“Der Versuch Als Vermittler” Versus Newton's Experimentum Crucis

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

“Der Versuch Als Vermittler” Versus Newton's Experimentum Crucis The Nature of Light and Color: Goethe’s “Der Versuch als Vermittler” versus Newton’s Experimentum Crucis James A. Marcum Baylor University In the seventeenth century, Newton published his famous experimentum crucis, in which he claimed that light is heterogeneous and is composed of rays with different refrangibilities. Experiments, especially the crucial experi- ment, were important for justifying Newton’s theory of light, and eventually his theory of color. A century later, Goethe conducted a series of experiments on the nature of color, especially in contradistinction to Newton, and he de- fended his research with a methodological principle formulated in “Der Versuch als Vermittler.” Goethe’s principle included two elements: a series of experiments and resultant higher empirical evidence, which functioned as me- diator between the objective (a natural phenomenon) and the subjective (a theory or hypothesis). Although the notion of experimentum crucis became popular among scientists for reconstructing experimental research and for jus- tifying theories, especially for rhetorical purposes, Newton’s justiªcation of his theory of light and color is best reconstructed in terms of Goethe’s method- ological principle. Finally, Goethe’s principle has important consequences for the contemporary philosophical underdetermination thesis. 1. Introduction In the seventeenth century Isaac Newton conducted experiments to determine the nature of sunlight, especially as it relates to colored I thank Ernst Hamm for drawing my attention to Goethe’s “Der Versuch als Vermittler” essay and Jed Buchwald, William Cowling, Francesco Guala, Robert Iliffe, Clark Muenzer, Den- nis Sepper, Alan Shapiro, Friedrich Steinle, Friedel Weinert, and Gábor Zemplén, for their stimulating discussion and insightful comments on earlier manuscript drafts. Baylor Uni- versity supported my research through sabbatical funding. A shorter version of this paper was presented at the First Conference in Integrated History and Philosophy of Science, Centre for Philosophy of Science, University of Pittsburgh, Pittsburgh, PA, October 11– 14, 2007, and may be found at: http://philsci-archive.pitt.edu/archive/00003602/01/ Marcum-&hps_ms.doc. Perspectives on Science 2009, vol. 17, no. 4 ©2009 by The Massachusetts Institute of Technology 457 Downloaded from http://www.mitpressjournals.org/doi/pdf/10.1162/posc.2009.17.4.457 by guest on 27 September 2021 458 The Nature of Light and Color rays.1 These experiments were reported in a letter read, in Newton’s ab- sence, at the Royal Society in London and published in its Philosophical Transactions. According to Newton, sunlight is composed of a “Heteroge- neous mixture of differently refrangible Rays” (1671/2, p. 3079). The theory, he claimed, is established on a single experiment, an experimentum crucis, in which Newton refracted sunlight with a prism into a color spectrum— each colored ray with a speciªc refrangibility, or angle of refraction. With a second prism, he demonstrated that each refracted ray of the color spec- trum is dispersed to the same degree as with the ªrst prism. Based on the crucial experiment, Newton distinguished his theory of light, as well as his theory of color, from competing theories—e.g. the notion of light as rotating globules, as championed by René Descartes. And the notion of crucial experiment formed, at that time, an important component of Newton’s experimental philosophy (Sabra [1967] 1981; Sepper 1994). In the eighteenth century, in a critique of Newton’s theory of light and color based on the experimentum crucis, Johann Wolfgang von Goethe claimed that Newton’s theory is an artiªcial construct of the human intel- lect and, as such, is not derived from nature itself. Speciªcally, he argued that Newton’s experiments—especially the experimentum crucis—represent an artiªcial step and not a natural one, in examining nature. The result of Newton’s artiªcial method, argued Goethe, is a distorted view not only of light and color but also of nature itself. “Indeed, according to Goethe,” claims Myles Jackson, “Newton’s entire doctrine was based on an artiªcial case, the crucial experiment” (1994, p. 686). In contradistinction to New- ton, Goethe claimed that he was able to discover nature’s laws without ªrst imposing human preconception onto a natural phenomenon. To that end, Goethe devised and conducted a series of experiments in which he al- tered systematically the experimental conditions in terms of the prism’s refracting angle, the distance from the subject to the prism, and the object viewed (Ribe and Steinle 2002). The result of these experiments was evi- dence of a higher sort that mediated between the observer’s theory or hy- pothesis and the observed, and allowed the phenomenon to be understood in a holistic fashion. The Newton-Goethe historical case study has important implications for the underdetermination thesis (UDT) of contemporary philosophy of science (Hesse 1980; Klee 1997; Ladyman 2002; Laudan and Leplin 1991; and Stanford 2001).2 Brieºy, the UDT claims that evidence, whether from 1. Although “colored ray(s)” is a phrase not used by Newton, it is used herein for con- venience. 2. UDT has also been at the center of the realism-antirealism debate, especially in terms of John Worrall’s notion of structural realism (Kukla 1998; Ladyman 1998; Leplin 1997; Niiniluoto 1999; Psillos 1999; and Worrall 1989). Downloaded from http://www.mitpressjournals.org/doi/pdf/10.1162/posc.2009.17.4.457 by guest on 27 September 2021 Perspectives on Science 459 the laboratory or the ªeld, is incapable of supporting conclusively a partic- ular theory with respect to its rivals. The reason is that there are always a number of possible competing theories that can account for the evidence equally well. In other words, the various rival theories are empirically equivalent. The case study reconstructed herein corroborates the UDT in that evidence, especially obtained from an experimentum crucis, is incapable of supporting conclusively one theory over its rivals. However, it also chal- lenges the UDT in that the evidence obtained from a well structured ex- perimental series is more likely to support a theory with respect to its competitors, than evidence from a limited or unstructured set of experi- ments or especially from a single even though crucial experiment. The current case study demonstrates that evidence from an experimental series generally provides the necessary and sufªcient warrant for justifying a par- ticular theory choice, until of course additional evidence is eventually ob- tained that may lead to either modiªcation or replacement of the theory. In this paper, I examine the difference between Newton’s and Goethe’s approaches to investigating the nature of light and color. First, I discuss brieºy Newton’s famous experimentum crucis, in which he claimed that light is heterogeneous and is composed of rays with different refrangibilities, as well as his experimental philosophy. I then reconstruct Goethe’s experi- ments on the nature of color and discuss his methodological principle for- mulated in the well known essay “Der Versuch als Vermittler,” especially in contradistinction to Newton’s methodology. Goethe’s principle is ex- pounded in terms of series of experiments and resultant higher empirical evidence, as mediator between the objective (i.e. a natural phenomenon) and the subjective (i.e. theory or hypothesis). I then reconstruct the exper- iments Newton reported in the 1671/2 Philosophical Transactions letter to justify his theory of light and color in terms of Goethe’s methodological principle rather than in terms of a crucial experiment, even though New- ton was—or at least his followers were—not necessarily interested in a ho- listic picture of nature or in the relationship of the subjective to the objec- tive.3 Finally, I conclude the paper with a discussion of the consequences of Goethe’s methodological principle for the contemporary UDT. 2. Newton’s experimentum crucis In a published letter to the Royal Society of London, dated 19 February 1671/2, Newton reported an experimentum crucis (Fig. 1) in which he took a board (Bd) with a small hole (x) and placed it behind a prism (A), which received sunlight (S) from a small hole in the window shutter of a dark- 3. Neil Ribe (1985) argues that the conºict between Goethe and Newton is more than simply competing theories of color but also includes methodological issues. Downloaded from http://www.mitpressjournals.org/doi/pdf/10.1162/posc.2009.17.4.457 by guest on 27 September 2021 460 The Nature of Light and Color Figure 1. Newton’s experimentum crucis (reproduced from Newton 1672). See text for details. ened room. Another board (DE) with a small hole (y) was placed 12 feet from the ªrst board, so that a portion of the incident light would pass through the hole of the second board. A second prism (F) was then placed behind the hole of the second board, which further dispersed the light onto a nearby wall (GH). By slowly rotating the ªrst prism about its axis, Newton was able to make different sections of the initial image pass through the hole in the second board and then observe where it fell on the wall. What Newton observed in the experimentum crucis was that the part of the initial image—an oblong image composed of a spectrum of individual colors—which is refracted greatest (i.e. the color blue) by the ªrst prism is also refracted the greatest by the second prism, compared to that part of the initial image refracted the least (i.e. the color red). From these results, Newton concluded that “Light consists of Rays differently refrangible” (1671/2, p. 3079). He went on in the second part of the letter to outline his “doctrine of colours,” based on his theory of light, in which the various spectral colors exhibited different “degrees of Refrangibility” (Newton 1671/2, p.
Recommended publications
  • Dossier Pierre Duhem Pierre Duhem's Philosophy and History of Science
    Transversal: International Journal for the Historiography of Science , 2 (201 7) 03 -06 ISSN 2526 -2270 www.historiographyofscience.org © The Author s 201 7 — This is an open access article Dossier Pierre Duhem Pierre Duhem’s Philos ophy and History of Science Introduction Fábio Rodrigo Leite 1 Jean-François Stoffel 2 DOI: http://dx.doi.org/10.24117/2526-2270.2017.i2.02 _____________________________________________________________________________ We are pleased to present in this issue a tribute to the thought of Pierre Duhem, on the occasion of the centenary of his death that occurred in 2016. Among articles and book reviews, the dossier contains 14 contributions of scholars from different places across the world, from Europe (Belgium, Greece, Italy, Portugal and Sweden) to the Americas (Brazil, Canada, Mexico and the United States). And this is something that attests to the increasing scope of influence exerted by the French physicist, philosopher and 3 historian. It is quite true that since his passing, Duhem has been remembered in the writings of many of those who knew him directly. However, with very few exceptions (Manville et al. 1927), the comments devoted to him exhibited clear biographical and hagiographic characteristics of a generalist nature (see Jordan 1917; Picard 1921; Mentré 1922a; 1922b; Humbert 1932; Pierre-Duhem 1936; Ocagne et al. 1937). From the 1950s onwards, when the studies on his philosophical work resumed, the thought of the Professor from Bordeaux acquired an irrevocable importance, so that references to La théorie physique: Son objet et sa structure became a common place in the literature of the area. As we know, this recovery was a consequence of the prominence attributed, firstly, to the notorious Duhem-Quine thesis in the English- speaking world, and secondly to the sparse and biased comments made by Popper that generated an avalanche of revaluations of the Popperian “instrumentalist interpretation”.
    [Show full text]
  • One of the Most Celebrated Physics Experiments of the 20Th Cent
    Not Only Because of Theory: Dyson, Eddington and the Competing Myths of the 1919 Eclipse Expedition Introduction One of the most celebrated physics experiments of the 20th century, a century of many great breakthroughs in physics, took place on May 29th, 1919 in two remote equatorial locations. One was the town of Sobral in northern Brazil, the other the island of Principe off the west coast of Africa. The experiment in question concerned the problem of whether light rays are deflected by gravitational forces, and took the form of astrometric observations of the positions of stars near the Sun during a total solar eclipse. The expedition to observe the eclipse proved to be one of those infrequent, but recurring, moments when astronomical observations have overthrown the foundations of physics. In this case it helped replace Newton’s Law of Gravity with Einstein’s theory of General Relativity as the generally accepted fundamental theory of gravity. It also became, almost immediately, one of those uncommon occasions when a scientific endeavor captures and holds the attention of the public throughout the world. In recent decades, however, questions have been raised about possible bias and poor judgment in the analysis of the data taken on that famous day. It has been alleged that the best known astronomer involved in the expedition, Arthur Stanley Eddington, was so sure beforehand that the results would vindicate Einstein’s theory that, for unjustifiable reasons, he threw out some of the data which did not agree with his preconceptions. This story, that there was something scientifically fishy about one of the most famous examples of an experimentum crucis in the history of science, has now become well known, both amongst scientists and laypeople interested in science.
    [Show full text]
  • Constructing Natural Historical Facts BACONIAN NATURAL HISTORY in NEWTON’S FIRST PAPER on LIGHT and COLORS
    OUP UNCORRECTED PROOF – FIRSTPROOFS, Mon Feb 10 2014, NEWGEN 2 Constructing Natural Historical Facts BACONIAN NATURAL HISTORY IN NEWTON’S FIRST PAPER ON LIGHT AND COLORS Dana Jalobeanu* The peculiar structure of Newton’s first published paper on light and colors has been the subject of an astonishing diversity of readings: to date, scholars still do not agree as to what Newton wanted to prove in this paper or how he proved it.1 The structure of the paper is far from transparent. It consists of two very different parts: a historical account of what Newton called his “crucial experiment,” and a “doctrine of colors” consisting of thirteen propositions and an illustrative experiment. Equally debated has been the “style” of Newton’s demonstration.2 Newton begins the first part with an extensive his- torical account of how he became interested in the “celebrated phenomena of colors” and later reached one of its major results: that the shape of the spectrum refracted * Research for this paper has been supported by the grant PN-II-ID-PCE-2011-3-0719, “From Natural History to Science,” awarded by the CNCS. 1 The paper has been read, in turns, as a formal blunder of a young upstart who dared to make a clear break with the mitigated skepticism and anti-dogmatism of the Royal Society, and as a brilliant exercise of rhetoric aiming to rewrite in the “scientific style of the day” the results of six long years of optical research. The reason for the exercise of rhetoric has also been the subject of fierce debates.
    [Show full text]
  • Alchemy Is One of the Great Losers in the Historiography of Science
    1 ©William R. Newman (Copyrighted Preprint: To Appear in Lumière et vision dans les sciences et dans les arts, de l'Antiquité du XVIIe siècle, Danielle Jacquart and Michel Hochmann, editors, Librairie Droz.) Newton’s Early Optical Theory and its Debt to Chymistry William R. Newman Indiana University ©William R. Newman 2 ©William R. Newman Newton’s Early Optical Theory and its Debt to Chymistry Introduction In the years immediately preceding Isaac Newton’s experimental demonstration that sunlight is actually a composition of heterogeneous spectral rays rather than being perfectly homogeneous, a sophisticated methodology based on the analysis and resynthesis of gross matter had decisively shown that chemical compounds were also made up of heterogeneous components. Although modern scholars tend to associate the experimental approach of seventeenth-century corpuscular matter theory with mechanical philosophers such as Pierre Gassendi and Robert Boyle, an extensive alchemical tradition extending from the High Middle Ages up to Boyle’s immediate predecessors had long used the analytic retrievability of the constituents of compounds to argue for the permanence of the ingredients that went into them. Boyle, in particular, was the direct heir of this lengthy alchemical tradition, especially in his use of the atomistic writings of the Wittenberg medical professor Daniel Sennert. It is a well known fact that the young Newton was heavily influenced by Boyle, but no one up to now has argued in detail for a transfer from Boyle’s work on “chymical” analysis and synthesis to the optical analyses and syntheses that formed the bases of Newton’s early optical work.1 Elsewhere I have argued that alchemical experimentation helped to bring a decisive end to traditional 3 ©William R.
    [Show full text]
  • Discovery of Acceleration of the Universe As an Experimentum Crucis
    Experimentum crucis Accelerating evolution of the Universe Summary Discovery of acceleration of the Universe as an experimentum crucis Marek Szyd lowski Pawe l Tambor Adam Krawiec Department of Theoretical Physics, Catholic University of Lublin M. Kac Complex Systems Research Center Institute of Economics and Management, Jagiellonian University 6th ECAP, 2008 Krak´ow, 22 August 2008 Experimentum crucis Accelerating evolution of the Universe Summary Outline 1 Experimentum crucis 2 Accelerating evolution of the Universe 3 Summary Experimentum crucis Accelerating evolution of the Universe Summary Experimentum crusis Isaac Newton first used the term experimentum crucis in his Opticks (1704). In sciences, an experimentum crucis, or critical experiment, is an experiment capable of decisively determining whether or not a particular hypothesis or theory is correct. In particular, such an experiment must typically be able to produce a predictable result that no established hypothesis or theory is capable of producing. Experimentum crucis Accelerating evolution of the Universe Summary Experimentum crucis Important remark of John Stuart Mill: Experimentum crucis consists of not only one but at least three. In the cosmological context the different astronomical observations are used together: SNIa, CMB, baryon oscillation peak, gravitational lensing. Lakatos distinguished in his concept of research programmes the ‘minor crucial experiments’ and ‘major crucial experiments’. The former is applied within the research programme (series of theories with the common hard core) while the latter is applied to competing research programmes. Experimentum crucis Accelerating evolution of the Universe Summary Experimentum crucis (Such, 1975) There are two practical approaches to conduct the experimentum crucis: In the framework of given theory we try to explain the occurring anomaly where new hypothesis explains it.
    [Show full text]
  • The Short History of Science
    PHYSICS FOUNDATIONS SOCIETY THE FINNISH SOCIETY FOR NATURAL PHILOSOPHY PHYSICS FOUNDATIONS SOCIETY THE FINNISH SOCIETY FOR www.physicsfoundations.org NATURAL PHILOSOPHY www.lfs.fi Dr. Suntola’s “The Short History of Science” shows fascinating competence in its constructively critical in-depth exploration of the long path that the pioneers of metaphysics and empirical science have followed in building up our present understanding of physical reality. The book is made unique by the author’s perspective. He reflects the historical path to his Dynamic Universe theory that opens an unparalleled perspective to a deeper understanding of the harmony in nature – to click the pieces of the puzzle into their places. The book opens a unique possibility for the reader to make his own evaluation of the postulates behind our present understanding of reality. – Tarja Kallio-Tamminen, PhD, theoretical philosophy, MSc, high energy physics The book gives an exceptionally interesting perspective on the history of science and the development paths that have led to our scientific picture of physical reality. As a philosophical question, the reader may conclude how much the development has been directed by coincidences, and whether the picture of reality would have been different if another path had been chosen. – Heikki Sipilä, PhD, nuclear physics Would other routes have been chosen, if all modern experiments had been available to the early scientists? This is an excellent book for a guided scientific tour challenging the reader to an in-depth consideration of the choices made. – Ari Lehto, PhD, physics Tuomo Suntola, PhD in Electron Physics at Helsinki University of Technology (1971).
    [Show full text]
  • History Syndrome OR Popperian Credentials of Geology PS MOHARIR
    Proc. Indian Acad. Sci. (Earth Planet. Sci.), Vol. 102, No. 2, June 1993,. pp. 283-305. Printed in India. History syndrome OR Popperian credentials of Geology P S MOHARIR National Geophysical Research Institute, Uppal Road, Hyderabad 500 007 India. MS received 12 June 1991; revised 28 December 1992 Abstract. Earth-science is greatly concerned with history. It is argued by some that a historical discipline is not a science. This is contrary to the conclusion from the demarcation criteria of Popper, set to separate science from formal disciplines such as metaphysics, mathematics and logic. Others have spoken of the unity of all sciences. Classification of intellectual activities is based on oenus proximum and differentia specifica. Hence the two viewpoints can be readily reconciled. Earth-science has been criticized variously for being descriptive, inductive, explanatory, etc. Other historical and concrete sciences have also attracted similar adverse comments. These issues are discussed at length to argue that Popper's work should be extended further to define a demarcation of science into immanent and historical. It is also argued that the rignur of cognitive and logical determinants of science is not an adequate reason to embrace sociological models of science. Further, sociological/logical models of science present a misleading dichotomy. Keywords. Demarcation criteria; historical sciences; Kuhnian model; mathematicalization; earth-science revolution. 1. Introduction The purpose of this paper is to discuss whether geology can be a science. Science is a modern catchword. Therefore, everyone is bound to argue that his discipline is science and then proceed to define it. Most such definitions are territorial.
    [Show full text]
  • Annual Report 2003 3
    PL0401646 INSTYTUT PROBLEMÓW JĄDROWYCH im. Andrzeja Sołtana THE ANDRZEJ SOŁTAN INSTITUTE FOR NUCLEAR STUDIES INSTYTUT PROBLEMOW J&DROWYCH im. Andrzeja Soltana The Andrzej Softan INSTITUTE FOR NUCLEAR STUDIES INIS-PL- 0007 ANNUAL REPORT PL-05-400 OTWOCK-8WIERK, POLAND tel.: 048 22 718 0 83 fax: 048 22 779 34 1 e-mail: sinsipj.gov.pi http:Hwww.ipj.gov.pi Editors: D. Chmielewska E. Infeld Z. Preibisz P. ?upraftki Secretarial work and layout: A. Odziemczyk K. Traczyk Cover design G. Karczmarczyk Printed by Zakfad Graficzny UW, zam. 280/2004 ISSN 1232-5309 Annual Report 2003 3 CONTENTS 1. GENERAL INFORMATION 7 1- MANAGEMENT OF THE INSTITUTE 7 2. SCIENTIFIC COUNCIL 8 3. DEPARTMENTS OF THE INSTITUTE I 0 4. SCIENTIFIC STAFF OF THE INSTITUTE 5 . V IS IT IN G SC IE N T IST S ....................................................................................................... 13 6. GRANTS 15 7. DEGREES 18 8. CONFERENCES AND WORKSHOPS ORGANIZED BY IPJ ........................................... 1 8 11. REPORTS ON RESEARCH BY DEPARTMENT 19 1 NUCLEAR REACTIONS I 9 2. NUCLEAR SPECTROSCOPY AND TECHNIQUE ............................................................ 35 3. DETECTORS AND NUCLEAR ELECTRONICS ............................................................... 55 4. RADIATION SHIELDING AND DOSIMETRY ................................................................. 69 5. PLASMA PHYSICS AND TECHNOLOGY ........................................................................ 79 6. H IG H EN E R G Y PH Y SIC S ..................................................................................................
    [Show full text]
  • Robert Finlay, 'Weaving the Rainbow: Visions of Color in World History'
    Weaving the Rainbow: Visions of Color in World History robert finlay University of Arkansas udwig Wittgenstein wrote his last work, Remarks on Colour, during a visit to Vienna in 1950 and while dying of cancer in Cambridge theL following year. The slim book represented a return to a theme of his earliest writings, for he had dealt with the thorny problem of the logi- cal structure of color concepts in Tractatus Philosophico-Mathematicus (1908).1 Remarks on Colour sets forth a broad range of what Wittgen- stein called “puzzle questions”: Why is white not considered a color? What makes bright colors bright? Are “pure” colors mere abstractions, never found in reality? What is the relationship between the world of objects and the world of consciousness? Is there such a thing as a “natural history of color”? Faced with more conundrums than answers, Wittgenstein despaired that the logic of color perceptions could be clarifi ed: “there is merely an inability to bring the concepts into some kind of order. We stand there like the ox in front of the newly-painted stall door.” 2 Wittgenstein’s refl ections on color took place upon a fault line divid- ing the followers of Isaac Newton (1642–1727) from those of Johann Wolfgang von Goethe (1749–1832). Wittgenstein remarked that he found Newtonian questions interesting but not gripping, and although 1 Ray Monk, Ludwig Wittgenstein: The Duty of Genius (New York: Free Press, 1990), pp. 561–568; J. Westphal, Colour: Some Philosophical Problems from Wittgenstein (Oxford: Basil Blackwell, 1984), pp. 6–7, 11. 2 Ludwig Wittgenstein, Remarks on Colour, ed.
    [Show full text]
  • A History of Science, V1
    A History of Science, V1 Henry Smith Williams A History of Science, V1 Table of Contents A History of Science, V1.....................................................................................................................................1 Henry Smith Williams.............................................................................................................................1 VOLUME I. THE BEGINNINGS OF SCIENCE...................................................................................1 BOOK I.................................................................................................................................................................1 I. PREHISTORIC SCIENCE...................................................................................................................2 II. EGYPTIAN SCIENCE.......................................................................................................................9 III. SCIENCE OF BABYLONIA AND ASSYRIA..............................................................................19 IV. THE DEVELOPMENT OF THE ALPHABET..............................................................................30 V. THE BEGINNINGS OF GREEK SCIENCE...................................................................................36 VI. THE EARLY GREEK PHILOSOPHERS IN ITALY...................................................................38 VII. GREEK SCIENCE IN THE EARLY ATTIC PERIOD...............................................................48 VIII. POST−SOCRATIC SCIENCE
    [Show full text]
  • Newton's Experimentum Crucis from a Constructivist Point of View
    Humboldt University of Berlin Philosophy Term Paper Winter Term 2008/09 Newton’s Experimentum Crucis from a Constructivist Point of View Author: Philipp Kanschik Supervisor: Prof. Dr. Olaf Müller Student No.: 522919 Institute for Philosophy Address: Jonasstraße 28 Humboldt University 12053 Berlin of Berlin Germany Phone: 0049 30 29045786 E-mail: [email protected] Date of completion: April 3rd, 2009 Table of Content 1. Introduction: Science and Reality 4 2. Simon Schaffer's Constructivist Approach 7 2.1 Realism and Constructivism 7 2.2 Leviathan and the Air-Pump 10 3. Facts and Theory in Newton's Letter from 1672 17 3.1 Facts 17 3.2 Theory 20 3.3 What Does the Experimentum Crucis Prove? 21 4. Newton's Experimentum Crucis from a Constructivist 25 Point of View 4.1 Evaluating Experimental Matters of Fact 25 4.2 Material Technology: Prisms as an Experimental 27 Instrument 4.3 Literary Technology: Newton's Overconfidence 31 4.4 Social Technology: Newton's Authority 35 5. Conclusion and Outlook: What Schaffer Should 40 Have Done Appendix 43 References 46 2 I, Philipp Kanschik, hereby declare this work to be my own, that I have acknowledged all the sources I have consulted in the paper itself and not only in the bibliography, that all wording unaccompanied by a reference is my own, and that no part of this essay can be found on the internet. I acknowledge that this paper has not been handed in at another university in order to obtain an academic degree. Signature 3 1. Introduction: Science and Reality Being skeptical about reality has become easy.
    [Show full text]
  • David Hume Has Been Largely Read As a Philosopher but Not As a Scientist
    THE VERA CAUSA PRINCIPLE IN 18 TH CENTURY MORAL PSYCHOLOGY 1 FERNANDO MORETT David Hume has been largely read as a philosopher but not as a scientist. In this article I discuss his work exclusively as a case of science; in particular as a case of early modern science. I compare the moral psychology of self-interest, sympathy and sentiments of humanity he argues for with the moral psychology of universal self-interest from Bernard Mandeville, presenting the controversy between the two as a case of theory choice. David Hume, Adam Smith and Francis Hutcheson regarded the psychology of self-interest advanced by Thomas Hobbes and Bernard Mandeville as the rival theory to be defeated; it was a theory making ‘so much noise in the world’, Smith reports 2. Hume positively praises Mandeville’s theory in the first pages of the Treatise . This volume pays more attention to self-interest than An Enquiry Concerning the Principles of Morals, in which Hume discusses the disinterested passions of humanity and benevolence in more detail. Both Hume and Smith were highly critical of Mandeville’s theory, which they considered to be ‘malignant’ and ‘wholly pernicious’ because it leaves no grounds for ‘feelings sympathy and humanity’. They actually allude to Mandeville with epithets such as ‘sportive sceptic’ and ‘superficial reasoner’, whose reasoning is ‘ingenious sophistry’. 3 Hume strongly criticises the self-interested individuals described by Mandeville who are ‘monsters’ ‘unconcerned, either for the public good of a community or the private utility of others’ 4; they are replicas of Ebenezer Scrooge who even at Christmas shows no humanity, no concern for others.
    [Show full text]