Redalyc.HERACLITUS, PLATO, and the PHILOSOPHIC DOGS (A

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Redalyc.HERACLITUS, PLATO, and the PHILOSOPHIC DOGS (A Revista Archai E-ISSN: 1984-249X [email protected] Universidade de Brasília Brasil Hülsz Piccone, Enrique HERACLITUS, PLATO, AND THE PHILOSOPHIC DOGS (A NOTE ON REPUBLIC II, 375E-376C) Revista Archai, vol. 15, núm. 15, julio-diciembre, 2015, pp. 105-115 Universidade de Brasília Available in: http://www.redalyc.org/articulo.oa?id=586161413012 How to cite Complete issue Scientific Information System More information about this article Network of Scientific Journals from Latin America, the Caribbean, Spain and Portugal Journal's homepage in redalyc.org Non-profit academic project, developed under the open access initiative desígnio 15 jul/dez 2015 HERACLITUS, PLATO, AND THE PHILOSOPHIC DOGS (A NOTE ON REPUBLIC II, 375E-376C) * Enrique Hülsz Piccone PICCONE, E. H. (2015). Heraclitus, Plato, and the philosophic dogs (a note on Republic II, 375e-376c). Archai, n. 15, jul. – dez., p. 105-115 DOI: http://dx.doi.org/10.14195/1984-249X_15_10 * Universidad Nacional RESUMO: Este artigo focaliza uma instância negligen- Autônoma de México - Although the influence of Heraclitus on the [email protected] ciada da recepção platônica de Heráclito na República (II, ancient philosophical tradition can be taken for 375e-376c), e tenta mostrar que é provável que a passagem granted as a matter of fact, it’s often hard to pin it de Platão seja uma alusão a B 97 de Heráclito («Os cães down with enough precision in every instance. Pos- ladram para quem eles não conhecem») e B 85 («É difícil sibly one of the most revealing test cases is Plato, lutar contra o thymos, pois o que se almeja com isso se in whose written works there is a deeply-embedded, paga com ψυχή). A principal reivindicação é que com o opaque image of Heraclitus, widely acknowledged uso que faz da imagem de cães, Platão volta os seus olhos in the Cratylus and the Theaetetus (which contain para Heráclito, e convida a explorar de a possibilidade que seven of the nine explicit mentions by name in pelo menos alguns elementos da Kallipolis de Platão possam the dialogues and attribute him certain famous 1 derivar de Heráclito - especialmente alguns fragmentos éti- doctrines ). Actually, the presence of Heraclitus in cos e políticos. Uma breve pesquisa acerca desses elementos Plato goes far beyond these two dialogues, and can sugere haver uma profunda afinidade filosófica entre os dois be detected in a considerable number of the writings 2 autores em diversas áreas importantes (como a chamada in the Corpus Platonicum . As a rule, Plato doesn’t «psicologia moral» e o «intelectualismo ético»), e questiona quote Heraclitus much and when he does, he doesn’t o lugar comum da interpretação tradicional de Heráclito give his words exactly and fully, but adapts them como um defensor da moral aristocrática. to his own context, substantially transforming the PALAVRAS­‑CHAVE: Platão, Heráclito, cães, thymos, originals. Scholarship has not been particularly keen phylakes, demos, polloi, aristoi. on detecting the relevance of Heraclitus’ art and thought in the Republic, although it might turn out ABSTRACT: The paper focuses on a neglected instance to be important for a right understanding of Plato’s of the Platonic reception of Heraclitus in the Republic (II, own philosophical message at several crucial points 375e-376c), trying to show that it’s likely that Plato’s of the argument (particularly books V-VII). In what passage makes an allusion to Heraclitus’ B97 (“Dogs bark follows, I will not even attempt a rough general at whom they don’t know”) and B85 (“It’s difficult to fight sketch of the latter aspect, but will deal instead θυμός, for what it longs for it pays with ψυχή”). The main with just one instance of the reception of Heraclitus in book II (375e-376c). This note sets out to show 105 3 claim is that Plato’s use of the image of dogs looks back to of the gods in their mythological tales . Pre-Socratic 4 Heraclitus, which invites an exploration of the possibility influences here should include Xenophanes in that at least some elements of Plato’s kallipolis might the first place, but a harsh attitude towards the derive from Heraclitus – particularly from some ethical and founding fathers of Greek παιδεία — extended to political fragments. A brief survey of these suggests a deep Xenophanes himself — is also very conspicuous in 5 philosophical affinity among the two authors in several some Heraclitean fragments . Plato’s own criticism important areas (as the so-called ‘moral psychology’ and of traditional poetry comes up as part of the initial ‘ethical intellectualism’), and questions the commonplace development of the appropriate παιδεία for the traditional interpretation of Heraclitus as a defender of young Guardians (φύλακες, introduced at 374d). aristocratic morality. At this early stage of the long narrative argument KEYWORDS: Plato, Heraclitus, dogs, thymos, phylakes, these “Guardians” refer to the emerging class of demos, polloi, aristoi. professional soldiers in the “luxurious” or “swollen” 6 city , resulting from the fast-growing needs of the that it’s likely that Plato’s passage on the philo- imagined community of citizens and a combination sophic dogs makes an allusion to Heraclitus (DK22 of factors such as overpopulation, the consequent B97: “Dogs bark at whom they don’t recognize”). need to make war, and the principle of division of In what concerns the interpretation of Heraclitus work according to each one’s natural abilities. Later enigmatic dictum, Plato seems to give a different on, an élite of philosopher-kings will gradually de- side of the philosophy of the Ephesian, suggesting velop out of these primitive Guardians (who will be an anthropological (ethical and political) context of then distinguished from the shepherds, and referred 7 application. I’ll argue that Plato’s use of the image to as “helpers” ), and eventually become the ruling of dogs looks back to and sheds light on Heraclitus’ class, coming into full view in book V. For the time thought, and explore the possibility that some being, besides the producers and craftsmen, there elements of Plato’s kallipolis might be connected is only this class in charge of warfare (offensive and to ideas in Heraclitus. Inter-textual analysis calls defensive), which will be expected to enforce law for a fair assessment of the relevant texts of both and order within the state, and to act always with authors, which is not an easy task, each one of them the interest of the whole city in mind. being difficult to interpret in their own right. The Before getting to the question of the rear- influence of Heraclitus on Plato and the Platonic ing, training and right education of the Guardians, reception of Heraclitus constitute a territory not the interlocutors face the preliminary problem of often visited by interpreters and commentators, the mere possibility of breeding good watch-dogs sometimes slippery and always full of hermeneutical for the city, fierce and ‘high-spirited’. At 374a-b, challenges. So: Cave canes! Socrates insists that in every case, whether horse, The project of designing in thought an ideal dog or any other animal, there’s no courageousness polis is conceived precisely in book II of Plato’s without a high-spirited nature; for, he tells the Republic (369c ff.), as the course that the search impetuous Glaucon: for the nature of justice must follow, yielding as a general answer (in book IV, 443c-d) the inner Don’t you know spirit (θυμός) is an invincible thing ἁρμονία both of the soul and the city. A quick look that no one wants to fight with, and that its presence at book II as a whole shows an obvious surfacing makes every soul (ψυχή) fearless and unconquerable 8 of a well-known (though not unique) Heraclitean in the face of every danger? theme, in the specific criticism of Homer and Hesiod, leading to censorship and eventual banishment of Socrates’ revealing connection of θυμός and politically incorrect poetry from the καλλίπολις ψυχή anticipates the moral psychology of book IV, — as it is later called (V, 527c2) —, because of the where ψυχή is the broader concept and θυμός is 9 harmful effects of the immoral and false depiction one of its constituent parts . Perhaps significantly, 106 desígnio 15 jul/dez 2015 Socrates may be evoking a famous saying of Heracli- our Guardian still needs this: to become in his nature tus (B85): “It’s hard to fight passion θυμός( ), for a lover of wisdom (φιλόσοφος τὴν φύσιν), besides what it longs for, it pays with soul (ψυχή)”. That being high-spirited (τῷ θυμοειδεῖ)? Heraclitus’ saying is in Plato’s mind here is sug- [376a] [Gl.] What? I don’t understand. gested by the close lexical parallelism among Plato’s [soc.] This, precisely, you can see in dogs, and it’s ἄμαχόν τε καὶ ἀνίκητον θυμός and Heraclitus’ something worthy of admiration in a beast. θυμῷ μάχεσθαι χαλεπόν, and reinforced by [Gl.] What do you mean? the idea of ψυχή as the epistemic subject and the [soc.] That when a dog sees a stranger, he gets moral agent, so prominently held by Plato’s Socrates. angry (ὃν μὲν ἂν ἴδῃ ἀγνῶτα, χαλεπαίνει), even if The starting-point of our passage is the as- he hasn’t received any harm from him. But when it’s similation of the natures of the Guardians-to-be someone known, he greets him (ὃν δ' ἂν γνώριμον, and dogs of a good breed (375a). Guardians should ἀσπάζεται), even if he never benefitted from him. possess the same qualities as good dogs — gentle- Or have you never wondered about this? ness towards the οἰκείοι and not only fierceness [Gl.] I had not until now turned my attention to towards strangers.
Recommended publications
  • A Cardinal Sin: the Infinite in Spinoza's Philosophy
    Macalester College DigitalCommons@Macalester College Philosophy Honors Projects Philosophy Department Spring 2014 A Cardinal Sin: The nfinitI e in Spinoza's Philosophy Samuel H. Eklund Macalester College, [email protected] Follow this and additional works at: http://digitalcommons.macalester.edu/phil_honors Part of the Philosophy Commons Recommended Citation Eklund, Samuel H., "A Cardinal Sin: The nfinitI e in Spinoza's Philosophy" (2014). Philosophy Honors Projects. Paper 7. http://digitalcommons.macalester.edu/phil_honors/7 This Honors Project is brought to you for free and open access by the Philosophy Department at DigitalCommons@Macalester College. It has been accepted for inclusion in Philosophy Honors Projects by an authorized administrator of DigitalCommons@Macalester College. For more information, please contact [email protected]. A Cardinal Sin: The Infinite in Spinoza’s Philosophy By: Samuel Eklund Macalester College Philosophy Department Honors Advisor: Geoffrey Gorham Acknowledgements This thesis would not have been possible without my advisor, Professor Geoffrey Gorham. Through a collaborative summer research grant, I was able to work with him in improving a vague idea about writing on Spinoza’s views on existence and time into a concrete analysis of Spinoza and infinity. Without his help during the summer and feedback during the past academic year, my views on Spinoza wouldn’t have been as developed as they currently are. Additionally, I would like to acknowledge the hard work done by the other two members of my honors committee: Professor Janet Folina and Professor Andrew Beveridge. Their questions during the oral defense and written feedback were incredibly helpful in producing the final draft of this project.
    [Show full text]
  • The Death of Heraclitus Fairweather, Janet Greek, Roman and Byzantine Studies; Fall 1973; 14, 3; Proquest Pg
    The Death of Heraclitus Fairweather, Janet Greek, Roman and Byzantine Studies; Fall 1973; 14, 3; ProQuest pg. 233 The Death of Heraclitus Janet Fairweather ECENTLY there has been a revival of interest in a theory, Roriginally put forward by A. Gladisch,l about one ancient ac­ count of the death of Heraclitus. According to Neanthes of Cyzicus 2 Heraclitus, suffering from dropsy, attempted to cure him­ self by covering his body with manure and lying out in the sun to dry, but he was made unrecognizable by the dung covering and was finally eaten by dogs. Gladisch and others have seen in this anecdote a veiled allusion to a certain Zoroastrian ritual, described in the Videvdat (8.37f), in which a man who has come into contact with a corpse which has not been devoured by scavengers is supposed to rid himself of the polluting demon, Nasu the Druj, by lying on the ground, covering himself with bull's urine, and having some dogs brought to the scene. The fact that we find both in Neanthes' tale and in this ritual the use of bovine excreta, exposure of a man's body in the sun, and the inter­ vention of dogs has seemed to some scholars too remarkable to be coincidental. Gladisch and, following him, F. M. Cleve3 have seen in Neanthes' anecdote an indication that Heraclitus might have ordered a Zoroastrian funeral for himself. M. L. West,4 more cautiously and subtly, has suggested that the story of the manure treatment and the dogs could have originated as an inference from some allusion Hera­ clitus may have made to the purification ritual in a part of his work now lost, perhaps in connection with his sneer (fr.86 Marcovich=B 5 D/K) at people who attempt to rid themselves of blood pollution by spilling more blood.
    [Show full text]
  • Epicurus Epicurus Was Born in February 341 BCE
    Epicurus Epicurus was born in February 341 BCE. He earned his basic education in philosophy after four years of tutoring, and at the age of 18, Epicurus served in the military for two years in Athens. After completing his education, Epicurus began teaching around the Aegean, eventually settling back in Athens. There, he purchased some land and founded a school which was given the name of ‘The Garden’, for its construction in the garden of his house. The Garden soon became a notable institute for the progress of philosophical education, and it also held the exclusivity of being the first philosophical Greek institute that allowed women to take part in learning. Epicurus strongly advocated friendship as an important root for a happy and fulfilling life, and thus, his school provided the community with the opportunity to interact and form constructive relationships. Epicurus has played an extremely vital role in the progress of science as a discipline. Epicurus was the first Greek philosopher to attempt to break free society from religious superstitions by preaching that God does not punish or reward humans, and that a man’s sole objective should be to form a self-sufficient and happy life by surrounding oneself with reliable and cherished friends. Epicurus was a strong advocate of free will. The development of a pleasant and comfortable life, in his view, was the core purpose of life, and good and bad consequences could only be evaluated on the principles of pain and pleasure. Epicurus believed that whatever serves to provide pleasure can be termed as good, and whatever leads to discomfort can be termed as bad.
    [Show full text]
  • The Heraclitus Anecdote: De Partibus Animalium I 5.645A17-23
    Ancient Philosophy 21 (2001) ©Mathesis Publications 1 The Heraclitus Anecdote: De Partibus Animalium i 5.645a17-23 Pavel Gregoric Chapter 5 of the first book of Aristotle’s De Partibus Animalium contains a short self-contained treatise (644b22-645a36) which has been characterised as a ‘protreptic to the study of animals’ (Peck in Aristotle 1937, 97). Such a charac- terisation of the treatise may be misleading, because Aristotle does not seem to have composed it in order to motivate his audience to go out in the field and study animals, but rather to kindle their interest in the scientific account of ani- mals which he is about to provide. It is reasonable to suppose that Aristotle’s audience, eager to learn something valuable and dignified, needed an explanation of why they should like to hear, amongst other animals, about sponges, snails, grubs, and other humble creatures which are displeasing even to look at, not to mention witnessing the dissections that might have accompanied Aristotle’s lec- tures on animals (cf. Bonitz 1870, 104a4-17; Lloyd 1978). Aristotle explains why such ignoble animals deserve a place in a scientific account of animals and he illustrates that with an anecdote about Heraclitus. So one must not be childishly repelled by the examination of the humbler animals. For in all things of nature there is some- thing wonderful. And just as Heraclitus is said to have spoken to the visitors who wanted to meet him and who stopped as they were approaching when they saw him warming himself by the oven (e‰don aÈtÚn yerÒmenon prÚw t“ fipn“)—he urged them to come in without fear (§k°leue går aÈtoÁw efisi°nai yarroËntaw), for there were gods there too (e‰nai går ka‹ §ntaËya yeoÊw)—so one must approach the inquiry about each animal without aversion, since in all of them there is something natural and beautiful.
    [Show full text]
  • BY PLATO• ARISTOTLE • .AND AQUINAS I
    i / REF1,l!;CTit.>NS ON ECONOMIC PROBLEMS / BY PLATO• ARISTOTLE • .AND AQUINAS ii ~FLECTIONS ON ECONO:MIC PROBLEMS 1 BY PLA'I'O, ARISTOTLE, JJJD AQUINAS, By EUGENE LAIDIBEL ,,SWEARINGEN Bachelor of Science Oklahoma Agricultural and Mechanical Collage Stillwater, Oklahoma 1941 Submitted to the Depertmeut of Economics Oklahoma Agricultural and Mechanical College In Partial Fulfillment of the Requirements for the Degree of MASTER OF SCIENCE 1948 iii f.. 'I. I ···· i·: ,\ H.: :. :· ··: ! • • ~ ' , ~ • • !·:.· : i_ ·, 1r 1i1. cr~~rJ3t L l: i{ ,\ I~ Y , '•T •)() 1 0 ,1 8 API-'HOV~D BY: .J ,.· 1.., J l.;"t .. ---- -··- - ·- ______.,.. I 7 -.. JI J ~ L / \ l v·~~ u ' ~) (;_,LA { 7 {- ' r ~ (\.7 __\ _. ...A'_ ..;f_ ../-_" ...._!)_.... ..." ___ ......._ ·;...;;; ··-----/ 1--.,i-----' ~-.._.._ :_..(__,,---- ....... Member of the Report Committee 1..j lj:,;7 (\ - . "'·- -· _ .,. ·--'--C. r, .~-}, .~- Q_ · -~ Q.- 1Head of the Department . · ~ Dean of the Graduate School 502 04 0 .~ -,. iv . r l Preface The purpose and plan of this report are set out in the Introduction. Here, I only wish to express my gratitude to Professor Russell H. Baugh who has helped me greatly in the preparation of this report by discussing the various subjects as they were in the process of being prepared. I am very much indebted to Dr. Harold D. Hantz for his commentaries on the report and for the inspiration which his classes in Philosophy have furnished me as I attempted to correlate some of the material found in these two fields, Ecor!.Omics and Philosophy. I should like also to acknowledge that I owe my first introduction into the relationships of Economics and Philosophy to Dean Raymond Thomas, and his com~ents on this report have been of great value.
    [Show full text]
  • A Philosophical Inquiry Into the Development of the Notion of Kalos Kagathos from Homer to Aristotle
    The University of Notre Dame Australia ResearchOnline@ND Theses 2006 A philosophical inquiry into the development of the notion of kalos kagathos from Homer to Aristotle Geoffrey Coad University of Notre Dame Australia Follow this and additional works at: https://researchonline.nd.edu.au/theses Part of the Philosophy Commons COMMONWEALTH OF AUSTRALIA Copyright Regulations 1969 WARNING The material in this communication may be subject to copyright under the Act. Any further copying or communication of this material by you may be the subject of copyright protection under the Act. Do not remove this notice. Publication Details Coad, G. (2006). A philosophical inquiry into the development of the notion of kalos kagathos from Homer to Aristotle (Master of Philosophy (MPhil)). University of Notre Dame Australia. https://researchonline.nd.edu.au/theses/13 This dissertation/thesis is brought to you by ResearchOnline@ND. It has been accepted for inclusion in Theses by an authorized administrator of ResearchOnline@ND. For more information, please contact [email protected]. A PHILOSOPHICAL INQUIRY INTO THE DEVELOPMENT OF THE NOTION OF KALOS KAGATHOS FROM HOMER TO ARISTOTLE Dissertation submitted for the Degree of Master of Philosophy Geoffrey John Coad School of Philosophy and Theology University of Notre Dame, Australia December 2006 TABLE OF CONTENTS Abstract iv Declaration v Acknowledgements vi INTRODUCTION 1 CHAPTER 1: The Fish Hook and Some Other Examples 6 The Sun – The Source of Beauty 7 Some Instances of Lack of Beauty: Adolf Hitler and Sharp Practices in Court 9 The Kitchen Knife and the Samurai Sword 10 CHAPTER 2: Homer 17 An Historical Analysis of the Phrase Kalos Kagathos 17 Herman Wankel 17 Felix Bourriott 18 Walter Donlan 19 An Analysis of the Terms Agathos, Arete and Other Related Terms of Value in Homer 19 Homer’s Purpose in Writing the Iliad 22 Alasdair MacIntyre 23 E.
    [Show full text]
  • Herakleitos (121.6Kb)
    The Reign of the Whirlwind 122 Chapter 7 Herakleitos ----------- 1. Life and book We have very little reliable information about the life of Herakleitos son of Bloson, of Ephesos. It is clear from the biographical accounts that survive, that the Alexandrian scholars could find little, even though they were not fussy about reliability. They made up anecdotes to fit some of the more striking sayings of this paradox-loving writer; and as a result, “Herakleitos the Dark” became even more obscure. We have to guess, first, at his dates. He knows something about Pythagoras and Xenophanes; and Parmenides seems to know something about him. We can hazard the conjecture that his book was written by 500 BCE (when Xenophanes had still the last quarter of his long life to live, and Pythagoras was in his last years). This would make 545 BCE a reasonable guess for his birth date. He probably died before 480.i Herakleitos belonged to the ancient royal clan of Ephesos. He is said to have deposited his book in the great temple of Artemis for which his native city was famous (22 A 1).ii We can fairly suppose that it was in his eyes the worthy trophy of a greater victory than any triumph in arms. Whether he was actually melancholic (“the weeping philosopher” as he came to be called)iii we cannot say. He was certainly both an angry man, and an intellectual aristocrat. There are some The Reign of the Whirlwind 123 “sayings” of his that were not in the book. In one plausible story, he “upbraids the Ephesians .
    [Show full text]
  • Brsq 0096.Pdf
    /,,-,,,.I (hrir"M/W:|J,„'JJ(// Bulk Mail -:::-``.::`:.1:.t` U.S. Postage ci{08O#altruntr%%ditl.i PAID Permit No. 5659 CfldemmJin, ORE 23307 Alexandria, VA MR. DENNIS J. DARLAND /9999 .1965 WINDING HILLS RD. (1304) DAVENPORT IA 52807 T=..:€,,5fa=.`¥ _ atiTst:.:..¥5 3`=3 13LT„j§jLj;,:j2F,f:Lu,i,:,„„„„3.,§§.i;§„L„;j„§{j;;`„„:i THE BHRTRAND RUSSELL SOCIHTY QUARTERLY Newsletter o the Bertrand Russell Socie November 1997 No. 96 FROM THH EDITOR John Shosky ................................... 3 FROM THE PRESIDHNT John R. Lenz ................................... 4 BERTRAND RUSSELL SOCIETY CONFERENCH: 19-21 JUNE 1998 ...................... RUSSELL NEWS: Publications, etc ....................... 6 RUSSELL'S PLATO David Rodier ................................... 7 A BOOK REVIEW John Shosky .................................. 19 MEMORY COMES AND GOES: A Video Review Cliff Henke ................................... 22 THE GREATER ROCHESTER RUSSELL SET Peter Stone ................................... 24 BERTRAND RUSSELL SOCIETY Membership PI.orlles ............................ 25 BERTRAND RUSSELL SOCIETY 1998 Call for Board Nominations .................. 27 BERTRAND RUSSELL SOCIETY Membership pror]]e Form . 29 1 FROM THE EDITOR BHRTRAND RUSSELL SOCIETY John Shosky 1998 Membership Renewal Form ................... 31 American University Wc beSn this issue with a report from the society president, John Lenz. He will announce the preliminary details of the Annual Bertrand Russell Society Corferencc, which will be held June 19-21 at the Ethics Center of the University of South Florida in St. Petersburg. John's report will be followed by "Russell News", which is a column of short blurbs about Russell, works on Russell, society happenings, reports on members, general gossip, and other vital talking points for the informed and discerning society member. In my view, the standard of information one should strive for, in a Platonic sense, is Ken Blackwell, the guru of Russell trivia, realizing that Ken has a considerable head start on all of us.
    [Show full text]
  • Following the Argument Where It Leads
    Following The Argument Where It Leads Thomas Kelly Princeton University [email protected] Abstract: Throughout the history of western philosophy, the Socratic injunction to ‘follow the argument where it leads’ has exerted a powerful attraction. But what is it, exactly, to follow the argument where it leads? I explore this intellectual ideal and offer a modest proposal as to how we should understand it. On my proposal, following the argument where it leaves involves a kind of modalized reasonableness. I then consider the relationship between the ideal and common sense or 'Moorean' responses to revisionary philosophical theorizing. 1. Introduction Bertrand Russell devoted the thirteenth chapter of his History of Western Philosophy to the thought of St. Thomas Aquinas. He concluded his discussion with a rather unflattering assessment: There is little of the true philosophic spirit in Aquinas. He does not, like the Platonic Socrates, set out to follow wherever the argument may lead. He is not engaged in an inquiry, the result of which it is impossible to know in advance. Before he begins to philosophize, he already knows the truth; it is declared in the Catholic faith. If he can find apparently rational arguments for some parts of the faith, so much the better: If he cannot, he need only fall back on revelation. The finding of arguments for a conclusion given in advance is not philosophy, but special pleading. I cannot, therefore, feel that he deserves to be put on a level with the best philosophers either of Greece or of modern times (1945: 463). The extent to which this is a fair assessment of Aquinas is controversial.1 My purpose in what follows, however, is not to defend Aquinas; nor is it to substantiate the charges that Russell brings against him.
    [Show full text]
  • Homer's Odyssey in the Hands of Its Allegorists: Many Paths to Explain the Cosmos
    Safari Grey Homer’s Odyssey in the Hands of its Allegorists: Many Paths to Explain the Cosmos Summary The allegorical exegetic tradition was arguably the most popular form of literary criticism in antiquity. Amongst the ancient allegorists we encounter a variety of names and philo- sophic backgrounds spanning from Pherecydes of Syros to Proclus the Successor. Many of these writers believed that Homer’s epics revealed philosophical doctrines through the means of hyponoia or ‘undermeanings’.Within this tradition was a focus on cosmological, cosmogonical and theological matters which attracted a variety of commentators despite their philosophical backgrounds. It is the intention of this paper to draw attention to two writers: Heraclitus, and Porphyry of Tyre. This paper also intends to demonstrate that the tradition of cosmic allegorical exegesis is still practiced in modern scholarship. Keywords: Homer; literary criticism; allegory; Heraclitus; Porphyry; cosmology; metaphor Die allegorische exegetische Tradition war wohl die populärste Form der Literaturkritik in der Antike. Unter den antiken Allegorien begegnen wir einer Vielzahl von Namen und phi- losophischen Hintergründen, die von Pherecydes von Syros bis zu Proclus der Nachfolger reichen. Viele dieser Autoren glaubten, Homers Epen enthüllten philosophische Lehren durch Hyponoie oder ,Unterschätzung‘. In dieser Tradition lag der Fokus auf kosmologi- schen, kosmogonischen und theologischen Fragen, die trotz ihrer philosophischen Hinter- gründe eine Vielzahl von Kommentatoren anzogen.
    [Show full text]
  • Socrates and Democratic Athens: the Story of the Trial in Its Historical and Legal Contexts
    Princeton/Stanford Working Papers in Classics Socrates and democratic Athens: The story of the trial in its historical and legal contexts. Version 1.0 July 2006 Josiah Ober Princeton University Abstract: Socrates was both a loyal citizen (by his own lights) and a critic of the democratic community’s way of doing things. This led to a crisis in 339 B.C. In order to understand Socrates’ and the Athenian community’s actions (as reported by Plato and Xenophon) it is necessary to understand the historical and legal contexts, the democratic state’s commitment to the notion that citizens are resonsible for the effects of their actions, and Socrates’ reasons for preferring to live in Athens rather than in states that might (by his lights) have had substantively better legal systems. Written for the Cambridge Companion to Socrates. © Josiah Ober. [email protected] Socrates and democratic Athens: The story of the trial in its historical and legal contexts. (for Cambridge Companion to Socrates) Josiah Ober, Princeton University Draft of August 2004 In 399 B.C. the Athenian citizen Socrates, son of Sophroniscus of the deme (township) Alopece, was tried by an Athenian court on the charge of impiety (asebeia). He was found guilty by a narrow majority of the empanelled judges and executed in the public prison a few days later. The trial and execution constitute the best documented events in Socrates’ life and a defining moment in the relationship between Greek philosophy and Athenian democracy. Ever since, philosophers and historians have sought to
    [Show full text]
  • Lucan's Natural Questions: Landscape and Geography in the Bellum Civile Laura Zientek a Dissertation Submitted in Partial Fulf
    Lucan’s Natural Questions: Landscape and Geography in the Bellum Civile Laura Zientek A dissertation submitted in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy University of Washington 2014 Reading Committee: Catherine Connors, Chair Alain Gowing Stephen Hinds Program Authorized to Offer Degree: Classics © Copyright 2014 Laura Zientek University of Washington Abstract Lucan’s Natural Questions: Landscape and Geography in the Bellum Civile Laura Zientek Chair of the Supervisory Committee: Professor Catherine Connors Department of Classics This dissertation is an analysis of the role of landscape and the natural world in Lucan’s Bellum Civile. I investigate digressions and excurses on mountains, rivers, and certain myths associated aetiologically with the land, and demonstrate how Stoic physics and cosmology – in particular the concepts of cosmic (dis)order, collapse, and conflagration – play a role in the way Lucan writes about the landscape in the context of a civil war poem. Building on previous analyses of the Bellum Civile that provide background on its literary context (Ahl, 1976), on Lucan’s poetic technique (Masters, 1992), and on landscape in Roman literature (Spencer, 2010), I approach Lucan’s depiction of the natural world by focusing on the mutual effect of humanity and landscape on each other. Thus, hardships posed by the land against characters like Caesar and Cato, gloomy and threatening atmospheres, and dangerous or unusual weather phenomena all have places in my study. I also explore how Lucan’s landscapes engage with the tropes of the locus amoenus or horridus (Schiesaro, 2006) and elements of the sublime (Day, 2013).
    [Show full text]