From Newton to Hawking: a History of Cambridge University’S Lucasian Professors of Mathematics Edited by Kevin C

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

From Newton to Hawking: a History of Cambridge University’S Lucasian Professors of Mathematics Edited by Kevin C Cambridge University Press 978-0-521-66310-6 - From Newton to Hawking: A History of Cambridge University’s Lucasian Professors of Mathematics Edited by Kevin C. Knox and Richard Noakes Index More information Index aberration, stellar 309, 352–5 analysis, mathematical 13, 27–8, 245, acoustics 3, 442, 453 249–53, 256, 258–61, 266, 279, 288, Adams Prize 355, 438 304–5, 394, 414 Addison, Joseph 162 ‘Analytical Revolution’ 233–6, 249–50 aerodynamics 3, 442 Analytical Society 35, 233–6, 249–50, aesthetics, in mathematics 38, 412, 414–17 258–61, 270, 287 Aether and Matter 355, 363, 369–73 Anglicanism 86–8, 100–4, 196–8, 221–34, æther 246–7, 8 and British tradition 308–9, 361 Anne, Queen 151, 153 and earth’s motion 40, 309, 352–9, 373, antiparticles 395–6, 399, 418 375–8, 380 Arago, Dominique-Franc¸ois-Jean, and and force 367–72 electromagnetism 251, 265, 276, 285 and matter 40, 92, 309, 349–60, 371, Arianism see also Newton and Whiston 377–8, 381 85–6, 102–4, 119–21, 136, 148–55 and unification of physics 362–9, 380–1 Aristotle 10, 104–5 theories of 22–3, 37, 274, 282, 308–9, 344, artificial intelligence 36, 243, 259–62, 267, 349–73, 375–83 272, 278, 285–6, 453–7 Agnesi, Donna Maria Gaetana 16, 199 artisanal skill 242–3, 267 agnosticism 316 astronomical observatories 246, 256, 262–3, Airy, George Biddell 1, 4, 14, 29, 36, 246–9, 276, 288 251–7, 261–2, 264–7, 270–7, 285, 287, Astronomical Society 245, 249, 259, 263, 266 298–9 astronomy and Babbage 247–8, 251, 268, 270–1, 275, in Cambridge curriculum 9, 250, 297–8 277, 284, 287 observational 16, 247, 258, 276, 288, and Lucasian chair 246–7, 257, 268, 270–5 297–8, 436 and machine semiotics 265, 267 atheism 285–7 and machines 246–7, 265–6 Atiyah, Michael 440 and mathematical analysis 266 atomic physics 329, 347, 382, 390–1, 394 and mathematical teaching 266, 272–4 atomic weapons 410–11 and observatory management 272–3, attraction see gravity 275–6, 288 Atwood, George 226 and optical researches 2–3, 264, 274 Atwood’s machine 15, 19, 223, 266 and treadmills 272–3, 288 and Whewell 248, 254, 261, 266, 275, 282 Babbage, Charles 1, 4, 6, 9, 16, 20, 28, 35–6, as Astronomer Royal 246–7, 287 210, 234–5, 241–89, 302, 304, 323, 451, education and early career 253–4, 257 457 Airy’s criterion 2 and Airy 6, 247–8, 251, 268, 270–1, 275, alchemy 87–92, 119, 123 277, 284 algebraic analysis see analysis, mathematical and calculating engines 1, 6, 19, 36, 241–3, Allin, Richard 157 248, 259–60, 262, 266, 271, 276, 278–9, Ampere,` Andre-Marie´ 251, 265 281, 285, 287, 457 © Cambridge University Press www.cambridge.org Cambridge University Press 978-0-521-66310-6 - From Newton to Hawking: A History of Cambridge University’s Lucasian Professors of Mathematics Edited by Kevin C. Knox and Richard Noakes Index More information 476 index and factory system 36, 242–3, 248, 267–8, Bohr, Niels 329, 387, 390, 394, 399–400, 278–82, 286 419 and Herschel 234–5, 241–2, 257–8, 279 Boldero, Edward 60 and Lucasian chair 4, 6, 242–7, 252, 256, Born, Max 41, 391 268, 270–2, 277–83, 304, 452 Boswell, William 48–9, 190 and machinery 36, 242–3, 251, 253, 259, Boyle, Robert 74–5, 90, 147 265, 270, 280–2, 285, 287 Bradley, James 179 and mathematical analysis 6, 28, 231–4, Brewster, David 278, 283 249–50, 253, 256, 258–9, 266–7, 276, Bridgewater Treatises 22, 282, 285 278–9, 281, 284–5 Brief History of Time A 40, 433, 445–6, 452 and mental mechanisms 36, 243, 251, 259, Briggs, Henry 48, 54 262, 267, 272, 278, 285–6 Bristol College 299–300 and machine semiotics 36, 259, 265–8, 272 Bristol University 391, 398 and politics 30, 243, 282 British Association for the Advancement of and religion 19, 22, 231–4, 285–6 Science 278, 287, 320, 323, 350, 363, and tours 241–2, 251, 265, 268, 271, 277, 368 281, 285, 287 Bromhead, Edward 259, 261, 269–70 and Whewell 248, 253, 260, 282–6 Brougham, Henry 324–5 early career 245, 256–7 Brouncker, Lord William 62 Babington, Humphrey 73, 113 Browning, Bishop Ralph 60 Banks, Joseph 217 Bruce, Jacob 191 Barrow, Isaac 25, 27, 29, 31, 49–63, 79–83, Buck, Thomas 49–50, 56, 62, 465–6, 470 145–6, 171, 175–6, 252, 277, 463, 470 Burke, Edmund 179, 189–90 and mathematics 53–4, 56–60 Burnet, Thomas 19–20, 96–8 and Newton 61–3 Byron, Lady see Lovelace, Lady Ada Augusta and publishing 63–5 and Royalist sympathies 53 calculating engine, Babbage’s 36, 241–3, 248, education of 50–3 259–60, 266, 271, 276, 278–9, 285–8, 457 Geometrical Lectures 60 calculus, Newtonian 79–80, 83, 89, 194–200, Mathematical Lectures 64 209, 219, 230–7, 245, 249–51, 260–1 optical lectures of 60, 63–5, 80–1 Cambridge Centre of Mathematical Studies religious commitments 61–2, 64 17 Barrow’s Proof 2 Cambridge City Council 451 Batchelor, George 426, 440 Cambridge Philosophical Society 256, 259, Belfast Academical Institution 345–6 261–2, 265, 267, 298–9 Bentley, Richard 18, 118, 140–1, 149, 175–6, Cambridge University 222 Acts 253, 255 Berkeley, Bishop George 196–7, 228 and endowments 257, 452 biblical exegesis 147–51, 315–16 and women 15–16, 331–2 Big Bang 21, 38, 396, 412, 436, 439, 444, 449 colleges 10–11, 16, 174–5, 245–8, 250, ‘big science’ 16, 396, 437, 442 262–3, 268–70, 283, 285, 288 Biographia Britannica 177 curriculum 8–12, 15, 174–5, 179–85, Biot, Jean-Baptiste 251, 252, 258–9 196–9, 218–31, 245, 247, 250, 254, black holes 436–40 260–1, 266, 287–8, 297–9, 304–5, 331, Blake, William 32 333–4 Board of Longitude 246, 252, 259, 266, 275, Elizabethan 9 278 examinations 10–11, 249–50, 253–6, body, the 23–6, 227–8, 316–18, 404, 425–34, 260–1, 279, 283–4, 297–8, 300, 302–5, 449–56 307, 314 Bohm, David 411, 420 experimental and theoretical physics 393 © Cambridge University Press www.cambridge.org Cambridge University Press 978-0-521-66310-6 - From Newton to Hawking: A History of Cambridge University’s Lucasian Professors of Mathematics Edited by Kevin C. Knox and Richard Noakes Index More information index 477 mathematical traditions 35, 245–58, Colson, Nathaniel 191 268–88, 304–5, 314, 331, 349, 357, comets 4, 18, 33, 98–100, 105, 110, 139–40, 360–1, 372, 381, 383, 397–8 155–7 mixed mathematics 249, 256, 262 communism, and British science 408, 411, religion at 9, 112–8, 148–55, 196–8, 420 222–35, 245–8, 252, 255–6, 268, 287, complementarity 400 300, 315, 322 computers see also artificial intelligence and Cambridge University Library 5, 455, 467 calculating engines 1, 40–1, 430–1, 448, Cambridge University Observatory 246, 256, 451–6 262–3, 265, 276 Concorde 442 Carlyle, Thomas 6 conditional immortality 316–17, 334 cathode rays 326, 329 Conduitt, John 73 Catholicism 27, 100–4, 112–14, 119–22, contraction hypothesis 353–8, 362, 376–8 412–13, 444–5 Cooper, Samuel 226 Catton, Thomas 263, 276 Copenhagen interpretation 400, 419–20 Cauchy, Augstin 250, 259–60 cosmology see also Newton and Cavendish Laboratory 16–17, 288, 314, 329, Newtonianism 396–7, 403, 408–9, 331, 334, 347, 382, 393 412–13, 418, 435–40, 442 celestial mechanics 78, 92–100, 104–12, 125, Cotes, Roger 145, 162–3, 182–3, 185 222, 246, 260–1, 263–4, 266, 285 Creation, the see also Creationism 96–9 centrifugal force see force Creationism 37, 318–19, 322, 412, 444–5, 447 centripetal force see force Cromwell, Oliver 53 Challis, James 301–2, 307–8, 312 Crookes, William 325–6 Charles II 461, 470 Crucial experiment, Newton’s see Charterhouse school 117 experimentum crucis chemistry 39, 87–92, 119, 123, 217–18, 224, Cubitt, William 265, 272–3 325, 421 Cumberland, Duke of (William) 194 Christ’s College, Cambridge 223 Cunningham, Ebenezer 382 Church of England see Anglicanism curriculum see Cambridge University, Civil War, English 19, 27, 49, 53 curriculum Clarke, Samuel 148, 153, 221 current, electric 350–2 Classical Tripos 255, 298, 305 Cygnus X-1 437 Clement, Joseph 267, 277, 279 Clinton, Bill 431, 448 d’Alembert, Jean le Rond 206, 215, 220 coaching system 12, 253–5, 288, 302, 357 Darwin, Charles Robert 22, 286, 316, 327–8, Colby, Thomas 262, 270 333 Cole, William 190 Darwinism 22, 36–7, 318–23 Coleridge, Samuel Taylor 231 Davies, Richard 184 colleges see Cambridge University colleges Davy, Humphry 217 Collins, John 57, 59–65, 79–82, 87 de Broglie, Louis 391 Colson, John 21, 29, 34, 171–200, 216, 220 deduction, philosophical 247, 255, 261, 274, and Bishop Berkeley 197–8 285–6 education of 191–2 de Duillier, Nicholas Fatio 117–18, 123, 160 Historical, Critical and Etymological de Moivre, Abraham 118 Dictionary of the Bible 193–4 De Morgan, Augustus 228–9, 237, 286 Lady’s System of Analyticks 199 De Quincey, Thomas 214 mathematical work 194–200 Dee, John 45 Method of Fluxions 194–8 Defoe, Daniel 160 translations by 193–4, 198–9 Department of Applied Mathematics and Colson, John Sr 190–1 Theoretical Physics 17, 405, 430 © Cambridge University Press www.cambridge.org Cambridge University Press 978-0-521-66310-6 - From Newton to Hawking: A History of Cambridge University’s Lucasian Professors of Mathematics Edited by Kevin C.
Recommended publications
  • Dossier Pierre Duhem Pierre Duhem's Philosophy and History of Science
    Transversal: International Journal for the Historiography of Science , 2 (201 7) 03 -06 ISSN 2526 -2270 www.historiographyofscience.org © The Author s 201 7 — This is an open access article Dossier Pierre Duhem Pierre Duhem’s Philos ophy and History of Science Introduction Fábio Rodrigo Leite 1 Jean-François Stoffel 2 DOI: http://dx.doi.org/10.24117/2526-2270.2017.i2.02 _____________________________________________________________________________ We are pleased to present in this issue a tribute to the thought of Pierre Duhem, on the occasion of the centenary of his death that occurred in 2016. Among articles and book reviews, the dossier contains 14 contributions of scholars from different places across the world, from Europe (Belgium, Greece, Italy, Portugal and Sweden) to the Americas (Brazil, Canada, Mexico and the United States). And this is something that attests to the increasing scope of influence exerted by the French physicist, philosopher and 3 historian. It is quite true that since his passing, Duhem has been remembered in the writings of many of those who knew him directly. However, with very few exceptions (Manville et al. 1927), the comments devoted to him exhibited clear biographical and hagiographic characteristics of a generalist nature (see Jordan 1917; Picard 1921; Mentré 1922a; 1922b; Humbert 1932; Pierre-Duhem 1936; Ocagne et al. 1937). From the 1950s onwards, when the studies on his philosophical work resumed, the thought of the Professor from Bordeaux acquired an irrevocable importance, so that references to La théorie physique: Son objet et sa structure became a common place in the literature of the area. As we know, this recovery was a consequence of the prominence attributed, firstly, to the notorious Duhem-Quine thesis in the English- speaking world, and secondly to the sparse and biased comments made by Popper that generated an avalanche of revaluations of the Popperian “instrumentalist interpretation”.
    [Show full text]
  • One of the Most Celebrated Physics Experiments of the 20Th Cent
    Not Only Because of Theory: Dyson, Eddington and the Competing Myths of the 1919 Eclipse Expedition Introduction One of the most celebrated physics experiments of the 20th century, a century of many great breakthroughs in physics, took place on May 29th, 1919 in two remote equatorial locations. One was the town of Sobral in northern Brazil, the other the island of Principe off the west coast of Africa. The experiment in question concerned the problem of whether light rays are deflected by gravitational forces, and took the form of astrometric observations of the positions of stars near the Sun during a total solar eclipse. The expedition to observe the eclipse proved to be one of those infrequent, but recurring, moments when astronomical observations have overthrown the foundations of physics. In this case it helped replace Newton’s Law of Gravity with Einstein’s theory of General Relativity as the generally accepted fundamental theory of gravity. It also became, almost immediately, one of those uncommon occasions when a scientific endeavor captures and holds the attention of the public throughout the world. In recent decades, however, questions have been raised about possible bias and poor judgment in the analysis of the data taken on that famous day. It has been alleged that the best known astronomer involved in the expedition, Arthur Stanley Eddington, was so sure beforehand that the results would vindicate Einstein’s theory that, for unjustifiable reasons, he threw out some of the data which did not agree with his preconceptions. This story, that there was something scientifically fishy about one of the most famous examples of an experimentum crucis in the history of science, has now become well known, both amongst scientists and laypeople interested in science.
    [Show full text]
  • Constructing Natural Historical Facts BACONIAN NATURAL HISTORY in NEWTON’S FIRST PAPER on LIGHT and COLORS
    OUP UNCORRECTED PROOF – FIRSTPROOFS, Mon Feb 10 2014, NEWGEN 2 Constructing Natural Historical Facts BACONIAN NATURAL HISTORY IN NEWTON’S FIRST PAPER ON LIGHT AND COLORS Dana Jalobeanu* The peculiar structure of Newton’s first published paper on light and colors has been the subject of an astonishing diversity of readings: to date, scholars still do not agree as to what Newton wanted to prove in this paper or how he proved it.1 The structure of the paper is far from transparent. It consists of two very different parts: a historical account of what Newton called his “crucial experiment,” and a “doctrine of colors” consisting of thirteen propositions and an illustrative experiment. Equally debated has been the “style” of Newton’s demonstration.2 Newton begins the first part with an extensive his- torical account of how he became interested in the “celebrated phenomena of colors” and later reached one of its major results: that the shape of the spectrum refracted * Research for this paper has been supported by the grant PN-II-ID-PCE-2011-3-0719, “From Natural History to Science,” awarded by the CNCS. 1 The paper has been read, in turns, as a formal blunder of a young upstart who dared to make a clear break with the mitigated skepticism and anti-dogmatism of the Royal Society, and as a brilliant exercise of rhetoric aiming to rewrite in the “scientific style of the day” the results of six long years of optical research. The reason for the exercise of rhetoric has also been the subject of fierce debates.
    [Show full text]
  • Alchemy Is One of the Great Losers in the Historiography of Science
    1 ©William R. Newman (Copyrighted Preprint: To Appear in Lumière et vision dans les sciences et dans les arts, de l'Antiquité du XVIIe siècle, Danielle Jacquart and Michel Hochmann, editors, Librairie Droz.) Newton’s Early Optical Theory and its Debt to Chymistry William R. Newman Indiana University ©William R. Newman 2 ©William R. Newman Newton’s Early Optical Theory and its Debt to Chymistry Introduction In the years immediately preceding Isaac Newton’s experimental demonstration that sunlight is actually a composition of heterogeneous spectral rays rather than being perfectly homogeneous, a sophisticated methodology based on the analysis and resynthesis of gross matter had decisively shown that chemical compounds were also made up of heterogeneous components. Although modern scholars tend to associate the experimental approach of seventeenth-century corpuscular matter theory with mechanical philosophers such as Pierre Gassendi and Robert Boyle, an extensive alchemical tradition extending from the High Middle Ages up to Boyle’s immediate predecessors had long used the analytic retrievability of the constituents of compounds to argue for the permanence of the ingredients that went into them. Boyle, in particular, was the direct heir of this lengthy alchemical tradition, especially in his use of the atomistic writings of the Wittenberg medical professor Daniel Sennert. It is a well known fact that the young Newton was heavily influenced by Boyle, but no one up to now has argued in detail for a transfer from Boyle’s work on “chymical” analysis and synthesis to the optical analyses and syntheses that formed the bases of Newton’s early optical work.1 Elsewhere I have argued that alchemical experimentation helped to bring a decisive end to traditional 3 ©William R.
    [Show full text]
  • Discovery of Acceleration of the Universe As an Experimentum Crucis
    Experimentum crucis Accelerating evolution of the Universe Summary Discovery of acceleration of the Universe as an experimentum crucis Marek Szyd lowski Pawe l Tambor Adam Krawiec Department of Theoretical Physics, Catholic University of Lublin M. Kac Complex Systems Research Center Institute of Economics and Management, Jagiellonian University 6th ECAP, 2008 Krak´ow, 22 August 2008 Experimentum crucis Accelerating evolution of the Universe Summary Outline 1 Experimentum crucis 2 Accelerating evolution of the Universe 3 Summary Experimentum crucis Accelerating evolution of the Universe Summary Experimentum crusis Isaac Newton first used the term experimentum crucis in his Opticks (1704). In sciences, an experimentum crucis, or critical experiment, is an experiment capable of decisively determining whether or not a particular hypothesis or theory is correct. In particular, such an experiment must typically be able to produce a predictable result that no established hypothesis or theory is capable of producing. Experimentum crucis Accelerating evolution of the Universe Summary Experimentum crucis Important remark of John Stuart Mill: Experimentum crucis consists of not only one but at least three. In the cosmological context the different astronomical observations are used together: SNIa, CMB, baryon oscillation peak, gravitational lensing. Lakatos distinguished in his concept of research programmes the ‘minor crucial experiments’ and ‘major crucial experiments’. The former is applied within the research programme (series of theories with the common hard core) while the latter is applied to competing research programmes. Experimentum crucis Accelerating evolution of the Universe Summary Experimentum crucis (Such, 1975) There are two practical approaches to conduct the experimentum crucis: In the framework of given theory we try to explain the occurring anomaly where new hypothesis explains it.
    [Show full text]
  • The Short History of Science
    PHYSICS FOUNDATIONS SOCIETY THE FINNISH SOCIETY FOR NATURAL PHILOSOPHY PHYSICS FOUNDATIONS SOCIETY THE FINNISH SOCIETY FOR www.physicsfoundations.org NATURAL PHILOSOPHY www.lfs.fi Dr. Suntola’s “The Short History of Science” shows fascinating competence in its constructively critical in-depth exploration of the long path that the pioneers of metaphysics and empirical science have followed in building up our present understanding of physical reality. The book is made unique by the author’s perspective. He reflects the historical path to his Dynamic Universe theory that opens an unparalleled perspective to a deeper understanding of the harmony in nature – to click the pieces of the puzzle into their places. The book opens a unique possibility for the reader to make his own evaluation of the postulates behind our present understanding of reality. – Tarja Kallio-Tamminen, PhD, theoretical philosophy, MSc, high energy physics The book gives an exceptionally interesting perspective on the history of science and the development paths that have led to our scientific picture of physical reality. As a philosophical question, the reader may conclude how much the development has been directed by coincidences, and whether the picture of reality would have been different if another path had been chosen. – Heikki Sipilä, PhD, nuclear physics Would other routes have been chosen, if all modern experiments had been available to the early scientists? This is an excellent book for a guided scientific tour challenging the reader to an in-depth consideration of the choices made. – Ari Lehto, PhD, physics Tuomo Suntola, PhD in Electron Physics at Helsinki University of Technology (1971).
    [Show full text]
  • History Syndrome OR Popperian Credentials of Geology PS MOHARIR
    Proc. Indian Acad. Sci. (Earth Planet. Sci.), Vol. 102, No. 2, June 1993,. pp. 283-305. Printed in India. History syndrome OR Popperian credentials of Geology P S MOHARIR National Geophysical Research Institute, Uppal Road, Hyderabad 500 007 India. MS received 12 June 1991; revised 28 December 1992 Abstract. Earth-science is greatly concerned with history. It is argued by some that a historical discipline is not a science. This is contrary to the conclusion from the demarcation criteria of Popper, set to separate science from formal disciplines such as metaphysics, mathematics and logic. Others have spoken of the unity of all sciences. Classification of intellectual activities is based on oenus proximum and differentia specifica. Hence the two viewpoints can be readily reconciled. Earth-science has been criticized variously for being descriptive, inductive, explanatory, etc. Other historical and concrete sciences have also attracted similar adverse comments. These issues are discussed at length to argue that Popper's work should be extended further to define a demarcation of science into immanent and historical. It is also argued that the rignur of cognitive and logical determinants of science is not an adequate reason to embrace sociological models of science. Further, sociological/logical models of science present a misleading dichotomy. Keywords. Demarcation criteria; historical sciences; Kuhnian model; mathematicalization; earth-science revolution. 1. Introduction The purpose of this paper is to discuss whether geology can be a science. Science is a modern catchword. Therefore, everyone is bound to argue that his discipline is science and then proceed to define it. Most such definitions are territorial.
    [Show full text]
  • Annual Report 2003 3
    PL0401646 INSTYTUT PROBLEMÓW JĄDROWYCH im. Andrzeja Sołtana THE ANDRZEJ SOŁTAN INSTITUTE FOR NUCLEAR STUDIES INSTYTUT PROBLEMOW J&DROWYCH im. Andrzeja Soltana The Andrzej Softan INSTITUTE FOR NUCLEAR STUDIES INIS-PL- 0007 ANNUAL REPORT PL-05-400 OTWOCK-8WIERK, POLAND tel.: 048 22 718 0 83 fax: 048 22 779 34 1 e-mail: sinsipj.gov.pi http:Hwww.ipj.gov.pi Editors: D. Chmielewska E. Infeld Z. Preibisz P. ?upraftki Secretarial work and layout: A. Odziemczyk K. Traczyk Cover design G. Karczmarczyk Printed by Zakfad Graficzny UW, zam. 280/2004 ISSN 1232-5309 Annual Report 2003 3 CONTENTS 1. GENERAL INFORMATION 7 1- MANAGEMENT OF THE INSTITUTE 7 2. SCIENTIFIC COUNCIL 8 3. DEPARTMENTS OF THE INSTITUTE I 0 4. SCIENTIFIC STAFF OF THE INSTITUTE 5 . V IS IT IN G SC IE N T IST S ....................................................................................................... 13 6. GRANTS 15 7. DEGREES 18 8. CONFERENCES AND WORKSHOPS ORGANIZED BY IPJ ........................................... 1 8 11. REPORTS ON RESEARCH BY DEPARTMENT 19 1 NUCLEAR REACTIONS I 9 2. NUCLEAR SPECTROSCOPY AND TECHNIQUE ............................................................ 35 3. DETECTORS AND NUCLEAR ELECTRONICS ............................................................... 55 4. RADIATION SHIELDING AND DOSIMETRY ................................................................. 69 5. PLASMA PHYSICS AND TECHNOLOGY ........................................................................ 79 6. H IG H EN E R G Y PH Y SIC S ..................................................................................................
    [Show full text]
  • Robert Finlay, 'Weaving the Rainbow: Visions of Color in World History'
    Weaving the Rainbow: Visions of Color in World History robert finlay University of Arkansas udwig Wittgenstein wrote his last work, Remarks on Colour, during a visit to Vienna in 1950 and while dying of cancer in Cambridge theL following year. The slim book represented a return to a theme of his earliest writings, for he had dealt with the thorny problem of the logi- cal structure of color concepts in Tractatus Philosophico-Mathematicus (1908).1 Remarks on Colour sets forth a broad range of what Wittgen- stein called “puzzle questions”: Why is white not considered a color? What makes bright colors bright? Are “pure” colors mere abstractions, never found in reality? What is the relationship between the world of objects and the world of consciousness? Is there such a thing as a “natural history of color”? Faced with more conundrums than answers, Wittgenstein despaired that the logic of color perceptions could be clarifi ed: “there is merely an inability to bring the concepts into some kind of order. We stand there like the ox in front of the newly-painted stall door.” 2 Wittgenstein’s refl ections on color took place upon a fault line divid- ing the followers of Isaac Newton (1642–1727) from those of Johann Wolfgang von Goethe (1749–1832). Wittgenstein remarked that he found Newtonian questions interesting but not gripping, and although 1 Ray Monk, Ludwig Wittgenstein: The Duty of Genius (New York: Free Press, 1990), pp. 561–568; J. Westphal, Colour: Some Philosophical Problems from Wittgenstein (Oxford: Basil Blackwell, 1984), pp. 6–7, 11. 2 Ludwig Wittgenstein, Remarks on Colour, ed.
    [Show full text]
  • A History of Science, V1
    A History of Science, V1 Henry Smith Williams A History of Science, V1 Table of Contents A History of Science, V1.....................................................................................................................................1 Henry Smith Williams.............................................................................................................................1 VOLUME I. THE BEGINNINGS OF SCIENCE...................................................................................1 BOOK I.................................................................................................................................................................1 I. PREHISTORIC SCIENCE...................................................................................................................2 II. EGYPTIAN SCIENCE.......................................................................................................................9 III. SCIENCE OF BABYLONIA AND ASSYRIA..............................................................................19 IV. THE DEVELOPMENT OF THE ALPHABET..............................................................................30 V. THE BEGINNINGS OF GREEK SCIENCE...................................................................................36 VI. THE EARLY GREEK PHILOSOPHERS IN ITALY...................................................................38 VII. GREEK SCIENCE IN THE EARLY ATTIC PERIOD...............................................................48 VIII. POST−SOCRATIC SCIENCE
    [Show full text]
  • Newton's Experimentum Crucis from a Constructivist Point of View
    Humboldt University of Berlin Philosophy Term Paper Winter Term 2008/09 Newton’s Experimentum Crucis from a Constructivist Point of View Author: Philipp Kanschik Supervisor: Prof. Dr. Olaf Müller Student No.: 522919 Institute for Philosophy Address: Jonasstraße 28 Humboldt University 12053 Berlin of Berlin Germany Phone: 0049 30 29045786 E-mail: [email protected] Date of completion: April 3rd, 2009 Table of Content 1. Introduction: Science and Reality 4 2. Simon Schaffer's Constructivist Approach 7 2.1 Realism and Constructivism 7 2.2 Leviathan and the Air-Pump 10 3. Facts and Theory in Newton's Letter from 1672 17 3.1 Facts 17 3.2 Theory 20 3.3 What Does the Experimentum Crucis Prove? 21 4. Newton's Experimentum Crucis from a Constructivist 25 Point of View 4.1 Evaluating Experimental Matters of Fact 25 4.2 Material Technology: Prisms as an Experimental 27 Instrument 4.3 Literary Technology: Newton's Overconfidence 31 4.4 Social Technology: Newton's Authority 35 5. Conclusion and Outlook: What Schaffer Should 40 Have Done Appendix 43 References 46 2 I, Philipp Kanschik, hereby declare this work to be my own, that I have acknowledged all the sources I have consulted in the paper itself and not only in the bibliography, that all wording unaccompanied by a reference is my own, and that no part of this essay can be found on the internet. I acknowledge that this paper has not been handed in at another university in order to obtain an academic degree. Signature 3 1. Introduction: Science and Reality Being skeptical about reality has become easy.
    [Show full text]
  • David Hume Has Been Largely Read As a Philosopher but Not As a Scientist
    THE VERA CAUSA PRINCIPLE IN 18 TH CENTURY MORAL PSYCHOLOGY 1 FERNANDO MORETT David Hume has been largely read as a philosopher but not as a scientist. In this article I discuss his work exclusively as a case of science; in particular as a case of early modern science. I compare the moral psychology of self-interest, sympathy and sentiments of humanity he argues for with the moral psychology of universal self-interest from Bernard Mandeville, presenting the controversy between the two as a case of theory choice. David Hume, Adam Smith and Francis Hutcheson regarded the psychology of self-interest advanced by Thomas Hobbes and Bernard Mandeville as the rival theory to be defeated; it was a theory making ‘so much noise in the world’, Smith reports 2. Hume positively praises Mandeville’s theory in the first pages of the Treatise . This volume pays more attention to self-interest than An Enquiry Concerning the Principles of Morals, in which Hume discusses the disinterested passions of humanity and benevolence in more detail. Both Hume and Smith were highly critical of Mandeville’s theory, which they considered to be ‘malignant’ and ‘wholly pernicious’ because it leaves no grounds for ‘feelings sympathy and humanity’. They actually allude to Mandeville with epithets such as ‘sportive sceptic’ and ‘superficial reasoner’, whose reasoning is ‘ingenious sophistry’. 3 Hume strongly criticises the self-interested individuals described by Mandeville who are ‘monsters’ ‘unconcerned, either for the public good of a community or the private utility of others’ 4; they are replicas of Ebenezer Scrooge who even at Christmas shows no humanity, no concern for others.
    [Show full text]