Gilles Deleuze and Metaphysics

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Gilles Deleuze and Metaphysics Gilles Deleuze and Metaphysics Gilles Deleuze and Metaphysics Edited by Alain Beaulieu, Edward Kazarian, and Julia Sushytska LEXINGTON BOOKS Lanham • Boulder • New York • London Published by Lexington Books An imprint of The Rowman & Littlefield Publishing Group, Inc. 4501 Forbes Boulevard, Suite 200, Lanham, Maryland 20706 www.rowman.com Unit A, Whitacre Mews, 26-34 Stannery Street, London SE11 4AB Copyright © 2014 by Lexington Books All rights reserved. No part of this book may be reproduced in any form or by any electronic or mechanical means, including information storage and retrieval systems, without written permission from the publisher, except by a reviewer who may quote passages in a review. British Library Cataloguing in Publication Information Available Library of Congress Cataloging-in-Publication Data Gilles Deleuze and metaphysics / edited by Alain Beaulieu, Edward Kazarian, and Julia Sushytska. pages cm Includes index. ISBN 978-0-7391-7475-3 (cloth : alk. paper) -- ISBN 978-0-7391-7476-0 (electronic) 1. Deleuze, Gilles, 1925-1995. 2. Metaphysics. I. Beaulieu, Alain, 1940- editor. B2430.D454G535 2014 110--dc23 2014037493 The paper used in this publication meets the minimum requirements of American National Standard for Information Sciences—Permanence of Paper for Printed Library Materials, ANSI/NISO Z39.48-1992. Printed in the United States of America CONTENTS Foreword: The Problem of an Immanent Metaphysics vii Arnauld Villani Introduction: Gilles Deleuze and Metaphysics? 1 Alain Beaulieu, Edward Kazarian, and Julia Sushytska 1 Leaving Metaphysics? Deleuze on the Event 17 Alberto Anelli 2 Mathematics, Structure, Metaphysics: Deleuze and Category Theory 45 Rocco Gangle 3 Difference and Speculation: Heidegger, Meillassoux, and Deleuze 63 on Sufficient Reason Sjoerd van Tuinen 4 The Physics of Sense: Bruno, Schelling, Deleuze 91 Joshua Ramey and Daniel Whistler 5 The Obscure Metaphysics of Gilles Deleuze 115 Julia Sushytska 6 Deleuze and Badiou on Being and the Event 137 Alain Beaulieu 7 Disanalogous Being: Deleuze, Spinoza, and Univocal Metaphysics 153 Adrian Switzer 8 Crowned Anarchies, Substantial Attributes, and the Transcendental 179 Problem of Stupidity Gregory Kalyniuk 9 Revolution and the Return of Metaphysics 207 Thomas Nail 10 Whence Intensity? Deleuze and the Revival of a Concept 225 Mary Beth Mader About the Contributors 249 Index 253 FOREWORD The Problem of an Immanent Metaphysics Arnaud Villani There is undoubtedly something twisted in the classical history of philosophy. Indeed, subject to the request, which I gladly accepted, to write a preface for a collection of texts about Deleuze and his immanent metaphysics, my immediate reflex as professional philosopher was to try to justify this last form of meta- physics, as if it were some fantastic figure in the contemporary landscape. On reflection, what I mean to show is entirely the opposite, that transcendent meta- physics, far from being a pleonasm, constitutes a monstrous requirement that is primarily in need of justification. We can feel this in the 1981 interview where Deleuze, on draft paper and with a green ballpoint pen, answers my question about the “end of metaphysics” and its “overcoming” in a few words: “I feel I am a pure metaphysician.”1 This could be understood as: “I feel that I belong to a line of thinkers that has, with Nietzsche and Whitehead, its great texts and titles. No need to argue, there is metaphysics. The ‘end of metaphysics’ only signifies ‘the end of the metaphys- ics that believes itself to be or pretends to be transcendent.’ But in reality, there has never been any other kind of metaphysics than an immanent metaphysics.” So if the burden of proof is to be inverted, what title could transcendent metaphysics produce to certify and grant it, if not a completely contingent fac- ticity of “turning” in history—the strategies and benefits of which need to be analyzed—then at least a simple right to exist? Indeed, one can think that what comes “after the books on physics” and, oddly enough, after the “First Philoso- phy” that implied no “beyond,” takes the name metaphysics; it is symptomatic of what happened, namely an extension of Pythagorism that nevertheless modi- fies its essence. Indeed, the acroamatic teaching of Pythagoras, even though it was grounded on Number, did not intend to eliminate the sensible, but rather, in the manner of all the Pre-Socratics, to deliver its Rule or Principle. The sover- eign abstraction that Plato believed he saw there transfers the “world to be put in order” to an abstract world composed of what escapes the sensible and time! As if a mathematical abstraction, even a “spermatic” one, could replace the living- vii viii FOREWORD concrete real! As if the real world becomes mute in an outgrowth of the Rule! One finds there, as Nietzsche would say, a “knack,” a sleight of hand. Eternal and unchanging as a mathematical symbol, the Idea takes the place of the real that it was supposed to put in order. But this science of the Idea never concerns the world; it is not a position regarding the world, but the world’s denial. Conversely, to feel like a pure metaphysician, to want at any price a meta- physics for our time and for all times, is to search in a more appropriate way for the principle that would allow the world to endure in its composition of the mul- tiple and to remain immanent instead of being submitted to the edict of inexist- ence. Metaphysics is linked to the immanence of a world that continues to exist despite the forces that are pulling it in opposite directions and tending to make it explode (polyplangtôn, says Parmenides, fragment XVI). Since the first Greek thinkers, the principle that allows the world to persist within immanence— whether it is a matter, after the Elements that are too elementary, of Number, Logos, Being, Love/Hate, or Noûs—is a balanced principle of organization, and never a principle of choice between the elements of the world, never a principle of exclusive judgment in the name of the Best that would permit, in all inno- cence, the rejection or crossing out of the real. Let us suppose, moreover, that we did not have in Plato the arguments in the Phaedo (67) against the body, or in the Republic on the exact line of exclusions desirable for trimming the fat from the City. The Ideas would then be the control points of the sensible, and not fortresses which supervise its exile or extermination. The Idea would be like a sketch, a model for improving the sensible: the prelude to an algebra of the sensible. Metaphysics would once again take up with a heuristic of the treasures of the sensible, with their ideal combinatory. Plato was preoccupied by presence in person: one can feel it in his defense of orality against writing. In fact, this is a crucial point. What is important is not the emergence of the individual, for which Hegel was hoping and which Plato would hinder. What is important is the irreplaceability of beings. The member of a traditional community is not an individual, and yet he is irreplaceable. He can be neither displaced nor replaced, because he has a place assigned in society and in the nature-universe. He is absolutely resistant to abstraction. Now, what is an idea or a theory if not what can constantly be displaced? One could draw upon an etymology of the word “immanent”: “what re- mains within, remains there, holds on firmly to its location.” This comes closer to the animal which is unable to leave the unity that its body forms with what models it and is modeled on it (Umwelt). The transcendent, in a general sense, is what detaches and unbinds itself (see the importance of the chain for Parmeni- des), as the supposed soul does in relation to the body. The gesture of transcend- ence, in its simplest and most foundational meaning, is the tearing-away, the annulment, so comparable to the conceptual, of adhesion to concrete situations. The “primitive” is in its place, it has the sense of the “earth,” because it is held in the diverse and confrontational concreteness of narrative, of dances and songs, of the clan, of the community, of nature, of the universe, of the Forces present everywhere and of the dead. How can one live the concreteness of THE PROBLEM OF AN IMMANENT METAPHYSICS ix situations (by definition a situation is always concrete) if one is displaceable and replaceable? The respect for concreteness—which needs to be substituted (in terms of philosophical importance) for finitude—consists in remaining tied to a body, to a port, to the dead. Ulysses comes back to Ithaca. Being is the opposite of floating, in empty liberty, nowhere. There are thus two reasons to assert that metaphysics is immanent: respect for the real understood as “this world,” and respect for the chance to enjoy a place and an irreplaceable. Conversely, we see that the transcendent respects neither this world nor irreplaceability. If one asks, with good reason, whether this concept of place is not too es- sentialist to suit Deleuze’s philosophy, one would have to answer without hesita- tion, in short, that the “place” of each difference is simultaneously constitutive of the fold and submitted to a thousand cuttings and buildings-up of waves that re-determine it while making it travel. In this way, these places, by creating a block while remaining nomadic, differ radically from any assigned location. In other words, they are relational and correspond to what Kant speaks of as the difference between Grenz, the boundary, and Schranke, the limit. But this world and irreplaceability carry difference along with them. This world is only well-balanced dosage of differences, and irreplaceability is the uniqueness of what has no equivalent and cannot be reproduced.
Recommended publications
  • Metaphysics Today and Tomorrow*
    1 Metaphysics Today and Tomorrow* Raphaël Millière École normale supérieure, Paris – October 2011 Translated by Mark Ohm with the assistance of Leah Orth, Jon Cogburn, and Emily Beck Cogburn “By metaphysics, I do not mean those abstract considerations of certain imaginary properties, the principal use of which is to furnish the wherewithal for endless dispute to those who want to dispute. By this science I mean the general truths which can serve as principles for the particular sciences.” Malebranche Dialogues on Metaphysics and Religion 1. The interminable agony of metaphysics Throughout the twentieth century, numerous philosophers sounded the death knell of metaphysics. Ludwig Wittgenstein, Rudolf Carnap, Martin Heidegger, Gilbert Ryle, J. L. Austin, Jacques Derrida, Jürgen Habermas, Richard Rorty, and, henceforth, Hilary Putnam: a great many tutelary figures have extolled the rejection, the exceeding, the elimination, or the deconstruction of first philosophy. All these necrological chronicles do not have the same radiance, the same seriousness, nor the same motivations, but they all agree to dismiss the discipline, which in the past was considered “the queen of the sciences”, with a violence at times comparable to the prestige it commanded at the time of its impunity. Even today, certain philosophers hastily spread the tragic news with contempt for philosophical inquiry, as if its grave solemnity bestowed upon it some obviousness. Thus, Franco Volpi writes: ‘Grand metaphysics is dead!’ is the slogan which applies to the majority of contemporary philosophers, whether continentals or of analytic profession. They all treat metaphysics as a dead dog.1 In this way, the “path of modern thought” would declare itself vociferously “anti- metaphysical and finally post-metaphysical”.
    [Show full text]
  • Kant Et L'humain
    KANT ET L’HUMAIN GÉOGRAPHIE, PSYCHOLOGIE, ANTHROPOLOGIE À LA MÊME LIBRAIRIE Années 1747-1781. Kant. Avant la Critique de la raison pure, sous la direction de Luc Langlois, 352 p., 2009. L’année 1790. Kant. Critique de la faculté de juger. Beauté, vie, liberté, sous la direction de Christophe Bouton, Fabienne Brugère et Claudie Lavaud, 352 p., 2008. L’année 1793. Kant. Sur la politique et la religion, sous la direction de Jean Ferrari, 272 p., 1995. L’année 1795. Kant. Essai sur la paix, sous la direction de Pierre Laberge, Guy Lafrance et Denis Dumas, 406 p., 1997. L’année 1796. Kant. Sur la paix perpétuelle. De Leibniz aux héritiers de Kant, sous la direction de Simone Goyard-Fabre et Jean Ferrari, 216 p., 1998. L’année 1797. Kant. La métaphysique des mœurs, sous la direction de Simone Goyard- Fabre et Jean Ferrari, 144 p., 2000. L’année 1798. Kant. Sur l’anthropologie, sous la direction de Jean Ferrari, 224 p., 1997. Années 1796-1803. Kant. Opus postumum. Philosophie, science, éthique et théologie, sous la direction de Ingeborg Schüssler, édité par Christophe Erismann, 246 p., 2001. Années 1781-1801. Kant. Critique de la raison pure. Vingt ans de réception, sous la direction de Claude Piché, 288 p., 2002. Kant. Les sources de la philosophie kantienne aux XVII e et XVIII e siècles, sous la direction de Lukas K. Sosoe et Robert Theis, 384 p., 2005. Kant et les Lumières européennes, sous la direction de Lorenzo Bianchi, Jean Ferrari et Alberto Postigliola, 374 p., 2009. Kant et Wolff. Héritages et ruptures, sous la direction de Sophie Grapotte et Tinca Prunea-Bretonnet, 236 p., 2011.
    [Show full text]
  • 1 Political Dilemmas Angel R. Oquendo
    1 Political Dilemmas Angel R. Oquendo* I. Introductory Comments II. The Appeal of a Perfectly Coherent System of Principles III. Biting the Bullet: Confronting Political Dilemmas IV. Three Examples: Orangemen, Quebec Anglophones, and Surrogate Mothers V. Counter Reflections I. Introductory Comments Fundamental principles, such as those of democracy and human rights, are sometimes dramatically at odds with each other. It is a mistake to regard these cases as involving only apparent conflicts, which vanish upon closer inspection. One must instead acknowledge that the two norms at issue clash in the specific context and that opting for one over another will produce a real sense of loss, even if the choice is correct. The community will come to regret not its endorsement of the prevailing principle, but rather * Law Professor at the University of Connecticut School of Law. A.B., M.A., Ph.D., Harvard University; J.D., Yale University. I would like to thank Luiz Bernardo Araújo, Maria Clara Dias, Eduardo Fermandois, Donald Ipperciel, Luc Langlois, Wilson Mendonça, Claude Piché, Alan Ritter, Shaina Spreng, Mauricio Suárez, Daniel Löwe, and Jorge Vergara for their comments and suggestions on earlier drafts. I have provided my own translation of the non-English quotations. 2 its neglect of the alternative. It will have to make amends vis-à-vis the individuals or groups it has let down in the process. Thus, the notion of an irreducible dilemma, which Bernard Williams invokes in his discussions on morality,1 applies with equal force in the realm of political philosophy. This kind of predicament brings about extensive collective pain, and at times even tragedy.
    [Show full text]
  • PHI 516/GER 566/REL 516 Special Topics In
    PHI 516/GER 566/REL 516 Special Topics in History of Phil: Knowledge & Belief in Kant, Fichte, Hegel Instructor: Andrew Chignell ([email protected]) Spring 2020, Marx 201, Th 1:30-4:20 Office: 232 1879 Hall; Office Hours: Tues 4-5:30 and by appt A seminar on Kantian epistemology and pistology (the theory of faith or acceptance). Topics include: the nature and ethics of assent (holding-for-true); the nature of knowledge; fallibilism and infallibilism about epistemic justification; cognition and spontaneity; noumenal ignorance; opinion and common sense; epistemic autonomy; and the structure of practical arguments, both pragmatic and moral. In the final weeks of the seminar we will consider how some of these themes are treated by two of Kant’s most influential successors – J.G. Fichte and G.W.F. Hegel. Along the way, we will look at some broadly Kantian efforts in contemporary epistemology by authors like Mark Schroeder and Kurt Sylvan. Assignments: 1. Short reflections: Everyone taking the course for credit is asked to submit five 1-2 page reflections. Often these will simply elaborate a question about the reading, but they can also involve criticism or constructive work. These are due on Wednesday night before class at 11.59pm, and should focus on the readings for the following day’s class. Graded on a satisfactory/unsatisfactory basis, they are worth (combined) 30% of the grade. As long as you’re doing the required reading, it shouldn’t be hard to achieve full credit for this. 2. Presentation: Ph.D. students have the opportunity (but not the obligation) to give a short presentation to the seminar.
    [Show full text]
  • An Enc Ohn Rea Ethnicity As Post-Modernism W Uovo Barocco Le Mythe De Railleurs Strangers' Fugue
    NO 1 • May/June 1985 Contemporary Music An Enc ohn Rea Ethnicity as Post-Modernism W uovo Barocco Le mythe de railleurs Strangers' Fugue: An Interview with Aldo Mazza Vice Versa Advertising: phone: (416) 367- 3828 Date of Publication: May 1985. Transcultural Magazine pu­ Second Class mail registration blished bimonthly by Les Edi­ No. 6385. All correspondence tions Vice Versa enr. P.O. Box should be directed to Vice Ver­ 821, N.D.G. Station Montréal, sa. P.O. Box 821, N.D.G. Sta­ Québec, H4A 3S2, ISSN tion, Montréal, Québec, H4A AN ENCOUNTER 0821682-7 3S2. Editorial Board: Lamberto Opinions expressed outside of f/t. *m Tassinari, Bruno Ramirez, Ful- specifically marked editorials vio Caccia, Antonio D'Alfonso are not necessarily held by each and every individual Toronto Bureau: Joseph Ma- member of the editorial group. viglia, Antonino Mazza. Mario Godlowski, Damiano Pietro- Manuscripts not accompanied paolo by a stamped, self-addressed envelope will not be returned. Design: Gianni Caccia Typesetting: Les Ateliers Chio- ra Inc. Vice Versa gratefully acknow­ Proofreader: Ann Vergeylen ledges the support of the Ca­ nada Council, and the Minis­ Printing: Payette & Simms tère des Communautés cultu­ Distribution: Les Messageries relles et de l'immigration du de Presse Internationale, Mon­ Québec tréal, Toronto, phone: (416) 928-0099 Cover: Serge Brunelle Read Mary Melfi A Bride in Three Acts MARY MELFI III i Capezio Gucmici Editions and Dance and A Queen Is Holding Vice Versa and Words a Mummified Cat MARY MELFI Capezio : EN IS I The Art rn^Sfi Guernica EdkiûOI of Dance Guernica P.O.
    [Show full text]
  • Wayne Hankey, 9/11 and the History of Philosophy
    Animus 11 (2006) www.swgc.mun.ca/animus. 9/11 And The History Of Philosophy Wayne Hankey Dalhousie University [email protected] Introduction There is nothing more significant about a philosophy than how it situates itself within or in respect to the history of philosophy. When it locates itself historically, a form of philosophy defines what philosophy itself is by placing this mode of human living, reflection, speaking, and writing vis-à-vis that in relation to which it emerged and has developed. This placing occurs in respect to genres (e.g. poetry, prose, face-to-face discourse, introspection, writing) and to other representations or imitations of the whole (e.g. most importantly, at least at its origins, to myth and religion and, in more modern times, to what are commonly called “sciences”). Designating its normal setting is also part of this historical placing. It will involve the question put most influentially in our time by Pierre Hadot as to whether philosophy is properly a way of life—as it was indisputably when it began and throughout the Hellenic and Hellenistic periods. As a way of life philosophy was thus carried on both in agora and in monastery, both in prison and in episcopal and imperial curia, both in the Neoplatonic schools headed by a “divine” successor to Plato and in Islamic halqa which took up their studies from the commentaries on the classical philosophical texts produced in the late ancient Neoplatonic and Peripatetic schools. For Hadot, philosophy’s move out of these situations and making the university its normal location was of the utmost significance.
    [Show full text]
  • Kant Und Die Philosophie in Weltbürgerlicher Absicht
    Kant und die Philosophie in weltbürgerlicher Absicht Akten des XI. Kant-Kongresses 2010 Bearbeitet von Kant-Gesellschaft e.V., Stefano Bacin, Alfredo Ferrarin, Claudio La Rocca, Margit Ruffing 1. Auflage 2013. Buch. ca. 4000 S. Hardcover ISBN 978 3 11 024648 3 Format (B x L): 15,5 x 23 cm Gewicht: 6541 g Weitere Fachgebiete > Philosophie, Wissenschaftstheorie, Informationswissenschaft > Philosophie: Allgemeines > Westliche Philosophie: Transzendentalphilosophie, Kritizismus schnell und portofrei erhältlich bei Die Online-Fachbuchhandlung beck-shop.de ist spezialisiert auf Fachbücher, insbesondere Recht, Steuern und Wirtschaft. Im Sortiment finden Sie alle Medien (Bücher, Zeitschriften, CDs, eBooks, etc.) aller Verlage. Ergänzt wird das Programm durch Services wie Neuerscheinungsdienst oder Zusammenstellungen von Büchern zu Sonderpreisen. Der Shop führt mehr als 8 Millionen Produkte. Gesamtinhaltsverzeichnis Band 1 Siglenverzeichnis .................................... XIII Erçffnung Massimo Barale Zur Erçffnung . .................................... 3 Bernd Dçrflinger Begrßung durch den Ersten Vorsitzenden der Kant-Gesellschaft 5 Claudio La Rocca Begrßung durch den Ersten Vorsitzenden der Societ Italiana di Studi Kantiani . .................................... 7 Verleihung der Kant-Preise Klaus Dsing Laudatio auf Prof. Dr. Mario Pedro Miguel Caimi ........... 15 Mario Caimi Danksagung . .................................... 21 Franca Casali Begrßung durch die Prsidentin der Stiftung „Silvestro Marcucci“ 25 Heiner F. Klemme Laudatio auf
    [Show full text]
  • Revue Sciences/Lettres, 1 | 2013, « Transferts Culturels » [En Ligne], Mis En Ligne Le 18 Avril 2013, Consulté Le 22 Octobre 2020
    Revue Sciences/Lettres 1 | 2013 Transferts culturels Cultural transfers Michel Espagne et Valérie Gérard (dir.) Édition électronique URL : http://journals.openedition.org/rsl/82 DOI : 10.4000/rsl.82 ISSN : 2271-6246 Éditeur Éditions Rue d'Ulm Référence électronique Michel Espagne et Valérie Gérard (dir.), Revue Sciences/Lettres, 1 | 2013, « Transferts culturels » [En ligne], mis en ligne le 18 avril 2013, consulté le 22 octobre 2020. URL : http://journals.openedition.org/ rsl/82 ; DOI : https://doi.org/10.4000/rsl.82 Ce document a été généré automatiquement le 22 octobre 2020. © Revue Sciences/Lettres 1 SOMMAIRE Éditorial Monique Canto-Sperber et Michel Espagne Problèmes et concepts La notion de transfert culturel Michel Espagne La naissance de l’historiographie romaine : la canonisation de la mémoire nationale selon un modèle étranger Dominique Briquel L’histoire culturelle de l’Europe d’un point de vue transnational Blaise Wilfert-Portal Camus postcolonial ? Dominique Combe D’Hollywood à Hong Kong, de Hong Kong à Hollywood : des transferts culturels éminemment paradoxaux (de 1979 à nos jours) Jean-Étienne Pieri De la traductibilité des Savoirs Charles Alunni Transformations de la phénoménologie À propos de Neue Phänomenologie in Frankreich, par Hans-Dieter Gondek et László Tengelyi Christian Sommer Pratiques de la recherche Transmettre: sciences, œuvres, créations Les archives de la création à l’âge du tout numérique Pierre-Marc de Biasi Comment les sciences durent Éric Brian Enregistrer ou l’archivage de la mesure Denis Beaudouin et Michel Laguës Revue Sciences/Lettres, 1 | 2013 2 Traduire : concepts, œuvres, langues Les intraduisibles Entretien avec François THOMAS (novembre 2010) Barbara Cassin « Il faut être anglais et avoir une bonne dose de punch dans le crâne pour apprécier les scènes de Falstaff.
    [Show full text]
  • Heralding a New Enlightenment
    M. Heidegger et le concept de « destruction ». Méthode ou manière de philosopher ? (M. Heidegger and the Concept of “Deconstruction”: A Method or a Way of Philosophizing?) Florin Crîșmăreanu* Abstract: In the pages of this article I will try to briefly analyze the issue of ‘deconstruction’ [Destruktion / Abbau] in the texts of M. Heidegger. The intention is to catalogue some of the sources that may have inspired the German philosopher in this sense. However, unlike his predecessors who have discussed the aspect of ‘deconstruction’, M. Heidegger is perceived as an author that applies this procedure to diverse areas of his thought. In the posterity of the German philosopher, a significant contribution having J. Derrida, ‘deconstruction’ creates its way towards certain autonomy. From this point on, ‘deconstruction’ is no longer a simple method applied in various areas at a certain moment in time. Keywords: M. Heidegger, metaphysics, method, deconstruction, hermeneutics, tradition INTRODUCTION « L’onto-théologie ou comment s’en débarrasser: comme dans la pièce de Ionesco, l’opération prend des proportions tellement gigantesques parce que personne n’a l’air de savoir d’où elle provient ni en qui elle consiste » (Grondin 1990, 170). La problématique de la destruction semble avoir retenu longuement Heidegger. « Destruction » / « déconstruction » (Destruktion / Abbau) se présente(nt) comme une constante de la philosophie de M. Heidegger. Ma thèse est la suivante: la destruction est plus qu’une méthode – et dans ce sens nous pouvons parler d’une « donation » dans la destruction – elle est une manière de philosopher, parce que au * Florin Crîșmăreanu ( ) Research Department, Faculty of Philosophy and Social-Political Sciences, “Alexandru Ioan Cuza” University of Iași, Romania e-mail: [email protected] AGATHOS, Volume 9, Issue 2 (17): 45-57 © www.agathos-international-review.com CC BY NC 2018 Florin Crîșmăreanu « bout » (dans le sens de l’ « accomplissement ») de la destruction s’ouvre l’accès à l’Être.
    [Show full text]
  • Aufklärung Herausgegeben Von Martin Mulsow, Gideon Stiening Und Friedrich Vollhardt
    Aufklärung Herausgegeben von Martin Mulsow, Gideon Stiening und Friedrich Vollhardt 30 30 Meiner 30 Gegenstand des Jahrbuches Aufklärung ist die Erforschung des 18. Jahrhunderts und seiner Wirkungsgeschichte. Das Streben nach Aufklärung Interdisziplinarität war eine dominierende Tendenz und Ausdruck der Integrationskraft der Epoche. Der Umbruch des kulturellen und zivi• lisatorischen Selbstverständnisses sowie die Entfaltung der bürger• THEMA: Pfl icht und Verbindlichkeit bei Kant lichen Gesellschaft wurden von ihm mitbestimmt. Dieser Idee ver• Aufklärung Dieter Hüning: Christian Wolffs Konzeption der Verbindlichkeit. Eine Antizipation sucht die Aufklärung zu entsprechen. der Ethik Kants? Luc Langlois: Der Begriff der Verbindlichkeit bei Baumgarten und sein Einfl uss auf Fachübergreifend angelegt, führt das Jahrbuch thematisch fl exibel Kants Moralphilosophie Ergebnisse und Perspektiven der verschiedenen Forschungsdiszipli• Christel Fricke: Die Quadratur des Kreises – Kants Moralphilosophie und ihr nen im Hinblick auf sachliche Schwerpunkte zusammen, die durch crusianisches Erbe Kurzbiographien, Diskussionen sowie Forschungs• und Literatur• Antonino Falduto: Praktische Verbindlichkeit und göttliche Weltordnung in berichte ergänzt werden. Der Gedanke der erkenntnisfördernden Fichtes Versuch einer Critik aller Offenbarung Kraft der offenen, unparteiischen Diskussion war eine der wichtigsten Martin Brecher: Ein Zwangsrecht auf Geschlechtsverkehr? Das kantische Vernunftrecht und die ,eheliche Pfl icht‘ Überzeugungen des Jahrhunderts. Es ist diese Grundhaltung der Heiner F. Klemme: Radikal human. Kants erweiterter Pfl ichtbegriff von 1797 Aufklärung, die auch die Anlage des Jahrbuches bestimmt. Achim Vesper: Kant über moralischen Wert und Gesinnung Manfred Baum: „Pfl icht! du erhabener, großer Name“. Betrachtungen zu Pfl icht und Verbindlichkeit bei Kant Martin Bondeli: Karl Leonhard Reinholds Forderung erster Grundsätze der Moral und des Naturrechts Gabriel Rivero: Von der Abhängigkeit zur Notwendigkeit.
    [Show full text]
  • La Sympathie Comme Révélation De La Valeur D'autrui
    La sympathie comme révélation de la valeur d’autrui Intersubjectivité, affectivité et axiologie chez Max Scheler dans Nature et formes de la sympathie Mémoire Yail Angela Peraza Herrera Maîtrise en philosophie Maître ès arts (M.A.) Québec, Canada © Yail Angela Peraza Herrera, 2018 La sympathie comme révélation de la valeur d’autrui Intersubjectivité, affectivité et axiologie chez Max Scheler dans Nature et formes de la sympathie Mémoire Yail Angela Peraza Herrera Sous la direction de : Luc Langlois, directeur de recherche RÉSUMÉ L’objectif de ce mémoire est de dégager la conception de Scheler à propos de la sympathie et de l’amour développée dans Nature et formes de la sympathie. Plus précisément, nous visons à montrer avec l’auteur que, contrairement à ce que proposent les théories psychologiques, lesdits sentiments constituent des actes purs émergeant d’une dimension supérieure, métempirique de l’homme, leur fonction étant de saisir certaines qualités également à caractère pur : les valeurs portées par ceux qui font l’objet de notre sympathie et de notre amour. Afin de mener à terme notre projet, notre premier chapitre abordera les conditions de base pour la rencontre intersubjective, thème sous-jacent de tout l’ouvrage. Nous montrerons alors que cette dernière est fondée sur deux actes à caractère eidétique : la conscience de l’altérité au sens général et la perception d’un autre au sens concret. Néanmoins, étant donné que cela n’est que le début du lien avec autrui, notre deuxième chapitre présentera –suite à la critique des théories psychologiques de la sympathie- la hiérarchie schelerienne des sentiments sympathiques, actes supérieurs à la perception.
    [Show full text]
  • 9/11 and the History of Philosophy
    Animus 11 (2006) www.swgc.mun.ca/animus. 9/11 and the History of Philosophy Wayne Hankey Dalhousie University [email protected] INTRODUCTION There is nothing more significant about a philosophy than how it situates itself within or in respect to the history of philosophy. When it locates itself historically, a form of philosophy defines what philosophy itself is by placing this mode of human living, reflection, speaking, and writing vis-à-vis that in relation to which it emerged and has developed. This placing occurs in respect to genres (e.g. poetry, prose, face-to-face discourse, introspection, writing) and to other representations or imitations of the whole (e.g. most importantly, at least at its origins, to myth and religion and, in more modern times, to what are commonly called “sciences”). Designating its normal setting is also part of this historical placing. It will involve the question put most influentially in our time by Pierre Hadot as to whether philosophy is properly a way of life—as it was indisputably when it began and throughout the Hellenic and Hellenistic periods. As a way of life philosophy was thus carried on both in agora and in monastery, both in prison and in episcopal and imperial curia, both in the Neoplatonic schools headed by a “divine” successor to Plato and in Islamic halqa which took up their studies from the commentaries on the classical philosophical texts produced in the late ancient Neoplatonic and Peripatetic schools. For Hadot, philosophy’s move out of these situations and making the university its normal location was of the utmost significance.
    [Show full text]