Classical Methods for the Modern Lawyer

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Classical Methods for the Modern Lawyer CLASSICAL METHODS FOR THE MODERN LAWYER: THE INTERPLAY BETWEEN ETHICS, MORALITY AND EFFICACY IN THE TRANSACTIONAL CONTEXT Gerald T. Nowak, P.C. PRACTISING LAW INSTITUTE: DRAFTING AND NEGOTIATING CORPORATE AGREEMENTS 2011 Chicago, Illinois -- February 10, 2011 K&E 14501746.2 Gerald T. ("Jerry") Nowak is a corporate partner in the Chicago office of Kirkland & Ellis LLP. He has a broad transactional practice, including capital markets transactions, M&A transactions and corporate governance matters. His capital markets practice focuses on complex securities matters, including initial public offerings, high yield offerings, spin-offs, tender offers and investment grade debt offerings. His M&A practice includes public and private acquisitions for private equity funds and public companies. He holds a B.A. from Michigan State University, an M.B.A from Auburn University and a J.D. from the University of Michigan Law School, none of which are in philosophy. ii K&E 14501746.2 I. INTRODUCTION A. Ethics, Morality and Efficacy As lawyers, we are bound by a code of ethics that regulates both what we do and how we do it. There are any number of technical rules that govern a lawyer’s behavior, from rules limiting lawyer advertising to rules regulating conflicts of interest, and, apropos to this article, rules regulating how we conduct ourselves in transactional negotiations. Much of the substance of the ethical rules can be summed up by the Cub Scout’s exhortation to “do your best” and “tell the truth.” The rules that govern a lawyer’s behavior are commonly referred to as “legal ethics” or the “ethical rules.” This nomenclature can be confusing to those of us who, prior to being taught otherwise, tended to conflate “ethics” with “morality.” At least in the legal arena, the two bear only a passing resemblance to one another. The ethical rules require a minimum standard of conduct that, as we will see, is not particularly demanding. The precise definitions of ethics and morality are well beyond the scope of this article. Nevertheless, a brief discussion of ethics and morality will be useful both as a counterpoint to the ultimate conclusion of this article and as a measure of just how far the ethical rules fall short of what most consider ethical or moral behavior. I will use Aristotle’s Nichomachean Ethics and West Point’s honor code as reference points for what it means to be “ethical” in the classical sense of the word. I will also discuss the advantages of using the techniques of classical rhetoric in the corporate transactional context. Through that discussion, I will argue for why and how holding oneself to a higher standard of truthfulness is actually both in a lawyer’s self interest and in the client’s self interest. Ultimately, being seen as an honest negotiator is advantageous both to you as a lawyer and to your client, and thus is both desirable in its own right and entirely consistent with the goal of being an effective negotiator for your client. 1 K&E 14501746.2 B. Legal Ethics As stated above, a transactional lawyer’s ethical obligations basically come down to two guiding principles: first, do a good job for your client, and second, refrain from lying in doing so. In the words of the ABA’s model rules of professional conduct, “[a]s [a] negotiator, a lawyer seeks a result advantageous to the client but consistent with requirements of honest dealings with others.” In that regard, there are a couple of specific rules that apply: First, we should be competent: “Rule 1.1 Competence. A lawyer shall provide competent representation to a client. Competent representation requires the legal knowledge, skill, thoroughness and preparation reasonably necessary for the representation.” And second, we should tell the truth: “Rule 4.1 Truthfulness In Statements To Others. In the course of representing a client a lawyer shall not knowingly: (a) make a false statement of material fact or law to a third person; or (b) fail to disclose a material fact to a third person when disclosure is necessary to avoid assisting a criminal or fraudulent act by a client… .” This rule has been expounded upon by the ABA in the context of the transactional lawyer: “ABA Formal Opinion 06-439. [S]tatements regarding a party’s negotiating goals …, as well as statements that can fairly be characterized as ‘puffing,’ are ordinarily not considered ‘false statements of material fact’… .” While the Cub Scout’s oath to “do your best” translates pretty well into Rule 1.1, it is doubtful that many pack leaders are instructing their scouts in the nuances of Rule 4.1. To begin, note that the rule only prohibits false statements of material fact or law. Immaterial falsehoods appear to be permitted, albeit not encouraged. But more tellingly, note the prohibition on omissions. Omissions are only prohibited where the failure to make a disclosure is necessary to avoid assisting a client in a criminal or fraudulent act. As a moral code, this rule fails the red face test. But consider it in context. As lawyers, we are an agent for the client. Rule 4.1 tells us at a minimum what we must do and what we can’t do regardless of our client’s interests. We need to dig a little deeper to understand how we should behave when there are multiple ethically permissible choices available. 2 K&E 14501746.2 C. Ethics and Morality Ethics and morality are not synonyms. Not only are they not the same thing, but the terms themselves have different meanings to different people. Over history, there have been any number of definitions of ethics or ethical codes. As one notable example, in his Nichomachean Ethics, Aristotle postulated that the goal of ethics was to achieve the highest end, which to him was human happiness. All activities were but a means to that end. Happiness was achieved by living in accordance with appropriate virtues, including courage, justice, temperance, modesty and truthfulness. Each of these virtues was not, as is common in modern discourse, at the opposite end of the spectrum from its correlative vice. Rather, each occupied the middle ground, or mean, between two extremes, neither of which were desirable. So, for example, in the realm of fear and confidence, courage is the appropriate mean between rash action and cowardice. Similarly, truthfulness is the appropriate mean between boastfulness and understatement. Note that ethical conduct, at least to Aristotle, bears only a passing resemblance to what many would call “morality.” It is more like Jeremy Bentham’s philosophy of “utilitarianism,” which in fact owed much to Aristotle’s worldview. In some contexts, the notion of ethical behavior takes on heroic proportions. In the military, particularly at military academies, people are expected to comport to a rigorous honor code that generally prohibits all forms of dishonesty. West Point’s formulation of the honor code is representative in that regard: “A Cadet will not lie, cheat, or steal, nor tolerate those who do.” As in all things military, there are rules and regulations that back up that simple statement, but without diluting the rigor of the basic rule. So, for example, under West Point’s honor code, “lying” is defined as deliberately deceiving another by stating an untruth or by any direct form of communication, including the telling of a partial truth and the vague or ambiguous use of information or language with the intent to deceive or mislead. Compare that to ABA’s Rule 4.1. Similarly, “tolerating” is defined as failing to report an unresolved incident with honor implications to proper authority within a reasonable length of time. Unyielding in its ethical simplicity. 3 K&E 14501746.2 At the end of the day, morality is one of those terms that everyone uses, everyone knows what they mean when they say it, but in fact has no unambiguous definition. According to Merriam-Webster (paraphrased), “Morality” is a doctrine or system of behavior relating to principles of right and wrong or sanctioned by or operative on one's conscience or ethical judgment. This definition, of course, begs the question of what is “right” and what is “wrong”? That question is often profoundly difficult, as in, for example, the case where you have one too many persons riding in a sinking lifeboat. But in this context, the question is not that difficult. It is virtually always, regardless of what code you live by, morally right to be forthright and honest and morally wrong to be dishonest or duplicitous. The question is not whether it is right to be honest, but whether it is smart. Is it advantageous to us as lawyers and to our clients to be honest and forthright? That is where classical rhetoric comes in. D. Classical Rhetoric What is “rhetoric”? Put simply, rhetoric is the art of persuasion, deconstructed and analyzed for maximum effect. It formed the basis of an elite education in classical Greece and Rome and for centuries was an important part of any advanced liberal education in western Europe and the United States. Aristotle wrote what is still the defining treatise on rhetoric. Cicero studied and practiced rhetoric at the highest level. The Founding Fathers were highly schooled in rhetorical principles. Rhetoric has a long and distinguished pedigree. Somewhere along the way, rhetoric as a field of study came into disfavor -- think of the phrases “empty rhetoric” (useless at best, misleading at worst) and “rhetorical question” (a useless question that does not merit an answer). To the ancients, rhetoric did not carry a connotation of “emptiness.” The ancients, including Aristotle, Cicero and others whose names are not typically associated with vacuity of any kind, recognized that there is value in consensual agreement, and that the alternative is often either a deadweight loss associated with failing to reach agreement, or worse (in the political sphere) the imposition by force of what could not be agreed by rhetorical persuasion.
Recommended publications
  • Critical Inquiry As Virtuous Truth-Telling: Implications of Phronesis and Parrhesia ______
    ______________________________________________________________________________ Critical Inquiry as Virtuous Truth-Telling: Implications of Phronesis and Parrhesia ______________________________________________________________________________ Austin Pickup, Aurora University Abstract This article examines critical inquiry and truth-telling from the perspective of two comple- mentary theoretical frameworks. First, Aristotelian phronesis, or practical wisdom, offers a framework for truth that is oriented toward ethical deliberation while recognizing the contingency of practical application. Second, Foucauldian parrhesia calls for an engaged sense of truth-telling that requires risk from the inquirer while grounding truth in the com- plexity of human discourse. Taken together, phronesis and parrhesia orient inquirers to- ward intentional truth-telling practices that resist simplistic renderings of criticality and overly technical understandings of research. This article argues that truly critical inquiry must spring from the perspectives of phronesis and parrhesia, providing research projects that aim at virtuous truth-telling over technical veracity with the hope of contributing to ethical discourse and social praxis. Keywords: phronesis, praxis, parrhesia, critical inquiry, truth-telling Introduction The theme of this special issue considers the nature of critical inquiry, specifically methodological work that remains committed to explicit goals of social justice and the good. One of the central concerns of this issue is that critical studies have lost much of their meaning due to a proliferation of the term critical in educational scholarship. As noted in the introduction to this issue, much contemporary work in education research that claims to be critical may be so in name only, offering but methodological techniques to engage in critical work; techniques that are incapable of inter- vening in both the epistemological and ontological formations of normative practices in education.
    [Show full text]
  • Phronesis, Artifacts and Leadership Practice
    Phronesis, Artifacts and Leadership Practice Richard Halverson University of Wisconsin - Madison Abstract This paper develops Aristotle’s idea of phronesis, or practical wisdom, as a framework to access, represent and communicate the complexity of successful instructional leadership practice in schools. The design and use of artifacts, the tools leaders develop and implement in their practice, provide a window into the patterns of problem-setting and problem-solving that guide the expression of phronesis in school leadership. Introduction It has long been recognized that where you find good schools, you also often find the legacy of strong leadership. Prior research has defined many of the characteristics of schools with strong instructional programs, such as professional community grounded in instruction among teachers and leaders, a shared sense of instructional vision, group ownership of the instructional process and links between supervisory, assessment and instructional practices. 1 School leaders are responsible for the design and maintenance of these essential conditions in existing school systems.2 However, while we know quite a bit about the characteristics of such school communities, we know quite a bit less about how these characteristics develop together to become distinctive features of the school community. A strong professional community among teachers, for example, can either presuppose or help create group ownership of instructional process, which in turn may Submitted for publication: Please to not cite without the author’s permission 1 2 depend upon or generate the need for stronger internal linkages between assessment and instruction. The implementation and coordination of these conditions is an important aspect of improving student learning in schools.3 Accessing how school leaders understand and manage schools calls for a new approach to understanding the leadership practice.
    [Show full text]
  • Book Review F
    Book Review F. J. Mootz III and G. H. Taylor, eds. Gadamer and Ricoeur: Critical Horizons for Contemporary Hermeneutics (New York/London: Continuum, 2011), 297 pp. Marc-Antoine Vallée EHESS (Paris) Études Ricœuriennes / Ricœur Studies, Vol 3, No 2 (2012), pp. 171-173 ISSN 2155-1162 (online) DOI 10.5195/errs.2012.153 http://ricoeur.pitt.edu This work is licensed under a Creative Commons Attribution-Noncommercial-No Derivative Works 3.0 United States License. This journal is published by the University Library System of the University of Pittsburgh as part of its D-Scribe Digital Publishing Program, and is cosponsored by the University of Pittsburgh Press. Book Review F. J. Mootz III and G. H. Taylor, eds. Gadamer and Ricoeur: Critical Horizons for Contemporary Hermeneutics (New York/London: Continuum, 2011), 297 pp. Five years ago, it was totally impossible to find a book entirely dedicated to a systematic study of the complex relations between the hermeneutics of Gadamer and Ricoeur. This was quite surprising if we consider the importance of these two philosophers to the development of a hermeneutical philosophy over the last century. Fortunately, it seems that the relevance of a critical discussion on Gadamer’s and Ricoeur’s hermeneutics has recently become more obvious, first with the publication of Daniel Frey’s book on L’interprétation et la lecture chez Ricoeur et Gadamer (2008), and now with this initiative of Francis J. Mootz III and George H. Taylor to bring into conversation "Gadamerian and Ricoeurian scholars" in one volume. The result of this well- inspired idea is a book containing twelve chapters studying, from different perspectives, the agreements and disagreements between Gadamer’s and Ricoeur’s philosophies, not without significant convergences and divergences between the authors.
    [Show full text]
  • Management Education from Episteme to Phronesis: the Contribution of French Didactic Theory Corinne Hahn, Christophe Vignon
    Management education from episteme to phronesis: The contribution of French didactic theory Corinne Hahn, Christophe Vignon To cite this version: Corinne Hahn, Christophe Vignon. Management education from episteme to phronesis: The contribu- tion of French didactic theory. Management Learning, SAGE Publications, 2019, 50 (3), pp.337-354. 10.1177/1350507619831118. halshs-02068936 HAL Id: halshs-02068936 https://halshs.archives-ouvertes.fr/halshs-02068936 Submitted on 25 Apr 2019 HAL is a multi-disciplinary open access L’archive ouverte pluridisciplinaire HAL, est archive for the deposit and dissemination of sci- destinée au dépôt et à la diffusion de documents entific research documents, whether they are pub- scientifiques de niveau recherche, publiés ou non, lished or not. The documents may come from émanant des établissements d’enseignement et de teaching and research institutions in France or recherche français ou étrangers, des laboratoires abroad, or from public or private research centers. publics ou privés. Management education from episteme to phronesis: The contribution of French didactic theory Corinne Hahn ESCP Europe Christophe Vignon University of Rennes 1, France Abstract In this article, we review some of the criticisms levelled at current management education provided by business schools and the recommendations made by critical management studies scholars. These authors generally recommend placing greater emphasis on phronesis, that is, the manager’s practical wisdom. We investigated this path and formulated a practical solution, rooted in the operational framework provided by French didactic theory. It takes the form of a specific pedagogical device, the aim of which is to foster closer connections between experience acquired in professional settings and theoretical knowledge derived from management sciences.
    [Show full text]
  • International Journal of Action Research Volume 5, Issue 1, 2009
    International Journal of Action Research Volume 5, Issue 1, 2009 Editorial Werner Fricke, Øyvind Pålshaugen 5 Popular Education and Participatory Research: Facing Inequalities in Latin America Danilo R. Streck 13 Organizing – A Strategic Option for Trade Union Renewal? Klaus Dörre, Hajo Holst, Oliver Nachtwey 33 Phronesis as the Sense of the Event Ole Fogh Kirkeby 68 Opening to the World through the Lived Body: Relating Theory and Practice in Organisation Consulting Robert Farrands 114 Book review Olav Eikeland (2008): The Ways of Aristotle. Aristotelian phrónêsis, Aristotelian Philosophy of Dialogue, and Action Research reviewed by Ole Fogh Kirkeby 144 Phronesis as the Sense of the Event Ole Fogh Kirkeby In this article, the Greek concept of phronesis is analyzed on the basis of its philosophical roots, and the indispensability of its strong normative content is emphasized. This creates a distance to most of the recent under- standing of phronesis as prudence, and hence as practical wisdom with a pragmatic and strategic content. The strong dilemmas created by the nor- mative background of real phronesis present management and leadership as a choice in every situation. From this foundation, phronesis is inter- preted as primarily the sense of the event, and an alternative concept of the event is developed. The presentation of the event also demands a theory of the relation of mind and matter, and hence of the body in the event. This is achieved under inspiration from Stoic philosophy. With this in mind, the more serious approaches to practical wisdom: phronesis as determinant of meta-concepts of research; phronesis as a liberating organizational strategy of learning; phronesis as a strategy of knowledge management; phronesis as a narrative strategy; and phronesis as the capacity of the leader, are presented and analyzed.
    [Show full text]
  • May 2021 PAULA LOUISE GOTTLIEB Department of Philosophy 5185 Helen C
    May 2021 PAULA LOUISE GOTTLIEB Department of Philosophy 5185 Helen C. White Hall 600 North Park Street University of Wisconsin-Madison Madison, Wisconsin 53706 (608) 263 0253 (office) (608) 265 3701 (fax) [email protected] (e-mail) gottlieb.philosophy.wisc.edu (web site) Present Position: Full Professor of Philosophy and Affiliate Professor of Classical and Near Eastern Studies Education: St. Hilda’s College, Oxford University, England 1977-83: B.A. Hons. in Literae Humaniores (Ancient Greek and Latin Literature; Philosophy and Ancient Greek and Roman History) 1981 B.Phil. in Philosophy (Moral and Political Philosophy, Philosophical Logic and Aristotle) 1983 M.A. 1986 Cornell University 1983-88: M.A. in Philosophy 1986 Ph.D. in Philosophy 1988 Areas of Specialization: Ancient Greek Philosophy; Ethics B.Phil. Thesis: “Some Problems of Akrasia in Aristotle and Modern Writers” Main Supervisor: M. J. Woods; also Susan Hurley Doctoral Dissertation: “Aristotle and the Measure of All Things” Committee: T. H. Irwin (main supervisor), Gail Fine, David Lyons and Sydney Shoemaker Employment: Assistant Professor, University of Wisconsin-Madison, Fall 1988-Spring 1994 Associate Professor, University of Wisconsin-Madison, Summer 1994-Fall 1999 Full Professor, University of Wisconsin-Madison, from Fall 1999 1 Honors and Awards: Oxford: Open Exhibition, 1977-81 Christina Keith Travel Prize (awarded by the college), 1979 Postgraduate College Scholarship, 1981-83 Cornell: Sage Graduate Fellowship, 1983-84 Martin McVoy Trust Fellowship, 1987-88 Messenger-Chalmers prize for “the doctoral dissertation giving evidence of the best research and most fruitful thought” in the Humanities (University-wide, Cornell University, 1989) Honorable mention in the Guilford Prize for the best-written dissertation (University- wide, Cornell University, 1989) University nomination for a National Endowment for the Humanities summer stipend, 1991.
    [Show full text]
  • An Aristotelian Interpretation of Practical Wisdom: the Case of Retirees
    University of Wollongong Research Online Faculty of Business - Papers Faculty of Business January 2019 An Aristotelian interpretation of practical wisdom: the case of retirees Peter R. Massingham University of Wollongong, [email protected] Follow this and additional works at: https://ro.uow.edu.au/buspapers Recommended Citation Massingham, Peter R., "An Aristotelian interpretation of practical wisdom: the case of retirees" (2019). Faculty of Business - Papers. 1640. https://ro.uow.edu.au/buspapers/1640 Research Online is the open access institutional repository for the University of Wollongong. For further information contact the UOW Library: [email protected] An Aristotelian interpretation of practical wisdom: the case of retirees Abstract This paper aims to improve understanding of the concept of practical wisdom. The theoretical lens used is Aristotle's practical rationality or 'phronesis'. Researchers argue that practical wisdom should be used as an organising framework for professional knowledge. Aristotle believed that practical wisdom as the highest intellectual virtue. Phronesis is the complicated interactions between general (theory) and practical (judgement). The contribution of this paper is to discuss the properties of practical wisdom and how they interact based on an interpretation of retirees' knowledge. The paper summarises in-depth face- to-face interviews with nine retirees, i.e., nine separate case studies. A structured interview guideline based on a conceptual framework derived from literature was used to examine the nature of retirees' practical wisdom. People with wisdom make better decisions. Whereas episteme's technical knowledge may address complicated tasks, techne's wisdom enables people to resolve truly complex tasks. Techne provides personal judgement which enables the professional to judge their actions from an external and internal perspective.
    [Show full text]
  • Aristotle's Phronesis: Putting Some Meat on The
    ARISTOTLE’S PHRONESIS: PUTTING SOME MEAT ON THE PHILOSOPHY OF INNOVATION Gabriel J. Costello 1. Introduction Dante in the Divine Comedy describes his encounter with Aristotle as follows: “I saw the master sage of those who know” Inferno Canto IV, 131 (Dante, 1984 translation) . Dante considered Aristotle as epitomizing the pinnacle of human reason and his references to Aristotle came second only to that of the Bible. Without doubt, Aristotle is one of the most influential thinkers in the history of western civilisation. His works have covered an eclectic range of subjects such as logic ethics, metaphysics, politics, natural science and physics (ODE, 2006). Aristotle’s science was not superseded until the scientific revolution of the 16th and 17th centuries (ODS, 1999). Crithcley (2001) points out that among other things, ancient philosophy endeavoured to amalgamate knowledge and wisdom: “namely, that knowledge of how things were the way they were would lead to wisdom in the conduct of one’s life. The assumption that ties knowledge and wisdom together is the idea that the cosmos as such expresses a human purpose. This is called the “teleological view of the universe” (p. 7). This paper will focus on Aristotle’s ethical writings, especially examining his synthesis of the ideas of knowledge and wisdom and their application in practice. This he achieved through the concept of phronesis (phronēsis) variously described as practical wisdom. Taylor (2005) explains phronesis as having, in ancient Greece, connotations of intelligence and soundness of judgement. In his deliberations on ethics, Aristotle used the term to represent the complete excellence of the practical intellect.
    [Show full text]
  • Krisanna M. Scheiter
    Krisanna M. Scheiter 308 Lamont Building | Union College | 807 Union Street | Schenectady, NY 12308 Email: [email protected] | Phone: (518) 388-6380 Website: http://muse.union.edu/scheitek/ Current and Past Positions 2012-Present Assistant Professor of Philosophy, Union College 2014-2015 John D. MacArthur Assistant Professorship, Union College 2010- 2012 Fay Sawyier Predoctoral Fellow, Illinois Institute of Technology Areas of Specialization Ancient Philosophy, Philosophy of Emotion Areas of Competence Moral Psychology, Early Modern Philosophy Education 2005-2012 PhD Philosophy, University of Pennsylvania Dissertation: Emotion, Imagination, and Feeling in Aristotle Committee: Susan Sauvé Meyer (supervisor), Charles Kahn, Gary Hatfield, Elisabeth Camp Abstract: I argue that the emotions, for Aristotle, belong to the faculty of imagination (phantasia) and are best described as pleasurable or painful images (phantasmata). As such, an emotion is a cognivitive appraisal of something as good or bad, without reaching the level of intellect (nous) and so without requiring belief (doxa). 2003-2005 MA Philosophy, University of Missouri-St. Louis Thesis: Aristotle’s Active Intellect and the Primary Mover Committee: Jon McGinnis (supervisor), James Buickerood, Eric Wiland 1999-2002 BA English, University of Missouri-St. Louis, cum laude 1 Awards and Fellowships March 11, 2015 Loeb Classical Library Foundation Fellowship (2015-2016) (Award: $35,000) “The Loeb Classical Library Foundation awards fellowships to qualified scholars to support research,
    [Show full text]
  • 1 CURRICULUM VITAE Michael J. White Fall, 2011 Academic Addresses Sandra Day O'connor College of Law Box 877906 Arizona State
    CURRICULUM VITAE Michael J. White Fall, 2011 Academic Addresses Sandra Day O’Connor College of Law Box 877906 Arizona State University Tempe, Arizona 85287-7906, USA and. School of Life Sciences Box 874501 Tempe, Arizona 85287-4501, USA Telephones: law (480) 965-0105; SoLS (480) 965-0219 Fax numbers: law (480) 965-2427 E-mail: [email protected] Education B.A. Anthropology, Arizona State University, 1970 M.A. Philosophy, University of California, San Diego, 1972 C.Phil. Philosophy, University of California, San Diego, 1973 Ph.D. Philosophy, University of California, San Diego, 1974 Academic Appointments, Fellowships, and Grants Teaching Assistant, Philosophy Department, University of California San Diego, 1971-1974 Assistant Professor of Philosophy, Arizona State University, 1974-1979 Visiting Assistant Professor of Philosophy, University of Texas at Austin, 1976-1977 Associate Professor of Philosophy, Arizona State University, 1979-1985 Visiting Associate Professor of Philosophy, University of Arizona, Fall, 1981 Professor of Philosophy, Arizona State University, 1985-present Fellow, National Humanities Center, 1988-1989 National Science Foundation Grant, “The Archaeology of Non-Archimedean Analysis,” 1997-1998 Professor of Law, Arizona State University, 2004-present Visiting Professor, University of Arizona, Spring 2009 1 Teaching Areas Ancient Philosophy, Science, and Mathematics Jurisprudence, Historical Jurisprudence, Social-Political Philosophy Formal Logic, including Modal and Tense Logic; Model Theory History and Philosophy of Mathematics and Physical Science History of Renaissance and Modern Philosophy, through Eighteenth Century Publications Books: Political Philosophy: A Historical Perspective. [Forthcoming: this will be revised edition of the Oneworld volume, listed immediately below, which is now out of print.] Oxford and New York: Oxford University Press, Fall 2011 or Spring 2012.
    [Show full text]
  • Aristotelian Phronesis As a Key Factor for Leadership in the Knowledge-Creating Company According to Ikujiro Nonaka* Germán Scalzo** Guillermo Fariñas***
    ARISTOTELIAN PHRONESIS AS A KEY FACTOR FOR LEADERSHIP IN THE KNOWLEDGE-CREATING COMPANY ACCORDING TO IKUJIRO NONAKA* Germán Scalzo** Guillermo Fariñas*** * doi: 10.11144/Javeriana.cao31-57.apkfl. Reflection paper. Received: 28/04/2018 and accepted: 14/11/2018. Cite as: Scalzo, G., & Fariñas, G. (2018). Aristotelian phronesis as a key factor for leadership in the knowledge-creating company according to Ikujiro Nonaka. Cuadernos de Administración, 31(57), 19-44. http://dx.doi.org/10.11144/Javeriana.cao31-57.apkfl. ** Universidad Panamericana, Mexico. E-mail: [email protected] *** Universidad Monteávila, Venezuela. E-mail: [email protected] Cuad. admon.ser.organ. Bogotá (Colombia), 31 (57): 19-44, julio-diciembre de 2018 | issn 0120-3592 / e-issn 1900-7205 19 Germán Scalzo, Guillermo Fariñas Aristotelian phronesis ABSTRACT. In the last decades, there has been an increasing interest on knowledge as a key factor for in the business realm. Japanese scholar Ikujiro Nonaka was among the main theoretical and practical contributors to knowledge creation in organizations, leadership in the as well as a promoter of including practical reason in the research of business knowledge-creating topics such as decision-making, knowledge management, ethics and leadership. company according to In his theory, a Western classical tradition, namely the virtue of phronesis, is Ikujiro Nonaka combined with the Japanese notion of Ba (context-based learning), to explain the way people engage in communities of practice as opportunities for learning. This paper describes his theory of knowledge creation, pointing to phronetic leadership skills as essential drivers of knowledge creation in organizations, in light of the Western classical tradition.
    [Show full text]
  • Judging in the Public Realm
    JUDGING IN THE PUBLIC REALM A Kantian Approach to the Deliberative Concept of Ethico-Political Judgment and an Inquiry into Public Discourse on Prenatal Diagnosis Cornelis Dekker Linköping Studies in Arts and Science, No. 466 Department of Technology and Social Change, Linköping University Linköping 2009 Linköping Studies in Arts and Science • No 466 At the Faculty of Arts and Science at Linköpings universitet, research and doctoral studies are carried out within broad problem areas. Research is organized in interdisciplinary research environments and doctoral studies mainly in graduate schools. Jointly, they publish the series Linköping Studies in Arts and Science. This thesis comes from the Department of Technology and Social Change at the Tema Institute. Distributed by : Department of Technology and Social Change Linköping University SE- 581 83 Linköping, Sweden http://www.tema.liu.se/tema-t/ Edition 1:1 ISBN: 978-91-7393-739-9 ISSN: 0282-9800 © Cornelis Dekker Print: Liu Tryck. Linköping 2009. Cover design: Tomas Hägg CONTENTS 1. PUBLIC DELIBERATION AND ETHICO-POLITICAL JUDGMENT 9 1.1 An inquiry into public deliberation 10 1.2 The deliberative concept of ethico-political judgment 17 1.3 Outline 30 Φ PART 1 THE IDEAL OF ETHICO-POLITICAL JUDGMENT: HOW TO DELIBERATE 2. JUSTIFYING JUDGINGS 33 2.1 Kantian normative reasons 34 2.2 Intersubjectivity from Kant to Habermas 49 2.3 The unforced force of normative reasons 62 3. THE CAPACITY TO JUDGE 69 3.1 Arendt on the power of judgment 69 3.2 ‘Enlarged thought’ and the law 87 3.3 Impartiality of judgment and the other 98 4.
    [Show full text]