Kitsch and Contemporary Culture

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Kitsch and Contemporary Culture Kitsch and contemporary culture Bert Olivier Philosophy, Centre for Advanced Studies, University of Port Elizabeth, South Africa. E-mail: [email protected] This paper addresses the question of kitsch by interpreting it as :'bad" a:t of a partic~lar kind. It draws mainl~, but not exclusively, on Karsten Harries's phenomenological exploratIOn of kItsch to pr?vIde a. framewor~ from whIch to approach kitsch in contemporary (postmodern) culture. It is shown that, by u.ncovenng attnb~tes of kItsch su~h as the self-enjoyment of the spectator and lack of reflective distance, Harries provIdes valuable pomters for assessmg what is ultimately the anaesthetizing political function of kitsch in contemporary culture. Kitsch is one of the major problems of the remembered and the sentimentalism which present. This claim may seem far-fetched to pervades it (that is, the wallowing in the some people, especially to those who take a feelings that accomp-any the memories). certain delight in "art objects" which do not The point is that kitsch manifests itself hide their status as "kitsch", like a "retro"­ whenever feelings seem to have lost their telephone in the shape of a 50s pink Cadillac correlates, their "objects"; whenever the whose roof serves as the receiver. 1 But this world, objects, and even other people, seem is not really surprising - those objects derive to have retreated, to be out of reach, so that their charm from the aura of nostalgia which "enjoyment" is ultimately enjoyment of surrounds them, something that is one's feelings and sensations for their own paradoxically reminiscent of a more sake instead of for the sake of "authentic" era, despite the artificiality of communicating with others or with things in the "art object". Hence, what is charming the world. When Fredric Jameson (1993: 10- about the pink Cadillac-cum-telephone is 16) talks about the "waning of affect" in what it represents - its "bygone" referent, as postmodernity, and reminds readers that this it were, namely the historical era which it does make room for experiencing feeling in evokes so powerfully on the part of people a different register, namely that of who are old enough to be transported to their "intensities", I believe he is on the same rock "n roll youth by its sight. There is terrain, although he does not mention kitsch another reason why it is paradoxical, by name. Perhaps this is because kitsch has however. There is no doubt that the become the rule in popular culture from sentimentalism with which people may painting to television soapies and regard the miniature Cadillac-phone marks it mainstream Hollywood movies. as kitsch, but the memories of authenticity But what, precisely, is kitsch? evoked by it tend to undermine its Answering this question would certainly kitschiness precisely because these are clarify what was said above, and Karsten probably memories of excitement and desire Harries (1968: 73-83; 149-152) is an - desire that can be attached, in memory, to invaluable source of insight in this regard. I specific individuals, like lovers and friends. shall try to give a succinct account of Conversely, the sentimentalism so typical of Harries's fairly extended phenomenology of kitsch tends to subvert the authenticity of the kitsch, because it dates back to the late memories in question. The paradox , then , 1960s and I would like to expand on it by consists in the tension between what is relating it to the present. Harries reminds 104 Digitised by the University of Pretoria, Library Services one that a theory or philosophy of art should aestheticall y exemplary by being make room for the recognition of bad art as "harmonious", unified and technically well as of good or "great" art - so-called faultless, even "perfect" - as Canaday "masterpieces"; otherwise there would by observed about Bouguereau's paintings and implication only be great art and non-art. His Kerman about Richard Strauss's operatic analysis of kitsch as "bad" art of a certain music (specifically Salome and Der variety places it in a broader context than Rosenkavalier). The nature of this what might be expected, by showing that it "perfection" is hinted at in Canaday's involves moral considerations as well, rather description of Bouguereau's work as than merely aesthetic ones.2 In fact, one "perfectly false", and as perfection of "a might say that Harries's interpretation of perverse kind" (quoted in Harries 1968: 76). kitsch reveals that it is an index of the Kerman's description of Strauss's Salome, impossibility of isolating art from ethics. namely that it has been composed with the Harries discusses the historical "greatest skill", and that it "carries harmonic provenance of the term "kitsch" in the audacity farther than ever before" (quoted in second half of the 19th century. It is linked to Harries 1968: 76) is similar. Even though he the English verb "sketch", on the one hand, recognizes Strauss's masterly technique, and the unfamiliar German word, "kitschen" however, he denounces it for "the most (to play with mud), on the other. He gives banal sound" in opera, and for its "sugary more credence to the latter derivation, orgasm". pointing to the similarities between If these epithets do not yet convey what smoothed-out mud and the texture or colour is distinctive about kitsch in art and music, of many 19th.;.century academic paintings. Kerman's insistence, that these two operas The term "kitsch" was probably first used to by Strauss "are false works in which refer to certain genre paintings such as those everything goes depressingly right" (quoted which, with the tourist market in mind, in Harries 1968: 76) must surely strike a represented "pure", unspoilt Alpine familiar chord with early 21 st-century mountain scenes. Importantly, Harries viewers who have been overexposed to (1968: 75) observes that: mainstream Hollywood movies and television soaps of the "Everything-will-and­ The word soon acquired overtones of moral disapproval: those paintings were called Kitsch does-work-out-in-the-end"-variety. I am which seemed to show a lack of integrity and which referring to the kind of movie that was catered to the longings of the sentimental bourgeois. ruthlessly parodied in Aronofsky's recent It is in this sense that the word appears in art criticism today ... Kitsch is considered bad art; on critical film, Requiem for a Dream (2001):1 the other hand, Kitsch is not simply bad art, but bad Goethe's well-known dictum comes to art of a particular kind. Here 'bad' is used not so mind, that nothing is as depressing as a much in an aesthetic as in a moral sense. Kitsch is perverted art, and to understand this perversion, we succession of good days. Why? Because in have to relate art to a standard of truth or morality. human life as it is, full of trials and If aesthetics conceives itself to be only an tribulations, everyday experience teaches autonomous discipline, divorced from ethics and ontology, it must fail to understand Kitsch, for one to "expect the unexpected,,:4 mishaps, Kitsch is a hybrid. accidents, unanticipated debts, illnesses and so forth. Hence, as Goethe keenly observed, This may appear incongruous, given the when things have been going smoothly for startling fact - as Harries (1968: 75) points longer than usual, one tends to wonder, out - that kitsch often strikes one as being semi-superstitiously, when the "inevitable" 105 Digitised by the University of Pretoria, Library Services mishap will occur. And the point about is accompanied by a bracketing-out of kitsch is that it covers up this salient trait of everyday, practical concerns, matched by a human experience under a layer of fleshing-out of the experience (as sentimentalism, illusion and falsity which "aesthetic") on a new perceptual basis functions like an anaesthetic or worse, a created by the "distance" in question.6 powerful narcotic, inducing a kind of stupor Phenomenologically speaking, this distance that consists in a denial of these inescapable varies from person to person according to features of human finitude. Is it at all their ability to sustain it, as well as regarding surprising, then, that so many people whom the kind of object depicted and the manner Marxists would call bourgeois adorn their or style in which it has been done. A still life lounges and dining rooms with kitsch of food may remind someone of his or her paintings or reproductions suffused with hunger, while a nude may arouse someone sentimentalism, such as a picture of a wide­ sexually because of an inability on the eyed, vulnerable-looking child whose eyes spectator's part to sustain the "distance" are filled with tears - an act that offers no required for an aesthetic experience.7 guarantee that such people are capable of Needless to say, in these instances the works bestowing genuine care or love on their own would not succeed as art. children. But what is the relevance of this for the This is not to argue that an unmitigated dubious moral status of kitsch? As Harries existential pessimism should, ideally, be (1968: 77) suggests, one might conclude that reflected in art. After all, if mishaps are to a kitsch is art without the proper "distance", greater or lesser degree inescapable, it is also keeping in mind the dependence of such true that pleasurable, fulfilling experiences distance on the individual's distancing are usually intertwined with these in those ability as well as on formal qualities of the human lives that are fortunately not subject artwork itself. That the matter is more to conditions of utter material deprivation or complex than Bullough's treatment of the poverty.
Recommended publications
  • Heidegger, Being and Time
    Heidegger's Being and Time 1 Karsten Harries Heidegger's Being and Time Seminar Notes Spring Semester 2014 Yale University Heidegger's Being and Time 2 Copyright Karsten Harries [email protected] Heidegger's Being and Time 3 Contents 1. Introduction 4 2. Ontology and Fundamental Ontology 16 3. Methodological Considerations 30 4. Being-in-the-World 43 5. The World 55 6. Who am I? 69 7. Understanding, Interpretation, Language 82 8. Care and Truth 96 9. The Entirety of Dasein 113 10. Conscience, Guilt, Resolve 128 11. Time and Subjectivity 145 12. History and the Hero 158 13. Conclusion 169 Heidegger's Being and Time 4 1. Introduction 1 In this seminar I shall be concerned with Heidegger's Being and Time. I shall refer to other works by Heidegger, but the discussion will center on Being and Time. In reading the book, some of you, especially those with a reading knowledge of German, may find the lectures of the twenties helpful, which have appeared now as volumes of the Gesamtausgabe. Many of these have by now been translated. I am thinking especially of GA 17 Einführung in die phänomenologische Forschung (1923/24); Introduction to Phenomenological Research, trans. Daniel O. Dahlstrom (Bloomington, Indiana University Press, 2005) GA 20 Prolegomena zur Geschichte des Zeitbegriffs (1925); History of the Concept of Time, trans. Theodore Kisiel (Bloomington, Indiana University Press, 1985) GA 21 Logik. Die Frage nach der Wahrheit (1925/26). Logic: The Question of Truth, trans. Thomas Sheehan GA 24 Die Grundprobleme der Phänomenologie (1927); The Basic Problems of Phenomenology, trans.
    [Show full text]
  • Running out of Space? Architecture and the Need for a Post-Copernican Geocentrism" February 23, 2017, Yale University
    Geocentrism 1 "Running out of Space? Architecture and The Need for a Post-Copernican Geocentrism" February 23, 2017, Yale University 1 For many years I taught a course called The Philosophy of Architecture. That I taught this course at all was the result of conversations with Kent Bloomer, who suggested, many years ago, that the undergraduate major could use such a course. Before then I had been teaching a course called The Philosophy of Modern Art. The Meaning of Modern Art, published in 1968, was the result of that course. That book was quite successful. After all these years it is still in print. But with its appearance I lost some of my interest in that course, and so I was quite ready to respond to Kent Bloomer’s invitation, especially so since my interest in architecture goes back to my childhood. That course, too, finally resulted in a Book, The Ethical Function of Architecture. It, too, has been successful. It was just honored with a second Festschrift. But, again, with the appearance of the book I lost some of my interest in the course, although I did teach it for one last time in the fall. But I have kept thinking and lecturing about architecture. Not that I have changed my position in any fundamental way. But circumstances have changed; the world has changed. More especially, the way we relate to space has changed and continues to change. Our understanding of space has changed; and since architecture may be understood as the art of bounding space that suggests that our understanding of architecture, too, will have changed.
    [Show full text]
  • In Defense of Sentimentality (The Passionate Life) (2004).Pdf
    In Defense of Sentimentality ROBERT C. SOLOMON OXFORD UNIVERSITY PRESS In Defense of Sentimentality thepassionatelife A Series on the Philosophy of Emotions by Robert C. Solomon Not Passion’s Slave: Emotions and Choice In Defense of Sentimentality In Defense of Sentimentalityrobert c. solomon 1 2004 1 Oxford New York Auckland Bangkok Buenos Aires Cape Town Chennai Dar es Salaam Delhi Hong Kong Istanbul Karachi Kolkata Kuala Lumpur Madrid Melbourne Mexico City Mumbai Nairobi Sa˜o Paulo Shanghai Taipei Tokyo Toronto Copyright # 2004 by Robert C. Solomon Published by Oxford University Press, Inc. 198 Madison Avenue, New York, New York 10016 www.oup.com Oxford is a registered trademark of Oxford University Press All rights reserved. No part of this publication may be reproduced, stored in a retrieval system, or transmitted, in any form or by any means, electronic, mechanical, photocopying, recording, or otherwise, without the prior permission of Oxford University Press. Library of Congress Cataloging-in-Publication Data Solomon, Robert C. In defense of sentimentality / Robert C. Solomon. p. cm.—(The passionate life) Includes bibliographical references and index. ISBN 0-19-514550-X 1. Emotions (Philosophy) 2. Sentimentalism. I. Title. B105.E46S665 2004 1280.37—dc22 2003061007 987654321 Printed in the United States of America on acid-free paper for Kathleen and Kathryn Higgins This page intentionally left blank Preface: Emotions and Sentimentality Feeling is everything.—Johan Wolfgang von Goethe Philosophy has as much to do with feelings as it does with thoughts and thinking. It requires sensitivity and devotion as well as curiosity about the world and a critical spirit.
    [Show full text]
  • Introduction to Ethics-1Vjjqv5
    Introduction to Ethics 1 Karsten Harries Introduction to Ethics Lecture Notes Fall Semester 2013 Yale University Copyright Karsten Harries Introduction to Ethics 2 Contents 1. Introduction I. Plato 2. Piety and Justice 3. Socrates Accused 4. A Dream of Homecoming 5. Body and Soul 6. Morality and Mortality 7. Transcendent Measures 8. The Good Life II. Bentham 9. Goodness and Pleasure 10. A Questionable Calculus 11. Crime and Punishment 12. The Ends of Government III. Kant 13. Duty and Inclination 14. The Categorical Imperative 15. Autonomy 16. Some Critical Questions IV. Kierkegaard 17. The Knight of Faith 18. The Challenge of Abraham 19. The Teleological Suspension of the Ethical 20. Pride and Concealment V. Nietzsche 21. History and Values 22. Beyond Good and Evil 23. Guilt and Bad Conscience 24. God and the gods 25. The Ascetic Ideal 26. Conclusion Introduction to Ethics 3 1. Introduction In the Philosophical Investigations Ludwig Wittgenstein writes that philosophical problems have the form "I do not know my way about." (PI 123) Philosophy, this suggests, has its origin in a loss of way or a dislocation. To be sure, not all problems having this form are therefore already philosophical. For example, to have lost one's way in a strange city hardly suffices to make one a philosopher? But why not? I would suggest that one reason is that in such cases our disorientation is only superficial: In a deeper sense we still know our place and what to do. Thus we could ask someone for help or look for a map. The problem poses itself against a background of unquestioned ways of doing things, on which we can fall back in our attempt to discover where we are and where we should be going.
    [Show full text]
  • The Abetment of Nihilism: Architectural Phenomenology's
    Benjamin M. Roth The Abetment Of Nihilism: Architectural Phenomenology’s Ethical Project But you did not and could not toss out of your heart that part of you from which the God notion had come. – Richard Wright, The Outsider Phenomenological theorists of architecture are admirably attuned to the ways in which our experience of the built envi- ronment is rich in meaning and value. Emphasize pure space and form, and questions of meaning won’t arise. Think of architecture as mere technology and they won’t either (one asks how to use a hammer, and for what, not what it means). In the middle of the 20th century, as Jorge Otero-Pailos writes, a group of architect-theorists retrospectively desig- nated as the architectural phenomenology movement, and who “thought individual experience had been impoverished by the process of industrialization and became disillusioned with the modernist faith in technology,” rose to prominence: “Out went the conviction that technology drove history, and in came the sense that architectural history was driven by 1 1. Jorge Otero-Pailos, Architecture’s the search for authentic, original human experiences.” More Historical Turn: Phenomenology and the Rise of the Postmodern (Minneapolis: University recently, phenomenology has inspired an even broader theo- of Minnesota Press, 2010), xi. rizing of architecture by thinkers like Karsten Harries (from philosophy) and Alberto Pérez-Gómez (from architectural history and theory) of a specifically ethical bent. Both Harries and Pérez-Gómez are dissatisfied with the current status of architecture, which they perceive as subservient to technol- ogy and in which they see an abdication of architecture’s abil- ity, even responsibility, to represent – that is, display back to us – meaning.
    [Show full text]
  • End and Origin of Art 1
    The End and Origin of Art 1 Karsten Harries The End and Origin of Art (Philosophy of Modern Art) Lecture Notes Fall Semester 2002 Yale University Copyright Karsten Harries The End and Origin of Art 2 Contents Preface 3 Introduction 1. Zips and Slashes 7 Part One: The End of Art 2. “I Can Do Everything” 26 3. Narratives of the End of Art 49 4. Hegel on the Death of Art 65 5. The Place of Art in the Age of the World-Picture 87 Part Two: The Need for Art 6. Between Hope and Resignation 101 7. Art as Origin 124 8. Art and the Sacred 141 9. The Golden Calf 160 Part Three: The Present and Future of Art 10. Kitsch, Vulgarity, and Abjection 178 11. The Sublime and the Interesting 197 12 Evening Art 214 13. Dreams of Alchemy 232 Conclusion 14. The Snake’s Promise Technology and Art at the Beginning of the Third Millennium 253 The End and Origin of Art 3 Preface In these lectures I attempt to show why art, especially painting, continues to matter, despite so much in today’s art-world that argues against this — and, as I will also show, such arguments are supported by the very shape of our modern world. The title demands explanation. End can mean something like death. In recent years there has thus been a great deal of talk about a possible death or end of art. But end can also mean telos or goal. And these two readings can merge: there may be a sense in which art has to die when it finally reaches its goal.
    [Show full text]
  • Nietzsche Truth, Value, Tragedy
    Nietzsche Harries 1 Karsten Harries Nietzsche Truth, Value, Tragedy Seminar Notes Spring Semester 2015 Yale University Copyright Karsten Harries Nietzsche Harries 2 Contents 1. Introduction: Nietzsche, Schopenhauer, and Wagner 3 2. "On the Pathos of Truth" I 32 3. “On the Pathos of Truth" II 45 4. "On Truth and Lie in an Extramoral Sense" I 59 5. "On Truth and Lie in an Extramoral Sense" I 76 6. Artisten-Metaphysik 87 7. Apollo and Dionysus 102 8. Socrates 119 9. Incipit Tragoedia 132 10. Old and New Values 146 11. The Problem of Time 154 12. The Eternal Recurrence 168 13. Conclusion: Tragedy and Redemption 186 Nietzsche Harries 3 1. Introduction: Nietzsche, Schopenhauer, and Wagner 1 In the 19th century the traditional Platonic-Christian conception of human being underwent a revolution in which we are still caught up and with which we still have to come to terms. Darwin is one name often mentioned in this connection, Marx another, Freud a third. In this seminar I would like to examine some aspects and consequences of this revolution by taking a look at some of Nietzsche's writings. This examination will focus on three themes, truth, value, and tragedy. My discussion will end with a consideration of Zarathustra,1 but much of it will be concerned with Nietzsche’s early writings, especially The Birth of Tragedy. To introduce that discussion I shall begin, however, by taking a careful look at two short essays dating from that period, at "The Pathos of Truth," dating from 1872, and "On Truth and Lie in an Extramoral Sense," dating from the following year.2 More clearly than The Birth of Tragedy3 these essays allow us to understand the nature of Nietzsche's philosophical project, his life-long struggle with nihilism.
    [Show full text]
  • Heidegger, Wittgenstein, and the Future of Philosophy
    Wittgenstein, Heidegger and the Future of Philosophy 1 Karsten Harries Wittgenstein, Heidegger and the Future of Philosophy Fall Semester 2014 Yale University Copyright Karsten Harries Wittgenstein, Heidegger and the Future of Philosophy 2 Contents 1. Introduction 4 2. Cartesian Method 14 3. Ontological Implications 27 4. The Adequacy of Pictures 39 5. Two Conflicting Interpretations of Language in Wittgenstein’s Tractatus 50 6. Truth and Transcendence 59 7. Heidegger’s Logical Beginnings 69 8. Nihilism and Mysticism 80 9. The Shipwreck of Philosophy 94 10. Legitimacy and Limits of Scientific Language 103 11. Two Conflicting Interpretations of Language in Wittgenstein’s Investigations 114 12. Ordinary Language as Ground 128 13. No Place for Freedom 138 14. Language and Fundamental Ontology 145 15. Discourse and Language 153 16. Idle Talk 163 17. Language and Authenticity 176 18. Poetry 190 19. The Ontological Difference and the Holy 199 20. Poetry and Truth 209 21. Is There a Measure on Earth? 218 22. Hölderlin, Patmos 229 Wittgenstein, Heidegger and the Future of Philosophy 3 23. Heidegger and Hölderlin 247 24. Poetry and Community 256 25. Poetry and Metaphysics 265 26. Conclusion 273 Wittgenstein, Heidegger and the Future of Philosophy 4 1. Introduction1 1 In the Philosophical Investigations Wittgenstein remarks that philosophical problems: have the form “I don 't know my way about.”2 Of course, not all problems having this form are therefore philosophical: e.g., to have lost one's way in some strange city hardly suffices to make one a philosopher. But why not? Is it perhaps because in such cases our disorientation is only superficial? In a deeper sense we still know our place and what to do.
    [Show full text]
  • PHL 317K Introduction to Philosophy of the Arts Fall 2014 Unique Numbers
    1 PHL 317K Introduction to Philosophy of the Arts Fall 2014 Unique numbers: 42940, 42945, 42950, 42955, 42960, 42962, 42963, 42964, TIME: Tuesdays and Thursdays, 2:00-2:50 p.m. and a third hour LOCATION: TTH 2:00 CAL 100 (Check your schedule for third hour location) INSTRUCTOR: Prof. Kathleen Higgins OFFICE: WAG 203 (512) 471-5564 OFFICE HOURS: Tuesdays and Thursdays, 10:45-11:45 a.m. E-MAIL: <[email protected]> COURSE DESCRIPTION: This course will consider some of the answers given in the Western philosophical tradition to questions about the nature of art and beauty, as well as offering a brief overview of some perspectives from Japan. Particular attention will be given to the distinction between art and reality, and to the nature of the aesthetic experience from the standpoint of both the artist and the observer. TEACHING ASSISTANTS: Simone Gubler Office: WAG 427 Office Hours E-mail address: <[email protected]> Brian Pollex Office: WAG 406 Office Hours: Mondays, 3:45-4:45 p.m. and Fridays, 2:15-3:15 p.m. E-mail address: <[email protected]> Hannah Trees Office: WAG 412 Office Hours E-mail address: <[email protected]> 2 TEXTBOOK: Kathleen Marie Higgins, ed., Aesthetics in Perspective GRADING AND IMPORTANT DATES: September 9 Short paper due 5% September 18 Journal topic #1 due September 25 Exam I 15% September 30 Journal topic #2 due October 2 Journal topic #3 due October 7 Journal topic #4 due October 16 Journal topic #5 due October 23 Journal topic #6 due October 30 Exam II 15% November 4 Journal topic #7 due November 6 Journal topic #8 due November 11 Journal topic #9 due November 13 Journal topic #10 due November 18 Take-home Exam III due 15% November 20 Journal topic #11 due November 25 Journal topic #12 due December 4 Final written project due 20% Participation 10% Journal Topics Total 20% NOTE: Participation includes attendance both in lectures and in discussion sections, in- class writing, in-class quizzes, etc.
    [Show full text]
  • Descent of the Logos Seminar Notes
    Descent of he Logos 1 Karsten Harries The Descent of the Logos Seminar Notes Fall Semester 2011 Yale University Copyright Karsten Harries Descent of he Logos 2 Contents 1. Introduction 3 2. Hölderlin and Hegel 14 3. Patmos 30 4. Heidegger's Way I: From Theology to Logic 46 5. Heidegger's Way II: Transformations of Logic 57 6. Authenticity and the Burden of Freedom 67 7. Art Work and Thing 78 8. Earth and World 89 9. Truth, Thing, and the Fourfold 103 10. On the Way to the Fourfold 114 11. The Fourfold Reconsidered 128 12. Nostalgia, Kitsch, and the Interesting 140 13. Conclusion: The Descent of the Logos 153 Descent of he Logos 3 1. Introduction I would like to begin this seminar with a look at the interview Heidegger granted the German weekly Der Spiegel on September 23, 1966 and which was published, according to his wishes, only after his death, in 1976.1 Heidegger had wanted to address some of the charges that had been made in connection with his involvement with National Socialism, especially his brief rectorate of 1933-1934. Much of what he has to say in that interview repeats what he had already written down in 1945, shortly after the end of the war. I do no want to go into most of the interview here.2 In this interview Heidegger was asked about a notorious remark found in the Introduction to Metaphysics, where he had insisted that what today is offered as philosophy of National Socialism has nothing to do with the inner truth and greatness of this movement (namely with the encounter of planetary technology and modern man).3 The Spiegel introduced its question with a remark that Heidegger got caught up in the politics of “this supposed new departure … by way of the university.” SPIEGEL: After about a year, you gave up the function again that you had assumed in this process.
    [Show full text]
  • History of Aesthetics 1
    History of Aesthetics 1 Karsten Harries History of Aesthetics Lecture Notes Fall Semester 2012 Yale University Copyright Karsten Harries History of Aesthetics 2 Contents I. Introduction 1. Does Art Still Matter? 3 II. Plato 2. Beauty as the Object of Love 12 3. Art as a Gift 21 4. Beauty and Truth 29 5. Socrates' Critique of the Poets 39 III. Aristotle 6. Art as Human Work 46 7. The Mimetic Character of Art 53 8. Tragedy 59 9. Ontological and Aesthetic Conceptions of Art 68 10. Beauty as the Epiphany of Form 75 IV. Kant 11. The Turn to Modern Aesthetics 82 12. Kant's System, Critique of Judgment, Introduction 89 13. Kant's Critique of Empiricism 97 14. Kant's Critique of Rationalism 104 15. The Sublime 112 16. The Creation of the Work of Art: The Aesthetic Idea 121 17. Genius and Taste 127 V. Hegel 18. Hegel on the Future of Art 134 19. Hegel's Determination of the Essence of Art 141 20. Towards a Philosophy of the History of Art 147 21. Tales of the End of Art 15 VI. Heidegger 22. Artwork, Equipment, Thing 163 23. Art as an Establishment of the World 171 24. Art as a Presentation of the Earth 177 25. Art and Truth 183 VII. Conclusion 26. Art Matters 191 History of Aesthetics 3 1. Introduction: Dos Art Still Matter? 1 Some time ago the New York Times mourned in an editorial the tragedy that just now, when the arts are flourishing in America they are yet “seriously threatened by a shortage of funds and support.” It is a lament that tends to return whenever either economic conditions or government policy has caused public support for the arts to dry up.
    [Show full text]
  • Environmental & Architectural Phenomenology. Vol. 20, No. 3
    Environmental & Architectural Phenomenology Volume 20 Number 3 Article 1 9-22-2009 Environmental & Architectural Phenomenology. Vol. 20, No. 3 Kansas State University. Architecture Department Follow this and additional works at: https://newprairiepress.org/eap Part of the Environmental Design Commons, and the Other Architecture Commons Vol. 20, No. 3, Fall 2009 (includes "items of interest," "citations received," and essays by Bernd Jager, Karsten Harries, Jeff Malpas & Edward Relph). Recommended Citation Kansas State University. Architecture Department (2009) "Environmental & Architectural Phenomenology. Vol. 20, No. 3," Environmental & Architectural Phenomenology: Vol. 20: No. 3. This Full Issue is brought to you for free and open access by New Prairie Press. It has been accepted for inclusion in Environmental & Architectural Phenomenology by an authorized administrator of New Prairie Press. For more information, please contact [email protected]. Environmental & Architectural Phenomenology, Vol. 20 [2009], No. Environmental & Architectural Phenomenology Vol. 20 ▪ No. 3 ISSN 1083-9194 www.arch.ksu.edu/seamon/EAP.html Fall ▪ 2009 th 1990—2009: Special 20 -anniversary issue! his EAP is a special issue to celebrate our scale realm of other places and global interconnect- 20th year of publication. It includes essays edness. Editor David Seamon begins this special by four scholars who have made impor- issue by discussing some key concerns readers have tant contributions to environmental and brought forward over the years in regard to the phe- Tarchitectural phenomenology. Psychologist Bernd nomenological efforts promoted by EAP. Jager explores how the lived nature of thresholds plays an indispensable role in human inhabitation, Below: In the very first issue of EAP, we asked whether there and philosopher Karsten Harries considers archi- might be a phenomenologically-inspired graphics of places, buildings, and environmental experiences.
    [Show full text]