Uva-DARE (Digital Academic Repository)

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Uva-DARE (Digital Academic Repository) UvA-DARE (Digital Academic Repository) Contextual metaphilosophy: the case of Wittgenstein Gakis, D. Publication date 2012 Link to publication Citation for published version (APA): Gakis, D. (2012). Contextual metaphilosophy: the case of Wittgenstein. Institute for Logic, Language and Computation. General rights It is not permitted to download or to forward/distribute the text or part of it without the consent of the author(s) and/or copyright holder(s), other than for strictly personal, individual use, unless the work is under an open content license (like Creative Commons). Disclaimer/Complaints regulations If you believe that digital publication of certain material infringes any of your rights or (privacy) interests, please let the Library know, stating your reasons. In case of a legitimate complaint, the Library will make the material inaccessible and/or remove it from the website. Please Ask the Library: https://uba.uva.nl/en/contact, or a letter to: Library of the University of Amsterdam, Secretariat, Singel 425, 1012 WP Amsterdam, The Netherlands. You will be contacted as soon as possible. UvA-DARE is a service provided by the library of the University of Amsterdam (https://dare.uva.nl) Download date:29 Sep 2021 Bibliography Abreu E Silva Neto, N. (2011) The Uses of “Forms of Life” and the Meanings of Life, in Padilla Galvez, J. and Gaffal, M. (eds.) Forms of Life and Language Games, Frankfurt: Ontos Verlag, p. 75-106 Adorno, T. W. (1981) Spengler after the Decline, in Prisms, Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, p. 51-72 Adorno, T. W. (1973) Negative Dialectics, New York: Continuum Agamben, G. (2000) Means without End: Notes on Politics, Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press Althusser, L. (1969) For Marx, London: Penguin Press Anderson P. (1998) The Origins of Postmodernity, London: Verso Apel, K. O. (1987) The Problem of Philosophical Foundations in Light of a Transcendental Pragmatics of Language, in Baynes, K., Bohman, J., and McCarthy, T. (eds.) After Philosophy: End or Transformation?, Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, p. 250-290 Apel, K. O. (1979) Wittgenstein and the Problem of Hermeneutic Understanding, in Towards a Transformation of Philosophy, London: Routledge, p. 1-45 Aristotle (1998) Nicomachean Ethics (Ross, W. D. trans.), New York: Oxford University Press Audi, R. (ed.) (1999) The Cambridge Dictionary of Philosophy (2nd ed.), Cambridge: Cambridge University Press Augustine of Hippo (1912) Confessions, Vol. 1: Books 1-8 (Loeb Classical Library, No. 26), Harvard: Harvard University Press Ayer, A. J. (1984) Freedom and Morality and Other Essays, New York: Oxford University Press Ayer, A. J. (1971) Language, Truth and Logic, Harmondsworth: Penguin Baker, G. P. and Hacker, P. M. S. (2009) Wittgenstein: Rules, Grammar, and Necessity: Essays and Exegesis of 185-242 (Volume 2 of an Analytical Commentary on the Philosophical Investigations) (2nd rev. ed.), Oxford: Blackwell Baker, G. P. and Hacker, P. M. S. (2005a) Wittgenstein: Understanding and Meaning, Volume 1 of an Analytical Commentary on the Philosophical Investigations, Part II: Exegesis §§1-184 (2nd rev. ed.), Oxford: Blackwell 295 296 Bibliography Baker, G. P. and Hacker, P. M. S. (2005b) Wittgenstein: Understanding and Meaning, Volume 1 of an Analytical Commentary on the Philosophical Investigations, Part I: Essays (2nd rev. ed.), Oxford: Blackwell Baltas, A., Gavroglu, K., and Kindi, V. (1997) A Discussion with Thomas S. Kuhn: A Physicist who Became a Historian for Philosophical Purposes, in Neusis, Vol. 6, p. 145-200 Bartley III, W. (1985) Wittgenstein (2nd ed. enlarged), La Salle, Ill.: Open Court Bax, C. (2011) Subjectivity after Wittgenstein: The Post-Cartesian Subject and the “Death of Man”, London: Continuum Beardsley, M. (1975) Aesthetics from Classical Greece to the Present: A Short History, Tuscaloosa, Al.: University of Alabama Press Benado, M. E. O., Bobenrieth, A., and Verdugo, C. (1998) Metaphilosophical Pluralism and Paraconsistency: From Orientative to Multi-level Pluralism, paper presented at the 20th World Congress of Philosophy, Boston, Massachusetts, http://www.bu.edu/wcp/Papers/Logi/LogiBobe.htm (last access: November 2009) Ben-Zvi, L. (1980) Samuel Beckett, Fritz Mauthner, and the Limits of Language, in PMLA, Vol. 95, No. 2, p. 183-200 Berman, M. (1983) All That Is Solid Melts Into Air: The Experience of Modernity, London: Verso Bernstein, R. (2008) Richard Rorty’s Deep Humanism, in New Literary History, Vol. 39, No. 1, p. 13-27 Bierce, A. (1996) The Devil’s Dictionary, Ware: Wordsworth Bird, A. (2009) Thomas Kuhn, in Zalta, E. (ed.) The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy, http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/fall2009/entries/thomas- kuhn/ (last access: May 2011) Bird, A. (2002) Kuhn’s Wrong Turning, in Studies in History and Philosophy of Science, Vol. 33, No. 3, p. 443-463 Black, M. (1978) Lebensform and Sprachspiel in Wittgenstein’s Later Work, in Leinfellner, E., Bergel, H., and Hübner, A. (eds.) Wittgenstein and his Impact on Contemporary Thought (Proceedings of the 2nd International Wittgenstein Symposium, Kirchberg am Wechsel, Austria, 1977), Vienna: Hölder-Pichler-Tempsky, p. 325- 331 Black, M. (1964) A Companion to Wittgenstein’s Tractatus, Ithaca, N.Y.: Cornell University Press Blattner, W. (2000) The Primacy of Practice and Assertoric Truth: Dewey and Heidegger, in Wrathall, M. and Malpas, J. (eds.) Heidegger, Authenticity, and Modernity: Essays in Honor of Hubert L. Dreyfus Vol. 1, Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, p. 231-250 Bloor, D. (2000) Wittgenstein as a Conservative Thinker, in Kusch, M. (ed.) The Sociology of Philosophical Knowledge, Dordrecht: Kluwer Academic Publishers, p. 1-14 Bibliography 297 Bloor, D. (1983) Wittgenstein: A Social Theory of Knowledge, New York: Columbia University Press Borges, J. L. (2000) Kafka and his Precursors, in Selected Non-Fictions, New York: Penguin, p. 363-365 Borges, J. L. (1998) Artifices (Foreword), in Collected Fictions, New York: Penguin, p. 129-130 Bourdieu, P., Chamboredon, J. C., and Passeron, J. C. (eds.) (1991) The Craft of Sociology: Epistemological Preliminaries (2nd ed.), New York: de Gruyter Bouveresse, J. (2011) Wittgenstein, von Wright and the Myth of Progress, in Paragraph, Vol. 34, No. 3, p. 301-321 Bouveresse, J. (1995) Wittgenstein Reads Freud: The Myth of the Unconscious, Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press Bouveresse, J. (1991) ‘The Darkness of this Time’: Wittgenstein and the Modern World, in Phillips Griffiths, A. (ed.) Wittgenstein: Centenary Essays, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, p. 11-39 Bouwsma, O. K. (1986) Wittgenstein: Conversations 1949-1951, Indianapolis: Hackett Bramann, J. (1985) Wittgenstein’s Tractatus and the Modern Arts, Rochester, NY: Adler Pub. Co. Brenkman, J. (2004) Freud the Modernist, in Micale, M. (ed.) The Mind of Modernism: Medicine, Psychology, and the Cultural Arts in Europe and America, 1880-1940, Stanford: Stanford University Press, p. 172-196 Bynum, T. W. and Reese, W. L. (1970) Editors’ Introduction, in Metaphilosophy, Vol. 1, No. 1, p. 1 Camus, A. (2005) The Myth of Sisyphus, London: Penguin Camus, A. (2000) The Rebel, London: Penguin Carnap, R. (1963) Library of Living Philosophers: The Philosophy of Rudolf Carnap, La Salle, Ill.: Open Court Carnap, R. (1959) The Elimination of Metaphysics Through Logical Analysis of Language, in Ayer, A. J. (ed.) Logical Positivism, Glencoe, Ill.: The Free Press, p. 60-81 Cartwright, N., Cat, J., Fleck, L., and Uebel, T. (1996) Otto Neurath: Philosophy Between Science and Politics, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press Castoriadis, C. (2002) On Plato’s Statesman, Stanford: Stanford University Press Castoriadis, C. (1997a) ‘The Only Way to Find Out If You Can Swim is to Get into the Water’: An Introductory Interview, in Curtis, D. A. (ed.) The Castoriadis Reader, Oxford: Blackwell, p. 1-34 Castoriadis, C. (1997b) On the Content of Socialism, in Curtis, D. A. (ed.) The Castoriadis Reader, Oxford: Blackwell, p. 40-105 Castoriadis, C. (1987) The Imaginary Institution of Society, Cambridge: Polity Press Castoriadis, C. (1984) The Crossroads in the Labyrinth, Cambridge, MA: MIT Press 298 Bibliography Cavafy, C. P. (1904) Waiting for the Barbarians, in Savidis, G. (ed.) (1992) Collected Poems (Revised Edition), Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, p. 18-19 Cavell, S. (2002) The Availability of Wittgenstein’s Later Philosophy, in Must We Mean What We Say?, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, p. 44-72 Cavell, S. (1996a) Epilogue: The Investigation’s Everyday Aesthetics of Itself, in Mulhall, S. (ed.) The Cavell Reader, Oxford: Blackwell, p. 369-389 Cavell, S. (1996b) Declining Decline, in Mulhall, S. (ed.) The Cavell Reader, Oxford: Blackwell, p. 321-352 Cedarbaum, D. G. (1983) Paradigms, in Studies in Philosophy and History of Science Part A, Vol. 14, No. 3, p. 173-213 Chandler, D. (2000) Technological or Media Determinism, http://www.aber.ac.uk/ media/Documents/tecdet/tecdet.html (last access: January 2012) Chisholm, R. (1941) Sextus Empiricus and Modern Empiricism, in Philosophy of Science, Vol. 8, No. 3, p. 371-384 Cioffi, F. (1998) Wittgenstein on Freud and Frazer, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press Cohn, N. (1970) The Pursuit of the Millennium: Revolutionary Millenarians and Mystical Anarchists of the Middle Ages (Revised and Enlarged Edition), New York: Oxford University Press Collins, R. (2000) Reply to Reviewers and Symposium Commentators, in Philosophy of the Social Sciences, Vol. 30, No. 2, p. 299-325. Collins, R. (1998) Sociology of Philosophies: A Global Theory of Intellectual Change, Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press Conant, J. (2007) Mild Mono-Wittgensteinianism, in Crary, A. (ed.) Wittgenstein and the Moral Life: Essays in Honor of Cora Diamond, Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, p. 31-142 Conant, J. (2006) Wittgenstein’s Later Criticism of the Tractatus, in Pichler, A. and Säätelä, S. (eds.) Wittgenstein: The Philosopher and his Works, Vienna: Ontos Verlag, p. 172-204 Conant, J. (2005) What Ethics in the Tractatus is Not, in Philips, D. Z. and von der Ruhr, M. (eds.) Religion and Wittgenstein’s Legacy, Aldershot: Ashgate, p. 39- 95 Conant, J. (2004) Why Worry about the Tractatus?, in Stocker, B. (ed.) Post- Analytic Tractatus, Aldershot: Ashgate, p.
Recommended publications
  • Elisabeth Leinfellner.Indd
    Drei Pioniere der philosophisch-linguistischen Analyse von Zeit und Tempus: Mauthner, Jespersen, Reichenbach Elisabeth Leinfellner, Wien [A philosophical school in Tlön] reasons that the present is indefi nite, that the future has no reality other than as a present hope, that the past has no reality other than as a present memory. Jorge Luis Borges, Tlön, Uqbar, Orbis Tertius 1. Einleitung: die semantische Rolle der Tempora Unsere alltägliche, ,psychologische‘, aber auch die abstrakte newtonsche oder mathematische Vorstellung von Zeit – die ,klassischen‘ Zeitvorstellungen – laufen darauf hinaus, dass es eine einfache lineare Abfolge von Vergangen- heit-Gegenwart-Zukunft gibt. Analysiert man jedoch natürliche Sprachen, dann bietet sich ein anderes, komplexeres Bild: Würde man der einfachen, klassischen Vorstellung folgen, dann käme man in der Sprache mit drei Tempora aus: Präsens, Präteritum, Futurum. Ein Blick in die Grammatiken verschiedener Sprachen zeigt aber, dass es auch andere Tempora neben die- sen dreien gibt, so im heutigen Deutsch das Plusquamperfekt und das Fu- turum exactum. Gewisse Tempora und auch temporale Ersatzformen lösen mehr oder minder glücklich das Problem, dass z.B. in einer Erzählung im Präteritum manchmal auch im zeitlichen Rückgriff eine Vergangenheit vor der Vergangenheit dargestellt werden muss, oder eine Zukunft in der Ver- gangenheit. Die Ursachen für eine nicht chronologische Darstellung sind vielfältig, z.B. stilistisch-textliche oder dass wir uns an Ereignisse nicht im- mer in der richtigen Reihenfolge erinnern. Weiters muss die Verwendung der Tempora in erzählenden Texten die Rekonstruktion des chronologischen Ablaufs von Ereignissen erlauben, z.B. aus praktischen Gründen. Dass Texte keineswegs immer chronologisch geordnet sind, hat in verschiedenen Disziplinen und oft im Gefolge des russischen Formalismus zu einer Unterscheidung zwischen zwei zeitlichen Achsen geführt, der chronologischen Achse der Abfolge der Ereignisse, und F.
    [Show full text]
  • A History of Women Philosophers Vol. IV
    A HISTORY OF WOMEN PHILOSOPHERS A History of Women Philosophers 1. Ancient Women Philosophers, 600 B.C.-500 A.D. 2. Medieval, Renaissance and Enlightenment Women Philosophers, 500-1600 3. Modern Women Philosophers, 1600-1900 4. Contemporary Women Philosophers, 1900-today PROFESSOR C. J. DE VOGEL A History of Women Philosophers Volume 4 Contemporary Women Philosophers 1900-today Edited by MARY ELLEN WAITHE Cleveland State University, Cleveland, U.S.A. Springer-Science+Business Media, B. V. Library of Congress Cataloging in Publication Data Contemporary women philosophers : 1900-today / edited by Mary Ellen Waithe. p. cm. -- (A History of women philosophers ; v. 4.) Includes bibliographical references (p. xxx-xxx) and index. ISBN 978-0-7923-2808-7 ISBN 978-94-011-1114-0 (eBook) DOI 10.1007/978-94-011-1114-0 1. Women philosophers. 2. Philosophy. Modern--20th century. r. Waithe. Mary Ellen. II. Series. Bl05.W6C66 1994 190' .82--dc20 94-9712 ISBN 978-0-7923-2808-7 printed an acid-free paper AII Rights Reserved © 1995 Springer Science+Business Media Dordrecht Originally published by Kluwer Academic Publishers in 1995 Softcover reprint ofthe hardcover lst edition 1995 No part of the material protected by this copyright notice may be reproduced or utilized in any form or by any means, electronic or mechanical, including photocopying, recording or by any information storage and retrieval system, without written permission from the copyright owner. Contents Acknowledgements xv Introduction to Volume 4, by Mary Ellen Waithe xix 1. Victoria, Lady Welby (1837-1912), by William Andrew 1 Myers I. Introduction 1 II. Biography 1 III.
    [Show full text]
  • WISDOM (Tlwma) and Pffllosophy (FALSAFA)
    WISDOM (tLWMA) AND PfflLOSOPHY (FALSAFA) IN ISLAMIC THOUGHT (as a framework for inquiry) By: Mehmet ONAL This thcsis is submitted ror the Doctor of Philosophy at the University of Wales - Lampeter 1998 b"9tr In this study the following two hypothesisare researched: 1. "WisdotW' is the fundamental aspect of Islamic thought on which Islamic civilisation was established through Islamic law (,Sharfa), theology (Ldi-M), philosophy (falsafq) and mysticism (Surism). 2. "Due to the first hypothesis Islamic philosophy is not only a commentary on the Greek philosophy or a new form of Ncoplatonism but a native Islamic wisdom understandingon the form of theoretical study". The present thesis consists of ten chaptersdealing with the concept of practical wisdom (Pikmq) and theoretical wisdom (philosophy or falsafa). At the end there arc a gcncral conclusion,glossary and bibliography. In the introduction (Chapter One) the definition of wisdom and philosophy is establishedas a conceptualground for the above two hypothesis. In the following chapter (Chapter Two) I focused on the historical background of these two concepts by giving a brief history of ancient wisdom and Greek philosophy as sourcesof Islamic thought. In the following two chapters (Chapter Three and Four) I tried to bring out a possibledefinition of Islamic wisdom in the Qur'5n and Sunna on which Islamic jurisprudence (fiqh), theology (A-alim), philosophy (falsafq) and mysticism (Sufism) consistedof. As a result of the above conceptual approaching,I tried to reach a new definition for wisdom (PiLma) as a method that helps in the establishmentof a new Islamic way of life and civilisation for our life.
    [Show full text]
  • Linguistic Scepticism in Mauthner's Philosophy
    LiberaPisano Misunderstanding Metaphors: Linguistic ScepticisminMauthner’s Philosophy Nous sommes tous dans un désert. Personne ne comprend personne. Gustave Flaubert¹ This essayisanoverview of Fritz Mauthner’slinguistic scepticism, which, in my view, represents apowerful hermeneutic category of philosophical doubts about the com- municative,epistemological, and ontological value of language. In order to shed light on the main features of Mauthner’sthought, Idrawattention to his long-stand- ing dialogue with both the sceptical tradition and philosophyoflanguage. This con- tribution has nine short sections: the first has an introductory function and illus- tratesseveral aspectsoflinguistic scepticism in the history of philosophy; the second offers acontextualisation of Mauthner’sphilosophyoflanguage; the remain- der present abroad examination of the main features of Mauthner’sthought as fol- lows: the impossibility of knowledge that stems from aradicalisationofempiricism; the coincidencebetween wordand thought,thinkingand speaking;the notion of use, the relevanceoflinguistic habits,and the utopia of communication; the decep- tive metaphors at the root of an epoché of meaning;the new task of philosophyasan exercise of liberation against the limits of language; the controversial relationship between Judaism and scepticism; and the mystical silence as an extreme conse- quence of his thought.² Mauthnerturns scepticism into aform of life and philosophy into acritique of language, and he inauguratesanew approach that is traceable in manyGerman—Jewish
    [Show full text]
  • Language As Metaphor P
    E-Revista de Estudos Interculturais do CEI – ISCAP N.º 3, maio de 2015 MAUTHNER VERSUS WITTGENSTEIN: LANGUAGE AS METAPHOR Paulo Barroso Escola Superior de Educação de Viseu Centro de Estudos de Comunicação e Linguagens da Faculdade de Ciências Sociais e Humanas – Universidade Nova de Lisboa [email protected] Abstract Mauthner esteemed language as a philosophical inquiry. He measured the philosophical entailments between language and reality and the consequent knowledge produced by such entailments. He questioned language’s aptitude to express and represent reality and, according to him, language is a critical source of knowledge and an unfaithful representation of reality, because there is a gap between language and reality, i.e. language distorts perception and engenders false and fictitious assumptions about reality. Language fosters superstition, creates gods and idols and exerts a dominating power over the intellect. Mauthner pointed out a critique of language based on metaphors, which would serve to address and clarify the deformation of reality. Wittgenstein, unlike himself suggested, was inspired by Mauthner. Both showed interest toward the critical analysis of language and there are many conceptual similarities between their language’s conceptions (e.g. concerning the use of metaphors to understand language). Therefore, this paper seeks a) to emphasize Mauthner’s metaphors on language as an accurate interpretation regarding the philosophical entailments between language and reality, and b) to demonstrate the epistemological legacy of Mauthner’s critique of language to Wittgenstein’s philosophy of language. Keywords: language; Mauthner; metaphor; philosophy of language; Wittgenstein. Resumo Mauthner encarava a linguagem como uma investigação filosófica. Assim, mediu os vínculos filosóficos entre linguagem e realidade e o consequente 1 conhecimento produzido por tais vínculos e questionou a aptidão da linguagem para expressar e representar a realidade.
    [Show full text]
  • Philosophy and the Mirror of Nature
    Philosophy and the Mirror of Nature RICHARD RORTY Princeton University Press Princeton, New Jersey Copyright © 1979 by Princeton University Press Published by Princeton University Press, Princeton, New Jersey All Rights Reserved Library of Congress Cataloging-in-Publication Data Rorty, Richard. Philosophy and the mirror of nature. Includes index. 1. Philosophy. 2. Philosophy, Modern. 3. Mind and body. 4. Representation (Philosophy) 5. Analysis (Philosophy) 6. Civilization-Philosophy. I. Title. B53·R68 190 79- 84013 ISBN 0-691-07236-1 ISBN 0-691-02016-7 pbk. Publication of this book has been aided by a grant from The National Endowment for the Humanities This book has been composed in Linotype Baskerville Princeton University Press books are printed on acid-free paper and meet the guidelines for permanence and durability of the Committee on Production Guidelines for Book Longevity of the Council on Library Resources Printed in the United States of America Second printing, with corrections, 1980 First Princeton Paperback printing, 1980 20 19 18 17 16 15 14 13 12 I I 10 TO M. V. R. When we think about the future of the world, we always have in mind its being at the place where it would be if it continued to move as we see it moving now. We do not realize that it moves not in a straight line, but in a curve, and that its direction constantly changes. Philosophy has made no progress? If somebody scratches where it itches, does that count as progress? If not, does that mean it wasn't an authentic scratch? Not an authentic itch? Couldn't this response to the stimulus go on for quite a long time until a remedy for itching is found? Wenn wir an die Zukunft der Welt denken, so meinen wir immer den Ort, wo sie sein wird, wenn sie so weiter Hiuft, wie wir sie jetzt laufen sehen, und denken nieht, da�s sie nieht gerade lauft, sondern in einer Kurve, und ihre Riehtung sieh konstant andert.
    [Show full text]
  • Wittgenstein's Vienna Our Aim Is, by Academic Standards, a Radical One : to Use Each of Our Four Topics As a Mirror in Which to Reflect and to Study All the Others
    TOUCHSTONE Gustav Klimt, from Ver Sacrum Wittgenstein' s VIENNA Allan Janik and Stephen Toulmin TOUCHSTONE A Touchstone Book Published by Simon and Schuster Copyright ® 1973 by Allan Janik and Stephen Toulmin All rights reserved including the right of reproduction in whole or in part in any form A Touchstone Book Published by Simon and Schuster A Division of Gulf & Western Corporation Simon & Schuster Building Rockefeller Center 1230 Avenue of the Americas New York, N.Y. 10020 TOUCHSTONE and colophon are trademarks of Simon & Schuster ISBN o-671-2136()-1 ISBN o-671-21725-9Pbk. Library of Congress Catalog Card Number 72-83932 Designed by Eve Metz Manufactured in the United States of America 8 9 10 11 12 13 14 15 16 The publishers wish to thank the following for permission to repro­ duce photographs: Bettmann Archives, Art Forum, du magazine, and the National Library of Austria. For permission to reproduce a portion of Arnold SchOnberg's Verklarte Nacht, our thanks to As­ sociated Music Publishers, Inc., New York, N.Y., copyright by Bel­ mont Music, Los Angeles, California. Contents PREFACE 9 1. Introduction: PROBLEMS AND METHODS 13 2. Habsburg Vienna: CITY OF PARADOXES 33 The Ambiguity of Viennese Life The Habsburg Hausmacht: Francis I The Cilli Affair Francis Joseph The Character of the Viennese Bourgeoisie The Home and Family Life-The Role of the Press­ The Position of Women-The Failure of Liberalism The Conditions of Working-Class Life : The Housing Problem Viktor Adler and Austrian Social Democracy Karl Lueger and the Christian Social Party Georg von Schonerer and the German Nationalist Party Theodor Herzl and Zionism The Redl Affair Arthur Schnitzler's Literary Diagnosis of the Viennese Malaise Suicide inVienna 3.
    [Show full text]
  • “Eff It”: Beckett And... Linguistic Skepticism
    210 SOFIA PHILOSOPHICAL REVIEW “Eff it”: Beckett and... linguistic skepticism Dirk Van Hulle (University of Antwerp, Belgium) Ever since the scholastics (and actually even since Plato and Aristotle), philophy – according to Schopenhauer – has been a sustained abuse of general concepts and abstractions, by means of which one separated what was inseperable and united what was incompatible. Building on Schopenhauer, Friedrich Nietzsche similarly concluded that every concept is created by treating different phenomena as if they were the same. And Fritz Mauthner developed this linguistic skepticism into a full-blown critique of language, which Beckett carefully read. The article attempts to inventory the studies that have already been devoted to Beckett’s attitude towards Mauthner, and to gauge the importance of the Austro-German tradition of linguistic skepticism (not just Mauthner but also Hofmannsthal, Schopenhauer, Nietzsche and Wittgenstein) for Beckett’s poetics. Samuel Beckett’s complex attitude toward language is often linked to his reading of Fritz Mauthner’s Beiträge zu einer Kritik der Sprache [Contributions to a Critique of Language] and its possible impact on his writings. David Hesla’s note at the end of The Shape of Chaos – “One of the howlers in this study may well be the omission of Fritz Mauthner”1 – indi- cates an awareness in the early 1970s of the potential importance of Mauthner’s Beiträge for Beckett’s work. In the meantime, several attempts have been made to assess and reassess Beckett’s relation to Mauthner’s work on the basis of his typed notes preserved at Trinity College Dublin (TCD MS 10971/5), the excerpts in his so-called “Whoroscope” Notebook at the University of Reading (UoR MS 3000), and James Joyce’s notes on Mauthner (in Finnegans Wake notebooks VI.B.41 and VI.B.46), made in 1 David H.
    [Show full text]
  • Wittgenstein, Anxiety, and Performance Behavior
    Incapacity Incapacity Wittgenstein, Anxiety, and Performance Behavior Spencer Golub northwestern university press evanston, illinois Northwestern University Press www.nupress.northwestern.edu Copyright © 2014 by Spencer Golub. Published 2014 by Northwestern University Press. All rights reserved. Printed in the United States of America 10 9 8 7 6 5 4 3 2 1 Library of Congress Cataloging-in-Publication Data Golub, Spencer, author. Incapacity : Wittgenstein, anxiety, and performance behavior / Spencer Golub. pages cm Includes bibliographical references and index. ISBN 978-0-8101-2992-4 (cloth : alk. paper) 1. Wittgenstein, Ludwig, 1889–1951. 2. Language and languages—Philosophy. 3. Performance—Philosophy. 4. Literature, Modern—20th century—History and criticism. 5. Literature—Philosophy. I. Title. B3376.W564G655 2014 121.68—dc23 2014011601 Except where otherwise noted, this book is licensed under a Creative Commons Attribution-NonCommercial-NoDerivatives 4.0 International License. To view a copy of this license, visit http://creativecommons.org/licenses/by-nc-nd/4.0/. In all cases attribution should include the following information: Golub, Spencer. Incapacity: Wittgenstein, Anxiety, and Performance Behavior. Evanston: Northwestern University Press, 2014. For permissions beyond the scope of this license, visit http://www.nupress .northwestern.edu/. An electronic version of this book is freely available, thanks to the support of libraries working with Knowledge Unlatched. KU is a collaborative initiative designed to make high-quality books open access for the public good. More information about the initiative and links to the open-access version can be found at www.knowledgeunlatched.org. For my mother We go towards the thing we mean. —Wittgenstein, Philosophical Investigations, §455 .
    [Show full text]
  • Samuel Beckett, Wilhelm Windelband And... Nominalist Philosophy
    SAMUEL BECKETT, WILHELM WINDELBAND AND... 89 Samuel Beckett, Wilhelm Windelband and... nominalist philosophy Matthew Feldman (University of Northampton, UK1) Wilhelm Windelband has been only recently recognised for his critical importance to Beckett’s artistic development and philosophical knowledge. However, unlike most of the philosophers contained in this collection, the neo-Kantian’s A History of Philosophy was specifically consulted by Beckett as a secondary source, one recounting the system of Western philosophy as an “integrated whole”. What is more, the revised 1901 A History of Philosophy may be one of the handful of texts most important to Beckett, rivalling even Dante’s Inferno and The Bible in terms of lifelong influence. To establish this empirical argument, the focus taken here will be directed upon the roughly 400 sides, recto and verso, of Beckett’s 267-folio “Philosophy Notes” that are taken from Windelband’s introductory text. While Beckett’s reading in Western philosophy before the second century A.D. is comprised from multiple sources evident in the “Philosophy Notes”, the final 1600 years of Western philosophy to Friedrich Nietzsche are mediated 1 I am grateful to the Bergen Research Foundation and the University of Bergen, Norway, for a Senior Research Fellowship with the 'Modernism and Christianity' project facilitating the completion of this text. I also gratefully acknowledge permission to quote from Samuel Beckett’s “Interwar Notes” from Mr Edward Beckett, the Estate of Samuel Beckett, and the Beckett International Foundation at the University of Reading, UK. Portions of this text were first presented at the June 2011 “Samuel Beckett: Out of the Archive” conference at the University of York; I am grateful to the conference organisers, Peter Fifield, Bryan Radley and Lawrence Rainey, for inviting me to organise the “Beckett and Philosophy” panel there, and for the helpful feedback received from delegates on my discussion of Windelband and nominalism.
    [Show full text]
  • Averroes' Search
    Silvia G. Dapía The Myth of the Framework in Borges’s “Averroes’ Search” ontext,” “framework,” “conceptual scheme,” “scheme of description,” “paradigm.” These terms emerge through- “C out much of twentieth-century philosophy of language and science. Sometimes they appear in connection to reference, as in Quine’s discussion of the translation of the alien word “gavagai,” which, relative to one context, refers, say, to undetached rabbit-parts, while relative to a different context, it refers, say, to temporal slices of rabbithood (35). Sometimes they appear in connection to theory change and incommensurability, as in Thomas Kuhn’s claim that comprehen- sive scientific theories—what he calls paradigms—share no concepts or meanings and are thus incommensurable; for example, the terms “mass” and “gravitation” in Newton’s classical physics cannot be equated with the same terms in Einstein’s relativistic paradigm (114; 117). Importantly, on these accounts there is no room for an all- encompassing super-context in which all disparate theories, para- digms, or conceptual schemes can be adequately translated. Rather there is a plurality of conceptual schemes, frameworks, paradigms. And this plurality constitutes a “context” in which Borges’s “Averroes’ Search” acquires special interest. Inspired by Floyd Merrell’s connec- tion of Borges’s story to Kuhn’s and the other radical philosophers’ version of incommensurability (220-23), I shall unravel here some of the threads of Borges’s story that are interwoven both with the more general notion of context as well as the more specific notions of concep- tual scheme, framework, or paradigm. 1. Missed Clues Averroes is working on his commentary on Aristotle, “the monumental work which would justify him in the eyes of men” (Labyrinths 149) 1.
    [Show full text]
  • Hamann, Nietzsche, and Wittgenstein on the Language of Philosophers” by Jonathan Gray
    This is a postprint version of “Hamann, Nietzsche, and Wittgenstein on the Language of Philosophers” by Jonathan Gray. For the final version please see Hamann and the Tradition, edited by Lisa Marie Anderson (Illinois: Northwestern University Press, 2012), pp. 104-121. Hamann, Nietzsche, and Wittgenstein on the Language of Philosophers Jonathan Gray Royal Holloway, University of London In this chapter I shall examine some of Johann Georg Hamann’s claims about how philosophers misuse, misunderstand, and are misled by language. I will then examine how he anticipates things that Friedrich Nietzsche and Ludwig Wittgenstein say on this topic. All three thinkers are suspicious of philosophers who consider artificial systems of “pure reason” or “formal logic” more valuable than natural language in the search for philosophical insight. They all challenge the notion that natural language “gets in the way” of reason, and should be radically formalized into (or even retired in favor of) a more logically or conceptually perfect language. Hamann is responding to the enthusiasm for reine Vernunft exhibited by his friend Immanuel Kant and the loose-knit group that would later come to be known as the Aufklärer. Nietzsche is profoundly critical of the idealism of many of his philosophical predecessors, including Kant, Hegel, and Schopenhauer. Wittgenstein turns away from Frege’s and Russell’s logical philosophies, and rejects the British idealism (deeply influenced by Kant and Hegel) that had been dominant in earlier decades. Hamann, Nietzsche, and Wittgenstein all contend that reason and logic come from and are dependent upon natural language, which changes over time, and which responds to the interests and circumstances of its users.
    [Show full text]