Women in Early Analytic Philosophy: Volume Volume 5, Number 2 Introduction Editor in Chief Maria Van Der Schaar and Eric Schliesser Kevin C
Total Page:16
File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb
Load more
Recommended publications
-
Guide to Proper Names and References in Gödel's “Protokolle
Guide to proper names and references in Gödel’s “Protokolle” notebook People Abel Othenio Abel (1875-1946) professor of paleontology and paleobiology at the University of Vienna. Founder of the group of professors known as the “Bärenhöhle” that blocked the appointment and promotion of Jews Adele Adele Nimbursky, née Porkert (1899–1981), Gödel’s girlfriend, separated from her first husband; she and Gödel would marry in September 1938 Bachmann Friedrich Bachmann (1909–1982), mathematician, doctoral student of Scholz’s at Münster, where he received his Ph.D. in 1933; from 1935 at University of Marburg, as assistant then Privatdozent Behmann Heinrich Behmann (1891–1970), German mathematician; his reply to Perelman’s criticism of Gödel’s result had appeared in the journal Mind in April 1937. He was dismissed from his position at the University of Halle after the war for his Nazi Party activities Beer Gustav Beer, member of the Vienna Circle and Menger’s Mathematical Colloquium Benjamin Abram Cornelius Benjamin (1897–1968), American philosopher of science on the University of Chicago faculty 1932 to 1945 Bernays Paul Bernays (1888–1977), Swiss mathematician and logician; close collaborator with David Hilbert on the foundations of mathematics and the axiomatization of set theory Brentano Franz Brentano (1838-1917), resigned as priest, Professor of Philosophy at the University of Vienna, founder of Gestalt Brunsvick Egon Brunswik (1903–1955), Hungarian-born psychologist, assistant to Karl Bühler in Vienna, active member of Otto Neurath’s “Unity of Science” movement Bühler Karl Bühler (1879–1963), professor of psychology at the University of Vienna. He led an effort to reorganize Vienna’s city schools by incorporating scientific findings from child psychology. -
6 X 10.5 Long Title.P65
Cambridge University Press 978-0-521-83843-6 - Seeing Wittgenstein Anew Edited by William Day and Victor J. Krebs Frontmatter More information Seeing Wittgenstein Anew Seeing Wittgenstein Anew is the first collection to examine Ludwig Wittgenstein’s remarks on the concept of aspect-seeing. These essays show that aspect-seeing was not simply one more topic of in- vestigation in Wittgenstein’s later writings, but, rather, that it was a pervasive and guiding concept in his efforts to turn philosophy’s attention to the actual conditions of our common life in language. Arranged in sections that highlight the pertinence of the aspect- seeing remarks to aesthetic and moral perception, self-knowledge, mind and consciousness, linguistic agreement, philosophical therapy, and “seeing connections,” the sixteen essays, which were specially commissioned for this volume, demonstrate the unity of not only Philosophical Investigations but also Wittgenstein’s later thought as a whole. They open up novel paths across familiar fields of thought: the objectivity of interpretation, the fixity of the past, the acquisition of language, and the nature of human conscious- ness. Significantly, they exemplify how continuing consideration of the interrelated phenomena and concepts surrounding aspect- seeing might produce a fruitful way of doing philosophy. William Day is Associate Professor of Philosophy at Le Moyne College. A recipient of fellowships from the National Endowment for the Humanities, he has written articles on aesthetics and moral per- fectionist thought, with particular focus on the work of Wittgenstein, Cavell, Emerson, and Confucian thinkers. Victor J. Krebs is Associate Professor of Philosophy at the Pontificia Universidad Católica del Perú. -
Esther Simpson - the Unknown Heroine
From The Jewish Chronicle, 11 May 2017 https://www.thejc.com/news/news-features/esther-simpson-the-unknown-heroine- 1.438317?highlight=Simpson David Edmonds May 11, 2017 Esther Simpson - the unknown heroine The extraordinary story of how one woman offered refuge to philosophers, scientists and musicians fleeing from the Nazis, and in doing so reshaped the cultural and intellectual landscape of the Western World. It’s not clear how Professor Stanislaus Jolles died. The year was 1943 and he was in his mid-eighties. But did he die from natural causes, did he kill himself, or was he killed? He was a Jew living in Berlin, after the systematic extermination of Jews had already begun, so anything is possible. The fate of his wife, Adele, is documented. In the year of her husband’s passing, she was transported south from the German capital to Theresienstadt concentration camp in Czechoslovakia. She perished in 1944. She was Miss Simpson to strangers, Esther to colleagues, Tess to some of her close friends. And she had many, many friends, among whom she counted Ludwig Wittgenstein, often described as the greatest philosopher of the twentieth century. Wittgenstein had been acquainted with Stanislaus Jolles for over three decades, ever since he’d left his palatial Viennese home in 1906 to study engineering in Berlin. Professor and Mrs Jolles had been his hosts. Stanislaus was a mathematician who came to look upon Ludwig like a son; he and his wife called him ‘little Wittgenstein’. During World War I, when Wittgenstein was fighting for the Austrians on the Eastern Front, they furnished him with a constant supply of bread, fruit-cake, and cigarettes. -
Westphal Says That His Exhibition of Two Sources of a Commitment in Kant to Mental Content Externalism Ought to Be Understood
Can Mental Content Externalism Prove Realism?1 (Axel Mueller, Northwestern University) Recently, Kenneth Westphal has presented a highly interesting and innovative reading of Kant's critical philosophy.2 This reading continues a tradition of Kant- scholarship of which, e.g., Paul Guyer's work is representative, and in which the anti- idealistic potential of Kant's critical philosophy is pitted against its idealistic self- understanding. Much of the work in this tradition leaves matters at observing the tensions this introduces in Kant's work. But Westphal's proposed interpretation goes farther. Its attractiveness derives for the most part from the promise that it permits an internal critique of Kant's transcendental idealism (TI), that is, a critique that is based on the very resources of Kantian transcendental philosophy.3 In contrast to these resources, which currently seem to go through a sort of revival in an enormous array of fields, TI is notorious for dismaying even sympathetic interpreters. How attractive and needed such an internal critique of TI would be becomes all the more patent when we place such a promise in the context of some of the contemporary discussions about TI after Allison's famous defense of it. Before directly engaging with Westphal's interpretation, I would therefore like to quickly sketch on what background it acquires its force (I). After characterizing the main features of Westphal's view (II), and supporting it in more detail by an account of Kant's theory of cognitive significance (III), I then want to review the extent of its success to present Kant as issuing an anti-skeptical argument (IV.1), or semantic views that are incompatible with TI (IV.2), or a 'proof of not merely empirical realism' (IV.3). -
2.2 Glock Et Al
Journal for the History of Book Symposium: Analytical Philosophy Hans-Johann Glock, What is Analytic Philosophy? Volume 2, Number 2 Introduction Hans-Johann Glock..................... 1 Editor in Chief Mark Textor, King’s College London Commentaries Guest Editor Leila Haaparanta......................... 2 Mirja Hartimo, University of Helsinki Christopher Pincock....................6 Editorial Board Panu Raatikainen........................11 Juliet Floyd, Boston University Graham Stevens.......................... 28 Greg Frost-Arnold, Hobart and William Smith Colleges Ryan Hickerson, University of Western Oregon Replies Henry Jackman, York University Hans-Johann Glock..................... 36 Sandra Lapointe, McMaster University Chris Pincock, Ohio State University Richard Zach, University of Calgary Production Editor Ryan Hickerson Editorial Assistant Daniel Harris, CUNY Graduate Center Design Douglas Patterson and Daniel Harris ©2013 The Authors What is Analytic Philosophy? shall not be able to respond to all of the noteworthy criticisms and questions of my commentators. I have divided my responses ac- Hans-Johann Glock cording to commentator rather than topic, while also indicating some connections between their ideas where appropriate. Let me start by thanking the Journal for the History of Analytical Phi- losophy for offering me this opportunity to discuss my book What is Analytical Philosophy? (Cambridge, 2008). I am also very grateful Hans-Johann Glock for the valuable feedback from the contributors. And I thank both University of Zurich the journal and the contributors for their patience in waiting for [email protected] my replies. I was pleased to discover that all of my commentators express a certain sympathy with the central contention of my book, namely that analytic philosophy is an intellectual movement of the twentieth-century (with roots in the nineteenth and offshoots in the twenty-first), held together by family-resemblances on the one hand, ties of historical influence on the other. -
Juliet Floyd
September 21, 2017 Juliet Floyd Department of Philosophy Work: + 01 (617) 353-3745 Boston University, 745 Commonwealth Avenue Fax: +01 (617) 353-6805 Boston, MA 02215 E-mail: jfl[email protected] Academic Positions: 2006- Professor of Philosophy, Boston University 2003- Affiliated faculty in the following Boston University programs: - Linguistics - Center for the Philosophy and History of Science - Institute for the Philosophy of Religion - Graduate Division of Religious Studies - European Studies Program - Institute of Editorial Studies 1996-2006 Associate Professor of Philosophy, Boston University 1995 Visiting Assistant Professor of Philosophy, Boston University 1993-94 Deputy Executive Officer, Graduate Program in Philosophy, C.U.N.Y. 1992-95 Graduate Faculty Member in Philosophy, C.U.N.Y. 1990-95 Assistant Professor of Philosophy, City College of New York, C.U.N.Y. Visiting Positions: 2012 Visiting Professor, Philosophy, Universit´eMichel de Montaigne Bordeaux 2009 Visiting Professor, Philosophy, Universit´ede Paris I Panth´eon-Sorbonne 2007 Visiting Professor, Facult¨atf¨urPhilosophie, Universit¨atWien 1996 Visiting Professor, Boston University Research: History and Development of Analytic and Twentieth Century Philosophy Philosophy of Logic and Mathematics, Philosophy of Language Philosophy of Completeness and Incompleteness Formal and Traditional Epistemology, Theories of Truth Modern Philosophy (Kant), Aesthetics, Wittgenstein, Pragmatism History and Philosophy of Science, especially Logic and Mathematics Philosophy of Emerging Computational -
Between the Lvov-Warsaw School and the Vienna Circle Volume 5, Number 2 Anna Brożek Editor in Chief Kevin C
JOURNAL FOR THE HISTORY OF ANALYTICAL PHILOSOPHY MARIA KOKOSZYńSKa: BETWEEN THE LVOV-WARSAW SCHOOL AND THE VIENNA CIRCLE VOLUME 5, NUMBER 2 ANNA BROżEK EDITOR IN CHIEF KEVIN C. KLEMENt, UnIVERSITY OF MASSACHUSETTS Maria Kokoszyńska-Lutmanowa (1905–1981) was one of the EDITORIAL BOARD most outstanding female representatives of the Lvov-Warsaw ANNALISA COLIVA, UnIVERSITY OF MODENA AND UC IRVINE School. After achieving her PhD in philosophy under Kazimierz GaRY EBBS, INDIANA UnIVERSITY BLOOMINGTON Twardowski’s supervision, she was Kazimierz Ajdukiewicz’s as- GrEG FROSt-ARNOLD, HOBART AND WILLIAM SMITH COLLEGES sistant. She was also influenced by Alfred Tarski whose results HENRY JACKMAN, YORK UnIVERSITY in semantics she analyzed and popularized. After World War SANDRA LaPOINte, MCMASTER UnIVERSITY II, she got the chair of logic in University of Wrocław and she CONSUELO PRETI, THE COLLEGE OF NEW JERSEY organized studies in logic in this academic center. MARCUS ROSSBERG, UnIVERSITY OF CONNECTICUT ANTHONY SKELTON, WESTERN UnIVERSITY In the 1930s, Kokoszyńska kept in contact with members of the MARK TEXTOR, KING’S COLLEGE LonDON Vienna Circle and became a kind of connecting factor between AUDREY YAP, UnIVERSITY OF VICTORIA Polish logicians and the Viennese group. In Poland, she pre- RICHARD ZACH, UnIVERSITY OF CALGARY sented the views of members of the Vienna Circle. In Vienna, REVIEW EDITORS she emphasized the results of her Polish colleagues. JULIET FLOYD, BOSTON UnIVERSITY CHRIS PINCOCK, OHIO STATE UnIVERSITY In the present paper, some of Kokoszyńska’s results connected with the matters discussed in the Vienna Circle are presented, ASSISTANT REVIEW EDITOR namely with the problem of metaphysics, the status of logic and SEAN MORRIS, METROPOLITAN STATE UnIVERSITY OF DenVER the idea of unity of science. -
Organisaties En Genootschappen
Organisaties en genootschappen. P. van Ulsen 7 november 2017 Inhoudsopgave 1 Wijsgeren sluiten de rijen —het interbellum 2 1.1 Beths denkbeelden over het belang van organisaties . 2 1.2 Nederlandse genootschappen . 11 1.2.1 Significa: in vogelvlucht . 12 1.2.2 Significa: denkbeelden. 19 1.2.3 Significa: Beths kritieken . 30 1.2.4 Significa: congressen en Synthese . 34 1.2.5 Internationale School voor Wijsbegeerte. 40 1.2.6 Genootschap voor Critische (Wetenschappelijke) Philosophie. 42 1.2.7 Algemene Nederlandse Vereniging van Wijsbegeerte . 45 1.2.8 Wiskundig Genootschap . 47 1.2.9 Akademie van Wetenschappen. 48 1.3 Internationale filosofische verenigingen . 50 1.3.1 Wiener Kreis: WK, Verein Ernst Mach, Berliner Gruppe . 50 1.3.2 Wiener Kreis: Nederland en de WK . 55 1.3.3 Wiener Kreis: Unity of Science Movement . 63 1.3.4 Institut International de (Collaboration) Philosophique. 67 1.3.5 Fed´ eration´ Internationale des Societ´ es´ de Philosophie. 69 2 Wetenschapsfilosofische organisaties —na WWII 70 2.1 Genootschappen ontstaan . 70 2.1.1 Societ´ e´ Internationale de Logique et de Philosophie des Sciences 70 2.1.2 Nederlandse Vereniging voor Logica. 72 2.1.3 UNESCO-organisaties: ICSU, CIPHS . 73 2.1.4 Kleinere organisaties: AIPS, IIST PSA, Phil.Sc.Group. 73 2.1.5 International Union of Philosophy of Science. 74 2.2 UIPS versus UIHS . 77 2.2.1 International Union of History of Sciences. 77 2.2.2 Association for Symbolic Logic. 81 2.3 Eenheid in Veelheid . 82 2.3.1 International Union of History and Philosophy of Sciences . -
Wittgenstein and His Literary Executors Volume 4, Number 3 Christian Erbacher Editor in Chief Kevin C
Journal FOR THE History OF Analytical Philosophy Wittgenstein AND His LiterARY ExECUTORS VOLUME 4, Number 3 Christian Erbacher Editor IN Chief KeVIN C. Klement, University OF Massachusetts Rush Rhees, Georg Henrik von Wright and Elizabeth Anscombe are well known as the literary executors who made Ludwig Editorial BoarD Wittgenstein’s later philosophy available to all interested read- Gary Ebbs, INDIANA University Bloomington ers. Their editions of Wittgenstein’s writings have become an GrEG Frost-Arnold, Hobart AND William Smith Colleges integral part of the modern philosophical canon. However, sur- Henry Jackman, YORK University prisingly little is known about the circumstances and reasons SandrA Lapointe, McMaster University that made Wittgenstein choose them to edit and publish his Lydia Patton, VirGINIA TECH papers. This essay sheds light on these questions by present- MarCUS Rossberg, University OF Connecticut ing the story of their personal relationships—relationships that, Mark TExtor, King’S College London on the one hand, gave Rhees, von Wright and Anscombe dis- AudrEY Yap, University OF Victoria tinct insights into Wittgenstein’s philosophizing; and, on the RicharD Zach, University OF Calgary other hand, let Wittgenstein assume that these three former stu- dents, and later colleagues and friends, were the most capable ReVIEW Editors of preparing his work for publication. Using hitherto unpub- Juliet Floyd, Boston University lished archival material as well as information from published Chris Pincock, Ohio State University recollections, the essay sketches the development of the per- sonal and philosophical bonds from which the literary heirs’ Assistant ReVIEW Editor distinct ways of handling Wittgenstein’s unpublished writings Sean Morris, MetrOPOLITAN State University OF Denver grew in later years. -
From Kant to Davidson Philosophy and the Idea of the Transcendental
From Kant to Davidson Philosophy and the idea of the transcendental Edited by Jeff Malpas First published 2003 by Routledge 11 New Fetter Lane, London EC4P 4EE Simultaneously published in the USA and Canada by Routledge 29 West 35th Street, New York, NY 10001 Routledge is an imprint of the Taylor & Francis Group This edition published in the Taylor & Francis e-Library, 2003. © 2003 Selection and editorial material, Jeff Malpas; individual chapters, the contributors All rights reserved. No part of this book may be reprinted or reproduced or utilised in any form or by any electronic, mechanical, or other means, now known or hereafter invented, including photocopying and recording, or in any information storage or retrieval system, without permission in writing from the publishers. British Library Cataloguing in Publication Data A catalogue record for this book is available from the British Library Library of Congress Cataloging in Publication Data From Kant to Davidson : philosophy and the idea of the transcendental / edited by Jeff Malpas. Includes bibliographical references and index. 1. Transcendentalism. 2. Philosophy–History. 3. Kant, Immanual, 1724–1804. I. Malpas J. E. B823 .F76 2002 141'.3dc21 2002068157 ISBN 0-203-21957-0 Master e-book ISBN ISBN 0-203-27465-2 (Adobe eReader Format) ISBN 0–415–27904–6 (Print Edition) Contents Notes on contributors vii Acknowledgements ix Introduction: The idea of the transcendental 1 JEFF MALPAS 1 Kant’s critical debut: The idea of the transcendental in Kant’s early thought 7 CAMILLA SERCK-HANSSEN -
Ludwig Wittgenstein and Hermann Broch: the Need for Fiction and Logic in Moral Philosophy Christopher Bailes Washington University in St
Washington University in St. Louis Washington University Open Scholarship All Theses and Dissertations (ETDs) 5-24-2012 Ludwig Wittgenstein and Hermann Broch: The Need for Fiction and Logic in Moral Philosophy Christopher Bailes Washington University in St. Louis Follow this and additional works at: https://openscholarship.wustl.edu/etd Recommended Citation Bailes, Christopher, "Ludwig Wittgenstein and Hermann Broch: The eN ed for Fiction and Logic in Moral Philosophy" (2012). All Theses and Dissertations (ETDs). 681. https://openscholarship.wustl.edu/etd/681 This Dissertation is brought to you for free and open access by Washington University Open Scholarship. It has been accepted for inclusion in All Theses and Dissertations (ETDs) by an authorized administrator of Washington University Open Scholarship. For more information, please contact [email protected]. WASHINGTON UNIVERSITY IN ST. LOUIS Department of Germanic Languages and Literatures Dissertation Examination Committee: Paul Michael Lützeler, Chair Julia Driver Matt Erlin Erin McGlothlin Gillian Russell Lynne Tatlock Ludwig Wittgenstein and Hermann Broch: The Need for Fiction and Logic in Moral Philosophy By Christopher Wade Bailes A dissertation presented to the Graduate School of Arts and Sciences of Washington University in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy May 2012 Saint Louis, Missouri Acknowledgements I would like to thank the Department of Germanic Languages and Literatures and Washington University in Saint Louis for their generous financial support. My dissertation benefited from various guest lecturers, conferences, and graduate seminars supported by the university, and would not have been financially feasible without the tuition waivers and more than adequate living stipends that kept me afloat. -
The Search Jor Logically Alien Thought: Descartes, Kant, Frege, and the Tractatus1
PHILOSOPHICAL TOPICS VOL. 20 NO. 1, FALL 1991 The Search Jor Logically Alien Thought: Descartes, Kant, Frege, and the Tractatus1 James Conant University ofPittsburgh [I]n order to draw a limit to thought we should have to be able to think both sides ofthis limit (we should there fore have to be able to think what cannot be thought). The limit can, therefore, only be drawn in language and what lies on the other side ofthe limit will be sim ply nonsense. -Ludwig Wittgenstein2 The only proper way to break an egg is from the inside. -Parva Gallina Rubra3 This essay is about three things: Wittgenstein's ideas conceming the question of the possibility of illogical thought, the sources of those ideas (especially in Kant and Frege), and Putnam's recent interest in both of these matters. Along the way, this paper briefly sketches the broad outlines of two almost parallel traditions ofthought about the laws oflogic: one rather long and complicated tradition called the History of Modem Philosophy, and one rather short and complicated one called Hilary Putnam. Here is a thumb nail version ofhow these two traditions align: Descartes thought the laws of logic were only contingently necessary; not so recent Putnam agreed. 8t. Thomas Aquinas believed that they were necessarily necessary; relatively recent Putnam agreed (this is only confusing ifyou think Aquinas should not 115 be a step ahead of Descartes). Kant thought they were simply necessary. Frege wanted to agree-but his manner of doing so raised the worry that there was no way in which to express his agreement that made sense.