Policy Distortion and Democratic Debilitation: Comparative Illumination of the Countermajoritarian Difficulty

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Policy Distortion and Democratic Debilitation: Comparative Illumination of the Countermajoritarian Difficulty Michigan Law Review Volume 94 Issue 2 1995 Policy Distortion and Democratic Debilitation: Comparative Illumination of the Countermajoritarian Difficulty Mark Tushnet Georgetown University Law Center Follow this and additional works at: https://repository.law.umich.edu/mlr Part of the Constitutional Law Commons, and the Supreme Court of the United States Commons Recommended Citation Mark Tushnet, Policy Distortion and Democratic Debilitation: Comparative Illumination of the Countermajoritarian Difficulty, 94 MICH. L. REV. 245 (1995). Available at: https://repository.law.umich.edu/mlr/vol94/iss2/2 This Article is brought to you for free and open access by the Michigan Law Review at University of Michigan Law School Scholarship Repository. It has been accepted for inclusion in Michigan Law Review by an authorized editor of University of Michigan Law School Scholarship Repository. For more information, please contact [email protected]. POLICY DISTORTION AND DEMOCRATIC DEBILITATION: COMPARATIVE ILLUMINATION OF THE COUNTERMAJORITARIAN DIFFICULTY Mark Tushnet* James Bradley Thayer set the terms of the past century's discus­ sion of judicial review in The Origin and Scope of the American Doctrine of Constitutional Law. 1 Thayer was concerned with what Alexander Bickel labeled the "countermajoritarian difficulty" with judicial review,2 that judicial review displaces decisions made by near-contemporaneous political majorities and therefore is open to the charge that it is undemocratic. Thayer attempted to minimize the displacement- of political majorities through his "clear error" rule, according to which courts should not overturn legislation un­ less "those who have the right to make laws have not merely made a mistake, but have made a very clear one, - so clear that it is not open to rational question."3 The generations that succeeded Thayer found that solution unpalatable.4 * Professor of Law, Georgetown University Law Center. B.A. 1967, Harvard; J.D. 1971, M.A. 1971, Yale. - Ed. I would like to thank Paul Gewirtz, Alan Hutchinson, Vicki Jack­ son, Elana Kagan, Dan Kahan, Donald Kommers, Wtlliam Landes, Roderick Macdonald, Michael Perry, David Schneiderman, Stephen Schulhofer, Carlos Vasquez, and Paul Weiler for their comments on a draft of this article, and Ian Ayres, Alan Schwartz, and Dan Shaviro for suggestions about particular lines of argument that I develop. Nona Liegeois and Melissa Newman provided valuable research assistance. I received helpful comments from partici­ pants in workshops at Yale Law School, Northwestern University Law School, the University of Chicago Center for Comparative Legal History and Law School, and New York University Law School. An early version of Parts II-A and Il-B was presented as part of the Eighth Seegers Lecture, Valparaiso University School of Law, in 1991, and I thank Dean Edward McGlynn Gaffney for inviting me to deliver the lecture. 1. James Bradley Thayer, The Origin and Scope of the American Doctrine of Constitu­ tional Law, 7 HAR.v. L. REv. 129 (1893). See generally Symposium, One Hundred Years of Judicial Review: The Thayer Centennial Symposium, 88 Nw. U. L. REv. 1 (1993). 2. ALEXANDER M. BICKEL, THE LEAST DANGEROUS BRANCH: THE SUPREME COURT AT THE BAR OF Pouncs 16-17 (1962). 3. Thayer, supra note 1, at 144. 4. Among contemporary constitutional theorists, almost no one accepts Thayer's minimalism across-the-board. Henry Monaghan may be the sole exception. See Henry P. Monaghan, Our Perfect Constitution, 56 N.Y.U. L. REv. 353 (1981). A broad generalization, inaccurate only at the margins, is that nearly every constitutional theorist urges minimal judi­ cial review and vigorous democratic dialogue on issues on which the theorist believes her preferred position is likely to prevail in the democratic dialogue and more-than-minimal re­ view on issues on which the theorist believes her preferred position is unlikely to prevail 245 246 Michigan Law Review [Vol. 94:245 Instead of reducing judicial review to Thayer's minimal level,s scholars have attempted to work around the countermajoritarian difficulty by identifying a domain in which more-than-minimal judi­ cial review is compatible with democratic theory. Some originalists conclude from their examination of the relevant materials that more-than-minimal judicial review is sometimes justified because judicial enforcement of the Constitution's original meaning carries out the only agreement binding the people's representatives.6 Process-oriented theorists argue that such review is justified when the majoritarian deficit associated with judicial review is smaller than the majoritarian deficit associated with other decisional processes.7 The variations on these themes have preoccupied con­ stitutional theorists in the United States for generations.8 Even Bickel's emphasis on justiciability doctrines as a way of reducing the occasions for judicial review was designed to ensure the effec­ tiveness of the Court's actions when it did exercise more-than­ minimal review. Perhaps democratic theory does allow for some displacement of near-contemporary majority views. Both Thayer and Bickel, how- there. For dramatic illustrations from two of the best, see CASS R. SuNSTEIN, THE PARTIAL CONSTITUTION (1993), especially at 315-17 (arguing that courts should require governments to fund abortions, at least in cases of rape and incest) and 228-30 (arguing that courts should not restrict government regulation of campaign finance), and Michael W. McConnell, The Selective Funding Problem: Abortions and Religious Schools, 104 HARv. L. REV. 989 (1991) (arguing that courts should require governments to assist parents with tuition charged by religious schools and that courts should not require governments to assist in paying for abortions). 5. I take the term "minimalist" from Michael J. Perry, The Constitution, the Courts, and the Question of Minimalism, 88 Nw. U. L. REV. 84 (1993). 6. That is, the justification for making originalist materials authoritative is that doing so carries out the agreement. For another band of originalists, originalism is justified, not be­ cause it is compatible with democracy, but because it is the only account of constitutionalism that is compatible with the proposition that the Constitution is law. For myself, I find this definitional "justification" of originalism normatively unsatisfying; justifying originalism as compatible with democracy, in contrast, has what I regard as the appropriate form. 7. This formulation is designed to take into account Charles Black's important but widely overlooked point that we ought to distinguish between judicial decisions overturning statutes, for example, a statute specifically authorizing searches of automobile junkyards on less-than­ probable cause, and judicial decisions overturning specific decisions made by officeholders, for example, a search of an automobile junkyard on less-than-probable cause by an individ­ ual police officer acting solely under her general authority to investigate the possibility that some crime has been committed. See CHA.ru.Es L. BLACK, JR., STRUCTURE AND RELATION· SHIP IN CONSTITUTIONAL LAW 77-93 (1969). A court's relative majoritarian deficit is surely larger in the first than in the second situation, and - perhaps - an individual police officer may have less majoritarian legitimacy than a court. 8. I do not exempt myself from this observation, although I believe that my critical ap­ proach did not force me to engage in a normative defense of any particular version of the allocational strategy I describe. See MARK TusHNET, RED, WHITE, AND BLUE: A CruncAL ANALYSIS OF CONSTITUTIONAL LAW (1988). But see PmuP BOBBITT, CONSTITUTIONAL IN· TERPRETATION 126-40 (1991) (characterizing my approach as prudentialist). November 1995] Comparative Countermajoritarian Difficulty 247 ever, were concerned with other costs associated with more-than­ minimal judicial review. Judicial review, according to Thayer, "has had a tendency to drive out questions of justice and right, and to fill the mind[s] of legislators with thoughts of mere legality . And moreover, even in the matter of legality, they have felt little respon­ sibility; if we are wrong, they say, the courts will correct it."9 Not only would judicial review displace majoritarian decisionmaking; it might also distort and debilitate it. First, judicial review might dis­ tort decisionmaking by injecting too many constitutional norms into the lawmaking process, supplanting legislative consideration of other arguably more important matters. Second, judicial review might debilitate decisionmaking by leading legislatures to enact laws without regard to constitutional considerations, counting on the courts to strike from the statute books those laws that violate the Constitution, leading to the problem of debilitation. Looked at from one point of view, these problems are in some tension. The problem of policy distortion arises when legislators take what the courts say about the Constitution's meaning too seri­ ously, and the problem of democratic debilitation arises when legis­ lators and their constituents do not take the Constitution's meaning - or more precisely, their own views about that meaning - seri­ ously enough. The problems would be troublesome if one occurred with respect to some issues and the other with respect to other is­ sues or at other times. A legislator may fail to give enough weight to constitutional concerns about welfare reform but may give too much weight to the Supreme Court's constitutional
Recommended publications
  • Book Note Justice Thomas’S Inconsistent Originalism
    BOOK NOTE JUSTICE THOMAS’S INCONSISTENT ORIGINALISM MY GRANDFATHER’S SON: A MEMOIR. By Clarence Thomas.1 New York: HarperCollins Publishers. 2007. Pp. xii, 289. $26.95. Since his infamous confirmation hearings, several of Justice Tho- mas’s biographers2 have struggled to understand and explain the ap- parent conflicts in the life and jurisprudence of a man who acknowl- edges that his conservative views do not comport with the traditional viewpoints of African Americans3 and who advocates an originalist in- terpretation of the Constitution.4 Justice Thomas has received harsh criticism from some of these biographers, and the debate surrounding his adequacy as a Supreme Court Justice has strong political under- pinnings.5 Seeking to correct other accounts of his life, which Justice Thomas views as partly “untrue, at times grossly so” (p. x), My Grand- father’s Son sheds new light on his personal history — especially the key roles race and religion played therein — but generally eschews di- rect discussion of his jurisprudential philosophy. Even so, Justice Thomas’s memoir illuminates his judicial philosophy, because that phi- losophy stems from the experiences and principles discussed in his book. My Grandfather’s Son begins with a description of Justice Tho- mas’s West African ancestry (p. 2) and early childhood. Born in a shanty in Pinpoint, Georgia, on June 23, 1948 (pp. 3–4), Thomas spent his early years fatherless, alongside his mother, Leola; aunt, Annie; and siblings, Emma Mae and Myers (pp. 1, 3). In 1954, Myers accidentally burned down their home (p. 6), and Leola took her sons to live in a de- ––––––––––––––––––––––––––––––––––––––––––––––––––––––––––––– 1 Associate Justice, Supreme Court of the United States.
    [Show full text]
  • Critical Constitutionalism Now
    Fordham Law Review Volume 75 Issue 2 Article 6 2006 Critical Constitutionalism Now Louis Michael Seidman Follow this and additional works at: https://ir.lawnet.fordham.edu/flr Part of the Law Commons Recommended Citation Louis Michael Seidman, Critical Constitutionalism Now, 75 Fordham L. Rev. 575 (2006). Available at: https://ir.lawnet.fordham.edu/flr/vol75/iss2/6 This Article is brought to you for free and open access by FLASH: The Fordham Law Archive of Scholarship and History. It has been accepted for inclusion in Fordham Law Review by an authorized editor of FLASH: The Fordham Law Archive of Scholarship and History. For more information, please contact [email protected]. Critical Constitutionalism Now Cover Page Footnote Carmack Waterhouse Professor of Constitutional Law, Georgetown University Law Center. Thanks to Alex Aleinikoff, Carrie Menkel-Meadow, Girardeau Spann, Mark Tushnet, and participants at the Fordham Law School symposium A New Constitutional Order? for comments on an earlier draft of this paper. This article is available in Fordham Law Review: https://ir.lawnet.fordham.edu/flr/vol75/iss2/6 CRITICAL CONSTITUTIONALISM NOW Louis Michael Seidman* In the fall of 1999, Mark Tushnet published a celebrated foreword to the Supreme Court edition of the Harvard Law Review arguing that the Rehnquist Court's decisions could be understood as part of an era marked by divided government and sharply reduced ambitions for the transformative potential of constitutional law. 1 Almost exactly two years later, on September 11, 2001, airplanes crashed into the World Trade Center. For the next three or four years, Tushnet's characterization of our times seemed exactly backward: We appeared to be in the middle of an era of united government and of quite dramatic constitutional transformation.
    [Show full text]
  • Defending Korematsu?: Reflections on Civil Liberties in Wartime
    View metadata, citation and similar papers at core.ac.uk brought to you by CORE provided by Georgetown Law Scholarly Commons Georgetown University Law Center Scholarship @ GEORGETOWN LAW 2003 Defending Korematsu?: Reflections on Civil Liberties in Wartime Mark V. Tushnet Georgetown University Law Center, [email protected] Copyright 2003 by The Board of Regents of the University of Wisconsin System; Reprinted by permission of the Wisconsin Law Review. Permitted use is limited to the work described above and does not include the right to grant to others permission to photocopy or otherwise reproduce this material except for copies permitted under the Copyright Act. This paper can be downloaded free of charge from: https://scholarship.law.georgetown.edu/facpub/246 2003 Wis. L. Rev. 273-307 (2003) This open-access article is brought to you by the Georgetown Law Library. Posted with permission of the author. Follow this and additional works at: https://scholarship.law.georgetown.edu/facpub Part of the Civil Rights and Discrimination Commons, and the Jurisprudence Commons GEORGETOWN LAW Faculty Publications February 2010 Defending Korematsu?: Reflections on Civil Liberties in Wartime* 2003 Wis. L. Rev. 273-307 (2003) Mark V. Tushnet Professor of Law Georgetown University Law Center [email protected] This paper can be downloaded without charge from: Scholarly Commons: http://scholarship.law.georgetown.edu/facpub/246/ SSRN: http://ssrn.com/abstract=368323 Posted with permission of the author * Copyright 2003 by The Board of Regents
    [Show full text]
  • Mark Tushnet: a Personal Reminiscence
    Georgetown University Law Center Scholarship @ GEORGETOWN LAW 2001 Mark Tushnet: A Personal Reminiscence Louis Michael Seidman Georgetown University Law Center, [email protected] This paper can be downloaded free of charge from: https://scholarship.law.georgetown.edu/facpub/905 90 Geo. L.J. 127-130 (2001) This open-access article is brought to you by the Georgetown Law Library. Posted with permission of the author. Follow this and additional works at: https://scholarship.law.georgetown.edu/facpub Part of the Legal Studies Commons SYMPOSIUM Justice, Democracy, and Humanity: A Celebration of the Work of Mark Tushnet Mark Tushnet: A Personal Reminiscence Louis MICHAEL SEIDMAN* The papers in this Symposium pay tribute to Mark Tushnet's astonishing energy, influence, originality, and sheer brilliance as a scholar. As important and interesting as they are, they do not come close to capturing the breadth of his work. How could they? My most recent check of the online version of the Index of Legal Periodicals reveals 242 articles and book reviews published by Tushnet since roughly 1980.1 Georgetown's Edward Bennett Williams Li- brary online catalogue lists an additional forty books and book chapters written by Tushnet. In this short Essay, I will not try to summarize this incredible output or detail the ways in which it has influenced the development of legal thought. I wish the others who attempt that task the best of luck. Instead, I feel much more confident in my ability to say something about a topic that is in some ways more important-the kind of person Mark Tushnet is.
    [Show full text]
  • Constitutional Law
    Constitutional Law EDITORIAL ADVISORS Rachel E. Barkow Segal Family Professor of Regulatory Law and Policy Faculty Director, Center on the Administration of Criminal Law New York University School of Law Erwin Chemerinsky Dean and Professor of Law University of California, Berkeley School of Law Richard A. Epstein Laurence A. Tisch Professor of Law New York University School of Law Peter and Kirsten Bedford Senior Fellow The Hoover Institution Senior Lecturer in Law The University of Chicago Ronald J. Gilson Charles J. Meyers Professor of Law and Business Stanford University Marc and Eva Stern Professor of Law and Business Columbia Law School James E. Krier Earl Warren DeLano Professor of Law The University of Michigan Law School Tracey L. Meares Walton Hale Hamilton Professor of Law Director, The Justice Collaboratory Yale Law School Richard K. Neumann, Jr. Professor of Law Maurice A. Deane School of Law at Hofstra University Robert H. Sitkoff John L. Gray Professor of Law Harvard Law School David Alan Sklansky Stanley Morrison Professor of Law Faculty Co-Director, Stanford Criminal Justice Center Stanford Law School Constitutional Law Eighth Edition Geoffrey R. Stone Edward H. Levi Distinguished Service Professor of Law University of Chicago Law School Louis Michael Seidman Carmack Waterhouse Professor of Constitutional Law Georgetown University Law Center Cass R. Sunstein Felix Frankfurter Professor of Law Harvard Law School Mark V. Tushnet William Nelson Cromwell Professor of Law Harvard Law School Pamela S. Karlan Kenneth & Harle Montgomery Professor of Public Interest Law Stanford Law School Copyright © 2018 Geoffrey R. Stone; Jessica C. Seidman and Andrew R. Seidman; Cass R.
    [Show full text]
  • Clarence X?: the Black Nationalist Behind Justice Thomas's Constitutionalism, 4 N.Y.U
    Notre Dame Law School NDLScholarship Journal Articles Publications 2009 Clarence X?: The lB ack Nationalist Behind Justice Thomas's Constitutionalism Stephen F. Smith Notre Dame Law School, [email protected] Follow this and additional works at: https://scholarship.law.nd.edu/law_faculty_scholarship Part of the Civil Rights and Discrimination Commons, and the Judges Commons Recommended Citation Stephen F. Smith, Clarence X?: The Black Nationalist Behind Justice Thomas's Constitutionalism, 4 N.Y.U. J.L. & Liberty 583 (2009). Available at: https://scholarship.law.nd.edu/law_faculty_scholarship/550 This Article is brought to you for free and open access by the Publications at NDLScholarship. It has been accepted for inclusion in Journal Articles by an authorized administrator of NDLScholarship. For more information, please contact [email protected]. JOURNAL OF LAW & LIBERTY ~NEW YORK UNIVERSITY CLARENCE X?: THE BLACK NATIONALIST BEHIND JUSTICE THOMAS'S CONSTITUTIONALISM Stephen F. Smith* In trod uction ......................................................................................... 584 I. Black Nationalism and Malcolm X ............................................ 586 II. Clarence Thom as as Clarence X ................................................. 590 A. Clarence X Confronts White Supremacy and Defends Black Institutions ................................................... 591 1. W hite suprem acy ........................................................... 591 2. Higher-education desegregation and historically black schools .............................................. 596 B. Clarence X Defends Civil Rights against Traditional Rem edies ............................................................ 601 Professor of Law, University of Notre Dame. This Essay is based on remarks pre- sented at the symposium held at New York University School of Law on the "Un- known Justice Thomas." I am grateful to the New York University Journal of Law & Liberty for sponsoring this symposium and for allowing me the honor of participat- ing in it.
    [Show full text]
  • Assessing Chief Justice William Rehnquist
    KEYNOTE ADDRESSES ASSESSING CHIEF JUSTICE WILLIAM REHNQUIST † ERWIN CHEMERINSKY How should a Chief Justice be assessed? This conference provides the occasion for considering this question as part of looking at the role of Chief Justice on the Supreme Court and in the American legal system. Rather than examining the office generally, I want to focus on assessing William Rehnquist as Chief Justice. One way of assessing any Chief Justice is in terms of her ability to achieve a substantive vision of the law. In this sense, few would disagree that John Marshall and Earl Warren were enormously successful in having their substantive visions reflected in the decisions of their Courts. Marshall’s visions of judicial review and federalism, among other crucial issues, were embodied in decisions like Marbury v. Madison1 and McCulloch v. Maryland,2 which provided a framework for government that lasts to this day. Earl War- ren’s visions of a more equal society better protecting the dignity of individuals were reflected in the desegregation cases,3 the rulings in- corporating the Bill of Rights,4 and the decisions requiring reappor- tionment of state legislatures.5 Writings on the Warren Court, both by † Alston & Bird Professor of Law and Political Science, Duke University. 1 5 U.S. (1 Cranch) 137, 180 (1803) (providing that the Supreme Court can re- view and invalidate laws that are unconstitutional). 2 17 U.S. (4 Wheat.) 316, 436-37 (1819) (establishing that states cannot tax an “in- strument employed by the government of the Union to carry its powers into execu- tion”).
    [Show full text]
  • Alarmism Versus Moderation in Responding to the Rehnquist Courtl
    Alarmism Versus Moderation in Responding to the Rehnquist Courtl MARK TUSHNET* INTRODUCTION ......................................................................................................... 47 I. THE SUPREME COURT, MODESTLY INTERPRETED ............................................ 48 A. Federalism................................................................................................ 49 1. Limits on Enumerated Powers ........................................................... 49 2. State Sovereignty Limitations .......................................................... 50 3. The Court's Failures to Act: Preemption and the Spending Power ....... 51 4. Conclusion ......................................................................................... 52 B. Individual Rights ...................................................................................... 53 1. Property Rights .................................................................................. 53 2. Free Expression ................................................................................. 54 3. Conclusion ......................................................................................... 55 C. Conclusion ............................................................................................... 55 II. THE IMPLICATIONS OF DIVIDED GOVERNMENT .............................................. 56 A. Divided Government ............................................................................... 57 B. Ideologically PolarizedGovernment .....................................................
    [Show full text]
  • Can Free Speech Be Progressive?
    CAN FREE SPEECH BE PROGRESSIVE? Louis Michael Seidman* Free speech cannot be progressive. At least it cannot be progressive if we are talking about free speech in the American context, with all the historical, sociological, and philosophical baggage that comes with the modern American free speech right. That is not to say that the right to free speech does not deserve protection. It might serve as an important side constraint on the pursuit of progressive goals and might even pro- tect progressives against the possibility of catastrophic outcomes. But the notion that our free speech tradition might be weaponized to advance progressive ends is fanciful. The American free speech tradition is too deeply rooted in ideas about fixed property rights and in an equation of freedom with government inaction to be progressive. Instead of wasting energy on futile efforts to upend our First Amendment traditions, progressives should work to achieve their goals directly. INTRODUCTION ........................................................................................2219 I. SOME DEFINITIONS, LIMITATIONS, AND GENERAL THROAT CLEARING ...........................................................................................2220 II. THE HISTORICAL RECORD .................................................................2226 III. FOUR REASONS WHY FREE SPEECH CANNOT BE PROGRESSIVE ...........2232 A. Free Speech and Property Entitlements ...................................2232 B. Free Speech and the Feasance–Nonfeasance Distinction ........2239 C. Free
    [Show full text]
  • Constitutional Hardball
    Georgetown University Law Center Scholarship @ GEORGETOWN LAW 2004 Constitutional Hardball Mark V. Tushnet Georgetown University Law Center, [email protected] This paper can be downloaded free of charge from: https://scholarship.law.georgetown.edu/facpub/555 http://ssrn.com/abstract=451960 37 J. Marshall L. Rev. 523-553 (2004) This open-access article is brought to you by the Georgetown Law Library. Posted with permission of the author. Follow this and additional works at: https://scholarship.law.georgetown.edu/facpub Part of the Constitutional Law Commons, and the Law and Politics Commons CONSTITUTIONAL HARDBALL MARK TuSHNET* I. INTRODUCTION: THE CONCEPT OF CONSTITUTIONAL HARDBALL, WITH SOME EXAMPLES For the past several years I have been noticing a phenomenon that seems to me new in my lifetime as a scholar of constitutional law. I call the phenomenon constitutional hardball. This Essay develops the idea that there is such a practice, that there is a sense in which it is new, and that its emergence (or re-emergence) is interesting because it signals that political actors understand that they are in a position to put in place a new set of deep institutional arrangements of a sort I call a constitutional order.l A shorthand sketch of constitutional hardball is this: it consists of political claims and practices-legislative and executive initiatives-that are without much question within the bounds of existing constitutional doctrine and practice but that are nonetheless in some tension with existing pre-constitutional understandings.2
    [Show full text]
  • The Secret History of American Constitutional Skepticism: a Recovery and Preliminary Evaluation
    ARTICLES THE SECRET HISTORY OF AMERICAN CONSTITUTIONAL SKEPTICISM: A RECOVERY AND PRELIMINARY EVALUATION Louis Michael Seidman* INTRODUCTION Over two centuries after its ratification, most Americans are still infatuated with their Constitution.1 At the beginning, few would have predicted this outcome. The Constitution was born out of bitter con- flict.2 For many Anti-federalists—perhaps a majority of the country3— * Carmack Waterhouse Professor of Constitutional Law, Georgetown University Law Cen- ter. I owe a special debt of gratitude to Michael Klarman, who gave me many, many single spaced pages of comments on an earlier draft of this article. I also received very helpful comments from Adam Cox, Michael Diamond, Peter Edelman, Daniel Ernst, Deborah Hellman, Aziz Huq, Vicki Jackson, Jerry Kang, Martin Lederman, Daryl Levinson, Debo- rah Malamud, Allegra McLeod, Thomas Nachbar, Gary Peller, Adam Samaha, Girardeau Spann, Mark Tushnet, Laura Weinrib, and participants at the Georgetown Faculty Work- shop, the Duke Roundtable on the Role of Custom, Convention, and Tradition in U.S. Constitutional Law, and the University of Virginia Legal Theory Workshop. I am grateful to Noah Baron, Hannah Kohler, Melissa Stewart, Morgan Stoddard, Katie Wrede, and the staff of the Georgetown Law Center Library for superb research assistance. 1 See, e.g., GfK Roper Pub. Affairs & Corporate Commc’ns, The AP-National Constitution Center Poll, August, 2012, at 5 (2012), available at http://constitutioncenter.org/media/ files/data_GfK_AP-NCC_Poll_August_GfK_2012_Topline_FINAL_1st_release.pdf (find- ing that almost seven in ten Americans agree that “[t]he United States Constitution is an enduring document that remains relevant today”). 2 See generally PAULINE MAIER, RATIFICATION: THE PEOPLE DEBATE THE CONSTITUTION, 1787-1788 (2010); WOODY HOLTON, UNRULY AMERICANS AND THE ORIGINS OF THE CONSTITUTION (2007); Bruce Ackerman & Neal Katyal, Our Unconventional Founding, 62 U.
    [Show full text]
  • David Fontana
    DAVID FONTANA George Washington University Law School 2000 H Street, N.W. Washington, D.C. 20052 +1 (202) 994-0577 [email protected] ACADEMIC EXPERIENCE George Washington University Law School Associate Professor of Law (with tenure) Courses: Constitutional Law, Comparative Constitutional Law, Criminal Procedure, Criminal Law, Comparative Law, Undergraduate Constitutional Law Other Teaching Short Courses for Yale Law School (with Steven Teles), the University of Georgia Law School and Loyola-LA Law School PROFESSIONAL ACTIVITIES Constitutional Assistance Project, Libyan and Tunisian Constitutional Congresses Provided expertise to drafters and nonprofit leaders revising constitutions in Libya and Tunisia House and Senate Judiciary Committees Regularly brief Senate and House members and staffers and testify on constitutional issues North Country Institute Co-created organization dedicated to fostering discussion about political realities of North Country region in far upstate New York. Financial support provided based on reactions to my popular press writing and book on the unique political dynamics of the region. Founder and Organizer, Annual Comparative Constitutional Law Roundtable Created annual academic gathering to discuss comparative constitutional law, featuring participation by U.S. Supreme Court Justices and foreign constitutional court judges. Reviewer/Referee Serve as peer reviewer in the areas of law and political science for Harvard Law Review, Yale Law Journal, University of Chicago Law Review, American Political Science Review, American Journal of Political Science, and Comparative Political Studies, as well as for Harvard University Press, Yale University Press, Oxford University Press and Cambridge University Press Term Member, Council on Foreign Relations United States Court of Appeals for the Ninth Circuit Law Clerk to the Honorable Dorothy W.
    [Show full text]