Nietzsche's Notebook of 1881: the Eternal Return of the Same Daniel

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Nietzsche's Notebook of 1881: the Eternal Return of the Same Daniel Nietzsche’s notebook of 1881: The Eternal Return of the Same By Daniel Fidel Ferrer Nietzsche’s notebook of 1881: The Eternal Return of the Same / By Daniel Fidel Ferrer. ©2021 Daniel Fidel Ferrer. All rights reserved. Attribution-NonCommercial-NoDerivs CC BY-NC-ND. Imprint 1.0 All Rights Reserved. droit d'auteur. Intended copies of this work can be used for research and teaching. No change in content and must include my name, Daniel Fidel Ferrer. This book first published in the year 2021 June. Paperback: 240 pages Publisher: Kuhn von Verden Verlag. Includes bibliographical references. 1). Philosophy. 2). Metaphysics. 3). Philosophy, German. 4). Philosophy, German - - 19th century. 5). Philosophy, German and Greek Influences Metaphysics. 6). Nihilism (Philosophy). 7). Eternal return. I. Nietzsche, Friedrich Wilhelm, 1844- 1900. II. Ferrer, Daniel Fidel, 1952-.[Translation from German into English of Friedrich Nietzsche’s notes of 1881]. Acknowledgment and dedication Acknowledgment and dedication to the many German philosophers, that I have had the pleasure to read and of course disagree. For non-philosophical reasons, I am also dedicating this book to the people of Khambholaj Village in the Anand District of Gujarat State, India. To Dr. Alfred Denker and Dr. Dr. Holger Zaborowski for all things Heideggerian. No one has read this book for errors. As always, any errors, mistakes or oversights etc. are mine alone. Given a couple more years, I could improve this book. This is a philosophical translation and not a philological translation. Started many years ago in Michigan. In between texts and e-mails there is indeed time to do a few things. Mean while the world caught in the nightmare of Covid-19. I hope is gets contained. The jar has been opened (πίθος pithos); and now let Pandora give us hope (ἐλπίς, Elpis). Dedicated to all those people that have reduced the suffering and those dedicated people that have worked on the vaccines to provide for hope and light at the end of our nightmare. Suggest you start watching this list of films featuring time loops: [https://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/List_of_films_featuring_time_loops] Nietzsche publisher’s advertisement in the back matter for Nietzsche’s collected writing, 19 volumes in 1922. Grossoktavausgabe Nietzsches Werke. Table of Contents Introduction and Preface (Pages: 1-11 ) Notebook: 11 = M III 1. Spring - Autumn 1881 11 [1 to 348] (Pages: 12-167 ) Nietzsche’s Notebooks in English: a Translator’s Introduction and Afterward (Pages: 168-183 ) The thought of the eternal return of the same (Pages: 184-197 ) Later Recapitulation note of 1888 14 [188] (Pages: 198-204 ) Rejection of the idea of eternal (Pages: 205 ) Translation of 4 notes by Nietzsche on Perspectivism (Pages: 206-210 ) Nietzsche gets some final few words (Pages: 211-216 ) Bibliographies (Pages: 217-236 ) Nietzsche’s notebook of 1881: The Eternal Return of the Same Introduction and Preface Friedrich Wilhelm Nietzsche (1844-1900). There are 106 separate physical notebooks (Notizheft) written by Nietzsche from 1870 to 1889 that exist today in the Nietzsche’ archives in Weimar, Germany. Some 8,000 pages by one account. Nachlass or the older spelling is “Nachlaß” (Nachlaß) which is literally, “after left’ or leftovers writings – after Nietzsche (1900) died. Nietzsche’s Nachlaß includes many more documents than just his notebooks, for example, essays, course lectures, letters, jotters, etc. [Gottfried Leibniz (1646–1716) has left us a Nachlass of over 200,000 pages]. The following is a translation of a single one of his notebooks dated 1881. In this notebook they are 348 notes. Nietzsche at the time was 36 years old. Many different topics are covered, however, this notebook is known for the first written notes on the Nietzsche’s thought (Lehre, doctrine) of the eternal return of the same. The description and importance of this particular ‘notebook’ of 1881 is clear from the authority of Paolo D'Iorio and I quote him: “M III 1 – such is the reference number of this in-octavo notebook kept in Weimar’s Goethe-Schiller archives – is made up of 160 pages, carefully covered in about 350 fragments belonging (except for a few rare exceptions) to the period from the spring to the fall of 1881 (DFGA/MIII-1). It is a secret notebook. Nietzsche did not use its content in any of the published works”. (Ibid. Paolo D'Iorio, page 62). More specific importance and amazing details from Paolo D’Iorio: “Colli and Montinari correctly wrote elsewhere that Nietzsche “had kept Notebook Page 1 of 240 Nietzsche’s notebook of 1881: The Eternal Return of the Same M III 1 with him for the entire final period of his creative activity” (cf. Colli- Montinari, Werke, 1972, p. 60). There is no doubt that the philosopher had the Notebook in his hands in the Fall of 1888, but it also bears signs of having been re- read in 1883, 1885 and during the Spring of 1888. For example, in the letter Gast from September 3rd 1883 (eKGWB/BVN-1883, 461), Nietzsche writes that he found again the first sketch of the eternal return. We can assert that there was another re-reading of this Notebook in the Summer of 1885 from the fact that eKGWB/NF-1885,36[15] from 1885 is a reworking of eKGWB/NF-1881,11[292], eKGWB/NF-1881,11[345] of 1881, eKGWB/NF1885,36[23] from 1885 of eKGWB/NF-1881,11[150], eKGWB/NF-1881,11[281] from 1881, eKGWB/NF- 1885,35[53] from 1885 of eKGWB/NF-1881,11[70] from 1881 and so on. Finally, the recapitulation of the doctrine in eKGWB/NF-1888, 14[188] of the spring 1888 is entirely derived from M III 1”. “The eternal return: genesis and interpretation” Paolo D'Iorio. - Lexicon Philosophicum: International Journal for the History of Texts and Ideas, #2. 2014. Background on the physical notebook. **“Composition dates from 21/03/1881 to 20/12/1881. Current: Shelf Mark 71/128 Large octavo notebook (16 x 23) bound in a brown cover. The notebook consists of 160 lined pages, written on working from the back of the notebook toward the front. The odd-numbered pages 159-3 have been paginated by Nietzsche as pages 1-78 and page 2 has been paginated by him as page 79. Page 133, however, has been accidentally skipped in this pagination. The notebook contains notes, aphorisms, plans and schemas from the period of The Gay Science. These notes were set to paper in the period between the spring and the autumn of 1881.” Page 2 of 240 Nietzsche’s notebook of 1881: The Eternal Return of the Same “KSA M III 1, Großoktavheft. 160 Seiten. Aufzeichnungen zu FW. Dispositionen und Fragmente. Frühjahr-Herbst 1881. Band 9:11”. 11 = M III 1. Frühjahr – Herbst 1881 11 = M III 1. Spring - Autumn 1881. **Footnote. Friedrich Nietzsche, Digital Facsimile Edition based on the original manuscripts and prints held at the Foundation of Weimar Classics, edited by Paolo D'Iorio. Nietzsche, Friedrich. Nachgelassene Fragmente Frühjahr 1881 bis Sommer 1882 [Frühjahr – Herbst 1881] Kritische Studienausgabe, KSA 09, pages 441-575. Nietzsche, Friedrich. Werke. Kritische Gesamtausgabe. (KGW) Friedrich Nietzsche: Werke. Abteilung 5: Werke, Kritische Gesamtausgabe, Abt.5, Bd.2, Idyllen aus Messina; Die fröhliche Wissenschaft; Nachgelassene Fragmente Frühjahr 1881 - Sommer 1882. Pages 339-473. KGW='V-2.339' to KGW=2.473'. Nietzsche Editions. Citation information: Martin Heidegger (1889-1976) usually used this earlier edition of Nietzsche works: Nietzsches Werke (Grossoktavausgabe) or Grossoktavausgabe Nietzsches Werke. (GOA). Leipzig: Kröner, 1901-1913. 19 v. in 19 cm. Vols. 9-14 have imprint: Leipzig, C. G. Naumann, 1901-1904. Examples from Heidegger are quotes that look like, 1881-82 (see XII, 18 f., number 35), CM see M lll I [197]. The edition that Heidegger owned: Unveröffentlichtes aus derZeit der Fröhlichen Wissenschaft und des Zarathustra (1881-1886). Neugestaltete Ausgabe. 3. Auflage Leipzig (Kröner) 1919. [MH GA 43, page 291. Heidegger’s library]. This notebook includes Nietzsche’s earliest notes about the thought: The Eternal Return of the Same”. This “heaviest weight” (größte Schwergewicht) or the most abysmal (profound, meinen abgründlichsten Gedanken!) (Part III, 13 of Thus Page 3 of 240 Nietzsche’s notebook of 1881: The Eternal Return of the Same Spoke Zarathustra, KSA 4, 271) weighed on Nietzsche and in these notes we get various versions of Nietzsche coming to grips with his thought. Nietzsche is trying to get it sorted out in his mind. What does it mean? What is the impact? At one place he calls it a Eine Wahrsagung (a divination, a prophecy). 1884 24 [1]. From Ecco Homo, Nietzsche writes about inspiration in general: “…a thought lights up in a flash, with necessity, without hesitation as to its form, - I never had any choice. A delight whose incredible tension sometimes triggers a burst of tears, sometimes automatically hurries your pace and sometimes slows it down; a perfect state of being outside yourself, with the most distinct consciousness of a host of subtle shudders and shiverings down to the tips of your toes; a profound joy…” Translation Judith Norman. We can image this for Nietzsche when the, “The basic conception of the work, the idea of eternal return, this highest formula of affirmation that can be achieved at all” (KSA 6: 335). Sometimes Nietzsche’s calls it a Lehre (doctrine, tenet, a teaching). Gedanken translated as thoughts (note: in this case not a single thought). What was Nietzsche’s state of mind in early August 1881? From a letter, he says: “The intensities of my feelings make me shiver and laugh - a couple of times I have not been able to leave the room for the ridiculous reason that my eyes were inflamed - what? Every time I wept too much the day before on my wanderings, not sentimental tears, but tears of exultation; while I sang and talked nonsense, filled with a new look that I have ahead of all people.” Page 4 of 240 Nietzsche’s notebook of 1881: The Eternal Return of the Same “This is no Switzerland, no Recoaro [trans note: Northern Italy], something completely different, at least something much more southern - I would have to go to the plateaus of Mexico on the calm ocean to find something similar (e.g.
Recommended publications
  • Nietzsche and Psychedelics – Peter Sjöstedt-H –
    Antichrist Psychonaut: Nietzsche and Psychedelics – Peter Sjöstedt-H – ‘… And close your eyes with holy dread, For he on honey-dew hath fed, And drunk the milk of Paradise.’ So ends the famous fragment of Kubla Khan by the Romantic poet, Samuel Taylor Coleridge. He tells us that the poem was an immediate transcription of an opium-induced dream he experienced in 1797. As is known, the Romantic poets and their kin were inspired by the use of psychoactive substances such as opium, the old world’s common pain reliever. Pain elimination is its negative advantage, but its positive attribute lies in the psychedelic (‘mind- revealing’)1 state it can engender – a state described no better than by the original English opium eater himself, Thomas De Quincey: O just and righteous opium! … thou bildest upon the bosom of darkness, out of the fantastic imagery of the brain, cities and temples, beyond the art of Phidias and Praxiteles – beyond the splendours of Babylon and Hekatómpylos; and, “from the anarchy of dreaming sleep,” callest into sunny light the faces of long-buried beauties … thou hast the keys of Paradise, O just, subtle, and mighty opium!2 Two decades following the publication of these words the First Opium War commences (1839) in which China is martially punished for trying to hinder the British trade of opium to the Chinese people. Though opium, derived from the innocent garden poppy Papavar somniferum, may cradle the keys to Paradise it also clutches the keys to Perdition: its addictive thus potentially ruinous nature is commonly known. Today, partly for these reasons, opiates are mostly illegal without license – stringently so in their most potent forms of morphine and heroin.
    [Show full text]
  • Augustine and the Art of Ruling in the Carolingian Imperial Period
    Augustine and the Art of Ruling in the Carolingian Imperial Period This volume is an investigation of how Augustine was received in the Carolingian period, and the elements of his thought which had an impact on Carolingian ideas of ‘state’, rulership and ethics. It focuses on Alcuin of York and Hincmar of Rheims, authors and political advisers to Charlemagne and to Charles the Bald, respectively. It examines how they used Augustinian political thought and ethics, as manifested in the De civitate Dei, to give more weight to their advice. A comparative approach sheds light on the differences between Charlemagne’s reign and that of his grandson. It scrutinizes Alcuin’s and Hincmar’s discussions of empire, rulership and the moral conduct of political agents during which both drew on the De civitate Dei, although each came away with a different understanding. By means of a philological–historical approach, the book offers a deeper reading and treats the Latin texts as political discourses defined by content and language. Sophia Moesch is currently an SNSF-funded postdoctoral fellow at the University of Oxford, working on a project entitled ‘Developing Principles of Good Govern- ance: Latin and Greek Political Advice during the Carolingian and Macedonian Reforms’. She completed her PhD in History at King’s College London. Augustine and the Art of Ruling in the Carolingian Imperial Period Political Discourse in Alcuin of York and Hincmar of Rheims Sophia Moesch First published 2020 by Routledge 2 Park Square, Milton Park, Abingdon, Oxon OX14 4RN and by Routledge 52 Vanderbilt Avenue, New York, NY 10017 Routledge is an imprint of the Taylor & Francis Group, an informa business Published with the support of the Swiss National Science Foundation.
    [Show full text]
  • Philosophical Practice As Contemplative Philosophy
    Practical Philosophy Spring 2006 Philosophical Practice as Contemplative Philosophy Ran Lahav As philosophical practitioners we are often asked: ‘What what is desirable, and adjusts philosophy to the demands is philosophical practice all about?’ And it is not easy to of the market. find a good answer, other than something like: ‘Well, philosophical practice is not one thing. There are all kinds But, hold on, one might say, is there anything wrong with of approaches.’ this contemporary trend? After all, people in today’s world want solutions to their problems, self-gratification, In this paper I would like to offer a distinction between recognition, profit, comfort, fun—so why should what seems to me three fundamentally different kinds of philosophers be different? Why shouldn’t they, too, join philosophical practice that are based on three different the market economy and sell what they have to offer to visions of the nature of philosophising. Through this those willing to pay? classification I will characterise a vision of philosophical practice that is close to my heart, which I feel is important My answer is that I don’t see anything wrong with helping and inspiring, but which is, unfortunately, often neglected. people feel better, on the contrary. But doing so is not really philosophy in the original, deep sense of the word. The Problem-Solving Approach It is no longer philo-sophia—a search inspired by a I think that in the eyes of many practitioners nowadays, yearning for wisdom, but rather a process dictated by the the main goal of philosophical practice is to help counselees client’s desire for comfort or security or satisfaction.
    [Show full text]
  • Averroes's Dialectic of Enlightenment
    59 AVERROES'S DIALECTIC OF ENLIGHTENMENT. SOME DIFFICULTIES IN THE CONCEPT OF REASON Hubert Dethier A. The Unity ofthe Intellect This theory of Averroes is to be combated during the Middle ages as one of the greatest heresies (cft. Thomas's De unitate intellectus contra Averroystas); it was active with the revolutionary Baptists and Thomas M"Unzer (as Pinkstergeest "hoch liber alIen Zerstreuungen der Geschlechter und des Glaubens" 64), but also in the "AufkHinmg". It remains unclear on quite a few points 65. As far as the different phases of the epistemological process is concerned, Averroes reputes Avicenna's innovation: the vis estimativa, as being unaristotelian, and returns to the traditional three levels: senses, imagination and cognition. As far as the actual abstraction process is concerned, one can distinguish the following elements with Avicenna. 1. The intelligible fonns (intentiones in the Latin translation) are present in aptitude and in imaginative capacity, that is, in the sensory images which are present there; 2. The fonns are actualised by the working of the Active Intellect (the lowest celestial sphere), that works in analogy to light ; 3. The intelligible fonns-in-act are "received" by the "possible" or the "material intellecf', which thereby changes into intellect-in-act, also called: habitual or acquired intellect: the. perfect form ofwhich - when all scientific knowledge that can be acquired, has been acquired -is called speculative intellect. 4. According to the Aristotelian principle that the epistemological process and knowing itselfcoincide, the state ofintellect-in-act implies - certainly as speculative intellect - the conjunction with the Active Intellect. 64 Cited by Ernst Bloch, Avicenna und die Aristotelische Linke, (1953), in Suhrkamp, Gesamtausgabe, 7, p.
    [Show full text]
  • Engadin ENGLISH EDITION MAGAZINE N MAGIC O
    ENGLISH Engadin MAGAZINE No . 3 W I N T E R –––––– 2 0 / 2 1 MAGIC ENGLISH EDITION 2 3 Engadin Winter — 20/21 Dear guests, Ideally we would like to magic you straight over to our valley, Germany but unfortunately we are not able to do that just yet. Instead, you can come to us along a World Heritage railway line of fairy-tale charm, Austria or travel over the bewitching snow-covered mountains with your own SWITZERLAND France GRAUBÜNDEN sleigh. We’re waiting for you: with sparkling powder snow, all kinds of gastronomic wizardry and the purest ice in the world. ENGADIN Italy We wish you happy reading and a good journey – and we look forward to welcoming you here soon! The people of the Engadin Lej da Segl Lej m m m m m m Cover photograph by Filip Zuan Filip by photograph Cover m m m m m Piz Bernina, 4,049 Bernina, Piz Piz Palü, 3,905 Palü, Piz Piz Scerscen, 3,971 Scerscen, Piz 3,937 Roseg, Piz m Map: Rohweder Piz Cambrena, 3,604 Cambrena, Piz Piz Tremoggla, 3,441 Tremoggla, Piz Piz Fora, 3,363 Fora, Piz m m m Piz Lagalb, 2,959 Lagalb, Piz Diavolezza, Diavolezza, 2,978 Piz Led, 3,088 Led, Piz Piz Corvatsch, 3,451 Corvatsch, Piz Diavolezza 3,433 Murtèl, Piz m Lago Bianco Lagalb Piz Lavirun, 3,058 Lavirun, Piz Val Forno Italy Punta Casana, 3,007 Casana, Punta Val Fex Corvatsch Punta Saliente, 3,048 Saliente, Punta Bernina Pass Surlej, 3,188 Piz Val Fedoz Maloja Pass Val Roseg MALOJA Swiss National Park Lej da Silvaplauna SILS SURLEJ ST.
    [Show full text]
  • Nietzsche and Eternal Recurrence: Methods, Archives, History, and Genesis
    University of South Florida Scholar Commons Graduate Theses and Dissertations Graduate School April 2021 Nietzsche and Eternal Recurrence: Methods, Archives, History, and Genesis William A. B. Parkhurst University of South Florida Follow this and additional works at: https://scholarcommons.usf.edu/etd Part of the Philosophy Commons Scholar Commons Citation Parkhurst, William A. B., "Nietzsche and Eternal Recurrence: Methods, Archives, History, and Genesis" (2021). Graduate Theses and Dissertations. https://scholarcommons.usf.edu/etd/8839 This Dissertation is brought to you for free and open access by the Graduate School at Scholar Commons. It has been accepted for inclusion in Graduate Theses and Dissertations by an authorized administrator of Scholar Commons. For more information, please contact [email protected]. Nietzsche and Eternal Recurrence: Methods, Archives, History, and Genesis by William A. B. Parkhurst A dissertation submitted in partial fulfillment of the requirement for the Doctor of Philosophy in Philosophy Department of Philosophy College of Arts and Sciences University of South Florida Major Professor: Joshua Rayman, Ph.D. Lee Braver, Ph.D. Vanessa Lemm, Ph.D. Alex Levine, Ph.D. Date of Approval: February 16th, 2021 Keywords: Fredrich Nietzsche, Eternal Recurrence, History of Philosophy, Continental Philosophy Copyright © 2021, William A. B. Parkhurst Dedication I dedicate this dissertation to my mother, Carol Hyatt Parkhurst (RIP), who always believed in my education even when I did not. I am also deeply grateful for the support of my father, Peter Parkhurst, whose support in varying avenues of life was unwavering. I am also deeply grateful to April Dawn Smith. It was only with her help wandering around library basements that I first found genetic forms of diplomatic transcription.
    [Show full text]
  • Reading Plato (After Nietzsche & Co.) DAVID FARRELL KRELL Depaul
    Plato Nietzsche & Reading (After Co.) DAVID FARRELL KRELL DePaul University Just for the record: Socrates stands so close to me that I am almost always fighting a battle with him. Friedrich Nietzsche, 1875 ["However, I believe that Plato was sick"]. Plato, Phaedo 59b10 Nietzsche and Plato: a frightful confrontation. From the many discussions of Plato in Nietzsche's works-there are well over five hundred direct references-we learn that Nietzsche viewed his life's task as overcoming Platonism. And, all reservations and qualifications aside, we know that Plato had something to do with Platonism. If the history of Western philosophy is a series of footnotes to Plato, if philosophy itself consists of variations on the theme of Platonism, then Nietzsche wants to write the last variation, the one that will exhaust all remaining possibilities for Platonism and bring philosophy as such to a close. It seems we can read sympathetically either Plato or Nietzsche, but not both: read Plato alone, and rest assured that Nietzsche is a dogmatist of the nastiest sort, more destructive even than Thrasymachus or Callicles; read Nietzsche alone, and rest assured that Plato is a decadent of the most contemptible sort, and a charlatan besides. Nietzsche calls him "a grand Cagliostro." Reading Plato after Nietzsche: is that possible at all?' It would not be too much to say that every indictment in the Nietzschean oeuvre of otherworldly metaphysics, morals, religion, and art directly involves Plato and Platonism. Philosophers are people who 46 want to hurry up and die, we read in Phaedo, so that they can float up to the ethereal realm of the pure ideas; to this end they despise the body and preach crusades against it, and lending death a hand, they mortify the flesh; they invent a God as anemic as themselves and invest their wretched hopes in him, dreaming heavenly dreams; even their music is lugubrious and bathetic, their dance a kind of solemn mummery.
    [Show full text]
  • The Practical Origins of Ideas
    The Practical Origins of Ideas Genealogy as Conceptual Reverse-Engineering MATTHIEU QUELOZ Under contract with Oxford University Press Abstract Why did such highly abstract ideas as truth, knowledge, or justice become so important to us? What was the practical point of coming to think in these terms? This book uncovers, develops, and defends a philosophical method that aims to answer such questions. This is the method of pragmatic genealogy: the telling of developmental narratives that seek to make sense of ideas in terms of their practical origins. Two principal theses structure the book. The first is that there is a pragmatic genealogical tradition which cuts across the analytic-continental divide, a tradition running from the state-of-nature stories of David Hume and the early genealogies of Friedrich Nietzsche to more recent work in analytic philosophy by Edward Craig, Bernard Williams, and Miranda Fricker. However, these genealogies combine fictionalising and historicising in ways that even those sympathetic to genealogy have found puzzling. Hence the book’s second, systematic thesis: we understand why both the fictionalising and the historicising are called for if we interpret these genealogies as dynamic models serving to reverse-engineer the points of ideas in relation to generic and socio-historically local needs. Pragmatic genealogy then emerges as having two attractive features. Far from issuing in the kind of reductively instrumental view of things often associated with naturalism, pragmatism, and genealogy, the method offers us explanation without reduction, helping us understand what led our ideas to shed the traces of their practical origins. And far from being normatively inert in the way that genealogical explanations are commonly taken to be, pragmatic genealogy can affect the space of reasons by helping us determine whether and when our ideas are worth having.
    [Show full text]
  • Stephen Pepper's World Hypotheses: Season 1, Episode 1 Welcome To
    Stephen Pepper’s World Hypotheses: Season 1, Episode 1 Welcome to the first episode of the Stephen Pepper thread. The focus of this post is World Hypotheses, Chapters 1-4. My reflections today are largely confined to definitional matters, but I also hope to set the stage for an examination (in my next post) of Pepper’s “root metaphor” theory. Perhaps the clearest path into Pepper’s thought is to consider the place where most of us began our intellectual journey: common sense. For Pepper, common sense includes “the sorts of things we think of when we ordinarily read the papers…or the sort of things we see and hear and smell and feel as we walK along the street or in the country…” (p. 39). Pepper considers common sense as a loose synonym for Plato’s notion of “opinion” (p. 39). I’m also reminded of the “natural attitude” described by phenomenologists. For Pepper, the world of common sense can be characterized as “secure” in the sense that it is “never lacking” – i.e., we can always fall back on it: • “No cognition can sink lower than common sense, for when we completely give up trying to Know anything, then is precisely when we Know things in the common-sense way. In that lies the security of common sense” (p. 43). But, in spite of its security, common sense is also “cognitively irritable”: • “The materials of common sense are changing, unchanging, contradictory, vague, rigid, muddled, melodramatically clear, unorganized, rationalized, dogmatic, shrewdly dubious, recKlessly dubious, piously felt, playfully enjoyed, and so forth.
    [Show full text]
  • Recent Ice Trends in Swiss Mountain Lakes: 20-Year Analysis of MODIS Imagery
    Noname manuscript No. (will be inserted by the editor) Recent Ice Trends in Swiss Mountain Lakes: 20-year Analysis of MODIS Imagery Manu Tom 1,2,3 · Tianyu Wu 1 · Emmanuel Baltsavias 1 · Konrad Schindler 1 Received: date / Accepted: date Abstract Depleting lake ice can serve as an indicator products. We find a change in Complete Freeze Dura- for climate change, just like sea level rise or glacial re- tion of -0.76 and -0.89 days per annum for lakes Sils and treat. Several Lake Ice Phenological (LIP) events serve Silvaplana, respectively. Furthermore, we observe plau- as sentinels to understand the regional and global cli- sible correlations of the LIP trends with climate data mate change. Hence, it is useful to monitor long-term measured at nearby meteorological stations. We notice lake freezing and thawing patterns. In this paper we re- that mean winter air temperature has negative correla- port a case study for the Oberengadin region of Switzer- tion with the freeze duration and break-up events, and land, where there are several small- and medium-sized positive correlation with the freeze-up events. Addition- mountain lakes. We observe the LIP events, such as ally, we observe strong negative correlation of sunshine freeze-up, break-up and ice cover duration, across two during the winter months with the freeze duration and decades (2000-2020) from optical satellite images. We break-up events. analyse time-series of MODIS imagery by estimating spatially resolved maps of lake ice for these Alpine Keywords lake ice monitoring · machine learning · lakes with supervised machine learning (and addition- semantic segmentation · satellite image processing · ally cross-check with VIIRS data when available).
    [Show full text]
  • The 'New' Heidegger
    Fordham University Masthead Logo DigitalResearch@Fordham Articles and Chapters in Academic Book Philosophy Collections 1-2015 The ‘New’ Heidegger Babette Babich [email protected] Follow this and additional works at: https://fordham.bepress.com/phil_babich Part of the Continental Philosophy Commons, Digital Humanities Commons, Ethics and Political Philosophy Commons, Other German Language and Literature Commons, Physical Sciences and Mathematics Commons, Radio Commons, and the Reading and Language Commons Recommended Citation Babich, Babette, "The ‘New’ Heidegger" (2015). Articles and Chapters in Academic Book Collections. 65. https://fordham.bepress.com/phil_babich/65 This Article is brought to you for free and open access by the Philosophy at DigitalResearch@Fordham. It has been accepted for inclusion in Articles and Chapters in Academic Book Collections by an authorized administrator of DigitalResearch@Fordham. For more information, please contact [email protected]. Chapter 10 The ‘New’ Heidegger Babette Babich 10.1 Calculating Heidegger: From the Old to the New The ‘new’ Heidegger corresponds less to what would or could be the Heidegger of the moment on some imagined ‘cutting edge’ than it corresponds to what some wish they had in Heidegger and above all in philosophical discussions of Heidegger’s thought. We have moved, we suppose, beyond grappling with the Heidegger of Being and Time . And we also tend to suppose a fairly regular recurrence of scandal—the current instantiation infl amed by the recent publication of Heidegger’s private, philosophical, Tagebücher, invokes what the editor of these recently published ‘black notebooks’ attempts to distinguish as Heidegger’s ‘historial antisemitism’ — ‘historial’ here serving to identify Heidegger’s references to World Jewry in one of the volumes.
    [Show full text]
  • The Rationality Postulate in Economics: Its Ambiguity, Its Deficiency and Its Evolutionary Alternative
    Walter Eucken Institut ORDO Constitutio in Libertate The Rationality Postulate in Economics: Its Ambiguity, its Deficiency and its Evolutionary Alternative Viktor J. Vanberg 03/3 Freiburger Diskussionspapiere zur Ordnungsökonomik Freiburg Discussion Papers on Constitutional Economics Institut für Allgemeine Wirtschaftsforschung Abteilung für Wirtschaftspolitik Albert-Ludwigs-Universität Freiburg i. Br. ISSN 1437-1510 The Rationality Postulate in Economics: Its Ambiguity, its Deficiency and its Evolutionary Alternative Viktor J. Vanberg 03/3 Albert-Ludwigs-Universität Freiburg und Walter Eucken Institut, Freiburg [email protected] Freiburger Diskussionspapiere zur Ordnungsökonomik Freiburg Discussionpapers on Constitutional Economics 03/3 ISSN 1437-1510 Walter Eucken Institut, Goethestr. 10, D-79100 Freiburg i. Br. Tel.Nr.: +49 +761 / 79097 0; Fax.Nr.: +49 +761 / 79097 97 http://www.walter-eucken-institut.de Institut für Allgemeine Wirtschaftsforschung; Abteilung für Wirtschaftspolitik; Albert-Ludwigs-Universität Freiburg, D-79085 Freiburg i. Br. Tel.Nr.: +49 +761 / 203 2317; Fax.Nr.: +49 +761 / 203 2322 http://www.vwl.uni-freiburg.de/fakultaet/wipo/ The Rationality Postulate in Economics: Its Ambiguity, its ∗ Deficiency and its Evolutionary Alternative by Viktor J. Vanberg Albert-Ludwigs-Universität Freiburg Wirtschafts- und Verhaltenswissenschaftliche Fakultät Abteilung Wirtschaftspolitik und Walter Eucken Institut 1. Introduction 2. Rationality Principle vs. Rationality Hypotheses 3. Gary S. Becker’s Economic Approach to Human Behavior: Rationality Principle or Rationality Hypothesis? 4. The ‘Economic Approach’ Between Rationality Principle and Rationality Hypotheses 5. An Evolutionary Alternative to the Rational Choice Paradigm 6. J.H. Holland’s Theory of Rule-Based Adaptive Agents 7. Rationality and Markets 8. Conclusion Abstract: Though the rationality postulate is generally considered the paradigmatic core of economics, there is little agreement about its specific content and methodological status.
    [Show full text]