Samuel Beckett, Wilhelm Windelband And... Nominalist Philosophy

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Samuel Beckett, Wilhelm Windelband And... Nominalist Philosophy SAMUEL BECKETT, WILHELM WINDELBAND AND... 89 Samuel Beckett, Wilhelm Windelband and... nominalist philosophy Matthew Feldman (University of Northampton, UK1) Wilhelm Windelband has been only recently recognised for his critical importance to Beckett’s artistic development and philosophical knowledge. However, unlike most of the philosophers contained in this collection, the neo-Kantian’s A History of Philosophy was specifically consulted by Beckett as a secondary source, one recounting the system of Western philosophy as an “integrated whole”. What is more, the revised 1901 A History of Philosophy may be one of the handful of texts most important to Beckett, rivalling even Dante’s Inferno and The Bible in terms of lifelong influence. To establish this empirical argument, the focus taken here will be directed upon the roughly 400 sides, recto and verso, of Beckett’s 267-folio “Philosophy Notes” that are taken from Windelband’s introductory text. While Beckett’s reading in Western philosophy before the second century A.D. is comprised from multiple sources evident in the “Philosophy Notes”, the final 1600 years of Western philosophy to Friedrich Nietzsche are mediated 1 I am grateful to the Bergen Research Foundation and the University of Bergen, Norway, for a Senior Research Fellowship with the 'Modernism and Christianity' project facilitating the completion of this text. I also gratefully acknowledge permission to quote from Samuel Beckett’s “Interwar Notes” from Mr Edward Beckett, the Estate of Samuel Beckett, and the Beckett International Foundation at the University of Reading, UK. Portions of this text were first presented at the June 2011 “Samuel Beckett: Out of the Archive” conference at the University of York; I am grateful to the conference organisers, Peter Fifield, Bryan Radley and Lawrence Rainey, for inviting me to organise the “Beckett and Philosophy” panel there, and for the helpful feedback received from delegates on my discussion of Windelband and nominalism. Finally, I would also like to extend my thanks to Erik Tonning, James Knowlson, John Pilling, and David Addyman for discussing, reading and commenting upon the ideas presented here; however, any mistakes are my own. 90 SOFIA PHILOSOPHICAL REVIEW entirely through A History of Philosophy. This large, concluding portion of the “Philosophy Notes” is here considered via the employment of Windelband’s reading of nominalism, in addition to his more general account of Western philosophy; one impacting upon Beckett as early as 1932, but lasting to the 1969 Nobel Prize and beyond. §1 I know of no work that presents so clearly in their succession the main problems of past thought, or brings out so connectedly and concentratedly the preparation that was made by the ancient phi- losophy for the introduction of Christianity, or that exhibits more justly the relations between it an the Christian thought of the first Christian centuries. It is gratifying to follow a writer so thor- oughly imbued with the principles of his own science, and so controlled by them, and who recognizes […] the progress of phi- losophy, and who does not claim for the latter more than its just due in the shaping of ecclesiastical dogmas. The book deserves the attention of all who would learn how thought has come to be what it is, and who would themselves “learn to think”. – 1893 review of A History of Philosophy2 Professor Wilhelm Windelband’s 681-page overview of Western philoso- phy, breathlessly endorsed in the contemporaneous review excerpted above, was not only useful to readers “who would themselves ‘learn to think.”’ In the case of Samuel Beckett, famously and on the contrary, his interest was nearly the op- posite. Rather than knowledge, what he increasingly viewed as “the loutishness of learning” – already decried in his 1934 poem, “Gnome” – is more likely to have motivated Beckett’s extensive note-taking from A History of Philosophy in the early 1930s.3 In the same spirit, he informed Anne Atik some four decades 2 Egbert C. Smyth, “Brief Notice of Important Books,” in The Andover Review: A Religious and Theological Monthly 114, (Nov./Dec. 1893), 776. 3 Samuel Beckett, “Gnome,” in Selected Poems: 1930-1989, edited by David Wheatley (London, Faber: 2009), 9. SAMUEL BECKETT, WILHELM WINDELBAND AND... 91 later, “you have to get back to ignorance”; put another way, even at the outset of his literary career, Beckett sought to “unlearn to think.”4 Given the genocidal disasters brought about by twentieth-century thinking, to which he was an en- gaged and traumatized witness, Beckett’s reminders of human ignorance are re- freshingly heretical. However, it remains the case that both “learn[ing] to think” and “unlearning to think” necessitated a prior knowledge of Western thought. That is to say, for systematic thinking to be turned on its head in characteristi- cally Beckettian fashion, knowledge of systematic thought – in this case, of Western philosophy from the ancient Greeks to Friedrich Nietzsche – was an es- sential precursor. Whether for “learned ignorance” or in pursuit of “the progress of phi- losophy,” it is clear above all that Beckett’s engagement with, and employ- ment of, Wilhelm Windelband was both extensive and profound. This is so much so, I want to suggest here, that the latter ought to be included in that “canon” of philosophers exerting the greatest influence upon Beckett’s crucial development in the years before his postwar breakthrough. When Beckett first encountered Windelband in (likely) mid-to-late 1932, perhaps nowhere else were the “evolution of the ideas of European philosophy” in terms of “the history of problems and conceptions [.…] as a connected and interrelated whole” more succinctly and accessibly presented than in A History of Philosophy.5 Furthermore, many of those frequently recognized as “Becket- tian” philosophers – Arnold Geulincx, Bishop Berkeley, Gottfried Leibniz and several others – were first encountered in the revised, second edition of A History of Philosophy from 1901. Before going on to explore some of phi- losophical debts to this text, however, a moment’s pause over the context and corpus of Beckett’s note-taking during this period is in order. During his years of self-education across the 1930s, Beckett took notes on a striking range of subjects. As James Knowlson’s imperative biography makes plain, this was a period of dejection, directionless travel, and uncer- tainty. On one hand, the death of Beckett’s father in June 1933 led him to two years of thrice-weekly analysis with the trainee psychotherapist Wilfred 4 Cited in Anne Atik, How It Was: A Memoir of Samuel Beckett (London, Faber and Fa- ber: 2001), 121. 5 Wilhelm Windelband, A History of Philosophy, 2 vols., trans. James H. Tufts (New York, Harper Torchbooks: 1958), ix-x. 92 SOFIA PHILOSOPHICAL REVIEW Bion between Christmastime 1933 and Christmastime 1935; but there were also panic attacks, psychosomatic illnesses, and a growing desire to leave the constraints of Ireland for the continent – or indeed anywhere, as sug- gested by letters to the Soviet filmmaker, Sergei Eisenstein, or applications for a lectureship in South Africa at this time.6 Adding to Beckett’s frustra- tions, furthermore, was a lack of critical success for his fiction, ranging from the failure to publish his first novel, Dream of Fair to Middling Women to literally dozens of rejection letters from publishers prior to Routledge’s pub- lication of Murphy in 1938.7 Comparatively more successful at this time were Beckett’s poems (notably the 1935 collection Echo’s Bones) and free- lance criticism (collected in the 1984 Disjecta), but this provided neither enough income to live on, nor enough plaudits to convince him that he was, at that time, what he was to become after 1945: a groundbreaking artist; a literary genius; and for some, the very conscience of the last century – or, to use a phrase from the 1969 Nobel Presentation Speech, “a miserere from all mankind, its muffled minor key sounding liberation to the oppressed, and comfort to those in need.”8 Long before that infamous pessimism and stoicism earned Beckett the Nobel Prize for Literature, then, were the far less celebrated, but no less im- portant, “years of wandering” also announced in the quatrain “Gnome.” As a number of critics in Beckett Studies have established over the last genera- tion, this period of intellectual gestation was vital for the breakthrough achieved in the “frenzy of writing” between 1945 and 1950 – a period pro- ducing Waiting for Godot and “The Trilogy” of novels (Molloy, Malone Dies and The Unnamable), amongst others. Considering that his 1996 au- thorized biography, Damned to Fame, largely sparked this empirical turn toward Beckett’s formative years, it is hard to disagree with the conclusion 6 See The Letters of Samuel Beckett, vol. I: 1929-1940, edited by Martha Dow Fehsenfeld and Lois Overbeck, with George Craig and Dan Gunn (Cambridge, Cambridge Univer- sity Press: 2009), 317, 523-28. 7 For insightful accounts of both of these publishing fiascos, see Mark Nixon ed., Samuel Beckett and Publishing (London, The British Library: 2011), especially chap- ters 1 and 3. 8 “Nobelprize.org,” available at: http://nobelprize.org/nobel_prizes/literature/laureates/ 1969/press.html (last accessed 20/5/11). SAMUEL BECKETT, WILHELM WINDELBAND AND... 93 regarding Beckett’s postwar creative burst offered there: “the ground was well prepared.”9 Nowhere are his provisions for an unsettled present and unknown future – captured by Beckett’s reflexive
Recommended publications
  • Elisabeth Leinfellner.Indd
    Drei Pioniere der philosophisch-linguistischen Analyse von Zeit und Tempus: Mauthner, Jespersen, Reichenbach Elisabeth Leinfellner, Wien [A philosophical school in Tlön] reasons that the present is indefi nite, that the future has no reality other than as a present hope, that the past has no reality other than as a present memory. Jorge Luis Borges, Tlön, Uqbar, Orbis Tertius 1. Einleitung: die semantische Rolle der Tempora Unsere alltägliche, ,psychologische‘, aber auch die abstrakte newtonsche oder mathematische Vorstellung von Zeit – die ,klassischen‘ Zeitvorstellungen – laufen darauf hinaus, dass es eine einfache lineare Abfolge von Vergangen- heit-Gegenwart-Zukunft gibt. Analysiert man jedoch natürliche Sprachen, dann bietet sich ein anderes, komplexeres Bild: Würde man der einfachen, klassischen Vorstellung folgen, dann käme man in der Sprache mit drei Tempora aus: Präsens, Präteritum, Futurum. Ein Blick in die Grammatiken verschiedener Sprachen zeigt aber, dass es auch andere Tempora neben die- sen dreien gibt, so im heutigen Deutsch das Plusquamperfekt und das Fu- turum exactum. Gewisse Tempora und auch temporale Ersatzformen lösen mehr oder minder glücklich das Problem, dass z.B. in einer Erzählung im Präteritum manchmal auch im zeitlichen Rückgriff eine Vergangenheit vor der Vergangenheit dargestellt werden muss, oder eine Zukunft in der Ver- gangenheit. Die Ursachen für eine nicht chronologische Darstellung sind vielfältig, z.B. stilistisch-textliche oder dass wir uns an Ereignisse nicht im- mer in der richtigen Reihenfolge erinnern. Weiters muss die Verwendung der Tempora in erzählenden Texten die Rekonstruktion des chronologischen Ablaufs von Ereignissen erlauben, z.B. aus praktischen Gründen. Dass Texte keineswegs immer chronologisch geordnet sind, hat in verschiedenen Disziplinen und oft im Gefolge des russischen Formalismus zu einer Unterscheidung zwischen zwei zeitlichen Achsen geführt, der chronologischen Achse der Abfolge der Ereignisse, und F.
    [Show full text]
  • A History of Women Philosophers Vol. IV
    A HISTORY OF WOMEN PHILOSOPHERS A History of Women Philosophers 1. Ancient Women Philosophers, 600 B.C.-500 A.D. 2. Medieval, Renaissance and Enlightenment Women Philosophers, 500-1600 3. Modern Women Philosophers, 1600-1900 4. Contemporary Women Philosophers, 1900-today PROFESSOR C. J. DE VOGEL A History of Women Philosophers Volume 4 Contemporary Women Philosophers 1900-today Edited by MARY ELLEN WAITHE Cleveland State University, Cleveland, U.S.A. Springer-Science+Business Media, B. V. Library of Congress Cataloging in Publication Data Contemporary women philosophers : 1900-today / edited by Mary Ellen Waithe. p. cm. -- (A History of women philosophers ; v. 4.) Includes bibliographical references (p. xxx-xxx) and index. ISBN 978-0-7923-2808-7 ISBN 978-94-011-1114-0 (eBook) DOI 10.1007/978-94-011-1114-0 1. Women philosophers. 2. Philosophy. Modern--20th century. r. Waithe. Mary Ellen. II. Series. Bl05.W6C66 1994 190' .82--dc20 94-9712 ISBN 978-0-7923-2808-7 printed an acid-free paper AII Rights Reserved © 1995 Springer Science+Business Media Dordrecht Originally published by Kluwer Academic Publishers in 1995 Softcover reprint ofthe hardcover lst edition 1995 No part of the material protected by this copyright notice may be reproduced or utilized in any form or by any means, electronic or mechanical, including photocopying, recording or by any information storage and retrieval system, without written permission from the copyright owner. Contents Acknowledgements xv Introduction to Volume 4, by Mary Ellen Waithe xix 1. Victoria, Lady Welby (1837-1912), by William Andrew 1 Myers I. Introduction 1 II. Biography 1 III.
    [Show full text]
  • Lotze and the Early Cambridge Analytic Philosophy
    LOTZE AND THE EARLY CAMBRIDGE ANALYTIC PHILOSOPHY ―This summer I‘ve read about a half of Lotze‘s Metaphysik. He is the most delectable, certainly, of all German writers—a pure genius.‖ William James, September 8, 1879.1 Summary Many historians of analytic philosophy consider the early philosophy of Moore, Russell and Wittgenstein as much more neo-Hegelian as once believed. At the same time, the authors who closely investigate Green, Bradley and Bosanquet find out that these have little in common with Hegel. The thesis advanced in this chapter is that what the British (ill-named) neo-Hegelians brought to the early analytic philosophers were, above all, some ideas of Lotze, not of Hegel. This is true regarding: (i) Lotze’s logical approach to practically all philosoph- ical problems; (ii) his treating of the concepts relation, structure (constructions) and order; (iii) the discussion of the concepts of states of affairs, multiple theory of judgment, general logical form; (iv) some common themes like panpsychism and contemplating the world sub specie aeternitatis. 1. LOTZE, NOT HEGEL, LIES AT THE BOTTOM OF CAMBRIDGE ANALYTIC PHILOSOPHY Conventional wisdom has it that the early philosophy of Moore and Russell was under the strong sway of the British ―neo-Hegelians‖. In the same time, however, those historians who investigate the British ―neo-Hegelians‖ of 1880–1920 in detail, turn attention to the fact that the latter are not necessarily connected with Hegel: William Sweet made this point in regard to 1 Perry (1935), ii, p. 16. Bosanquet,2 Geoffrey Thomas in regard to Green,3 and Peter Nicholson in regard to Bradley.4 Finally, Nicholas Griffin has shown that Russell from 1895–8, then an alleged neo-Hegelian, ―was very strongly influenced by Kant and hardly at all by Hegel‖.5 These facts are hardly surprising, if we keep in mind that the representatives of the school of T.
    [Show full text]
  • WISDOM (Tlwma) and Pffllosophy (FALSAFA)
    WISDOM (tLWMA) AND PfflLOSOPHY (FALSAFA) IN ISLAMIC THOUGHT (as a framework for inquiry) By: Mehmet ONAL This thcsis is submitted ror the Doctor of Philosophy at the University of Wales - Lampeter 1998 b"9tr In this study the following two hypothesisare researched: 1. "WisdotW' is the fundamental aspect of Islamic thought on which Islamic civilisation was established through Islamic law (,Sharfa), theology (Ldi-M), philosophy (falsafq) and mysticism (Surism). 2. "Due to the first hypothesis Islamic philosophy is not only a commentary on the Greek philosophy or a new form of Ncoplatonism but a native Islamic wisdom understandingon the form of theoretical study". The present thesis consists of ten chaptersdealing with the concept of practical wisdom (Pikmq) and theoretical wisdom (philosophy or falsafa). At the end there arc a gcncral conclusion,glossary and bibliography. In the introduction (Chapter One) the definition of wisdom and philosophy is establishedas a conceptualground for the above two hypothesis. In the following chapter (Chapter Two) I focused on the historical background of these two concepts by giving a brief history of ancient wisdom and Greek philosophy as sourcesof Islamic thought. In the following two chapters (Chapter Three and Four) I tried to bring out a possibledefinition of Islamic wisdom in the Qur'5n and Sunna on which Islamic jurisprudence (fiqh), theology (A-alim), philosophy (falsafq) and mysticism (Sufism) consistedof. As a result of the above conceptual approaching,I tried to reach a new definition for wisdom (PiLma) as a method that helps in the establishmentof a new Islamic way of life and civilisation for our life.
    [Show full text]
  • Husserl's Position Between Dilthey and the Windelband-Rickert School of Neo-Kantianism John E
    Sacred Heart University DigitalCommons@SHU Philosophy, Theology and Religious Studies Faculty Philosophy, Theology and Religious Studies Publications 4-1988 Husserl's Position Between Dilthey and the Windelband-Rickert School of Neo-Kantianism John E. Jalbert Sacred Heart University Follow this and additional works at: http://digitalcommons.sacredheart.edu/rel_fac Part of the Philosophy of Mind Commons, and the Philosophy of Science Commons Recommended Citation Jalbert, John E. "Husserl's Position Between Dilthey and the Windelband-Rickert School of Neo-Kantianism." Journal of the History of Philosophy 26.2 (1988): 279-296. This Article is brought to you for free and open access by the Philosophy, Theology and Religious Studies at DigitalCommons@SHU. It has been accepted for inclusion in Philosophy, Theology and Religious Studies Faculty Publications by an authorized administrator of DigitalCommons@SHU. For more information, please contact [email protected]. +XVVHUO V3RVLWLRQ%HWZHHQ'LOWKH\DQGWKH:LQGHOEDQG5LFNHUW 6FKRRORI1HR.DQWLDQLVP John E. Jalbert Journal of the History of Philosophy, Volume 26, Number 2, April 1988, pp. 279-296 (Article) 3XEOLVKHGE\7KH-RKQV+RSNLQV8QLYHUVLW\3UHVV DOI: 10.1353/hph.1988.0045 For additional information about this article http://muse.jhu.edu/journals/hph/summary/v026/26.2jalbert.html Access provided by Sacred Heart University (5 Dec 2014 12:35 GMT) Husserl's Position Between Dilthey and the Windelband- Rickert School of Neo- Kanuamsm JOHN E. JALBERT THE CONTROVERSY AND DEBATE over the character of the relationship between the natural and human sciences (Natur- und Geisteswissenschaflen) became a central theme for philosophical reflection largely through the efforts of theo- rists such as Wilhelm Dilthey and the two principal representatives of the Baden School of Neo-Kantians, Wilhelm Windelband and Heinrich Rickert.~ These turn of the century theorists are major figures in this philosophical arena, but they are by no means the only participants in the effort to grapple with this issue.
    [Show full text]
  • Wilhelm Windelband and the Problem of Relativism
    Wilhelm Windelband and the problem of relativism Katherina Kinzel, University of Vienna [email protected] This is a preprint version. The final edit will appear in British Journal for the History of Philosophy. Abstract This paper analyses the shifts in Wilhelm Windelband’s ‘critical philosophy of values’ as it developed hand in hand with his understanding of relativism. The paper has two goals. On the one hand, by analysing the role that relativism played in his philosophical project, it seeks to contribute to a better understanding of Windelband's intellectual development in the context of historicism and Neo-Kantianism. On the other hand, by highlighting Windelband’s contribution to the understanding of relativism, it sheds light on an important episode in the history of that problem. The paper distinguishes between three phases in Windelband’s thinking and shows that his views about relativism changed in close connection with his conception of history. The early Windelband thought that historicism was compatible with absolute validity because he was firmly convinced of historical progress. The mature Windelband rejected progress as a means for justifying validity and put the problem of relativism into sharp relief. In response to the failure of his mature philosophy to fend off relativism, the later Windelband strengthened the role of history again. The paper concludes that Windelband’s significance lies not in his arguments against relativism, but rather in having furthered philosophical understanding of the problems at stake. Keywords Wilhelm Windelband; Relativism; Historicism; Psychologism; Neo-Kantianism 1. Introduction In late nineteenth- and early twentieth-century Imperial Germany, relativism was a recurring topic of debate.
    [Show full text]
  • Linguistic Scepticism in Mauthner's Philosophy
    LiberaPisano Misunderstanding Metaphors: Linguistic ScepticisminMauthner’s Philosophy Nous sommes tous dans un désert. Personne ne comprend personne. Gustave Flaubert¹ This essayisanoverview of Fritz Mauthner’slinguistic scepticism, which, in my view, represents apowerful hermeneutic category of philosophical doubts about the com- municative,epistemological, and ontological value of language. In order to shed light on the main features of Mauthner’sthought, Idrawattention to his long-stand- ing dialogue with both the sceptical tradition and philosophyoflanguage. This con- tribution has nine short sections: the first has an introductory function and illus- tratesseveral aspectsoflinguistic scepticism in the history of philosophy; the second offers acontextualisation of Mauthner’sphilosophyoflanguage; the remain- der present abroad examination of the main features of Mauthner’sthought as fol- lows: the impossibility of knowledge that stems from aradicalisationofempiricism; the coincidencebetween wordand thought,thinkingand speaking;the notion of use, the relevanceoflinguistic habits,and the utopia of communication; the decep- tive metaphors at the root of an epoché of meaning;the new task of philosophyasan exercise of liberation against the limits of language; the controversial relationship between Judaism and scepticism; and the mystical silence as an extreme conse- quence of his thought.² Mauthnerturns scepticism into aform of life and philosophy into acritique of language, and he inauguratesanew approach that is traceable in manyGerman—Jewish
    [Show full text]
  • Philosophy in the Nineteenth Century
    GEORGEMASON UNIVERSITY UNIVERSllY LIBRARIES THE OXFORD HANDBOOK OF GERMAN PHILOSOPHY IN THE NINETEENTH CENTURY ............................................................................................................................................................... Edited by MICHAEL N. FORSTER and KRISTIN GJESDAL OXFORD U N lV ERSITY PR ESS OXFORD UNIVERSITY PRESS Great Clarendon Street , Oxford, o:u 6oP, United Kingdom Oxford University Press is a depart ment of the t:niver,11r of Chford It furthers the University's obJective of excellence m n·s~·arch, s.:hol.1r,h1r , . and edu cation by publishing wor ldwide . Oxford is a regmereJ trade mJrk ,,t Oxford University Press m the IJK and in certain other countnc, © The several contribu tors 1015 The moral rights of the authors have been asserted First Edition pub!t,hed 10 2015 Impress ion 1 All rights reserved . No part of this publication may be rerroJuceJ. stored in a retrieval system, or transmitted, in any form or by any mea ns, without the prior permiss ion in writing of Oxford University Press, or as npreHl y pcrm1tteJ by law, by licence or under terms agreed with the arpropr1ate repr oi:raph1,, rights organi zation. Enquiries concerning reproduction outsi de th e swre of the above should be sent to the Rights Department, Oxford tJ111vers1ty Pre,,, at the address above You must not circulate this work in any other form and you must impo se this same condit ion on any .icqu irt'r Published in the United States of America by Oxford University l're,s 198 Madison Avenue , New York, NY wo16, United StJ tes of Amer tCJ British Library Cataloguing in Puhlication l>Jta Data availa ble Library of Congress Control Numher: 2014946121 ISBN 978- 0 -19-969654 - 3 Printed and boun d by CPI Gro up (UK) Ltd, Croydon, CRO 4YY Links to thud party websites are provided by Oxford in !(OOJ faith anJ for information only.
    [Show full text]
  • Language As Metaphor P
    E-Revista de Estudos Interculturais do CEI – ISCAP N.º 3, maio de 2015 MAUTHNER VERSUS WITTGENSTEIN: LANGUAGE AS METAPHOR Paulo Barroso Escola Superior de Educação de Viseu Centro de Estudos de Comunicação e Linguagens da Faculdade de Ciências Sociais e Humanas – Universidade Nova de Lisboa [email protected] Abstract Mauthner esteemed language as a philosophical inquiry. He measured the philosophical entailments between language and reality and the consequent knowledge produced by such entailments. He questioned language’s aptitude to express and represent reality and, according to him, language is a critical source of knowledge and an unfaithful representation of reality, because there is a gap between language and reality, i.e. language distorts perception and engenders false and fictitious assumptions about reality. Language fosters superstition, creates gods and idols and exerts a dominating power over the intellect. Mauthner pointed out a critique of language based on metaphors, which would serve to address and clarify the deformation of reality. Wittgenstein, unlike himself suggested, was inspired by Mauthner. Both showed interest toward the critical analysis of language and there are many conceptual similarities between their language’s conceptions (e.g. concerning the use of metaphors to understand language). Therefore, this paper seeks a) to emphasize Mauthner’s metaphors on language as an accurate interpretation regarding the philosophical entailments between language and reality, and b) to demonstrate the epistemological legacy of Mauthner’s critique of language to Wittgenstein’s philosophy of language. Keywords: language; Mauthner; metaphor; philosophy of language; Wittgenstein. Resumo Mauthner encarava a linguagem como uma investigação filosófica. Assim, mediu os vínculos filosóficos entre linguagem e realidade e o consequente 1 conhecimento produzido por tais vínculos e questionou a aptidão da linguagem para expressar e representar a realidade.
    [Show full text]
  • Philosophy and the Mirror of Nature
    Philosophy and the Mirror of Nature RICHARD RORTY Princeton University Press Princeton, New Jersey Copyright © 1979 by Princeton University Press Published by Princeton University Press, Princeton, New Jersey All Rights Reserved Library of Congress Cataloging-in-Publication Data Rorty, Richard. Philosophy and the mirror of nature. Includes index. 1. Philosophy. 2. Philosophy, Modern. 3. Mind and body. 4. Representation (Philosophy) 5. Analysis (Philosophy) 6. Civilization-Philosophy. I. Title. B53·R68 190 79- 84013 ISBN 0-691-07236-1 ISBN 0-691-02016-7 pbk. Publication of this book has been aided by a grant from The National Endowment for the Humanities This book has been composed in Linotype Baskerville Princeton University Press books are printed on acid-free paper and meet the guidelines for permanence and durability of the Committee on Production Guidelines for Book Longevity of the Council on Library Resources Printed in the United States of America Second printing, with corrections, 1980 First Princeton Paperback printing, 1980 20 19 18 17 16 15 14 13 12 I I 10 TO M. V. R. When we think about the future of the world, we always have in mind its being at the place where it would be if it continued to move as we see it moving now. We do not realize that it moves not in a straight line, but in a curve, and that its direction constantly changes. Philosophy has made no progress? If somebody scratches where it itches, does that count as progress? If not, does that mean it wasn't an authentic scratch? Not an authentic itch? Couldn't this response to the stimulus go on for quite a long time until a remedy for itching is found? Wenn wir an die Zukunft der Welt denken, so meinen wir immer den Ort, wo sie sein wird, wenn sie so weiter Hiuft, wie wir sie jetzt laufen sehen, und denken nieht, da�s sie nieht gerade lauft, sondern in einer Kurve, und ihre Riehtung sieh konstant andert.
    [Show full text]
  • European Journal of Pragmatism and American Philosophy, IV - 1 | 2012, « Pragmatism and the Social Sciences: a Century of Influences and Interactions, Vol
    European Journal of Pragmatism and American Philosophy IV - 1 | 2012 Pragmatism and the Social Sciences: A Century of Influences and Interactions, vol. 2 Roberto Frega and Filipe Careira Da Silva (dir.) Electronic version URL: http://journals.openedition.org/ejpap/758 DOI: 10.4000/ejpap.758 ISSN: 2036-4091 Publisher Associazione Pragma Electronic reference Roberto Frega and Filipe Careira Da Silva (dir.), European Journal of Pragmatism and American Philosophy, IV - 1 | 2012, « Pragmatism and the Social Sciences: A Century of Influences and Interactions, vol. 2 » [Online], Online since 23 July 2012, connection on 23 September 2020. URL : http://journals.openedition.org/ejpap/758 ; DOI : https://doi.org/10.4000/ejpap.758 This text was automatically generated on 23 September 2020. Author retains copyright and grants the European Journal of Pragmatism and American Philosophy right of first publication with the work simultaneously licensed under a Creative Commons Attribution- NonCommercial-NoDerivatives 4.0 International License. 1 TABLE OF CONTENTS Symposia. Pragmatism and the Social Sciences: A Century of Influences and Interactions, vol.2 Pragmatism and the Social Sciences A Century of Influences and Interactions, vol. 2 Roberto Frega and Filipe Carreira da Silva Section I. Classical Pragmatists and Contemporary Sociology Peirce and Iconology Habitus, Embodiment, and the Analogy between Philosophy and Architecture Tullio Viola Experiencing Practical Knowledge Emerging Convergences of Pragmatism and Sociological Practice Theory Tanja Bogusz The Social Scientist, the Public, and the Pragmatist Gaze Exploring the Critical Conditions of Sociological Inquiry Philippe Gonzalez and Laurence Kaufmann Section II. Law, Power, and the Prospects of a Pragmatist Social Theory Naturalistic Values and Progressive Politics A Missing Link Between Pragmatism and Social Theory Christoph Henning American Pragmatism and European Social Theory Holmes, Durkheim, Scheler, and the Sociology of Legal Knowledge Frederic R.
    [Show full text]
  • Wittgenstein's Vienna Our Aim Is, by Academic Standards, a Radical One : to Use Each of Our Four Topics As a Mirror in Which to Reflect and to Study All the Others
    TOUCHSTONE Gustav Klimt, from Ver Sacrum Wittgenstein' s VIENNA Allan Janik and Stephen Toulmin TOUCHSTONE A Touchstone Book Published by Simon and Schuster Copyright ® 1973 by Allan Janik and Stephen Toulmin All rights reserved including the right of reproduction in whole or in part in any form A Touchstone Book Published by Simon and Schuster A Division of Gulf & Western Corporation Simon & Schuster Building Rockefeller Center 1230 Avenue of the Americas New York, N.Y. 10020 TOUCHSTONE and colophon are trademarks of Simon & Schuster ISBN o-671-2136()-1 ISBN o-671-21725-9Pbk. Library of Congress Catalog Card Number 72-83932 Designed by Eve Metz Manufactured in the United States of America 8 9 10 11 12 13 14 15 16 The publishers wish to thank the following for permission to repro­ duce photographs: Bettmann Archives, Art Forum, du magazine, and the National Library of Austria. For permission to reproduce a portion of Arnold SchOnberg's Verklarte Nacht, our thanks to As­ sociated Music Publishers, Inc., New York, N.Y., copyright by Bel­ mont Music, Los Angeles, California. Contents PREFACE 9 1. Introduction: PROBLEMS AND METHODS 13 2. Habsburg Vienna: CITY OF PARADOXES 33 The Ambiguity of Viennese Life The Habsburg Hausmacht: Francis I The Cilli Affair Francis Joseph The Character of the Viennese Bourgeoisie The Home and Family Life-The Role of the Press­ The Position of Women-The Failure of Liberalism The Conditions of Working-Class Life : The Housing Problem Viktor Adler and Austrian Social Democracy Karl Lueger and the Christian Social Party Georg von Schonerer and the German Nationalist Party Theodor Herzl and Zionism The Redl Affair Arthur Schnitzler's Literary Diagnosis of the Viennese Malaise Suicide inVienna 3.
    [Show full text]