Redalyc.A Hertzian Interpretation of Wittgenstein's Tractatus

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Redalyc.A Hertzian Interpretation of Wittgenstein's Tractatus Eidos: Revista de Filosofía de la Universidad del Norte ISSN: 1692-8857 [email protected] Universidad del Norte Colombia Bizarro, Sara A hertzian interpretation of Wittgenstein's Tractatus Eidos: Revista de Filosofía de la Universidad del Norte, núm. 13, julio-diciembre, 2010, pp. 150-165 Universidad del Norte Barranquilla, Colombia Available in: http://www.redalyc.org/articulo.oa?id=85418392008 How to cite Complete issue Scientific Information System More information about this article Network of Scientific Journals from Latin America, the Caribbean, Spain and Portugal Journal's homepage in redalyc.org Non-profit academic project, developed under the open access initiative A hertzian interpretation of Wittgenstein’s Tractatus Sara Bizarro resumen abstract En este artículo se compara a In this paper I will compare Hertz y a Wittgenstein para pro- Hertz and Wittgenstein in order poner una nueva interpretación del to bring forth a new interpretation Tractatus. Revisaré las ideas de Witt- of the Tractatus. I shall look at genstein sobre los objetos simples Wittgenstein’s ideas about simple y las compararé con las partículas objects and compare them with materiales de Hertz. Luego afirmaré Hertz’s material particles. I shall que si uno entiende las partículas then claim that if one understands materiales de Hertz como entidades Hertz’s material particles as logical lógicas que parecen más coordena- entities that are more co-ordinate das que físicas, se puede lograr una like than physical, one can reach interpretación del Tractatus que an interpretation of the Tractatus calla deliberadamente acerca de la that is deliberately silent about the naturaleza de la realidad y que por nature of reality, therefore escaping tanto escapa a las interpretaciones both objectivist and subjectivist objetivista y subjetivista del libro. interpretations of the book. This, I Pienso que este es solamente uno de think, is just one of the great results los grandes resultados de repensar of re-thinking Wittgenstein’s ideas las ideas de Wittgenstein a través through Hertz’s. de las de Hertz. keywords palabras clave Wittgenstein, Hertz, physics, philo- Wittgenstein, Hertz, física, filosofía sophy of science, history of philosophy de la ciencia, historia de la filosofía. eidos issn: 1692-8857 Fecha de recepción: septiembre 10 de 2010 Fecha de aceptación: septiembre 14 de 2010 [150] eidos nº13 (2010) págs. 150-165 A hertzian interpretation of Wittgenstein’s Tractatus Sara Bizarro* Universidad de Lisboa «As a matter of fact, we do not know, nor have we any means of knowing, whether our conceptions of things are in conformity with them in any other that this one fundamental respect». Heinrich Hertz, The principles of mechanics (2007, p. 2) Wittgenstein’s Tractatus and the Vienna Circle T raditionally, references to the Vienna Circle and to Wittgenstein’s Tractatus have appeared hand in hand. Wittgenstein’s impact in the Vienna Circle was unquestionably overwhelming. The Tractatus was extensively discussed by the members of the Cir- cle and some of its ideas where seminal for the development of the Circle’s philosophy. For instance, Carnap, in his notes about the Tractatus, said that it was «carefully read in the circle and everything talked through»1 and listed as positive influences the importance of language analysis for philosophy and the idea that the origin of philosophical pseudo questions was in the misuse of language. However, the paring up of Wittgenstein and the Vienna Cir- cle often lead to serious misinterpretations of the Tractatus. One example is the interpretation of Wittgenstein’s ideas about simple objects. In the Encyclopedia of Philosophy, edited by Paul Edwards (which by the way I think is still one of the best philosophy ency- clopedias around) Nicola Abbagnano writes: *[email protected] 1 Carnap’s paper at the Arquives for Scientific Philosophy. eidos nº13 (2010) págs. 150-165 [151] Una interpretación hertziana del Tractatus de Wittgenstein The sense-impressions spoken of by Pearson and the sensations spoken of by Mach, Avenarius, and Petzoldt as neutral elements that constitute all the facts of the world, both physical and psy- chical, correspond exactly to the objects (Gegenstände) spoken of by Ludwig Wittgenstein in his Tractatus Logico-Philosophicus as the constituents of atomic facts and to the elementary experiences (Elementarerlebnisse) spoken of by Rudolf Carnap in Der logische Aufbau der Welt (Abbagnano, 1967, p. 223). This interpretation of simple objects as sense impressions might have been suggested by Wittgenstein’s own allusion to color examples when referring to simple objects. For example, in 2.0131, while talking about objects, Wittgenstein says «A speck in the vi- sual field, though it need not be red, must have some color» and in 2.0251 he writes «Space, time, and color (being colored) are forms of objects». Although the meaning of these color examples might be vague, they seem to indicate that objects might have something to do with sense impressions if a speck in the visual field can be brought up in the context of discussing objects. However in 2.0232 Wittgenstein says «In a manner of speaking, objects are colorless». Therefore one must conclude that the use of color while speaking about objects should not lead one to sense impression interpreta- tion of Wittgenstein’s simple objects. In fact, if one reads 2.0131 and 2.0251 carefully one sees that Wittgenstein underlines he is not claiming that objects are patches of color, but that objects are the form that permits having some color or being colored. We shall return to this in the end of the paper. A Hertzian interpretation of objects will allow us to make perfect sense of these passages. Now I just want to underline that even if it might have been possible to interpret objects as sense impressions, it is not clear whether such interpretation holds at all. The question about how objects are to be interpreted is relevant when analyzing how the Tractatus relates to the philosophy of the Vienna Circle. One of the main ideas propagated by the Circle is the Verifiability Principle. This principle claims that a sentence [152] eidos nº13 (2010) págs. 150-165 Sara Bizarro has meaning only if it is in principle verifiable. This principle is usually claimed to have been inspired in Wittgenstein’s ideas since Wittgenstein defended that a proposition could be decomposed into elementary propositions whose names stand for objects. In this vein a proposition is true if it corresponds to the fact which it depicts. The Verifiability Principle is said to have been originated in these ideas. But, in order to know how to verify the meaning of a sentence, it seems that in the end, one must know which are the simple objects that correspond to the simple names. The idea that sense-impressions are such objects is an empiricist way of looking at them, but it is quite doubtful that this is what Wittgenstein had in mind when he talked of simple objects. Two traditional ways of understanding Wittgenstein’s objects In 1964 James Griffin’s “Wittgenstein’s Logical Atomism” and George Pitcher’s “The Philosophy of Wittgenstein”, presented what was then called a new interpretation of the Tractatus (Keyt, 1965). These books offered arguments against understanding objects as sense-impressions or sense-data and for understanding them as something like Hertz’s material particles. I shall present their arguments in this section but before that, I want to make clear what is at stake when one is trying to interpret what is meant by simple objects in the Tractatus. There are two different traditional ways of interpreting the Tractatus. These two interpretations were probably debated in the Vienna Circle and appear in Rose Rand’s2 notes, she writes: Logical Form and Form of Reality is considered by Wittgenstein to be Identical. How should this be understood? One cannot say that language and reality are similar. But should the described content have similarity with reality, so that the form 2 Rose Rand was a member of the Vienna Circle and later she was one of Witt- genstein’s students in Cambridge. eidos nº13 (2010) págs. 150-165 [153] Una interpretación hertziana del Tractatus de Wittgenstein of the content and the form of reality are the same? But even if that what is perceived and that what is thought are by comparison similar, can one equate reality with that what has been perceived? There are two possible interpretations: A. The content of my sen- tence is similar to Objective reality. B. The content of my sentence is similar to perceived reality and the rules which rein the contents of my sentence are superimposed to reality. The Tractatus does not have on it an explicit viewpoint. Neither is assumed that the real has a structure on its own and it is identical with the content of the sentences, nor that its structure is superim- posed by language. Only the general statement that logical form is the form of reality is said in the Tractatus (Rand, series 5, box 9, folder 11-18). So it seems to be a fundamental vagueness in the Tractatus as to the nature of reality and therefore also as to the nature of objects. However, commentators have tried to read the Tractatus in one way or the other. Interpretation A brings forth an objective reading of the Tractatus that makes the propositions of science propositions about Objective reality. Interpretation B creates a reading in which the world is constructed by language leading to a subjective view that can go as far as claiming that Wittgenstein is a solipsist. Each of these interpretations will also yield a specific view of what Wittgenstein’s simple objects are. In interpretation A objects can, for instance, be something like the particles postu- lated in physical theories, while in interpretation B objects could be subjective language laden with sense-data.
Recommended publications
  • Guide to Proper Names and References in Gödel's “Protokolle
    Guide to proper names and references in Gödel’s “Protokolle” notebook People Abel Othenio Abel (1875-1946) professor of paleontology and paleobiology at the University of Vienna. Founder of the group of professors known as the “Bärenhöhle” that blocked the appointment and promotion of Jews Adele Adele Nimbursky, née Porkert (1899–1981), Gödel’s girlfriend, separated from her first husband; she and Gödel would marry in September 1938 Bachmann Friedrich Bachmann (1909–1982), mathematician, doctoral student of Scholz’s at Münster, where he received his Ph.D. in 1933; from 1935 at University of Marburg, as assistant then Privatdozent Behmann Heinrich Behmann (1891–1970), German mathematician; his reply to Perelman’s criticism of Gödel’s result had appeared in the journal Mind in April 1937. He was dismissed from his position at ​ ​ the University of Halle after the war for his Nazi Party activities Beer Gustav Beer, member of the Vienna Circle and Menger’s Mathematical Colloquium Benjamin Abram Cornelius Benjamin (1897–1968), American philosopher of science on the University of Chicago faculty 1932 to 1945 Bernays Paul Bernays (1888–1977), Swiss mathematician and logician; close collaborator with David Hilbert on the foundations of mathematics and the axiomatization of set theory Brentano Franz Brentano (1838-1917), resigned as priest, Professor of Philosophy at the University of Vienna, founder of Gestalt Brunsvick Egon Brunswik (1903–1955), Hungarian-born psychologist, assistant to Karl Bühler in Vienna, active member of Otto Neurath’s “Unity of Science” movement Bühler Karl Bühler (1879–1963), professor of psychology at the University of Vienna. He led an effort to reorganize Vienna’s city schools by incorporating scientific findings from child psychology.
    [Show full text]
  • Esther Simpson - the Unknown Heroine
    From The Jewish Chronicle, 11 May 2017 https://www.thejc.com/news/news-features/esther-simpson-the-unknown-heroine- 1.438317?highlight=Simpson David Edmonds May 11, 2017 Esther Simpson - the unknown heroine The extraordinary story of how one woman offered refuge to philosophers, scientists and musicians fleeing from the Nazis, and in doing so reshaped the cultural and intellectual landscape of the Western World. It’s not clear how Professor Stanislaus Jolles died. The year was 1943 and he was in his mid-eighties. But did he die from natural causes, did he kill himself, or was he killed? He was a Jew living in Berlin, after the systematic extermination of Jews had already begun, so anything is possible. The fate of his wife, Adele, is documented. In the year of her husband’s passing, she was transported south from the German capital to Theresienstadt concentration camp in Czechoslovakia. She perished in 1944. She was Miss Simpson to strangers, Esther to colleagues, Tess to some of her close friends. And she had many, many friends, among whom she counted Ludwig Wittgenstein, often described as the greatest philosopher of the twentieth century. Wittgenstein had been acquainted with Stanislaus Jolles for over three decades, ever since he’d left his palatial Viennese home in 1906 to study engineering in Berlin. Professor and Mrs Jolles had been his hosts. Stanislaus was a mathematician who came to look upon Ludwig like a son; he and his wife called him ‘little Wittgenstein’. During World War I, when Wittgenstein was fighting for the Austrians on the Eastern Front, they furnished him with a constant supply of bread, fruit-cake, and cigarettes.
    [Show full text]
  • Between the Lvov-Warsaw School and the Vienna Circle Volume 5, Number 2 Anna Brożek Editor in Chief Kevin C
    JOURNAL FOR THE HISTORY OF ANALYTICAL PHILOSOPHY MARIA KOKOSZYńSKa: BETWEEN THE LVOV-WARSAW SCHOOL AND THE VIENNA CIRCLE VOLUME 5, NUMBER 2 ANNA BROżEK EDITOR IN CHIEF KEVIN C. KLEMENt, UnIVERSITY OF MASSACHUSETTS Maria Kokoszyńska-Lutmanowa (1905–1981) was one of the EDITORIAL BOARD most outstanding female representatives of the Lvov-Warsaw ANNALISA COLIVA, UnIVERSITY OF MODENA AND UC IRVINE School. After achieving her PhD in philosophy under Kazimierz GaRY EBBS, INDIANA UnIVERSITY BLOOMINGTON Twardowski’s supervision, she was Kazimierz Ajdukiewicz’s as- GrEG FROSt-ARNOLD, HOBART AND WILLIAM SMITH COLLEGES sistant. She was also influenced by Alfred Tarski whose results HENRY JACKMAN, YORK UnIVERSITY in semantics she analyzed and popularized. After World War SANDRA LaPOINte, MCMASTER UnIVERSITY II, she got the chair of logic in University of Wrocław and she CONSUELO PRETI, THE COLLEGE OF NEW JERSEY organized studies in logic in this academic center. MARCUS ROSSBERG, UnIVERSITY OF CONNECTICUT ANTHONY SKELTON, WESTERN UnIVERSITY In the 1930s, Kokoszyńska kept in contact with members of the MARK TEXTOR, KING’S COLLEGE LonDON Vienna Circle and became a kind of connecting factor between AUDREY YAP, UnIVERSITY OF VICTORIA Polish logicians and the Viennese group. In Poland, she pre- RICHARD ZACH, UnIVERSITY OF CALGARY sented the views of members of the Vienna Circle. In Vienna, REVIEW EDITORS she emphasized the results of her Polish colleagues. JULIET FLOYD, BOSTON UnIVERSITY CHRIS PINCOCK, OHIO STATE UnIVERSITY In the present paper, some of Kokoszyńska’s results connected with the matters discussed in the Vienna Circle are presented, ASSISTANT REVIEW EDITOR namely with the problem of metaphysics, the status of logic and SEAN MORRIS, METROPOLITAN STATE UnIVERSITY OF DenVER the idea of unity of science.
    [Show full text]
  • Organisaties En Genootschappen
    Organisaties en genootschappen. P. van Ulsen 7 november 2017 Inhoudsopgave 1 Wijsgeren sluiten de rijen —het interbellum 2 1.1 Beths denkbeelden over het belang van organisaties . 2 1.2 Nederlandse genootschappen . 11 1.2.1 Significa: in vogelvlucht . 12 1.2.2 Significa: denkbeelden. 19 1.2.3 Significa: Beths kritieken . 30 1.2.4 Significa: congressen en Synthese . 34 1.2.5 Internationale School voor Wijsbegeerte. 40 1.2.6 Genootschap voor Critische (Wetenschappelijke) Philosophie. 42 1.2.7 Algemene Nederlandse Vereniging van Wijsbegeerte . 45 1.2.8 Wiskundig Genootschap . 47 1.2.9 Akademie van Wetenschappen. 48 1.3 Internationale filosofische verenigingen . 50 1.3.1 Wiener Kreis: WK, Verein Ernst Mach, Berliner Gruppe . 50 1.3.2 Wiener Kreis: Nederland en de WK . 55 1.3.3 Wiener Kreis: Unity of Science Movement . 63 1.3.4 Institut International de (Collaboration) Philosophique. 67 1.3.5 Fed´ eration´ Internationale des Societ´ es´ de Philosophie. 69 2 Wetenschapsfilosofische organisaties —na WWII 70 2.1 Genootschappen ontstaan . 70 2.1.1 Societ´ e´ Internationale de Logique et de Philosophie des Sciences 70 2.1.2 Nederlandse Vereniging voor Logica. 72 2.1.3 UNESCO-organisaties: ICSU, CIPHS . 73 2.1.4 Kleinere organisaties: AIPS, IIST PSA, Phil.Sc.Group. 73 2.1.5 International Union of Philosophy of Science. 74 2.2 UIPS versus UIHS . 77 2.2.1 International Union of History of Sciences. 77 2.2.2 Association for Symbolic Logic. 81 2.3 Eenheid in Veelheid . 82 2.3.1 International Union of History and Philosophy of Sciences .
    [Show full text]
  • Women in Early Analytic Philosophy: Volume Volume 5, Number 2 Introduction Editor in Chief Maria Van Der Schaar and Eric Schliesser Kevin C
    JOURNAL FOR THE HISTORY OF ANALYTICAL PHILOSOPHY WOMEN IN EARLY ANALYTIC PHILOSOPHY: VOLUME VOLUME 5, NUMBER 2 INTRODUCTION EDITOR IN CHIEF MARIA VAN DER SCHAAR AND ERIC SCHLIESSER KEVIN C. KLEMENt, UnIVERSITY OF MASSACHUSETTS EDITORIAL BOARD ANNALISA COLIVA, UnIVERSITY OF MODENA AND UC IRVINE GaRY EBBS, INDIANA UnIVERSITY BLOOMINGTON GrEG FROSt-ARNOLD, HOBART AND WILLIAM SMITH COLLEGES HENRY JACKMAN, YORK UnIVERSITY SANDRA LaPOINte, MCMASTER UnIVERSITY CONSUELO PRETI, THE COLLEGE OF NEW JERSEY MARCUS ROSSBERG, UnIVERSITY OF CONNECTICUT ANTHONY SKELTON, WESTERN UnIVERSITY MARK TEXTOR, KING’S COLLEGE LonDON AUDREY YAP, UnIVERSITY OF VICTORIA RICHARD ZACH, UnIVERSITY OF CALGARY REVIEW EDITORS JULIET FLOYD, BOSTON UnIVERSITY CHRIS PINCOCK, OHIO STATE UnIVERSITY ASSISTANT REVIEW EDITOR SEAN MORRIS, METROPOLITAN STATE UnIVERSITY OF DenVER DESIGN DaNIEL HARRIS, HUNTER COLLEGE JHAPONLINE.ORG SPECIAL ISSUE: WOMEN IN EARLY ANALYTIC PHILOSOPHY © 2017 MARIA VAN DER SCHAAR AND ERIC SCHLIESSER EDITED BY MARIA VAN DER SCHAAR AND ERIC SCHLIESSER WOMEN IN EARLY ANALYTIC PHILOSOPHY: movement in the more strict sense of analytic philosophy, and VOLUME INTRODUCTION they were educated at the centres of analytic philosophy of their time. If we focus on the period before World War II, centres of MARIA VAN DER SCHAAR AND ERIC SCHLIESSER analytic philosophy in the strict sense are to be found in Lvov, Warsaw, Vienna, Cambridge, and Harvard. Of these, perhaps, the inclusion of Harvard is controversial, but the paper by Giulia Felappi helps us to understand why it is legitimate to include The three women that form the focus of this special issue, Susan Harvard. Stebbing (1895–1943), Susanne Langer (1895–1985), and Maria We speak of the Lvov-Warsaw School, the Vienna Circle, and Kokoszyńska (1905–1981), belong to the first group of women the Cambridge School of Analysis, and of British analytic philos- who became recognized philosophers by obtaining a perma- ophy in general.
    [Show full text]
  • Ludwig Wittgenstein and Hermann Broch: the Need for Fiction and Logic in Moral Philosophy Christopher Bailes Washington University in St
    Washington University in St. Louis Washington University Open Scholarship All Theses and Dissertations (ETDs) 5-24-2012 Ludwig Wittgenstein and Hermann Broch: The Need for Fiction and Logic in Moral Philosophy Christopher Bailes Washington University in St. Louis Follow this and additional works at: https://openscholarship.wustl.edu/etd Recommended Citation Bailes, Christopher, "Ludwig Wittgenstein and Hermann Broch: The eN ed for Fiction and Logic in Moral Philosophy" (2012). All Theses and Dissertations (ETDs). 681. https://openscholarship.wustl.edu/etd/681 This Dissertation is brought to you for free and open access by Washington University Open Scholarship. It has been accepted for inclusion in All Theses and Dissertations (ETDs) by an authorized administrator of Washington University Open Scholarship. For more information, please contact [email protected]. WASHINGTON UNIVERSITY IN ST. LOUIS Department of Germanic Languages and Literatures Dissertation Examination Committee: Paul Michael Lützeler, Chair Julia Driver Matt Erlin Erin McGlothlin Gillian Russell Lynne Tatlock Ludwig Wittgenstein and Hermann Broch: The Need for Fiction and Logic in Moral Philosophy By Christopher Wade Bailes A dissertation presented to the Graduate School of Arts and Sciences of Washington University in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy May 2012 Saint Louis, Missouri Acknowledgements I would like to thank the Department of Germanic Languages and Literatures and Washington University in Saint Louis for their generous financial support. My dissertation benefited from various guest lecturers, conferences, and graduate seminars supported by the university, and would not have been financially feasible without the tuition waivers and more than adequate living stipends that kept me afloat.
    [Show full text]
  • The Archivist's Archives. the Powerful Nijhoff and What Historians of Science Can Learn from His Legacy – Floris Boudens
    The Archivist’s Archives. The powerful Nijhoff and what historians of science can learn from his legacy – Floris Boudens Today the archive is an essential part of historical scholarship, a situation that came into being in the nineteenth century. This paper focusses on one of the first provincial archivists Isaac Anne Nijhoff who also pioneered in professionalizing the historical discipline. The aim of the paper is threefold. Firstly, it places the nineteenth century archive in historical context, and using Foucauldian concepts it showcases the power relations at play there, especially in the Guelders archive where Nijhoff worked. Secondly, drawing on primary sources it explains the significance of Nijhoff’s career as historian-archivist. Finally, this paper argues that a broader interpretation of the term ‘science archives’ is warranted , encompassing also patrimony such as Nijhoff’s. “Rembering the Scientific Self: A methodological argument for scientific self-archiving and “Living Archives” – Matthijs Sweekhorst To chronicle oneself—to document one’s progression as an academic actor—is often perceived as an act of haughtiness; if not as an act of pure hubris. Only once the academic peasant transcends the castes—if he does—and attracts some noble fame, his personality transcends from idealised irrelevancy to idolised historicity; and only then, is such a personality expected to be properly archived and documented. The paradox ought to be clear: we cannot expect Great Minds to uphold meticulous self-preservation, when throughout their juvenescence, we request that they abstain from precisely such practices. This paper argues that, rather than to suppress self-preservation out of some vain-driven humility or “will to willessness,” now is the time to acknowledge that the academic scholar has an obligation to his scientific self; an obligation to practice self-archiving.
    [Show full text]
  • VERIFICATIONISM | Lent 2019 | Maarten Steenhagen ([email protected])
    VERIFICATIONISM | Lent 2019 | Maarten Steenhagen ([email protected]) http://msteenhagen.github.io/teaching/2019ver/ Lecture 1: The verification principle A.J. Ayer (1946) Language, Truth and Logic. 2nd ed. (London: Gollancz), Intro. & ch. 1. Empirical hypotheses Science and metaphysics both make claims about how the world is. (e.g. ‘Not everything is conscious’; ‘All mammals have three middle ear bones’; ‘Time is relative to an observer’). Such claims are ‘hypotheses’ and we can ask whether they are true or false. Such questions can lead to disagreements among scientists, among metaphysicians, and among metaphysicians and scientists. If such a disagreement cannot (now) be settled, then we should take both parties to be rival views of reality. This puts science and metaphysics on a par. Recall what Hume said: “If we take in our hand any volume; of divinity or school metaphysics, for instance; let us ask, Does it contain any abstract reasoning concerning quantity or number? No. Does it contain any experimental reasoning concerning matter of fact and existence? No. Commit it then to the flames: for it can contain nothing but sophistry and illusion.” Ayer offers a ‘semantic weeding tool’ where Hume provided a psychological one. Ayer writes: “one cannot overthrow a system of transcendent metaphysics merely by criticizing the way in which it comes into being. What is required is rather a criticism of the nature of the actual statements which comprise it.” (1946, p.34) Logical positivism Ayer was strongly influenced by Logical Positivism. This movement in philosophy of science started in Vienna in the 1920s and 1930s.
    [Show full text]
  • Chapter 4 the Genesis of Karl Popper's Philosophical
    CHAPTER 4 THE GENESIS OF KARL POPPER’S PHILOSOPHICAL IDEAS 4.0 Introduction Karl Popper was one of the most prominent philosophers in the past century as he has been the most prolific, wide-ranging and the most influential among scientists. This sentence is evident as attested to the statement made by Sir Peter Medawar, a winner of the Nobel Prize for medicine and himself an experienced analyst of scientific thought and practise, that says: ‘I think Popper is incomparably the greatest philosopher of science that has ever been.’ Medawar’s judgment was subsequently affirmed by other eminent scientists, such as Sir Herman Bondi, who wrote, ‘there is no more to science than its method, and there is no more to its method than Popper has said’; and in similar vein, Sir John Eccles, another Nobel Prize winner, testified to the impact of Popper’s philosophy on his approach to research: ‘my scientific life owes so much to my conversion in 1945… to Popper’s teachings on the conduct of investigations… I have endeavoured to follow Popper in the formulation and in the investigation of fundamental problems in neurobiology’ (Magee 1975). Furthermore, recent survey of scholarly literature on totalitarianism and on social science methodology found him mentioned more often than any philosopher, including Hannah Arendt, Ludwig Wittgenstein, and Thomas Kuhn.56 And, in fact, in a time in the 56 Peter Hedström, Richard Swedberg, and Lars Udéhn in their “Popper’s Situational Analysis and Contemporary Sociology,” Philosophy of the Social Sciences, 28 (1998), 342-3, survey the five leading sociology journals in the United States, Britain, France, Germany, and Italy (1960-96).
    [Show full text]
  • Women in Early Analytic Philosophy: Volume Introduction
    UvA-DARE (Digital Academic Repository) Women in Early Analytic Philosophy Volume Introduction van der Schaar, M.; Schliesser, E. DOI 10.15173/jhap.v5i2.3142 Publication date 2017 Document Version Final published version Published in Journal for the History of Analytical Philosophy License CC BY-NC Link to publication Citation for published version (APA): van der Schaar, M., & Schliesser, E. (2017). Women in Early Analytic Philosophy: Volume Introduction. Journal for the History of Analytical Philosophy, 5(2). https://doi.org/10.15173/jhap.v5i2.3142 General rights It is not permitted to download or to forward/distribute the text or part of it without the consent of the author(s) and/or copyright holder(s), other than for strictly personal, individual use, unless the work is under an open content license (like Creative Commons). Disclaimer/Complaints regulations If you believe that digital publication of certain material infringes any of your rights or (privacy) interests, please let the Library know, stating your reasons. In case of a legitimate complaint, the Library will make the material inaccessible and/or remove it from the website. Please Ask the Library: https://uba.uva.nl/en/contact, or a letter to: Library of the University of Amsterdam, Secretariat, Singel 425, 1012 WP Amsterdam, The Netherlands. You will be contacted as soon as possible. UvA-DARE is a service provided by the library of the University of Amsterdam (https://dare.uva.nl) Download date:03 Oct 2021 JOURNAL FOR THE HISTORY OF ANALYTICAL PHILOSOPHY WOMEN IN EARLY ANALYTIC PHILOSOPHY: VOLUME VOLUME 5, NUMBER 2 INTRODUCTION EDITOR IN CHIEF MARIA VAN DER SCHAAR AND ERIC SCHLIESSER KEVIN C.
    [Show full text]
  • Warring with Chaos
    BOOKS & ARTS COMMENT of quantum mechanics. He also sets HISTORY OF SCIENCE Fermi’s work as an adviser and ad hoc problem solver at Los Alamos against the full drama of the Manhattan Project. In those intense and hectic days, Fermi’s Warring with chaos door was always open to provide on-the- fly solutions to any technical problem Jordi Cat on a history of the Vienna Circle, which experienced by an engineer or a physi- wielded science to counter the turmoil of the 1930s. cist designing the weapons. At the same time, Fermi and Laura heartily joined in the social life of Bathtub Row, the street arl Sigmund is alarmed. In Exact standards through where J. Robert Oppenheimer and other Thinking in Demented Times, the book series, the philo- project members lived. (Schwartz notes, Viennese mathematician and pio- sophical journal Erk- however, that Fermi watched the square Kneer of evolutionary game theory identifies enntnis, conferences dancing with some puzzlement, while sustained threats to rationality today, from and lectures. The Laura joined in.) religious fundamentalism to a “debilitating model they conceived The book is rich in political, historical flood of trash culture” and public ennui. was, first, based on for- and technical detail. But its prose style is Sigmund worries that many scientists ignore mal concepts and rules awkward. And I was irked by Schwartz’s these risks to their world view and work. — linguistic, logical or tendency to dwell on an issue, puzzling Sigmund compares our times with Austria Exact Thinking mathematical — simi- through various philosophical considera- between the world wars.
    [Show full text]
  • Philosophia Scientiæ, 19-1 | 2015, « Logic and Philosophy of Science in Nancy (II) » [En Ligne], Mis En Ligne Le 01 Mars 2015, Consulté Le 06 Novembre 2020
    Philosophia Scientiæ Travaux d'histoire et de philosophie des sciences 19-1 | 2015 Logic and Philosophy of Science in Nancy (II) Selected Contributed Papers from the 14th International Congress of Logic, Methodology and Philosophy of Science Pierre Édouard Bour, Gerhard Heinzmann, Wilfrid Hodges et Peter Schroeder-Heister (dir.) Édition électronique URL : http://journals.openedition.org/philosophiascientiae/1027 DOI : 10.4000/philosophiascientiae.1027 ISSN : 1775-4283 Éditeur Éditions Kimé Édition imprimée Date de publication : 1 mars 2015 ISBN : 978-2-84174-707-8 ISSN : 1281-2463 Référence électronique Pierre Édouard Bour, Gerhard Heinzmann, Wilfrid Hodges et Peter Schroeder-Heister (dir.), Philosophia Scientiæ, 19-1 | 2015, « Logic and Philosophy of Science in Nancy (II) » [En ligne], mis en ligne le 01 mars 2015, consulté le 06 novembre 2020. URL : http://journals.openedition.org/philosophiascientiae/ 1027 ; DOI : https://doi.org/10.4000/philosophiascientiae.1027 Ce document a été généré automatiquement le 6 novembre 2020. Tous droits réservés 1 This issue collects a selection of contributed papers presented at the 14th International Congress of Logic, Methodology and Philosophy of Science in Nancy, July 2011. These papers were originally presented within two of the main sections of the Congress. They deal with general philosophy of science (including ethical and historical aspects of philosophy of science), and philosophy of biology, physics, chemistry and economics. A first volume of contributed papers, dedicated to logic, philosophy
    [Show full text]