A Hundred Years of Philosophy

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

A Hundred Years of Philosophy A HUNDRED YEARS OF PHILOSOPHY John Passmore -*\ I f,o, )t, \.*_ PENGUIN BOOKS l'\ ("(" NOTES NOTBS formulated in words, or ever ent€red anybody's mind as a thought'. Thus a proposition is neither a set ofwords nor a thought; and logic is certainly oot, as had been traditionally supposed, a 'science of thought'. The pro- Notes position exists independently of statements; at the same time it is what statements mean. It bears a family resemblance to what Meinong was to CHAPTER 9 call an 'objective'. See the Historical Introduction to the English translation (1950) of The Paradoxes of the Infinite; H. R. Smart: 'Bolzano's Logio' l. SeeRussell's autobiography in The Philosophy of Bertrand Russelland (both (PX, 1944); Y. Bar-Hillel:'Bolzano's Propositional Logio' (Arch.fiir Math. Moore's in The Philosophy of G. E. Moore ed. P. A. Schilpp). Seealso (1958); (1958); Los.,1952) and 'Bolzano's Definition of Analytic Propositions' (Metho- A. R. White: G. E. Moore the Moore numbet of Philosophy (1960); dos, 1950); J. Berg: Bolzato's Logic (1962), On Husserl and Bolzano see lhc Moore number of JP R. B. Braithwaite: 'G. E. Moore 1873- Farber, op. cir. and H. Felsl'Bolzano und Husserl'(Pililot. Iarhbuch dar l95E' (PBA,1961); N. Malcolm; 'G. E. Moore'in Knowledgeand Certainty Gdrre sge se I Ischaft, 1926). (1963); D, Lewis: 'Moore's Realism' in Moore and Ryle (Iowa Publica- 19. For reservations and complications see H, Spiegelberg: 'Phetromeo- tions,2, 1965). ology of Direct Evidence' (PPiR, l94l). Compare Meinong's'evidence' and 2. Moore's chapter on 'The Ideal' in Principia Ethica did, howcver, Brentatro's'perception'. The connexion with the Platonic-Carlesian tradi- grcatly affect the cultural life ofour century through its influence on 'the group'- tion, which distinguishes between'essence' and 'existence', will be obvious. llloomsbury Roger Fry, J. M. Keynes, Virginia Woolf, E. M. (1949); More recently, Lotzc in his Logic had defended the conception of an Forster. SeeJ. M. Keynes: Two Memoirs R. F. Harrod,:. The Life of 'immediate certainty which, whethercalled intuition or by some othername, J. M. Keynes (1951); J. K. Johnstone: The Bloomsbury Group (19541. must be admitted to exist'. 3. The poet, Moore's brother. *e W. B. Yeats and T. S. Moore: Their (ed. 20. See J. S. Fulton: 'The Cartesianism of Phenomenolory'(Pi, 1940). Correspondence V. Bridge, 1953), which largely consists of an attempt 21. See Chapter 19 below for details. Anerican phenomenologists aro by Yeats to understand G. E. Moore and by T. S. Moore to explain him, generally unwilling to accept Husserl's movement in an Idealist directioa. with an occasional admonitory note by G. E. Moore. SeeespeciallyM.Fat&t: Naturalismand SubJecttvtsm(1959).See also J. M. 4. 'Moore's Technique' in The Philosophy of G. E. Moore. 5. Seehis'Reply to My Critics'in ThePhilosophy of G. E. Moore. Edie: 'Recent Work in Phenomenology' (APQ, 1964) - with exte.nsino as Sorze Main Problems of bibliographies, and J. Q. Lzuer:. The Triunph of Subjecttvity (1958). 6. At John Wisdom's instigation, Philosophy. 42. See the Memoirs by C. A. Mtce (PBA, 1945); C. D. Broad (Mbtd, 5. One of the most controverted points in recent philosophy. See H. 1945),R. Kdght(Br.Jnl. &1. Psych., 1946); J. Passmore(in Stout's Godazd Joachim: The Natwe of Truth (19061; G. E. Moore:'Mr Joachim's.lValzre Natwe, 1952). ol' Tr uth' and J oachim's Reply ( Mind, l9O7); B. Russell :' On Propositions : What and How They Mean'(PIS,S, l9l9); F. P. Ramsey 43. See the Metwir by A. S. and E. M. S. (1900; J. Bryce: 'Henry They Are and Sidgwick' in Stadles ln Contemporary Biography (1903); L. Srcphen: G. E. Moore :' Facts and Propositions' (PAS S, 1927); G. Ryle :'Are There (P,{S, 'Henry Sidgvick' (Mirrd, l90l) and in DNB; C. D, Broad: 'Henry Sidg- Propositions?' 1929)and the subsequenldiscussion with R. Robinson vick' in Ethics and the lllstory ofPhilosophy (1952). (Mittd, l93l): M. Schlick: 'Facts and Propositions' and C. G. Hempel: 24. Sec his 'Some Fundamental Points in the Theory of Knowledgo' 'Some Remarks on "Facts" and Propositions' (Atalysis, 1935); C. A. (1911), reprinted in Studles in Philosophy atd Psychology (1930) in which llaylis: 'Facts, Propositions, Exemplification and Truth' (Mind, 1948); he claims to have worked out his views, although he did not publish them, A. Kaplan and l. Copilowish: 'Must There Be Propositions?' (Mr'zd, before Twardowski's article appeared (in 1894). Findlay in his Melrcng't 1939); A. Church: 'On Carnap's Analysis of Statements of Assertion and Theory of Objects draws attention to important points of difference between llclief ' (,42olysri,s,1950). Meinong aod Stout, especially on the nature of'content'. 8. For a later discussion ofthe same problem see Moore's'External and 25. See also R. F. Hoernl€: 'Professor Stout's Theory of Possibilities, lnternal Relations'(PlS, 1919,reprinted in Studies).Stebbing reports, in Truth and Enot' (Mind, l93l) and Stout's reply: 'Truth and Reality' hcr contribution to the Philosophy of G. E. Moore, that Moore later'ex- (Mirrd,832\. prcssedhimselfas unable to understand what he couldpossiblyhave meant by the views that he had previously stated and was quite convinced that they wcre wrong'. See Ch. 3 for Bradley and Ch. 5 for James on this same dis- tinction. Seealso A,C.Ewing's Idealism(1934)which draws attention to the rnunifold ambiguities in the whole controversy, and Russell's'The Monistic 'l'hoory of Truth' (Philosophlcal Essays, l9l0). 9. See C. A, Strong: 'Has Mr Moore refuted ldealism?' (Mind, l9O5\; A, K. Rogpts:'Mr Moore's Refutation of ldealism'(PX, 1919); J. Laird's 558 559 NOTES NOTES (Mittd, 192!); C, J. Ducasse: 'Moore'r review of Philosophical Stadies Russell's Loeic' (Philosophy of Bertrand RussetD; S. Waterlow: .Somc (it The Philosophy of G- E- Moore); B. Bosan' Refutation of Idealism' Philosophical Implications of Mr B. Russell's Logical Theory of Mathe_ qtet: in Contemporary Philosophy (1921). .Mr The Meet@ of Extremes matics'(P/,S, 1909); P. E. B. Jourdain: Bertrand Russell's First Work by Stout and Moore on 'The Status of Senso' 10. See the symposium on the Principles of Mathematics' (Monist, l9l2); F. p. Ramsey: Iila (PAS, Pratt: Moore's Realism (JP, 1923); M' C' Data' l9l3); J. B. 'Mr I.'oundationsof Mathenutics and Other Logical Essays(1931); F. Wais- E. Moore's Discussion of Sense-Data' (Monist, 1924)i Swabey: 'Mr G. mann: Introduction to Mathenatical Thinking (1930; J. Jorgensen: ,{ of Critical Philosophv' (PzaS, 1937); Joha .Whitehead A. E. Murphy: 'T\vo Versions Treatice of Formal Ingic (1931); E. J. Nelson: and Russell's (PlS' T. P. Nunn :' Sens€-Dat' Wisdom :' Philosophical Perplexity' 1936); Theory of Deducti ot' (Bul l. Am. Ma th. Soc., 1934\. (PAS, and Physical Objects' l9l5). 15. SeeJ. A, Chadwick: 'Logical Constants, (Mind, 1927,). 1963 A. E. Murphy :' Moore's Defence of Com' I l. Seethe articles in RM, ; 16. See particularly the summary in the second ler;fixe of Ow Ktrowledge mon Sense' it Reason and the Common Good (1963); A' F' Holmes: of the External lltorld (1914\, (.tP, 1961); N. Malcolm's article in 'Moore's Appeal to Common Sense' 17. SeePrinciples of Mathematics. Ch. XXVI, for details. Moote's later essays are collected in The Philosophy of G, E, Moore. 18, For the Frege-Russell correspondence see J, van Heijenoort: ,Sou,,cs Philosophica I Papers (I 9 59)' Book in Mathematical Logic 1879-1931(1964). Analysis' in Arulysis (1934)' That jour' 12. Seealso'The Justification of | 9. First in Appendix B to The principles of Mathematics, then in articles (1933) as a medium of publication for short studies in tho nal was founded on 'Mathematical Logic as Based on the Theory of Types' (Am. Jnl, consulted for examples of, and papers ont analytic manner, and should be Maths.,l9O8) and 'La Th6orie des types logiques' (RMM, lgl}\, but most generally see Ch. 15 below; J. O' Urmson: analysis. On analysis lully in Principia Mathematica. There is a relatively popular presentation in (1956); M' Black, John Wisdom and M. Cornforth: ' ophical Arulysis Russell's articles on 'The Philosophy of Logical Atomism to July l9l9' in Philosophv?' (PISS' 1934); A. E. Dunca Analysis a Useful Method (Monist, l9l8-19). His hesitancies are most marked in his Introduction to Analyse Common-Sense?'(Pl Jones and A. J. Ayer: 'Does Philosophy Mathematical Philosophy (1919). Since the theory of types was presented Method of Analysis in Metaphysics' (P. 1937); L. S. Stebbing: 'The independently by Russell in these various places, it is reasonable to refer to 1938);M. Black:' 1932)and'Some PuzzlesAbout Analysis'(PlS' it as 'Russell's' although Whitehead no doubt had some effect upon (Mbtd, its sophical Analysis' (PAS, 1912), 'The Paradox of Analysis' lg44,, method of formulation. Informative?'(PPX,1945) and his introduc' 1945),'How Can Analysisbe 20. For subsequent criticisms of Russell's account of vicious circles, see A. C. Ewing:'T\r'o Kinds of Analysio' tionto PhilosophicalArulysis,1950; Kurt Giidel: 'Russell's Mathematical l-ogic, (philosophy of Bertrand Rus- (Analysis, 1935) and'Philosophical Analvsis' (Philosophical Studies: sell). Stebbrzg, 1948); C. Lewy: 'Some Remarks Essaysin Memory of L, Susan 21. Particularly'the Dedekind cut'. SeeGiidel, op. cir. and G. H. Hardy Analysis' (Amlris, 1937); M. Macdonald'sIntroductioo to A Cowse of Pwe Mathenarics (1908). (1954). and Arclysis 22. ln Proceedings of the Inndon Mathematical Sociery, reprinted in the particularly Philosophv of Bertand Russell (ed. 13. See The posthnmons collection The Foundatlorrs of Mathenattcs and Other Loglcat Bertrand Russell's Conslruction of the External 1944): C. A. Fritz: trssays (ed. R. B.
Recommended publications
  • Brian Mcguinness Ist Am 23
    In Honor of Brian McGuinness Josef Mitterer My relation to Brian McGuinness is the respectful relation of a younger colleague and -- many years back -- the relation of an admiring student who met him in Graz where he became an honorary professor in 1988. The achievements of Brian McGuinness have been praised so often and by so many that it is not easy to say something new, to find new praise which has not been offered already by someone else. The basic data: Brian was born 90 years and 4 days ago -- he studied at Oxford university and spent 35 years a Tutor, as a Fellow and a University Lecturer at Queens College. From 1989 to 2002 he was a Professor of History of Scientific Thought at the University of Siena. From the list of universities where he taught as a guest professor: Stanford, Princeton, Bejing, Rome, Leiden, Graz ... Brian McGuinness has authored and edited more than 30 books. They include a new translation of the Tractatus, the edition and translation of the Prototractatus -- both together with David Pears – and together with Joachim Schulte he published the definitive edition of the Tractatus, one of the most influential philosophical books of the 20th century. It is safe to say that nobody in Academia has done as much for the recognition of Wittgenstein in particular and of Austrian Philosophy in general as Brian McGuinness in the course of 60 years of writing and lecturing. The academic world is inhabited by a variety of species. A very rare one is that of the geniuses who publish very little in their lifetime but fill notebooks, journals and "Zettel" with ideas – (nowadays more likely hard discs or memory sticks) 1 which are then left to hardworking academics who clear up the mess and edit collected works which establish the lasting fame and influence of those thinkers.
    [Show full text]
  • Hacker's Complaint
    VOL. NO. JULY CONTENTS ARTICLES Intentionalism and the Imaginability of the Inverted Spectrum Eric Marcus Metaphysical Arguments against Ordinary Objects Amie L. Thomasson Kant’s Transcendental Strategy John J. Callanan True Emotions Mikko Salmela Wittgenstein and Strong Mathematical Verificationism Cyrus Panjvani DISCUSSIONS Hacker’s Complaint Scott Soames Are There Non-Existent Intentionalia? Alberto Voltolini CRITICAL STUDY The Sort of Creature You Are Anselm W. Müller BOOK REVIEWS BLACKWELL PUBLISHING FOR THE SCOTS PHILOSOPHICAL CLUB AND THE UNIVERSITY OF ST ANDREWS The Philosophical Quarterly, Vol. , No. July ISSN – DISCUSSIONS HACKER’S COMPLAINT B S S My goal in writing ‘Philosophical Analysis in the Twentieth Century’ was to identify and explain the most important achievements of analytic philosophy which every student of the subject should be aware of, as well as those of its failures from which we have the most to learn. I attempted to do this by constructing a history that was itself a piece of analytic philosophy in its emphasis on analysis, reconstruction and criticism of arguments. In rebutting Hacker’s critique of it, I explain how my goal shaped my selection of topics, with special reference to the ordinary language period. I correct his misrepresentations of my treatment of the philosophers of this period, I demonstrate his failure to grasp, or understand the significance of, the Kripkean necessary a posteriori, and I reveal the misconceptions in his criticism of my interpretation of the ‘Tractatus’. I I am grateful to the Editors for inviting me to reply to P.M.S. Hacker’s review in this journal of my Philosophical Analysis in the Twentieth Century.1 I begin with his complaint about the materials I chose to discuss: In its selection of materials it is unrepresentative: significant figures are omitted and pivotal works are not discussed ..
    [Show full text]
  • THE PROPOSITION-AS-RULES IDEA* Christoffer Gefwert Academy of Finland, Helsinki
    SLAGP1TB3303 March 1984 WE) THE PROPOSITION-AS-RULES IDEA* Christoffer Gefwert Academy of Finland, Helsinki and Stanford Linear Accelerator Center Stanford University, Stanford, Caltfornia [email protected] Submitted to Synthese * Work supported in part by the Department of Energy, contract DEAC03- 76SF00515 and by the Academy of Finland. ..a single insight at the start is worth more than ever so many in the middle. Ludwig Wittgemtein . 0. INTRODUCTION: BROUWER AND WITTGENSTEIN. On 10th of March 1928, L.E.J.Brouwer, the main proponent of the intu- itionist philosophy of mathematics, came to Vienna to deliver a lecture entitled Mathematics, Science and Language.l Wittgenstein was present, together with Herbert Feigl and Friedrich Waismann, among the public attending Brouwer’s lecture.:! According to Feigl, perhaps this was the turning point, because after- wards, in a cafe, Wittgenstein suddenly began talking philosophy.3 It seems, in retrospect, that Brouwer’s lecture made a lasting impression on Wittgenstein. That he seems to have been influenced by Brouwer, is documented in a letter from Bertrand Russell to G.E.Moore in 1930, where we read: “He (Wittgenstein) uses the words ‘space’ and ‘grammar’ in peculiar senses, which are more or less connected with each other. He holds that if it is significant to say ‘This is red’ it-cannot be significant to say ‘This is loud’. There is one ‘space’ of colours and another ‘space’ of sounds. These ‘spaces’ are apparently given a priori in the Kantian sense, or at least not perhaps exactly that, but something not so very different. Mistakes in grammar result from confusing ‘spaces’.
    [Show full text]
  • Guide to Proper Names and References in Gödel's “Protokolle
    Guide to proper names and references in Gödel’s “Protokolle” notebook People Abel Othenio Abel (1875-1946) professor of paleontology and paleobiology at the University of Vienna. Founder of the group of professors known as the “Bärenhöhle” that blocked the appointment and promotion of Jews Adele Adele Nimbursky, née Porkert (1899–1981), Gödel’s girlfriend, separated from her first husband; she and Gödel would marry in September 1938 Bachmann Friedrich Bachmann (1909–1982), mathematician, doctoral student of Scholz’s at Münster, where he received his Ph.D. in 1933; from 1935 at University of Marburg, as assistant then Privatdozent Behmann Heinrich Behmann (1891–1970), German mathematician; his reply to Perelman’s criticism of Gödel’s result had appeared in the journal Mind in April 1937. He was dismissed from his position at ​ ​ the University of Halle after the war for his Nazi Party activities Beer Gustav Beer, member of the Vienna Circle and Menger’s Mathematical Colloquium Benjamin Abram Cornelius Benjamin (1897–1968), American philosopher of science on the University of Chicago faculty 1932 to 1945 Bernays Paul Bernays (1888–1977), Swiss mathematician and logician; close collaborator with David Hilbert on the foundations of mathematics and the axiomatization of set theory Brentano Franz Brentano (1838-1917), resigned as priest, Professor of Philosophy at the University of Vienna, founder of Gestalt Brunsvick Egon Brunswik (1903–1955), Hungarian-born psychologist, assistant to Karl Bühler in Vienna, active member of Otto Neurath’s “Unity of Science” movement Bühler Karl Bühler (1879–1963), professor of psychology at the University of Vienna. He led an effort to reorganize Vienna’s city schools by incorporating scientific findings from child psychology.
    [Show full text]
  • Susan Stebbing and the Vienna Circle on Moral Philosophy I Introduction
    Susan Stebbing and the Vienna Circle on Moral Philosophy Anne Siegetsleitner SWIP UK Panel at the Joint Session of the Mind Association and Aristotelian Society, University of Warwick, UK, July 11, 2015 Abstract: Susan Stebbing, who is rarely mentioned in the history of analytic philosophy, was a prominent figure in the Unity of Science movement and maintained relationships with leading members of the Vienna Circle. This paper compares Stebbing’s conception of moral philosophy to those of Carnap, Neurath, and Schlick. At first glance, the conceptions of moral philosophy held by Stebbing and the Vienna Circle differ widely, as Stebbing rejects the logical empiricist standard view of moral philosophy generally ascribed to the Vienna Circle. What we now call normative or substantial ethics – and what is ruled out by the standard view – is an essential part of moral philosophy in Stebbing’s conception. A closer look reveals, however, that Schlick shares this view. He practiced normative and applied ethics on a eudaimonistic basis. The discrepancies further diminish once more general questions are addressed. Stebbing, Carnap, Neurath and Schlick endorse the perspective of scientific humanism. They are convinced that it is the task of humanity itself to improve human life conditions and that science is one of the most valuable means to this improvement. Therefore, Stebbing is close to the Vienna Circle in her conception of moral philosophy once the Vienna Circle is no longer reduced to a general rejection of normative ethics, and scientific humanism is taken into account. New insights may be gained by reconsidering the Ethical Movement. I Introduction Susan Stebbing (1885–1943) was the first female professor of philosophy in Great Britain, a leading figure of the so-called Cambridge School of Analysis, co-founder of the journal Analysis, and president of the Mind Association as well as of the Aristotelian Society.
    [Show full text]
  • Bergsonism and the History of Analytic Philosophy
    palgrave.com Andreas Vrahimis 1st ed. 2022, Approx. 335 p. Bergsonism and the History Printed book Hardcover Ca. 109,99 € | Ca. £99.99 | Ca. of Analytic Philosophy $139.99 [1]Ca. 117,69 € (D) | Ca. 120,99 € (A) Series: History of Analytic Philosophy | Ca. CHF 130,00 Recovers work by women in the history of philosophy, namely L. Susan eBook Stebbing and Karin Costelloe-Stephen Available from your library or Examines the importance of responses to Bergsonism for the development of springer.com/shop the history of analytic philosophy MyCopy [3] Traces the Vienna Circle’s project of overcoming metaphysics back to earlier Printed eBook for just criticisms of Bergsonian intuition € | $ 24.99 During the first quarter of the twentieth century, the French philosopher Henri Bergson became springer.com/mycopy an international celebrity, profoundly influencing contemporary intellectual and artistic currents. Error[en_EN | Export.Bookseller. While Bergsonism was fashionable, L. Susan Stebbing, Bertrand Russell, Moritz Schlick, and MediumType | SE] Rudolf Carnap launched different critical attacks against some of Bergson’s views. This book examines this series of critical responses to Bergsonism early in the history of analytic philosophy. Analytic criticisms of Bergsonism were influenced by William James, who saw Bergson as an ‘anti-intellectualist’ ally of American Pragmatism, and Max Scheler, who saw him as a prophet of Lebensphilosophie. Some of the main analytic objections to Bergson are answered in the work of Karin Costelloe-Stephen. Analytic anti-Bergsonism accompanied the earlier refutations of idealism by Russell and Moore, and later influenced the Vienna Circle’s critique of metaphysics. It eventually contributed to the formation of the view that ‘analytic’ philosophy is divided from its ‘continental’ counterpart.
    [Show full text]
  • Friedrich Waismann - Causality and Logical Positivism Series: Vienna Circle Institute Yearbook
    springer.com B.F. McGuinness (Ed.) Friedrich Waismann - Causality and Logical Positivism Series: Vienna Circle Institute Yearbook A new understanding of Waismann's position in philosophy Sheds light on Waismannn's independent and inventive contributions to philosophy apart from his temporary function as Wittgenstein's spokesman Includes a publication of new or previously scattered material Friedrich Waismann (1896–1959) was one of the most gifted students and collaborators of Moritz Schlick. Accepted as a discussion partner by Wittgenstein from 1927 on, he functioned as spokesman for the latter’s ideas in the Schlick Circle, until Wittgenstein’s contact with this 2011, 372 p. most faithful interpreter was broken off in 1935 and not renewed when exile took Waismann to Cambridge. Nonetheless, at Oxford, where he went in 1939, and eventually became Reader Printed book in Philosophy of Mathematics (changing later to Philosophy of Science), Waismann made important and independent contributions to analytic philosophy and philosophy of science (for Hardcover example in relation to probability, causality and linguistic analysis). The full extent of these only 169,99 € | £149.99 | $219.99 became evident later when the larger (unpublished) part of his writings could be studied. His [1]181,89 € (D) | 186,99 € (A) | CHF 200,50 first posthumous work The Principles of Linguistic Philosophy (1965, 2nd edn.1997; German 1976) and his earlier Einführung in das mathematische Denken (1936) have recently proved of Softcover fresh interest to the scientific community. This late flowering and new understanding of 169,99 € | £149.99 | $219.99 Waismann’s position is connected with the fact that he somewhat unfairly fell under the [1]181,89 € (D) | 186,99 € (A) | CHF shadow of Wittgenstein, his mentor and predecessor.
    [Show full text]
  • Susan Stebbing, Incomplete Symbols, and Foundherentist Meta-Ontology Volume 5, Number 2 Frederique Janssen-Lauret Editor in Chief Kevin C
    JOURNAL FOR THE HISTORY OF ANALYTICAL PHILOSOPHY SUSAN STEBBING, INCOMPLETE SYMBOLS, AND FOUNDHERENTIST METa-ONTOLOGY VOLUME 5, NUMBER 2 FREDERIQUE JANSSEN-LAURET EDITOR IN CHIEF KEVIN C. KLEMENt, UnIVERSITY OF MASSACHUSETTS Susan Stebbing’s work on incomplete symbols and analysis EDITORIAL BOARD was instrumental in clarifying, sharpening, and improving the ANNALISA COLIVA, UnIVERSITY OF MODENA AND UC IRVINE project of logical constructions which was pivotal to early ana- GaRY EBBS, INDIANA UnIVERSITY BLOOMINGTON lytic philosophy. She dispelled use-mention confusions by re- GrEG FROSt-ARNOLD, HOBART AND WILLIAM SMITH COLLEGES stricting the term ‘incomplete symbol’ to expressions eliminable HENRY JACKMAN, YORK UnIVERSITY through analysis, rather than those expressions’ purported ref- SANDRA LaPOINte, MCMASTER UnIVERSITY erents, and distinguished linguistic analysis from analysis of CONSUELO PRETI, THE COLLEGE OF NEW JERSEY facts. In this paper I explore Stebbing’s role in analytic philos- MARCUS ROSSBERG, UnIVERSITY OF CONNECTICUT ophy’s development from anti-holism, presupposing that anal- ANTHONY SKELTON, WESTERN UnIVERSITY ysis terminates in simples, to the more holist or foundherentist MARK TEXTOR, KING’S COLLEGE LonDON analytic philosophy of the later 20th century. I read Stebbing AUDREY YAP, UnIVERSITY OF VICTORIA as a transitional figure who made room for more holist analytic RICHARD ZACH, UnIVERSITY OF CALGARY movements, e.g., applications of incomplete symbol theory to Quinean ontological commitment. Stebbing, I argue, is part of REVIEW EDITORS a historical narrative which starts with the holism of Bradley, JULIET FLOYD, BOSTON UnIVERSITY an early influence on her, to which Moore and Russell’s logi- CHRIS PINCOCK, OHIO STATE UnIVERSITY cal analysis was a response.
    [Show full text]
  • Nomination Form International Memory of the World Register
    Nomination form International Memory of the World Register Philosophical Nachlass of Ludwig Wittgenstein (Austria, Canada, Netherlands, UK) ID Code [2016-26] 1.0 Summary (max 200 words) The subject of this joint nomination is the complete philosophical Nachlass of Austrian-British philosopher Ludwig Wittgenstein. Ludwig Wittgenstein (1889-1951) is today widely recognized as one of the most important philosophers of the 20th century. His philosophy was the essential impulse to what was later called the “linguistic turn” in modern philosophy, but even beyond philosophy had a deep impact to many branches of the humanities and even in the arts. His famous Tractatus Logico-Philosophicus (written 1918, published1921), the only philosophical book he published during his lifetime, is one of the most influential philosophical books ever written. After a break of ten years - teaching as a primary school teacher and working as architect - Wittgenstein continued his philosophical work at the University of Cambridge and developed a new philosophy of ordinary language, which became one of the leading philosophical movements especially in the Anglo- American world. Wittgenstein was unable to realize his intention to publish his new ideas before his death in 1951. In 1953 his literary executors published the Philosophische Untersuchungen / Philosophical Investigations posthumously, which is seen as the magnum opus of his later philosophy and has become one of the most important books in the history of modern philosophy. Wittgenstein’s philosophical development from 1914 to the Tractatus and his continuous philosophical work from 1929 till the end of his life is documented in detail in his philosophical Nachlass. It was listed in a systematic and complete form in 1969 by Georg Henrik von Wright, his student and successor in his chair in Cambridge (“The Wittgenstein Papers” in: Philosophical Review Vol 78,4.1969, p 483-503).
    [Show full text]
  • The Vienna Circle Studies in the Origins, Development, and Influence of Logical Empiricism Series: Vienna Circle Institute Library
    springer.com Friedrich Stadler The Vienna Circle Studies in the Origins, Development, and Influence of Logical Empiricism Series: Vienna Circle Institute Library Presents an exemplary study of the rise of scientific thought and its vicissitudes in this century Contains the protocols of the Schlick Circle and an interview with Karl Popper Is the only available comprehensive history of the Vienna Circle in context in English This abridged and revised edition of the original book (Springer-Wien-New York: 2001) offers the only comprehensive history and documentation of the Vienna Circle based on new sources with an innovative historiographical approach to the study of science. With reference to previously unpublished archival material and more recent literature, it refutes a number of widespread clichés about "neo-positivism" or "logical positivism". Following some insights on the relation between the history of science and the philosophy of science, the book offers an 2015, XXXI, 681 p. 125 illus. accessible introduction to the complex subject of "the rise of scientific philosophy” in its socio- cultural background and European philosophical networks till the forced migration in the Anglo- Printed book Saxon world. The first part of the book focuses on the origins of Logical Empiricism before Hardcover World War I and the development of the Vienna Circle in "Red Vienna" (with the "Verein Ernst Mach"), its fate during Austro-Fascism (Schlick's murder 1936) and its final expulsion by 159,99 € | £139.99 | $199.99 [1]171,19 € (D) | 175,99 € (A) | CHF National-Socialism beginning with the "Anschluß" in 1938. It analyses the dynamics of the 189,00 Schlick-Circle in the intellectual context of "late enlightenment" including the minutes of the meetings from 1930 on for the first time published and presents an extensive description of Softcover the meetings and international Unity of Science conferences between 1929 and 1941.
    [Show full text]
  • Introduction 1 the Analyst in Training
    Notes Introduction 1. Herbert (1935: 4) 2. Mitford (1956) 3. Jepson (1937) and Thouless (1930) 4. Sayers (1971: 53, 58) 5. Woolf (1942) 6. Orwell (2000) 7. Penguin Books company website (http://www.penguin.co.uk/static/cs/uk/0 /aboutus/aboutpenguin_companyhistory.html), accessed 16th February 2012. 8. Waithe (1995: xl–xli) 9. Witt (2004: 9) 10. A. E. Heath in his Introduction to the Thinker’s Library edition of II, 1948. 11. See, for instance, Witt (2004: 1) 12. See, for instance, Rorty (1991) 13. Barth (1992: 1) 14. Warnock (1996: xxxiv) 15. Stebbing (1942a: 518) 16. Peggy Pyke-Lees, personal communication 17. Annotation on a letter from Stebbing to Ursula Roberts, 22 October 1922, Stanford University Libraries. 18. Obituary, Manchester Guardian, 13 September 1943. 19. Stebbing (1928b: 237) 20. Russell (1946: 864) 21. Gallie (1952: 32) 22. Floyd (2009: 162) 1 The Analyst in Training 1. Wisdom (1943) 2. Peggy Pyke-Lees, personal communication 3. Ibid. 4. Letter to Miss Jebb, 31 October 1943, RHC BC AR 150/D381 Archives, Royal Holloway, University of London 5. Wisdom (1943: 1) 6. Hamann and Arnold (1999: 139) 7. See, for instance, Robinson (2009: 69–75) 8. MacDonald (1943: 15) 9. See, for instance, Megson and Lonsay (1961: 49) 10. Bradbrook (1969: 56) 11. Oakeley (1948: 39) 187 188 Notes 12. Bradley (1893: 550) 13. Moore (1942: 18) 14. Ducasse (1942: 225) 15. Moore (1903a: 433) 16. Moore (1903a: 444) 17. Moore 1903a: 445) 18. Soames (2003 :12) 19. Moore (1939: 146) 20. Ibid. 21. Moore (1939: 150) 22. Moore (1925: 33) 23.
    [Show full text]
  • Wittgenstein's Kierkegaardian Argument Against Heidegger
    © Philosophical Writings Proceedings of the Fourteenth Annual British Postgraduate Philosophy Conference A CONFUSION OF CATEGORIES: WITTGENSTEIN’S KIERKEGAARDIAN ARGUMENT AGAINST HEIDEGGER Jonathan Beale – University of Reading Abstract A mysterious remark to Friedrich Waismann on 30 December 1929 marks the only occasion where Wittgenstein refers to both Heidegger and Kierkegaard. Yet although this has generated much controversy, little attention has been paid to the charge of nonsense that Wittgenstein here appears to bring against Heidegger; thus, the supporting argument that may be latent has not been unearthed. Through analysis of this remark, Wittgenstein‟s arguments in the Tractatus and „A Lecture on Ethics‟, and Heidegger‟s account of anxiety (Angst) in Being and Time, I argue that we can extract an argument against the central question of Heidegger‟s philosophy: the question of being. To understand this, I examine the Kierkegaardian ideas employed by Wittgenstein and Heidegger and attempt to show that this argument can be partly understood in Kierkegaardian terms. I further argue that examining what Heidegger means by „being‟ (Sein) shows that Wittgenstein‟s argument does not meet its target. Introduction In the following remark made to Friedrich Waismann on 30 December 1929 we see the only occurrence in Wittgenstein‟s remarks of both Heidegger‟s and Kierkegaard‟s names (and the first of only two references to Heidegger1): To be sure, I can imagine what Heidegger means by being [Sein] and anxiety [Angst]. Man has the urge to run up against the limits of language. Think for example of the astonishment that anything exists. This astonishment cannot be expressed in the form of a question, and 1 The second was in December 1932 (Wittgenstein & Waismann, pp.
    [Show full text]