solo: Faith in Spring .. Schubert , MISS HEBE SIMPSON Hymns: Nos. 115 and 63. March 26. Professor SUSAN STEBB1NG, M.A., D.Litt.—Science and "Hidden Reality." First two movements of Sonata in A, Op. 100, for Violin an . d Bra hms Pianoforte 1. Allegro Amabile. it. Andante tranquillo—vivace MISS BEKFRIX MARR AND MR. WILLIAM BUSCH Hymns : Nos. 94 and 76. Society's Pianist: MR. WILLIAM BUSCH VISITORS WELCOME A Collection is made at each Meeting to enable those present to contribute to the Society's expenses. OFFICIAL CAR PARK—Opposite Main Entrance. SOUTH PLACE ETHICAL SOCIETY, CONWAY HALL, RED LION SQUARE, LONDON, W.C. I . Chancery 8032 "THE OBJECTS OF THE SOCIETY arc the study and dissemination of ethical principles and the cultivation of a rational religious sentiment." MEMBERSHIP Any person in sympathy with the Objects of thc Society is cordially invited to become a MEMBER.
    [Show full text]