An Enquiry Concerning the Passions: a Critical Study of Hume's Four

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

An Enquiry Concerning the Passions: a Critical Study of Hume's Four An Enquiry Concerning the Passions: A critical study of Hume's Four Dissertations Amyas John Henry Merivale Submitted in accordance with the requirements for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy The University of Leeds School of Philosophy, Religion, and the History of Science June 2014 i The candidate confirms that the work submitted is his own and that appropriate credit has been given where reference has been made to the work of others. This copy has been supplied on the understanding that it is copyright material and that no quotation from the thesis may be published without proper acknowl- edgement. c University of Leeds and Amyas Merivale ii Acknowledgements I am enormously indebted to Helen Steward, my principal supervisor at Leeds, for her tireless attention to the detail of this work and the correction of countless errors along the way. Without her advice and support, moreover, the beast would have been considerably harder to tame, if it had not run away from me altogether. Immeasurable thanks are due to Peter Millican, my long-standing mentor and supervisor at a distance. We agree with each other to such an extent that I now find it difficult to recall where his ideas end and mine begin; both in the planning and the execution of this thesis he has been a generous and invaluable collaborator. I am grateful also to Matthew Kieran, my secondary supervisor at Leeds, for his assistance with the later chapters on aesthetics. In addition, various of the ideas herein have benefited greatly from discussions with James Arnold, Filippo Contesi, and Samuel Rickless. Finally, to Esther: for making this period such a happy one, and for her curiosity, patience, and support. iii Abstract Hume's first work, A Treatise of Human Nature, has traditionally received the lion's share of scholarly attention, at the expense of his later and more polished texts. The tide has started to shift in recent years, with the result that Hume's two Enquiries|his mature investigations of the understanding and morals|are now recognised as important works in their own right (though most commentators still continue to prefer the Treatise). With regard to Hume's work on the passions, however, Book 2 of the Treatise still commands all of the attention. In this thesis, I defend two important claims. The first is that Hume has a mature philosophy of emotion, significantly different|indeed, significantly im- proved|from that of the Treatise. Most strikingly, it is anti-egoist and anti- hedonist about motivation, where the Treatise had espoused a Lockean hedonism and egoism. In parts it is also more cognitivist, and although Hume remains as opposed to moral rationalism as he ever was, his arguments in support of this opposition are very different. The second claim is that Hume's mature philosophy of emotion is to be found, not in the Dissertation on the Passions, but rather in the full set of Four Dissertations in which this work first appeared, including also the Natural History of Religion, Of Tragedy, and Of the Standard of Taste. The passions, I argue, form the unifying theme of this collection, which is in effect Hume's Enquiry concerning the Passions. I maintain that they are profitably studied together on this understanding, and my thesis is offered as the first such study. v Conventions References to Hume's texts throughout use the following abbreviations, followed by Book, part, section, and paragraph numbers (as appropriate): T A Treatise of Human Nature L A Letter from a Gentleman to his Friend in Edinburgh E An Enquiry concerning Human Understanding M An Enquiry concerning the Principles of Morals D Dialogues concerning Natural Religion N The Natural History of Religion P A Dissertation on the Passions Tr Of Tragedy ST Of the Standard of Taste Other essays are abbreviated in a similar fashion, but only after they have been introduced by name, so that it will be obvious which essay is being cited. Page numbers are to the editions that most Hume scholars would now expect (Selby- Bigge's editions of the Treatise and Enquiries, Miller's edition of the Essays); full references are in the bibliography of primary sources at the end. The quo- tations themselves are taken from the editions, prepared by Peter Millican and me, available at http://www.davidhume.org/. I adopt the same referencing and abbreviation conventions as are used on that site. vii Quotations and references from other primary sources are from the editions listed in the bibliography. The page numbers are from modern editions, wherever these were easily available, but I cite these works using the original publication year, since I consider it desirable to be able to see at a glance when the thing in question was first said. The works often went through several editions in their authors' lifetimes, receiving additions and revisions in the process. My rule is to use the date of the earliest edition in which the quoted passage appeared. This has the effect that the same work is sometimes referred to with a different year. Butler's Sermons, for example, are typically referred to as \Butler (1726)"; but when I am quoting from Butler's preface, which was first added in the second edition, I use \Butler (1729)". A glance at the bibliography of primary sources will quickly reveal that these refer to different editions of the same text. viii Contents Introduction1 0.1 An enquiry concerning the passions.................1 0.2 Four/three/five/four dissertations..................3 0.3 Editing the Treatise ..........................6 0.4 Epicureans, Stoics, Platonists, ..................... 10 0.5 ... and Sceptics............................ 13 I The Butler Moment 19 1 Some Late Philosophers in England 21 1.1 Hutcheson against Clarke....................... 21 1.2 Hutcheson against Hobbes and Mandeville............. 23 1.3 Butler against Hobbes and Clarke.................. 26 1.4 Shaftesbury against Hobbes and Locke............... 30 1.5 Egoists, Sentimentalists, Rationalists................ 35 2 Motivation 39 2.1 The Butler paragraph......................... 39 2.2 Hedonism in the Treatise ....................... 42 2.3 The dignity of human nature..................... 45 2.4 The two Enquiries .......................... 47 2.5 Desire in the Dissertation on the Passions ............. 51 ix 3 Hume's Classification of the Passions 55 3.1 Impressions and sentiments..................... 55 3.2 Three more distinctions....................... 58 3.3 The Butler paragraph (again).................... 61 3.4 Calm and violent........................... 65 3.5 Some peculiar feelings........................ 69 4 Association, Comparison, Sympathy 73 4.1 The double relation theory...................... 74 4.2 Comparison.............................. 77 4.3 Sympathy............................... 79 4.4 More applications of sympathy.................... 83 4.5 The indirect passions......................... 88 5 Original Instincts 93 5.1 Object-directed desires and original instincts............ 93 5.2 Later traces of sympathy and comparison.............. 97 5.3 Ambition, vanity, and parental love................. 100 5.4 Sympathy and benevolence...................... 105 5.5 Sympathy and the rules of art.................... 108 6 The Development of Hume's Thought 113 6.1 Anti-egoism in the Treatise ...................... 113 6.2 Egoism, careless egoism, and anti-egoism.............. 117 6.3 Butler, not Hutcheson........................ 120 6.4 Going back to the source....................... 124 6.5 Why so much resistance?....................... 129 II The Third Enquiry 133 7 Superstition and the Passions 135 7.1 Reasons and causes.......................... 136 x 7.2 Superstition and true religion.................... 139 7.3 Hope and fear............................. 144 7.4 The origin of polytheism and monotheism............. 147 7.5 The miraculous and the momentous................. 149 8 Some Comparisons 153 8.1 Hobbes on the origin of religious belief............... 153 8.2 Comparisons between monotheism and polytheism......... 155 8.3 The bull-rush argument....................... 158 8.4 Hume's agnosticism and Hume's atheism.............. 160 8.5 The three Enquiries ......................... 163 9 The Intentionality of the Passions 167 9.1 Cognition and the passions...................... 167 9.2 The representative quality argument................ 171 9.3 Simple and complex.......................... 176 9.4 The double-relation passions..................... 178 9.5 The double relation theory (again)................. 183 10 Reason and Passion 189 10.1 Malebranche against the passions.................. 190 10.2 Clarke against the passions...................... 194 10.3 Hutcheson against the rationalists.................. 197 10.4 Hume against the rationalists.................... 202 10.5 The representative quality argument (again)............ 206 11 The Chemistry of the Passions 211 11.1 Two overlapping theories....................... 211 11.2 Du Bos................................. 214 11.3 Fontenelle............................... 217 11.4 Hume's change of mind........................ 219 11.5 Hume's later account......................... 222 xi xii 12 The Conversion Principle 227 12.1 Swallowing up: passions or emotions?................ 228 12.2 Movements in the spirits....................... 231 12.3 Conversion............................... 233 12.4 Before and after............................ 236 12.5 A subtler interpretation....................... 240 13 Passion and Value 245 13.1 The sceptical principle........................ 245 13.2
Recommended publications
  • Life with Augustine
    Life with Augustine ...a course in his spirit and guidance for daily living By Edmond A. Maher ii Life with Augustine © 2002 Augustinian Press Australia Sydney, Australia. Acknowledgements: The author wishes to acknowledge and thank the following people: ► the Augustinian Province of Our Mother of Good Counsel, Australia, for support- ing this project, with special mention of Pat Fahey osa, Kevin Burman osa, Pat Codd osa and Peter Jones osa ► Laurence Mooney osa for assistance in editing ► Michael Morahan osa for formatting this 2nd Edition ► John Coles, Peter Gagan, Dr. Frank McGrath fms (Brisbane CEO), Benet Fonck ofm, Peter Keogh sfo for sharing their vast experience in adult education ► John Rotelle osa, for granting us permission to use his English translation of Tarcisius van Bavel’s work Augustine (full bibliography within) and for his scholarly advice Megan Atkins for her formatting suggestions in the 1st Edition, that have carried over into this the 2nd ► those generous people who have completed the 1st Edition and suggested valuable improvements, especially Kath Neehouse and friends at Villanova College, Brisbane Foreword 1 Dear Participant Saint Augustine of Hippo is a figure in our history who has appealed to the curiosity and imagination of many generations. He is well known for being both sinner and saint, for being a bishop yet also a fellow pilgrim on the journey to God. One of the most popular and attractive persons across many centuries, his influence on the church has continued to our current day. He is also renowned for his influ- ence in philosophy and psychology and even (in an indirect way) art, music and architecture.
    [Show full text]
  • Kant on Empiricism and Rationalism
    HISTORY OF PHILOSOPHY QUARTERLY Volume 30, Number 1, January 2013 KANT ON EMPIRICISM AND RATIONALISM Alberto Vanzo his paper aims to correct some widely held misconceptions concern- T ing Kant’s role in the formation of a widespread narrative of early modern philosophy.1 According to this narrative, which dominated the English-speaking world throughout the twentieth century,2 the early modern period was characterized by the development of two rival schools: René Descartes’s, Baruch Spinoza’s, and G. W. Leibniz’s rationalism; and John Locke’s, George Berkeley’s, and David Hume’s empiricism. Empiricists and rationalists disagreed on whether all concepts are de- rived from experience and whether humans can have any substantive a priori knowledge, a priori knowledge of the physical world, or a priori metaphysical knowledge.3 The early modern period came to a close, so the narrative claims, once Immanuel Kant, who was neither an empiri- cist nor a rationalist, combined the insights of both movements in his new Critical philosophy. In so doing, Kant inaugurated the new eras of German idealism and late modern philosophy. Since the publication of influential studies by Louis Loeb and David Fate Norton,4 the standard narrative of early modern philosophy has come increasingly under attack. Critics hold that histories of early modern philosophy based on the rationalism-empiricism distinction (RED) have three biases—three biases for which, as we shall see, Kant is often blamed. The Epistemological Bias. Since disputes regarding a priori knowledge belong to epistemology, the RED is usually regarded as an epistemologi- cal distinction.5 Accordingly, histories of early modern philosophy based on the RED tend to assume that the core of early modern philosophy lies in the conflict between the “competing and mutually exclusive epis- temologies” of “rationalism and empiricism.”6 They typically interpret most of the central doctrines, developments, and disputes of the period in the light of philosophers’ commitment to empiricist or rationalist epistemologies.
    [Show full text]
  • Sense and Sensibility
    Nils Franzén Sense and Sensibility Four Essays on Evaluative Discourse Dissertation presented at Uppsala University to be publicly examined in Geijersalen, Thunbergsvägen 3H, Uppsala, Thursday, 20 September 2018 at 15:00 for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy. The examination will be conducted in English. Faculty examiner: Professor Pekka Väyrynen (University of Leeds, Faculty of Arts, Humanities and Cultures ). Abstract Franzén, N. 2018. Sense and Sensibility. Four Essays on Evaluative Discourse. 37 pp. Uppsala: Department of Philosophy. ISBN 978-91-506-2717-6. The subject of this thesis is the nature of evaluative terms and concepts. It investigates various phenomena that distinguish evaluative discourse from other types of language use. Broadly, the thesis argues that these differences are best explained by the hypothesis that evaluative discourse serves to communicate that the speaker is in a particular emotional or affective state of mind. The first paper, “Aesthetic Evaluation and First-hand Experience”, examines the fact that it sounds strange to make evaluative aesthetic statements while at the same time denying that you have had first-hand experience with the object being discussed. It is proposed that a form of expressivism about aesthetic discourse best explains the data. The second paper, “Evaluative Discourse and Affective States of Mind”, discusses the problem of missing Moorean infelicity for expressivism. It is argued that evaluative discourse expresses states of mind attributed by sentences of the form “Nils finds it wrong to tell lies”. These states, the paper argues, are non-cognitive, and the observation therefore addresses the problem of missing infelicity. The third paper, “Sensibilism and Evaluative Supervenience”, argues that contemporary theories about why the moral supervenes on the non-moral have failed to account for the full extent of the phenomenon.
    [Show full text]
  • Praying and Contemplating in Late Antiquity Religious and Philosophical Interactions
    Studien und Texte zu Antike und Christentum Studies and Texts in Antiquity and Christianity Herausgegeber / Editors Christoph Markschies (Berlin) · Martin Wallraff (München) Christian Wildberg (Princeton) Beirat / Advisory Board Peter Brown (Princeton) · Susanna Elm (Berkeley) Johannes Hahn (Münster) · Emanuela Prinzivalli (Rom) Jörg Rüpke (Erfurt) 113 Praying and Contemplating in Late Antiquity Religious and Philosophical Interactions Edited by Eleni Pachoumi and Mark Edwards Mohr Siebeck Eleni Pachoumi studied Classical Studies; 2007 PhD; worked as a Lecturer of Classical Philology at the University of Thessaly, the Aristotle University of Thessaloniki and the University of Patras; Research Fellow at North-West University; currently Lecturer at the Open University in Greece and Academic Visiting Fellow in the Faculty of Classics, University of Oxford. Mark Edwards, 1984 BA in Literae Humaniores; 1990 BA in Theology; 1988 D. phil.; 1989 – 93 Junior Fellowship at New College; Tutor in Theology at Christ Church, Oxford and University Lecturer in Patristics in the Faculty of Theology, University of Oxford; since 2014 Professor of Early Christian Studies. ISBN 978-3-16-156119-1 / eISBN 978-3-16-156594-6 DOI 10.1628 / 978-3-16-156594-6 ISSN 1436-3003 / eISSN 2568-7433 (Studien und Texte zu Antike und Christentum) The Deutsche Nationalbibliothek lists this publication in the Deutsche Nationalbiblio- graphie; detailed bibliographic data are available on the Internet at http://dnb.dnb.de. © 2018 Mohr Siebeck Tübingen. www.mohrsiebeck.com This book may not be reproduced, in whole or in part, in any form (beyond that per- mitted by copyright law) without the publisher’s written permission. This applies partic- ularly to reproductions, translations and storage and processing in electronic systems.
    [Show full text]
  • A Rationalist Argument for Libertarian Free Will
    A rationalist argument for libertarian free will Stylianos Panagiotou PhD University of York Philosophy August 2020 Abstract In this thesis, I give an a priori argument in defense of libertarian free will. I conclude that given certain presuppositions, the ability to do otherwise is a necessary requirement for substantive rationality; the ability to think and act in light of reasons. ‘Transcendental’ arguments to the effect that determinism is inconsistent with rationality are predominantly forwarded in a Kantian manner. Their incorporation into the framework of critical philosophy renders the ontological status of their claims problematic; rather than being claims about how the world really is, they end up being claims about how the mind must conceive of it. To make their ontological status more secure, I provide a rationalist framework that turns them from claims about how the mind must view the world into claims about the ontology of rational agents. In the first chapter, I make some preliminary remarks about reason, reasons and rationality and argue that an agent’s access to alternative possibilities is a necessary condition for being under the scope of normative reasons. In the second chapter, I motivate rationalism about a priori justification. In the third chapter, I present the rationalist argument for libertarian free will and defend it against objections. Several objections rest on a compatibilist understanding of an agent’s abilities. To undercut them, I devote the fourth chapter, in which I give a new argument for incompatibilism between free will and determinism, which I call the situatedness argument for incompatibilism. If the presuppositions of the thesis are granted and the situatedness argument works, then we may be justified in thinking that to the extent that we are substantively rational, we are free in the libertarian sense.
    [Show full text]
  • Hume's Pride Or Our Prejudice?
    24 Hume’s Pride or Our Prejudice? A New Take on Hume’s Love of Fame Nathan Porter University of Utah Abstract This paper examines David Hume’s desire for fame in his eighteenth-century context. It argues that in his day, a desire for fame was not at all reproachable, because it was to be won by doing something great for the world. In Hume’s case, this seems to have been the act of liberating humankind from religious tyranny. The paper further argues that our instinctive distaste for Hume’s unabashed longing for fame is likely an unintended byproduct of the democratic societies we inhabit, and suggests that we ought to rethink the idea of fame within our own context. Introduction Of all of the thinkers of the eighteenth-century Enlightenment, none has been more influential or garnered more infamy than David Hume. Born in Scotland in 1711, he began work on his magnum opus, A Treatise of Human Nature, while he was still in his early twenties, publishing it with little initial success in 1739.1 He tried his hand at essay writing, which proved a more publically fruitful endeavor than his more heavy-handed philosophizing. But the work that was most acclaimed in his day was his six-volume History of England, which turned out to be quite a popular success among his contemporaries. History has its way of turning the tables, however, and today Hume is primarily known for the works in which he presented radically skeptical views about religion, the world, and even rationality itself.
    [Show full text]
  • An Investigation Into a Postmodern Feminist Reading of Averroës
    Journal of Feminist Scholarship Volume 10 Issue 10 Spring 2016 Article 5 Spring 2016 Bodies and Contexts: An Investigation into a Postmodern Feminist Reading of Averroës Reed Taylor University of Arkansas at Little Rock Follow this and additional works at: https://digitalcommons.uri.edu/jfs Part of the Feminist, Gender, and Sexuality Studies Commons, Law and Gender Commons, and the Women's History Commons This work is licensed under a Creative Commons Attribution-Noncommercial-No Derivative Works 4.0 License. Recommended Citation Taylor, Reed. 2018. "Bodies and Contexts: An Investigation into a Postmodern Feminist Reading of Averroës." Journal of Feminist Scholarship 10 (Spring): 48-60. https://digitalcommons.uri.edu/jfs/vol10/ iss10/5 This Article is brought to you for free and open access by DigitalCommons@URI. It has been accepted for inclusion in Journal of Feminist Scholarship by an authorized editor of DigitalCommons@URI. For more information, please contact [email protected]. Taylor: Bodies and Contexts Bodies and Contexts: An Investigation into a Postmodern Feminist Reading of Averroës Reed Taylor, University of Arkansas at Little Rock Abstract: In this article, I contribute to the wider discourse of theorizing feminism in predominantly Muslim societies by analyzing the role of women’s political agency within the writings of the twelfth-century Islamic philosopher Averroës (Ibn Rushd, 1126–1198). I critically analyze Catarina Belo’s (2009) liberal feminist approach to political agency in Averroës by adopting a postmodern reading of Averroës’s commentary on Plato’s Republic. A postmodern feminist reading of Averroes’s political thought emphasizes contingencies and contextualization rather than employing a literal reading of the historical works.
    [Show full text]
  • Reason in Hume's Passions Nathan Brett, Katharina Paxman
    Reason in Hume's Passions Nathan Brett, Katharina Paxman Hume Studies, Volume 34, Number 1, April 2008, pp. 43-59 (Article) Published by Hume Society DOI: https://doi.org/10.1353/hms.0.0006 For additional information about this article https://muse.jhu.edu/article/365209 [ This content has been declared free to read by the pubisher during the COVID-19 pandemic. ] Hume Studies Volume 34, Number 1, April 2008, pp. 43–59 Reason in Hume’s Passions NATHAN BRETT AND KATHARina PAXMAN Abstract: Hume is famous for the view that “reason is, and ought only to be, the slave of the passions.” His claim that “we are no sooner acquainted with the impossibility of satisfying any desire, than the desire itself vanishes” is less well known. Each seems, in opposite ways, shocking to common sense. This paper explores the latter claim, looking for its source in Hume’s account of the passions and exploring its compatibility with his associationist psychology. We are led to the conclusion that this view—that desires vanish when fulfil- ment is deemed impossible—endows reason with a power over the passions that is at odds with its role as slave, and ultimately incompatible with a proper understanding of emotions such as grief. Such emotions involve continuing to want what one believes to be impossible. The human (and Humean) imagina- tion can sustain desires without the belief that fulfilment is possible. [N]othing is more certain, than that despair has almost the same effect upon us with enjoyment, and that we are no sooner acquainted with the impossibility of satisfying any desire, than the desire itself vanishes.
    [Show full text]
  • A-Z Entries List
    Alphabetical List of Entries Abelard, Peter Attributes, Divine Abortion Augustine of Hippo Action Augustinianism Adam Authority Adoptionism Agape Balthasar, Hans Urs von Agnosticism Bañezianism-Molinism-Baianism Albert the Great Baptism Alexandria, School of Baptists Alphonsus Liguori Barth, Karl Ambrose of Milan Basel-Ferrara-Florence, Council of Anabaptists Basil (The Great) of Caesarea Analogy Beatitude Angels Beauty Anglicanism Beguines Anhypostasy Being Animals Bellarmine, Robert Anointing of the Sick Bernard of Clairvaux Anselm of Canterbury Bérulle, Pierre de Anthropology Bible Anthropomorphism Biblical Theology Antinomianism Bishop Antinomy Blessing Antioch, School of Blondel, Maurice Apocalyptic Literature Boethius Apocatastasis Bonaventure Apocrypha Bonhoeffer, Dietrich Apollinarianism Book Apologists Bucer, Martin Apostle Bultmann, Rudolf Apostolic Fathers Apostolic Succession Calvin, John Appropriation Calvinism Architecture Canon Law Arianism Canon of Scriptures Aristotelianism, Christian Carmel Arminianism Casuistry Asceticism Catechesis Aseitas Catharism Athanasius of Alexandria Catholicism Atheism Chalcedon, Council of xiii Alphabetical List of Entries Character Diphysitism Charisma Docetism Chartres, School of Doctor of the Church Childhood, Spiritual Dogma Choice Dogmatic Theology Christ/Christology Donatism Christ’s Consciousness Duns Scotus, John Chrysostom, John Church Ecclesiastical Discipline Church and State Ecclesiology Circumincession Ecology City Ecumenism Cleric Edwards, Jonathan Collegiality Enlightenment
    [Show full text]
  • ABSTRACT Augustinian Auden: the Influence of Augustine of Hippo on W. H. Auden Stephen J. Schuler, Ph.D. Mentor: Richard Rankin
    ABSTRACT Augustinian Auden: The Influence of Augustine of Hippo on W. H. Auden Stephen J. Schuler, Ph.D. Mentor: Richard Rankin Russell, Ph.D. It is widely acknowledged that W. H. Auden became a Christian in about 1940, but relatively little critical attention has been paid to Auden‟s theology, much less to the particular theological sources of Auden‟s faith. Auden read widely in theology, and one of his earliest and most important theological influences on his poetry and prose is Saint Augustine of Hippo. This dissertation explains the Augustinian origin of several crucial but often misunderstood features of Auden‟s work. They are, briefly, the nature of evil as privation of good; the affirmation of all existence, and especially the physical world and the human body, as intrinsically good; the difficult aspiration to the fusion of eros and agape in the concept of Christian charity; and the status of poetry as subject to both aesthetic and moral criteria. Auden had already been attracted to similar ideas in Lawrence, Blake, Freud, and Marx, but those thinkers‟ common insistence on the importance of physical existence took on new significance with Auden‟s acceptance of the Incarnation as an historical reality. For both Auden and Augustine, the Incarnation was proof that the physical world is redeemable. Auden recognized that if neither the physical world nor the human body are intrinsically evil, then the physical desires of the body, such as eros, the self-interested survival instinct, cannot in themselves be intrinsically evil. The conflict between eros and agape, or altruistic love, is not a Manichean struggle of darkness against light, but a struggle for appropriate placement in a hierarchy of values, and Auden derived several ideas about Christian charity from Augustine.
    [Show full text]
  • The Political Theology of David Hume
    THE CATHOLIC UNIVERSITY OF AMERICA The Political Theology of David Hume A DISSERTATION Submitted to the Faculty of the School of Philosophy Of The Catholic University of America In Partial Fulfillment of the Requirements For the Degree Doctor of Philosophy By Jonathan H. Krause Washington, D.C. 2015 The Political Theology of David Hume Jonathan H. Krause, Ph.D. Director: John McCarthy, Ph.D. Hume’s concern for religion is evidenced by his references to it throughout his works. Indeed, he claims in the Natural History that “every enquiry, which regards religion, is of the utmost importance.” Commentators have often treated Hume’s interest in religion as theoretical, as though he was primarily concerned to establish religion’s truth or falsity. Yet in the Essays and History of England he indicates that disputes over religious forms and beliefs are “frivolous” and “utterly absurd.” This raises an obvious question: if disagreements concerning religion are “frivolous” and “absurd,” then why are inquiries regarding religion of “the utmost importance”? Hume’s answer is political in nature. “Religion,” he says in the History, “can never be deemed a point of small consequence in civil government.” He there calls our attention to religious disputes not on detached theoretical grounds, but “only so far as they have influence on the peace and order of civil society.” This dissertation argues that the way to approach Hume on religion is through his understanding of the relationship between religion and political life, that is to say, through his “political theology.” To bring out different aspects of the political problem of religion, each of this dissertation’s four chapters focuses on the textual analysis of a particular work: A Treatise of Human Nature, The Natural History of Religion, Dialogues Concerning Natural Religion, and The History of England.
    [Show full text]
  • The Strength of Hume's "Weak" Sympathy
    The Strength of Hume’s “Weak” Sympathy Andrew S. Cunningham Hume Studies Volume 30, Number 2, (2004), 237 - 256. Your use of the HUME STUDIES archive indicates your acceptance of HUME STUDIES’ Terms and Conditions of Use, available at http://www.humesociety.org/hs/about/terms.html. HUME STUDIES’ Terms and Conditions of Use provides, in part, that unless you have obtained prior permission, you may not download an entire issue of a journal or multiple copies of articles, and you may use content in the HUME STUDIES archive only for your personal, non-commercial use. Each copy of any part of a HUME STUDIES transmission must contain the same copyright notice that appears on the screen or printed page of such transmission. For more information on HUME STUDIES contact [email protected] http://www.humesociety.org/hs/ Hume Studies Volume 30, Number 2, November 2004, pp. 237–256 The Strength of Hume’s “Weak” Sympathy ANDREW S. CUNNINGHAM Introduction Hume’s understanding of sympathy in section 2.1.11 of the Treatise—that it is a mental mechanism1 by means of which one sentient being can come to share the psychological states of another2—has a particularly interesting implication. What the sympathizer receives, according to this definition, is the passing psychological “affection” that the object of his sympathy was experiencing at the moment of observation.3 Thus the psychological connection produced by Humean sympa­ thy is not between the sympathizer and the “other” as a “whole person” existing through time, but between the sympathizer and the other’s current mental state, detached from his or her diachronic psychological life.4 Some commentators profess themselves dissatisfied with the impersonality of this “limited sympathy” (as I will call it).
    [Show full text]