Organisaties En Genootschappen

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Organisaties En Genootschappen Organisaties en genootschappen. P. van Ulsen 7 november 2017 Inhoudsopgave 1 Wijsgeren sluiten de rijen —het interbellum 2 1.1 Beths denkbeelden over het belang van organisaties . 2 1.2 Nederlandse genootschappen . 11 1.2.1 Significa: in vogelvlucht . 12 1.2.2 Significa: denkbeelden. 19 1.2.3 Significa: Beths kritieken . 30 1.2.4 Significa: congressen en Synthese . 34 1.2.5 Internationale School voor Wijsbegeerte. 40 1.2.6 Genootschap voor Critische (Wetenschappelijke) Philosophie. 42 1.2.7 Algemene Nederlandse Vereniging van Wijsbegeerte . 45 1.2.8 Wiskundig Genootschap . 47 1.2.9 Akademie van Wetenschappen. 48 1.3 Internationale filosofische verenigingen . 50 1.3.1 Wiener Kreis: WK, Verein Ernst Mach, Berliner Gruppe . 50 1.3.2 Wiener Kreis: Nederland en de WK . 55 1.3.3 Wiener Kreis: Unity of Science Movement . 63 1.3.4 Institut International de (Collaboration) Philosophique. 67 1.3.5 Fed´ eration´ Internationale des Societ´ es´ de Philosophie. 69 2 Wetenschapsfilosofische organisaties —na WWII 70 2.1 Genootschappen ontstaan . 70 2.1.1 Societ´ e´ Internationale de Logique et de Philosophie des Sciences 70 2.1.2 Nederlandse Vereniging voor Logica. 72 2.1.3 UNESCO-organisaties: ICSU, CIPHS . 73 2.1.4 Kleinere organisaties: AIPS, IIST PSA, Phil.Sc.Group. 73 2.1.5 International Union of Philosophy of Science. 74 2.2 UIPS versus UIHS . 77 2.2.1 International Union of History of Sciences. 77 2.2.2 Association for Symbolic Logic. 81 2.3 Eenheid in Veelheid . 82 2.3.1 International Union of History and Philosophy of Sciences . 82 2.3.2 International Mathematical Union. 93 2.3.3 Wetenschapshistorici op water en brood . 97 1 3 De eerste jaren van de UIHPS 105 3.1 De UIHPS in de VS . 105 3.1.1 National Academy of Sciences . 105 3.1.2 National Committee UIHPS-VS . 107 3.2 Pecunia non olet . 110 3.2.1 Bestuur en bevoegdheden . 110 3.2.2 Functies bij PS (DLMPS), HS (DHS), UIHPS. 112 3.2.3 Symposia en congressen . 112 3.3 Een samenzwering . 116 3.3.1 Verdwenen notulen . 116 3.3.2 AIPS geelimineerd¨ . 119 3.3.3 AIPS: een dode staat op . 123 3.3.4 UIHPS, DLMPS, latere fasen . 125 3.4 Nawoord . 126 4 Redactioneel werk 126 4.1 Inleiding . 126 4.2 Studies in Logic . 128 4.2.1 Redactionele opzet . 128 4.2.2 Aandachtsgebieden . 133 4.3 Journal of Symbolic Logic . 149 4.4 Nawoord . 152 5 Supplementen 152 5.0.1 Afkortingen van organisaties . 152 5.0.2 Bronnen . 153 5.0.3 Dankbetuiging. 154 6 Bibliografie 154 1 Wijsgeren sluiten de rijen —het interbellum 1.1 Beths denkbeelden over het belang van organisaties Op het gebied van organiserend vermogen op logisch, wetenschapsfilosofisch en wijs- gerig terrein heeft Nederland een goed figuur geslagen. Er zijn tal van leidende figuren geweest van nationaal en international belang. Er is er echter maar e´en´ die allen slaat, en dat was E.W. Beth. Derhalve zal het verhaal over het reilen en zeilen van logische en methodologische verenigingen vooral op hem toegespitst worden, en daarmee vooral op de eerste twintig jaar na WWII. Bovendien had Beth zo zijn ideeen¨ over organisa- ties. Dat maakt een focus op hem ook interessanter. De anderen komen op hun tijd ook aan bod, en onder hen vallen niet de minsten. Voorbeelden van hen zijn A. Heyting, F. Staal, G. Mannoury, H. Freudenthal, L.E.J. Brouwer, A.G.M. van Melsen. Men kan hiermee doorgaan, velen hebben zich niet ontrokken aan deze taken van meer algemeen belang. Helaas kan niet aan iedereen aandacht worden geboden. 2 Een belangrijk bestanddeel van Beths bezigheden bestond uit zijn organisatorisch werk. Ook Heyting speelde naast Beth een rol bij tal van, ook internationale, geleerde genootschappen en organisaties. Hij was daarbij echter niet zo prominent aanwezig gelijk Beth. Vaak traden Beth en Heyting gezamenlijk op t.b.v. een door beiden gedeeld doel voor ogen. In alle gevallen was het vooral Beth, die met nieuwe dingen aan kwam en had Heyting een meer ondersteunende rol. Hierdoor zal de meeste aandacht in dit stuk vooral naar Beth uitgaan. Naast Beths algemene denkbeelden over het nut van organisaties, valt het practische deel uiteen in de volgende onderdelen: ◦ Organiserende bezigheden gerelateerd aan de Nederlandse en buitenlandse filosofie. ◦ Beths intree in internationale organisaties; de vorming van wetenschapsfilosofische en logische verenigingen. ◦ Vorming van de International Union of History and Philosophy of Sciences [UIHPS]. ◦ Redactioneel werk. Gedurende zijn gehele leven is Beth lidmaat geweest van vele organisaties. Be- stuursfuncties heeft hij nooit geschuwd. Veel tijd heeft hij gestoken in het oprichten of het bijeenbrengen van diverse verenigingen. Waarom stak hij daar zo veel tijd in, die hij toch beter aan wetenschappelijk werk had kunnen besteden? De doelen, die men met organisaties kan bereiken zijn belangenbehartiging, het uitgeven van periodieken, het organiseren van congressen en het kweken van een goede voedingsbodem voor we- tenschap en onderlinge contacten. Als deze ‘infrastructuur’ nog niet aanwezig is, dan zal men enige tijd er in moeten steken om daar later de vruchten van te kunnen plukken. Jammer genoeg kon in het geval van Beth van dat laatste geen sprake zijn vanwege zijn vroegtijdige overlijden. Maar niet alleen was Beth zelf een groot liefhebber van con- gressen, er was ook nog een ideologisch motief bij hem aanwezig. Congressen geven ruimte aan een internationaal forum en daar was hij een voorstander van. Een´ van de overwegingen daartoe wordt beschreven in Beth (1948a): ‘De hedendaagse totalitaire politiek kan voor een aanmerkelijk deel worden terugge- bracht tot de invloed van G.F. Hegel. De zeer grote, nog steeds voortdurende invloed van Hegel’s ideeen¨ is echter m.i. niet uit haar innerlijke gehalte te verklaren. Van meer belang is het feit, dat Hegel’s philosophie gedurende enige decennia een monopolie- positie heeft ingenomen. Van Pruissen uit is ze daarna haar zegetocht begonnen, eerst door Duitsland, vervolgens door Europa en zelfs daarbuiten. Was Hegel’s philosophie in een vroeg stadium van haar ontwikkeling blootgesteld geweest aan een discussie op internationaal plan, dan zou zij naar mijn mening zelfs in Pruissen nimmer een groot prestige hebben kunnen verwerven en zou ons wellicht veel ellende bespaard zijn ge- bleven.’ Een ander doel voor organisaties ligt in het uitgeven van periodieken. Een voor- beeld hiervan is de Association for Symbolic Logic [ASL] met de Journal of Symbolic Logic [JSL]. Sommige organisaties hadden geen eigen periodiek, maar hadden wel bin- dingen met bepaalde bladen, zoals de International Society for Significs [ISS] met Syn- these en de Societ´ e´ Internationale de Logique et de Philosophie des Sciences [SILPS] met Dialectica. Op vaderlandse bodem is de Algemene Nederlandse Vereniging voor Wijsbegeerte [ANVW] gelieerd aan het Algemeen Nederlands Tijdschrift voor Wijsbe- geerte [ANTW]. 3 Beths redactionele werk was niet organiserend werk in de strikte zin van het woord, maar droeg wel bij aan het internationale forum waar Beth een voorstander van was. De verspreiding en uitwisseling van wetenschappelijke ideeen¨ over de logica en weten- schapsfilosofie vinden hun schriftelijke en openbare voltooi¨ıng in boeken en tijdschrif- ten. Aan beide media heeft Beth bijgedragen door het oprichten van de boekenreeks Studies in Logic in een tijd toen er voor logica nog weinig lopende reeksen waren, en door zijn deelname aan de redactie van de Journal of Symbolic Logic. Belangenbehartiging kan ook een drijfveer tot het oprichten van organisaties vor- men. Men kan menen dat organisaties wel moeten leiden tot het verbeteren van we- tenschappelijk onderzoek. Dit kan op een deceptie uitdraaien. Veel werk, veel ruzie, weinig resultaten, die men aan het instandhouden van een organisatie kan toeschrijven. Een voorbeeld van het laatste vormt een brief van de logica-historicus I.M. Bochenski aan W.V. Quine: 1 ‘I have been deceived. It is in my opinion that international organizations do not help research. Moreover, if I have been personally drive out of the field of research for some years, this is due for a part at least, to the necessity of working for such organizations.’ Toch zag Bochenski wel wat in door mensen zoals hijzelf georganiseerde groepen. Anders staan anderen, in logica minder competente lieden, klaar dit te doen om onder de mom van logica eigenaardige ideeen¨ aan de man te brengen en geld op te strijken. Bochenski stond hierin niet alleen, Beth had hetzelfde idee. Dat idee zou voor Beth een leidraad vormen voor beslissingen en koers binnen zijn wetenschapspolitiek In 1959 gaf Beth een overzicht van het reilen en zeilen binnen de wereld van lo- gica en wetenschapsfilosofie. Dit deed hij, omdat mensen die werkzaam waren in deze vakgebieden en daarnaast bezig waren deze vakgebieden te institutionaliseren, veel- vuldig last hadden van allerlei aantijgingen, die zij moesten zien te weerleggen. De aantijgingen kwamen voornamelijk uit twee hoeken. De ene was die der filosofische diehards, de andere die der exacte wetenschappen. Ook binnen de laatste groep wer- den logica en wetenschapsfilosofie dikwijls niet al te serieus genomen. Binnen de voor naar erkenning hunkerende wetenschapsfilosofen en logici belangrijke International Council of Scientific Unions [ICSU] had men daar nogal eens last van. Het ‘propagan- darapport’ van Beth uit 1959 behelsde naast een algemene inleiding een overzicht van congressen, organisaties, tijdschriften en boekenreeksen om hem en de zijnen status te verlenen. Bovendien had men telkens weer te maken met de argumenten dat in vroeger tijd de wetenschapsfilosofen en logici nooit een eigen organisatie hadden opgericht, de wetenschappelijke resultaten uit deze hoek miniem waren en er geen internationale congressen georganiseerd werden. In het verlengde hiervan lag de bewering dat eigen- lijk alles al door de filosofen en wiskundigen gedekt werd.
Recommended publications
  • Guide to Proper Names and References in Gödel's “Protokolle
    Guide to proper names and references in Gödel’s “Protokolle” notebook People Abel Othenio Abel (1875-1946) professor of paleontology and paleobiology at the University of Vienna. Founder of the group of professors known as the “Bärenhöhle” that blocked the appointment and promotion of Jews Adele Adele Nimbursky, née Porkert (1899–1981), Gödel’s girlfriend, separated from her first husband; she and Gödel would marry in September 1938 Bachmann Friedrich Bachmann (1909–1982), mathematician, doctoral student of Scholz’s at Münster, where he received his Ph.D. in 1933; from 1935 at University of Marburg, as assistant then Privatdozent Behmann Heinrich Behmann (1891–1970), German mathematician; his reply to Perelman’s criticism of Gödel’s result had appeared in the journal Mind in April 1937. He was dismissed from his position at ​ ​ the University of Halle after the war for his Nazi Party activities Beer Gustav Beer, member of the Vienna Circle and Menger’s Mathematical Colloquium Benjamin Abram Cornelius Benjamin (1897–1968), American philosopher of science on the University of Chicago faculty 1932 to 1945 Bernays Paul Bernays (1888–1977), Swiss mathematician and logician; close collaborator with David Hilbert on the foundations of mathematics and the axiomatization of set theory Brentano Franz Brentano (1838-1917), resigned as priest, Professor of Philosophy at the University of Vienna, founder of Gestalt Brunsvick Egon Brunswik (1903–1955), Hungarian-born psychologist, assistant to Karl Bühler in Vienna, active member of Otto Neurath’s “Unity of Science” movement Bühler Karl Bühler (1879–1963), professor of psychology at the University of Vienna. He led an effort to reorganize Vienna’s city schools by incorporating scientific findings from child psychology.
    [Show full text]
  • Esther Simpson - the Unknown Heroine
    From The Jewish Chronicle, 11 May 2017 https://www.thejc.com/news/news-features/esther-simpson-the-unknown-heroine- 1.438317?highlight=Simpson David Edmonds May 11, 2017 Esther Simpson - the unknown heroine The extraordinary story of how one woman offered refuge to philosophers, scientists and musicians fleeing from the Nazis, and in doing so reshaped the cultural and intellectual landscape of the Western World. It’s not clear how Professor Stanislaus Jolles died. The year was 1943 and he was in his mid-eighties. But did he die from natural causes, did he kill himself, or was he killed? He was a Jew living in Berlin, after the systematic extermination of Jews had already begun, so anything is possible. The fate of his wife, Adele, is documented. In the year of her husband’s passing, she was transported south from the German capital to Theresienstadt concentration camp in Czechoslovakia. She perished in 1944. She was Miss Simpson to strangers, Esther to colleagues, Tess to some of her close friends. And she had many, many friends, among whom she counted Ludwig Wittgenstein, often described as the greatest philosopher of the twentieth century. Wittgenstein had been acquainted with Stanislaus Jolles for over three decades, ever since he’d left his palatial Viennese home in 1906 to study engineering in Berlin. Professor and Mrs Jolles had been his hosts. Stanislaus was a mathematician who came to look upon Ludwig like a son; he and his wife called him ‘little Wittgenstein’. During World War I, when Wittgenstein was fighting for the Austrians on the Eastern Front, they furnished him with a constant supply of bread, fruit-cake, and cigarettes.
    [Show full text]
  • Between the Lvov-Warsaw School and the Vienna Circle Volume 5, Number 2 Anna Brożek Editor in Chief Kevin C
    JOURNAL FOR THE HISTORY OF ANALYTICAL PHILOSOPHY MARIA KOKOSZYńSKa: BETWEEN THE LVOV-WARSAW SCHOOL AND THE VIENNA CIRCLE VOLUME 5, NUMBER 2 ANNA BROżEK EDITOR IN CHIEF KEVIN C. KLEMENt, UnIVERSITY OF MASSACHUSETTS Maria Kokoszyńska-Lutmanowa (1905–1981) was one of the EDITORIAL BOARD most outstanding female representatives of the Lvov-Warsaw ANNALISA COLIVA, UnIVERSITY OF MODENA AND UC IRVINE School. After achieving her PhD in philosophy under Kazimierz GaRY EBBS, INDIANA UnIVERSITY BLOOMINGTON Twardowski’s supervision, she was Kazimierz Ajdukiewicz’s as- GrEG FROSt-ARNOLD, HOBART AND WILLIAM SMITH COLLEGES sistant. She was also influenced by Alfred Tarski whose results HENRY JACKMAN, YORK UnIVERSITY in semantics she analyzed and popularized. After World War SANDRA LaPOINte, MCMASTER UnIVERSITY II, she got the chair of logic in University of Wrocław and she CONSUELO PRETI, THE COLLEGE OF NEW JERSEY organized studies in logic in this academic center. MARCUS ROSSBERG, UnIVERSITY OF CONNECTICUT ANTHONY SKELTON, WESTERN UnIVERSITY In the 1930s, Kokoszyńska kept in contact with members of the MARK TEXTOR, KING’S COLLEGE LonDON Vienna Circle and became a kind of connecting factor between AUDREY YAP, UnIVERSITY OF VICTORIA Polish logicians and the Viennese group. In Poland, she pre- RICHARD ZACH, UnIVERSITY OF CALGARY sented the views of members of the Vienna Circle. In Vienna, REVIEW EDITORS she emphasized the results of her Polish colleagues. JULIET FLOYD, BOSTON UnIVERSITY CHRIS PINCOCK, OHIO STATE UnIVERSITY In the present paper, some of Kokoszyńska’s results connected with the matters discussed in the Vienna Circle are presented, ASSISTANT REVIEW EDITOR namely with the problem of metaphysics, the status of logic and SEAN MORRIS, METROPOLITAN STATE UnIVERSITY OF DenVER the idea of unity of science.
    [Show full text]
  • Women in Early Analytic Philosophy: Volume Volume 5, Number 2 Introduction Editor in Chief Maria Van Der Schaar and Eric Schliesser Kevin C
    JOURNAL FOR THE HISTORY OF ANALYTICAL PHILOSOPHY WOMEN IN EARLY ANALYTIC PHILOSOPHY: VOLUME VOLUME 5, NUMBER 2 INTRODUCTION EDITOR IN CHIEF MARIA VAN DER SCHAAR AND ERIC SCHLIESSER KEVIN C. KLEMENt, UnIVERSITY OF MASSACHUSETTS EDITORIAL BOARD ANNALISA COLIVA, UnIVERSITY OF MODENA AND UC IRVINE GaRY EBBS, INDIANA UnIVERSITY BLOOMINGTON GrEG FROSt-ARNOLD, HOBART AND WILLIAM SMITH COLLEGES HENRY JACKMAN, YORK UnIVERSITY SANDRA LaPOINte, MCMASTER UnIVERSITY CONSUELO PRETI, THE COLLEGE OF NEW JERSEY MARCUS ROSSBERG, UnIVERSITY OF CONNECTICUT ANTHONY SKELTON, WESTERN UnIVERSITY MARK TEXTOR, KING’S COLLEGE LonDON AUDREY YAP, UnIVERSITY OF VICTORIA RICHARD ZACH, UnIVERSITY OF CALGARY REVIEW EDITORS JULIET FLOYD, BOSTON UnIVERSITY CHRIS PINCOCK, OHIO STATE UnIVERSITY ASSISTANT REVIEW EDITOR SEAN MORRIS, METROPOLITAN STATE UnIVERSITY OF DenVER DESIGN DaNIEL HARRIS, HUNTER COLLEGE JHAPONLINE.ORG SPECIAL ISSUE: WOMEN IN EARLY ANALYTIC PHILOSOPHY © 2017 MARIA VAN DER SCHAAR AND ERIC SCHLIESSER EDITED BY MARIA VAN DER SCHAAR AND ERIC SCHLIESSER WOMEN IN EARLY ANALYTIC PHILOSOPHY: movement in the more strict sense of analytic philosophy, and VOLUME INTRODUCTION they were educated at the centres of analytic philosophy of their time. If we focus on the period before World War II, centres of MARIA VAN DER SCHAAR AND ERIC SCHLIESSER analytic philosophy in the strict sense are to be found in Lvov, Warsaw, Vienna, Cambridge, and Harvard. Of these, perhaps, the inclusion of Harvard is controversial, but the paper by Giulia Felappi helps us to understand why it is legitimate to include The three women that form the focus of this special issue, Susan Harvard. Stebbing (1895–1943), Susanne Langer (1895–1985), and Maria We speak of the Lvov-Warsaw School, the Vienna Circle, and Kokoszyńska (1905–1981), belong to the first group of women the Cambridge School of Analysis, and of British analytic philos- who became recognized philosophers by obtaining a perma- ophy in general.
    [Show full text]
  • Ludwig Wittgenstein and Hermann Broch: the Need for Fiction and Logic in Moral Philosophy Christopher Bailes Washington University in St
    Washington University in St. Louis Washington University Open Scholarship All Theses and Dissertations (ETDs) 5-24-2012 Ludwig Wittgenstein and Hermann Broch: The Need for Fiction and Logic in Moral Philosophy Christopher Bailes Washington University in St. Louis Follow this and additional works at: https://openscholarship.wustl.edu/etd Recommended Citation Bailes, Christopher, "Ludwig Wittgenstein and Hermann Broch: The eN ed for Fiction and Logic in Moral Philosophy" (2012). All Theses and Dissertations (ETDs). 681. https://openscholarship.wustl.edu/etd/681 This Dissertation is brought to you for free and open access by Washington University Open Scholarship. It has been accepted for inclusion in All Theses and Dissertations (ETDs) by an authorized administrator of Washington University Open Scholarship. For more information, please contact [email protected]. WASHINGTON UNIVERSITY IN ST. LOUIS Department of Germanic Languages and Literatures Dissertation Examination Committee: Paul Michael Lützeler, Chair Julia Driver Matt Erlin Erin McGlothlin Gillian Russell Lynne Tatlock Ludwig Wittgenstein and Hermann Broch: The Need for Fiction and Logic in Moral Philosophy By Christopher Wade Bailes A dissertation presented to the Graduate School of Arts and Sciences of Washington University in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy May 2012 Saint Louis, Missouri Acknowledgements I would like to thank the Department of Germanic Languages and Literatures and Washington University in Saint Louis for their generous financial support. My dissertation benefited from various guest lecturers, conferences, and graduate seminars supported by the university, and would not have been financially feasible without the tuition waivers and more than adequate living stipends that kept me afloat.
    [Show full text]
  • The Archivist's Archives. the Powerful Nijhoff and What Historians of Science Can Learn from His Legacy – Floris Boudens
    The Archivist’s Archives. The powerful Nijhoff and what historians of science can learn from his legacy – Floris Boudens Today the archive is an essential part of historical scholarship, a situation that came into being in the nineteenth century. This paper focusses on one of the first provincial archivists Isaac Anne Nijhoff who also pioneered in professionalizing the historical discipline. The aim of the paper is threefold. Firstly, it places the nineteenth century archive in historical context, and using Foucauldian concepts it showcases the power relations at play there, especially in the Guelders archive where Nijhoff worked. Secondly, drawing on primary sources it explains the significance of Nijhoff’s career as historian-archivist. Finally, this paper argues that a broader interpretation of the term ‘science archives’ is warranted , encompassing also patrimony such as Nijhoff’s. “Rembering the Scientific Self: A methodological argument for scientific self-archiving and “Living Archives” – Matthijs Sweekhorst To chronicle oneself—to document one’s progression as an academic actor—is often perceived as an act of haughtiness; if not as an act of pure hubris. Only once the academic peasant transcends the castes—if he does—and attracts some noble fame, his personality transcends from idealised irrelevancy to idolised historicity; and only then, is such a personality expected to be properly archived and documented. The paradox ought to be clear: we cannot expect Great Minds to uphold meticulous self-preservation, when throughout their juvenescence, we request that they abstain from precisely such practices. This paper argues that, rather than to suppress self-preservation out of some vain-driven humility or “will to willessness,” now is the time to acknowledge that the academic scholar has an obligation to his scientific self; an obligation to practice self-archiving.
    [Show full text]
  • VERIFICATIONISM | Lent 2019 | Maarten Steenhagen ([email protected])
    VERIFICATIONISM | Lent 2019 | Maarten Steenhagen ([email protected]) http://msteenhagen.github.io/teaching/2019ver/ Lecture 1: The verification principle A.J. Ayer (1946) Language, Truth and Logic. 2nd ed. (London: Gollancz), Intro. & ch. 1. Empirical hypotheses Science and metaphysics both make claims about how the world is. (e.g. ‘Not everything is conscious’; ‘All mammals have three middle ear bones’; ‘Time is relative to an observer’). Such claims are ‘hypotheses’ and we can ask whether they are true or false. Such questions can lead to disagreements among scientists, among metaphysicians, and among metaphysicians and scientists. If such a disagreement cannot (now) be settled, then we should take both parties to be rival views of reality. This puts science and metaphysics on a par. Recall what Hume said: “If we take in our hand any volume; of divinity or school metaphysics, for instance; let us ask, Does it contain any abstract reasoning concerning quantity or number? No. Does it contain any experimental reasoning concerning matter of fact and existence? No. Commit it then to the flames: for it can contain nothing but sophistry and illusion.” Ayer offers a ‘semantic weeding tool’ where Hume provided a psychological one. Ayer writes: “one cannot overthrow a system of transcendent metaphysics merely by criticizing the way in which it comes into being. What is required is rather a criticism of the nature of the actual statements which comprise it.” (1946, p.34) Logical positivism Ayer was strongly influenced by Logical Positivism. This movement in philosophy of science started in Vienna in the 1920s and 1930s.
    [Show full text]
  • Chapter 4 the Genesis of Karl Popper's Philosophical
    CHAPTER 4 THE GENESIS OF KARL POPPER’S PHILOSOPHICAL IDEAS 4.0 Introduction Karl Popper was one of the most prominent philosophers in the past century as he has been the most prolific, wide-ranging and the most influential among scientists. This sentence is evident as attested to the statement made by Sir Peter Medawar, a winner of the Nobel Prize for medicine and himself an experienced analyst of scientific thought and practise, that says: ‘I think Popper is incomparably the greatest philosopher of science that has ever been.’ Medawar’s judgment was subsequently affirmed by other eminent scientists, such as Sir Herman Bondi, who wrote, ‘there is no more to science than its method, and there is no more to its method than Popper has said’; and in similar vein, Sir John Eccles, another Nobel Prize winner, testified to the impact of Popper’s philosophy on his approach to research: ‘my scientific life owes so much to my conversion in 1945… to Popper’s teachings on the conduct of investigations… I have endeavoured to follow Popper in the formulation and in the investigation of fundamental problems in neurobiology’ (Magee 1975). Furthermore, recent survey of scholarly literature on totalitarianism and on social science methodology found him mentioned more often than any philosopher, including Hannah Arendt, Ludwig Wittgenstein, and Thomas Kuhn.56 And, in fact, in a time in the 56 Peter Hedström, Richard Swedberg, and Lars Udéhn in their “Popper’s Situational Analysis and Contemporary Sociology,” Philosophy of the Social Sciences, 28 (1998), 342-3, survey the five leading sociology journals in the United States, Britain, France, Germany, and Italy (1960-96).
    [Show full text]
  • Women in Early Analytic Philosophy: Volume Introduction
    UvA-DARE (Digital Academic Repository) Women in Early Analytic Philosophy Volume Introduction van der Schaar, M.; Schliesser, E. DOI 10.15173/jhap.v5i2.3142 Publication date 2017 Document Version Final published version Published in Journal for the History of Analytical Philosophy License CC BY-NC Link to publication Citation for published version (APA): van der Schaar, M., & Schliesser, E. (2017). Women in Early Analytic Philosophy: Volume Introduction. Journal for the History of Analytical Philosophy, 5(2). https://doi.org/10.15173/jhap.v5i2.3142 General rights It is not permitted to download or to forward/distribute the text or part of it without the consent of the author(s) and/or copyright holder(s), other than for strictly personal, individual use, unless the work is under an open content license (like Creative Commons). Disclaimer/Complaints regulations If you believe that digital publication of certain material infringes any of your rights or (privacy) interests, please let the Library know, stating your reasons. In case of a legitimate complaint, the Library will make the material inaccessible and/or remove it from the website. Please Ask the Library: https://uba.uva.nl/en/contact, or a letter to: Library of the University of Amsterdam, Secretariat, Singel 425, 1012 WP Amsterdam, The Netherlands. You will be contacted as soon as possible. UvA-DARE is a service provided by the library of the University of Amsterdam (https://dare.uva.nl) Download date:03 Oct 2021 JOURNAL FOR THE HISTORY OF ANALYTICAL PHILOSOPHY WOMEN IN EARLY ANALYTIC PHILOSOPHY: VOLUME VOLUME 5, NUMBER 2 INTRODUCTION EDITOR IN CHIEF MARIA VAN DER SCHAAR AND ERIC SCHLIESSER KEVIN C.
    [Show full text]
  • Warring with Chaos
    BOOKS & ARTS COMMENT of quantum mechanics. He also sets HISTORY OF SCIENCE Fermi’s work as an adviser and ad hoc problem solver at Los Alamos against the full drama of the Manhattan Project. In those intense and hectic days, Fermi’s Warring with chaos door was always open to provide on-the- fly solutions to any technical problem Jordi Cat on a history of the Vienna Circle, which experienced by an engineer or a physi- wielded science to counter the turmoil of the 1930s. cist designing the weapons. At the same time, Fermi and Laura heartily joined in the social life of Bathtub Row, the street arl Sigmund is alarmed. In Exact standards through where J. Robert Oppenheimer and other Thinking in Demented Times, the book series, the philo- project members lived. (Schwartz notes, Viennese mathematician and pio- sophical journal Erk- however, that Fermi watched the square Kneer of evolutionary game theory identifies enntnis, conferences dancing with some puzzlement, while sustained threats to rationality today, from and lectures. The Laura joined in.) religious fundamentalism to a “debilitating model they conceived The book is rich in political, historical flood of trash culture” and public ennui. was, first, based on for- and technical detail. But its prose style is Sigmund worries that many scientists ignore mal concepts and rules awkward. And I was irked by Schwartz’s these risks to their world view and work. — linguistic, logical or tendency to dwell on an issue, puzzling Sigmund compares our times with Austria Exact Thinking mathematical — simi- through various philosophical considera- between the world wars.
    [Show full text]
  • Philosophia Scientiæ, 19-1 | 2015, « Logic and Philosophy of Science in Nancy (II) » [En Ligne], Mis En Ligne Le 01 Mars 2015, Consulté Le 06 Novembre 2020
    Philosophia Scientiæ Travaux d'histoire et de philosophie des sciences 19-1 | 2015 Logic and Philosophy of Science in Nancy (II) Selected Contributed Papers from the 14th International Congress of Logic, Methodology and Philosophy of Science Pierre Édouard Bour, Gerhard Heinzmann, Wilfrid Hodges et Peter Schroeder-Heister (dir.) Édition électronique URL : http://journals.openedition.org/philosophiascientiae/1027 DOI : 10.4000/philosophiascientiae.1027 ISSN : 1775-4283 Éditeur Éditions Kimé Édition imprimée Date de publication : 1 mars 2015 ISBN : 978-2-84174-707-8 ISSN : 1281-2463 Référence électronique Pierre Édouard Bour, Gerhard Heinzmann, Wilfrid Hodges et Peter Schroeder-Heister (dir.), Philosophia Scientiæ, 19-1 | 2015, « Logic and Philosophy of Science in Nancy (II) » [En ligne], mis en ligne le 01 mars 2015, consulté le 06 novembre 2020. URL : http://journals.openedition.org/philosophiascientiae/ 1027 ; DOI : https://doi.org/10.4000/philosophiascientiae.1027 Ce document a été généré automatiquement le 6 novembre 2020. Tous droits réservés 1 This issue collects a selection of contributed papers presented at the 14th International Congress of Logic, Methodology and Philosophy of Science in Nancy, July 2011. These papers were originally presented within two of the main sections of the Congress. They deal with general philosophy of science (including ethical and historical aspects of philosophy of science), and philosophy of biology, physics, chemistry and economics. A first volume of contributed papers, dedicated to logic, philosophy
    [Show full text]
  • Redalyc.A Hertzian Interpretation of Wittgenstein's Tractatus
    Eidos: Revista de Filosofía de la Universidad del Norte ISSN: 1692-8857 [email protected] Universidad del Norte Colombia Bizarro, Sara A hertzian interpretation of Wittgenstein's Tractatus Eidos: Revista de Filosofía de la Universidad del Norte, núm. 13, julio-diciembre, 2010, pp. 150-165 Universidad del Norte Barranquilla, Colombia Available in: http://www.redalyc.org/articulo.oa?id=85418392008 How to cite Complete issue Scientific Information System More information about this article Network of Scientific Journals from Latin America, the Caribbean, Spain and Portugal Journal's homepage in redalyc.org Non-profit academic project, developed under the open access initiative A hertzian interpretation of Wittgenstein’s Tractatus Sara Bizarro resumen abstract En este artículo se compara a In this paper I will compare Hertz y a Wittgenstein para pro- Hertz and Wittgenstein in order poner una nueva interpretación del to bring forth a new interpretation Tractatus. Revisaré las ideas de Witt- of the Tractatus. I shall look at genstein sobre los objetos simples Wittgenstein’s ideas about simple y las compararé con las partículas objects and compare them with materiales de Hertz. Luego afirmaré Hertz’s material particles. I shall que si uno entiende las partículas then claim that if one understands materiales de Hertz como entidades Hertz’s material particles as logical lógicas que parecen más coordena- entities that are more co-ordinate das que físicas, se puede lograr una like than physical, one can reach interpretación del Tractatus que an interpretation of the Tractatus calla deliberadamente acerca de la that is deliberately silent about the naturaleza de la realidad y que por nature of reality, therefore escaping tanto escapa a las interpretaciones both objectivist and subjectivist objetivista y subjetivista del libro.
    [Show full text]