Heidegger, Wittgenstein, and the Future of Philosophy

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Heidegger, Wittgenstein, and the Future of Philosophy Wittgenstein, Heidegger and the Future of Philosophy 1 Karsten Harries Wittgenstein, Heidegger and the Future of Philosophy Fall Semester 2014 Yale University Copyright Karsten Harries Wittgenstein, Heidegger and the Future of Philosophy 2 Contents 1. Introduction 4 2. Cartesian Method 14 3. Ontological Implications 27 4. The Adequacy of Pictures 39 5. Two Conflicting Interpretations of Language in Wittgenstein’s Tractatus 50 6. Truth and Transcendence 59 7. Heidegger’s Logical Beginnings 69 8. Nihilism and Mysticism 80 9. The Shipwreck of Philosophy 94 10. Legitimacy and Limits of Scientific Language 103 11. Two Conflicting Interpretations of Language in Wittgenstein’s Investigations 114 12. Ordinary Language as Ground 128 13. No Place for Freedom 138 14. Language and Fundamental Ontology 145 15. Discourse and Language 153 16. Idle Talk 163 17. Language and Authenticity 176 18. Poetry 190 19. The Ontological Difference and the Holy 199 20. Poetry and Truth 209 21. Is There a Measure on Earth? 218 22. Hölderlin, Patmos 229 Wittgenstein, Heidegger and the Future of Philosophy 3 23. Heidegger and Hölderlin 247 24. Poetry and Community 256 25. Poetry and Metaphysics 265 26. Conclusion 273 Wittgenstein, Heidegger and the Future of Philosophy 4 1. Introduction1 1 In the Philosophical Investigations Wittgenstein remarks that philosophical problems: have the form “I don 't know my way about.”2 Of course, not all problems having this form are therefore philosophical: e.g., to have lost one's way in some strange city hardly suffices to make one a philosopher. But why not? Is it perhaps because in such cases our disorientation is only superficial? In a deeper sense we still know our place and what to do. Thus we could ask someone for help or look for a map. The problem poses itself against a background of unquestioned ways of doing things, on which we can fall back in our attempt to discover where we are and where we should go. Philosophical problems have no such background. They emerge only where human beings have begun to question the entire place assigned to them by nature, society, and history, and, searching for firmer ground, demand that his place be more securely established. The fundamental question of philosophy is “where is man's proper place?” and philosophy comes to an end when this question no longer is raised, either because man has become secure in knowledge or faith or because he has found it a treacherous question to which there is no answer. If it is a desire for security that leads human beings to philosophy that same desire can also lead them to forsake it. In dread of its restless questioning, man may ask to be delivered of philosophy and of the threat it poses to the security offered by what is generally accepted. Philosophy is then asked to reform and serve the established —some ideology or faith, science, or the reigning common sense for example — or, unable to perform such service, to criticize and finally destroy itself. Such doubts concerning philosophy are part of recent philosophizing. They have found expression in recurring attempts to move beyond what philosophy has been. Of 1 See Karsten Harries, "Wittgenstein and Heidegger: The Relationship of the Philosopher to Language," The Journal of Value Inquiry, vol. 2, no. 4, 1968, pp. 281-291. 2 Ludwig Wittgenstein, Philosophical Investigations [abbreviated PI], trans. G. E. M. Anscombe (New York: Macmillan, 1959) §123. Wittgenstein, Heidegger and the Future of Philosophy 5 these Heidegger's and Wittgenstein's have been the most significant. Both have provided interpretations of language that call philosophy in the traditional sense into question. In this course I shall examine and criticize certain theses fundamental to these interpretations in an attempt to show that philosophy, understood as the search for man's pIace, is both possible and necessary. 2 But why try to cover both Heidegger and Wittgenstein in one course? Do they not have their place in very different philosophical corners? What separates these two thinkers, often thought to have been the two most influential philosophers of the 20th century, is indeed more readily apparent than what unites them. ''What can be said at all can be said clearly; and what we cannot talk about we must pass over in silence," says Wittgenstein in the preface to the Tractatus.3 Such clarity is hardly what one associates with Heidegger’s writings. And although Wittgenstein was to abandon the position of the Tractatus, there still seems to be an almost insuperable gap separating the Investigations, with their emphasis on "our language" as the ground to which he bid philosophers return, from the dark sayings of the later Heidegger. The shared presuppositions that are necessary if there is to be a genuine conversation appear to be lacking. And yet there is much they share and in the past few decades there has been increasing discussion of what joins these two philosophers. I am thinking especially of philosophers like Stanley Cavell and Richard Rorty, where it is worth noting that both have their places on the fringes of today’s philosophical establishment and are more likely to be read in literature departments than in departments of philosophy. But what joins Heidegger and Wittgenstein is indeed apparent: in their very different ways, both have contributed decisively to the linguistic turn — the title of a collection of essays edited by Richard Rorty — that has shaped modern philosophy. Both were convinced that language mediates our access to reality. Heidegger thus was to call language “the 3 Ludwig Wittgenstein, Tractatus Logico-Philosophicus, trans. C. K. Ogden (London: Routledge, 1922) Wittgenstein, Heidegger and the Future of Philosophy 6 house of being,”4 a metaphor to which I shall have to return. Careful attention to language thus would seem to be essential to philosophy. But language is an elusive phenomenon. Where should we look to get at what matters here? Is it logic that holds the key, as the young Wittgenstein and the young Heidegger both thought? Is it ordinary language, as Wittgenstein’s Philosophical Investigations insist — and, as we shall see, Heidegger‘s position in Being and Time is not so very different? Or is it poetry, as Heidegger later came to think? Heidegger’s poetic thinking, to be sure, would appear to be representative of a kind of thinking with which Wittgenstein had no patience. In the end the paths marked out by these two thinkers would thus seem to diverge radically. And those who follow one or the other of these paths tend to publish in different journals, read different books, speak different languages. Those unfortunate enough to lose their way and to end up in the wrong camp may find it difficult to understand the curious language-games people there are playing. All the more reason for those who refuse to accept the division of philosophy into these different camps to consider the common origin of Wittgenstein's and Heidegger's thought. That this common origin has received insufficient attention is hardly an accident; both thinkers have invited such disregard of the past. This is certainly true of Wittgenstein: in the preface to the Tractatus he says explicitly that it is a matter of indifference to him whether the thoughts he is presenting were thought by some other thinker before him and suggests that the problems that have figured in traditional philosophy rest on a misuse of language. In the Investigations he suggests that these problems are generated by an idling of language. One can point to such passages to present Wittgenstein as an anti-philosopher who has surpassed or undercut the philosophy of the past by showing that the puzzles that occupied it can be made to disappear by "bringing words back from their metaphysical to their everyday use."5 Heidegger, too, speaks of the end of traditional metaphysics; his own thinking is an attempt to step back to a more fundamental plane. This, it has been argued, makes it impossible to compare Heidegger to the philosophers of the past. His thinking is 4 Martin Heidegger, Brief über den Humanisnus (Frankfiurt am Main: Klostermann, 1949), Wegmarken (Frankfurt/M: Klostermann, 1967), p. 164. (GA 8) 5 Investigations §116. Wittgenstein, Heidegger and the Future of Philosophy 7 fundamental and original in a way that forbids all such comparisons.6 But if the work of the mature Heidegger and of the Wittgenstein of the Investigations does constitute a break with traditional, especially with Cartesian philosophy, as an effort to overcome that tradition, it retains its roots in it. An attempt to relate and evaluate Heidegger's and Wittgenstein's thought can be made by appealing to this common origin. This is made easier by the fact that both have written works that are still very much part of the Cartesian tradition, so that their break with it is at the same time also a break with an earlier phase of their own thinking. Thus Wittgenstein came to criticize the Tractatus, while Heidegger abandoned the views of his dissertation, Die Lehre vom Urteil im Psychologismus,7 and of his Habilitationsschrift, Die Kategorien- und Bedeutungslehre des Duns Scotus.8 2 Modern philosophy was given its direction by Descartes' method. But not just modern philosophy, modern science, and that is to say our technology, and that is to say, our modern world. To fully understand the nature of Heidegger's and Wittgenstein's move beyond this conception of philosophy it is necessary to see what is implied by Cartesian method — the first meetings of this course will be devoted to it. Of special interest here are the often neglected consequences that Descartes' method has for value theory.
Recommended publications
  • The Idea of Mimesis: Semblance, Play, and Critique in the Works of Walter Benjamin and Theodor W
    DePaul University Via Sapientiae College of Liberal Arts & Social Sciences Theses and Dissertations College of Liberal Arts and Social Sciences 8-2012 The idea of mimesis: Semblance, play, and critique in the works of Walter Benjamin and Theodor W. Adorno Joseph Weiss DePaul University, [email protected] Follow this and additional works at: https://via.library.depaul.edu/etd Recommended Citation Weiss, Joseph, "The idea of mimesis: Semblance, play, and critique in the works of Walter Benjamin and Theodor W. Adorno" (2012). College of Liberal Arts & Social Sciences Theses and Dissertations. 125. https://via.library.depaul.edu/etd/125 This Dissertation is brought to you for free and open access by the College of Liberal Arts and Social Sciences at Via Sapientiae. It has been accepted for inclusion in College of Liberal Arts & Social Sciences Theses and Dissertations by an authorized administrator of Via Sapientiae. For more information, please contact [email protected]. The Idea of Mimesis: Semblance, Play, and Critique in the Works of Walter Benjamin and Theodor W. Adorno A Dissertation Submitted in Partial Fulfillment of the Requirements for the Degree of Doctor of Philosophy October, 2011 By Joseph Weiss Department of Philosophy College of Liberal Arts and Sciences DePaul University Chicago, Illinois 2 ABSTRACT Joseph Weiss Title: The Idea of Mimesis: Semblance, Play and Critique in the Works of Walter Benjamin and Theodor W. Adorno Critical Theory demands that its forms of critique express resistance to the socially necessary illusions of a given historical period. Yet theorists have seldom discussed just how much it is the case that, for Walter Benjamin and Theodor W.
    [Show full text]
  • Heidegger, Being and Time
    Heidegger's Being and Time 1 Karsten Harries Heidegger's Being and Time Seminar Notes Spring Semester 2014 Yale University Heidegger's Being and Time 2 Copyright Karsten Harries [email protected] Heidegger's Being and Time 3 Contents 1. Introduction 4 2. Ontology and Fundamental Ontology 16 3. Methodological Considerations 30 4. Being-in-the-World 43 5. The World 55 6. Who am I? 69 7. Understanding, Interpretation, Language 82 8. Care and Truth 96 9. The Entirety of Dasein 113 10. Conscience, Guilt, Resolve 128 11. Time and Subjectivity 145 12. History and the Hero 158 13. Conclusion 169 Heidegger's Being and Time 4 1. Introduction 1 In this seminar I shall be concerned with Heidegger's Being and Time. I shall refer to other works by Heidegger, but the discussion will center on Being and Time. In reading the book, some of you, especially those with a reading knowledge of German, may find the lectures of the twenties helpful, which have appeared now as volumes of the Gesamtausgabe. Many of these have by now been translated. I am thinking especially of GA 17 Einführung in die phänomenologische Forschung (1923/24); Introduction to Phenomenological Research, trans. Daniel O. Dahlstrom (Bloomington, Indiana University Press, 2005) GA 20 Prolegomena zur Geschichte des Zeitbegriffs (1925); History of the Concept of Time, trans. Theodore Kisiel (Bloomington, Indiana University Press, 1985) GA 21 Logik. Die Frage nach der Wahrheit (1925/26). Logic: The Question of Truth, trans. Thomas Sheehan GA 24 Die Grundprobleme der Phänomenologie (1927); The Basic Problems of Phenomenology, trans.
    [Show full text]
  • Theories of Voice in Twentieth-Century Thought and Performance
    View metadata, citation and similar papers at core.ac.uk brought to you by CORE provided by Louisiana State University Louisiana State University LSU Digital Commons LSU Doctoral Dissertations Graduate School 2002 The sound of meaning: theories of voice in twentieth-century thought and performance Andrew McComb Kimbrough Louisiana State University and Agricultural and Mechanical College, [email protected] Follow this and additional works at: https://digitalcommons.lsu.edu/gradschool_dissertations Part of the Theatre and Performance Studies Commons Recommended Citation Kimbrough, Andrew McComb, "The ounds of meaning: theories of voice in twentieth-century thought and performance" (2002). LSU Doctoral Dissertations. 533. https://digitalcommons.lsu.edu/gradschool_dissertations/533 This Dissertation is brought to you for free and open access by the Graduate School at LSU Digital Commons. It has been accepted for inclusion in LSU Doctoral Dissertations by an authorized graduate school editor of LSU Digital Commons. For more information, please [email protected]. THE SOUND OF MEANING: THEORIES OF VOICE IN TWENTIETH-CENTURY THOUGHT AND PERFORMANCE A Dissertation Submitted to the Graduate Faculty of the Louisiana State University and Agricultural and Mechanical College in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy in The Department of Theatre by Andrew McComb Kimbrough B.A., Wake Forest University, 1984 M.F.A., Carnegie Mellon University, 1997 May 2002 © Copyright 2002 Andrew McComb Kimbrough All rights reserved ii To Liu Zhiguang iii TABLE OF CONTENTS ABSTRACT . .v CHAPTER 1 INTRODUCTION. 1 2 THE VOICE IN PALEOANTHROPOLOGY . 31 3 THE PHENOMENOLOGICAL VOICE. 82 4 THE MUTABLE VOICE IN THE LINGUISTIC TURN.
    [Show full text]
  • (Offen-Barkeit) of Différance, but Always from Within the Text
    Page 1 of 9 Original Research Beyond categories, proper names, types and norms toward a fragile openness (Offen-barkeit) of différance, but always from within the text Author: This article sought to respond to Wessel Stoker’s interpretation of transcendence, specifically 1 Johann-Albrecht Meylahn his last type: transcendence as alterity. It explored the possibilities of this last type as it moves Affiliation: beyond categories, proper names, types and norms toward a fragile openness of différance, 1Department of Practical always from within the text. This transcendence of alterity paves a way for discussion on what Theology, University of is beyond being or beyond language, either horizontally or vertically, so as to move away from Pretoria, South Africa dogmatic assertiveness toward a more poetic humility. This poetic humility, because of its Correspondence to: openness (Offen-barkeit) and its ‘undogmaticness’, offers a fragile creativeness to our cultural– Johann-Albrecht Meylahn social–environmental encounters and praxis. Such poetics is found in Heidegger’s work, as he interpreted humanity to dwell poetically in the house of being (language), if language speaks Email: as the Geläut der Stille. Yet Heidegger did not move far enough beyond names and proper [email protected] names, as he named and identified the kind of poetry that would be ‘proper’ to respond to the Postal address: Geläut der Stille. Derrida deconstructed Heidegger’s interpretation and exposed Heidegger’s PO Box 14885, Lyttelton disastrous method of capitalising cultural-political names, moving beyond such capitalisation 0140, South Africa of ‘proper’ names toward différance and a messianic expectation without Messiah. In this Dates: artricle, both Heidegger and Derrida’s conceptions were brought into dialogue with the Received: 22 Nov.
    [Show full text]
  • The Unfolding of Language and Being in Heidegger's Later Work, 1949-1976
    Duquesne University Duquesne Scholarship Collection Electronic Theses and Dissertations Fall 2009 Sprache als Be-wëgen: The nfoldinU g of Language and Being in Heidegger's Later Work, 1949-1976 Douglas F. Peduti Follow this and additional works at: https://dsc.duq.edu/etd Recommended Citation Peduti, D. (2009). Sprache als Be-wëgen: The nfoU lding of Language and Being in Heidegger's Later Work, 1949-1976 (Doctoral dissertation, Duquesne University). Retrieved from https://dsc.duq.edu/etd/1033 This Immediate Access is brought to you for free and open access by Duquesne Scholarship Collection. It has been accepted for inclusion in Electronic Theses and Dissertations by an authorized administrator of Duquesne Scholarship Collection. For more information, please contact [email protected]. SPRACHE ALS BE-WËGEN: THE UNFOLDING OF LANGUAGE AND BEING IN HEIDEGGER’S LATER WORK, 1949-1976 A Dissertation Submitted to the McAnulty College and Graduate School of Liberal Arts Duquesne University In partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy By Douglas Francis Peduti, S.J. December 2009 Copyright by Douglas F. Peduti, S.J. 2009 SPRACHE ALS BE-WËGEN: THE UNFOLDING OF LANGUAGE AND BEING IN HEIDEGGER’S LATER WORK, 1949-1976 By Douglas F. Peduti, S.J. Approved August 28, 2009 __________________________________ __________________________________ James Swindal, Ph.D. Richard Rojcewicz, Ph.D. Associate Professor of Philosophy Associate Professor of Philosophy (Dissertation Director) Point Park University (Reader) In memoriam, 27 February 2009 __________________________________ Wilhelm Wurzer, Ph.D. Andrew Cutrofello, Ph.D. Professor of Philosophy Professor and Graduate Program Director (Reader) Loyola University Chicago (Outside Reader) _________________________________ __________________________________ Christopher M.
    [Show full text]
  • Language Parasites
    language parasites Before you start to read this book, take this moment to think about making a donation to punctum books, an independent non-profit press @ https://punctumbooks.com/support If you’re reading the e-book, you can click on the image below to go directly to our donations site. Any amount, no matter the size, is appreciated and will help us to keep our ship of fools afloat. Contributions from dedicated readers will also help us to keep our commons open and to cultivate new work that can’t find a welcoming port elsewhere. Our adventure is not possible without your support. Vive la open-access. Fig. 1. Hieronymus Bosch, Ship of Fools (1490–1500) language parasites: of phorontology. Copyright © 2017 by Sean Braune. This work carries a Creative Commons BY-NC-SA 4.0 International license, which means that you are free to copy and redistribute the material in any medium or format, and you may also remix, transform and build upon the material, as long as you clearly attribute thew work to the authors (but not in a way that suggests the authors or punctum books endorses you and your work), you do not use this work for commercial gain in any form whatsoev- er, and that for any remixing and transformation, you distribute your rebuild under the same license. http://creativecommons.org/licenses/by-nc-sa/4.0/ First published in 2017 by punctum books, Earth, Milky Way. https://punctumbooks.com ISBN-13: 978-0-9985318-6-1 ISBN-10: 0-9985318-6-3 Library of Congress Cataloging Data is available from the Library of Congress Book design: Vincent W.J.
    [Show full text]
  • Thinking Between Heidegger and Dōgen
    echoes of no thing Before you start to read this book, take this moment to think about making a donation to punctum books, an independent non-profit press, @ https://punctumbooks.com/support/ If you’re reading the e-book, you can click on the image below to go directly to our donations site. Any amount, no matter the size, is appreciated and will help us to keep our ship of fools afloat. Contri- butions from dedicated readers will also help us to keep our commons open and to cultivate new work that can’t find a welcoming port elsewhere. Our ad- venture is not possible without your support. Vive la Open Access. Fig. 1. Hieronymus Bosch, Ship of Fools (1490–1500) echoes of no thing: thinking between heidegger and dōgen. Copyright © 2018 by Nico Jenkins. This work carries a Creative Commons BY-NC-SA 4.0 International license, which means that you are free to copy and redistribute the material in any medium or format, and you may also remix, transform and build upon the material, as long as you clearly attribute the work to the authors (but not in a way that suggests the authors or punctum books endorses you and your work), you do not use this work for commercial gain in any form whatsoever, and that for any remixing and transformation, you distribute your rebuild under the same license. http://creativecommons.org/licenses/by-nc-sa/4.0/ First published in 2018 by punctum books, Earth, Milky Way. https://punctumbooks.com ISBN-13: 978-1-950192-01-4 (print) ISBN-13: 978-1-950192-02-1 (ePDF) lccn: 2018968574 Library of Congress Cataloging Data is available from the Library of Congress Book design: Vincent W.J.
    [Show full text]
  • Rorty's Critique of Heidegger As a Metaphysician
    Aporia, Vol. I, No. 1 (Fall 1991) Rorty's Critique of Heidegger as a Metaphysician John M. Armstrong Richard Rorty aptly credits Martin Heidegger as being a decisive thinker in twentieth century philosophy and praises his critique of metaphysics as instrumental in overcoming the "other-worldliness" of philosophy. However, while Rorty's praise for Heidegger has made Heidegger's name more respectable among analytic philosophers, Rorty also criticizes Heidegger's talk of the "Thought of Being or the "openness of Being" as an unnecessary vestige of Platonism, a residue ofthe very metaphysical language that Heidegger is trying to overcome. Rorty writes,"Heidegger's attachment to the notion of'philosophy'— the pathetic notion that even after metaphysics goes, something called "Thought" might remain—is simply the sign of Heidegger's own fatal attachment to the tradition: the last infirmity of the greatest of the German professors"(1982,52). On Rorty's interpretation, this attach ment to the tradition is Heidegger's desire to get in touch with something in another realm called Being, a desire similar to Plato s search for the Forms,to Augustine's desire for God,and to Hegel's quest for Absolute Knowledge. I will show that Rorty interprets Heidegger as another metaphysi cian through what I think is a misguided reading of Heidegger's "Thought of Being." Rorty criticizes Heidegger for attempting to correctly apprehend Being—an other-worldly project unconcerned with the problems of his fellow human beings. However,in thinking the openness of Being, Heidegger was not concerned with apprehending Being correctly and although he was not engaged in finding cures for the ills of society, he was interested in how such cures might come about.
    [Show full text]
  • THE CATHOLIC UNIVERSITY of AMERICA Speaking and Thinking
    THE CATHOLIC UNIVERSITY OF AMERICA Speaking and Thinking about God in Rosenzweig and Heidegger A DISSERTATION Submitted to the Faculty of the School of Philosophy Of The Catholic University of America In Partial Fulfillment of the Requirements For the Degree Doctor of Philosophy By Paul Murphy Higgins Washington, D.C. 2013 Speaking and Thinking about God in Rosenzweig and Heidegger Paul Murphy Higgins, Ph.D. Director: Holger Zaborowski, D.Phil. In the early twentieth century, many philosophers began to reject Kantian and Hegelian approaches to the question of God and the philosophy of religion. The challenge was then to formulate a new way of talking about God within philosophy without necessarily having to revert to pre-modern accounts. These thinkers saw the importance of retaining the insights of modernity while also taking into account the Romantic and post-Romantic critiques of modernism as a one- sided or overly rationalistic enterprise. This dissertation seeks to provide a comprehensive picture of the approaches of Franz Rosenzweig and Martin Heidegger to rethinking the question of how philosophy is to proceed, especially in light of religious phenomena. Placing Rosenzweig and Heidegger in dialogue helps to further our understanding of both figures, particularly insofar as Rosenzweig’s thought might be used as a corrective to possible shortcomings in the later Heidegger. Many scholars have argued that there is something problematic about Heidegger’s religious thought, but Rosenzweig has been almost completely overlooked as an important corrective resource. Both Rosenzweig’s comprehensive account of the basic phenomena of human existence and his grammatical method for formulating this account share many of Heidegger’s insights, yet surpass them insofar as Rosenzweig is able to address the topic in a more philosophically cogent manner.
    [Show full text]
  • The House of Being: Poetry, Language, Place
    The House of Being: Poetry, Language, Place Jeff Malpas . I. One of the characteristic features of Heidegger's later thinking is its concern with language. Indeed, one might say that the centrality of this concern is a clear marker of the more strongly hermeneutical character of the later thinking (the thinking of the post-war years especially) compared to the earlier1 – a character that is present in spite of Heidegger's explicit claim to have abandoned hermeneutics (or, at least, to have abandoned the term) in his later work.2 The concern with language in the later Heidegger also coincides with a more explicit turn towards the topological – towards topos or place (Ort/Ortschaft).3 This is no mere coincidence. Not only are the topological and the hermeneutical themselves bound together,4 but Heidegger's topological 'turn' (which is really a return to something that is present throughout his thinking) itself develops out of his increasing engagement with both language and poetry especially as this is mediated through the work of Hölderlin.5 That these three – place, language, and poetry – are indeed tied together in the later Heidegger is especially evident in the 1947 'Letter on "Humanism"'. There Heidegger famously characterises language as "the house of being", adding that "in its home human being dwells".6 The themes of home and dwelling, and the very nature of the language that is invoked here, are connected directly back to Hölderlin7 in a way that is continuous with the engagement with the poet that had been underway in Heidegger's thinking for at least the previous fifteen years (from the early Hölderlin lectures beginning in 1934 to the Ister lectures of 19438), and that would continue long after (including the 1959 volume Unterwegs zur Sprache9).
    [Show full text]
  • Stony Brook University
    SSStttooonnnyyy BBBrrrooooookkk UUUnnniiivvveeerrrsssiiitttyyy The official electronic file of this thesis or dissertation is maintained by the University Libraries on behalf of The Graduate School at Stony Brook University. ©©© AAAllllll RRRiiiggghhhtttsss RRReeessseeerrrvvveeeddd bbbyyy AAAuuuttthhhooorrr... Discourses on Time in the European Avant-Garde A Dissertation Presented by Aaron Allen Hayes to The Graduate School in Partial Fulfillment of the Requirements for the Degree of Doctor of Philosophy in Music (Music History and Theory) Stony Brook University May 2016 Stony Brook University The Graduate School Aaron Allen Hayes We, the dissertation committee for the above candidate for the Doctor of Philosophy degree, hereby recommend acceptance of this dissertation. Judith Lochhead – Dissertation Advisor Professor, Department of Music, Stony Brook University Stephen Decatur Smith – Chairperson of Defense Assistant Professor, Department of Music, Stony Brook University Edward Casey Professor, Department of Philosophy, Stony Brook University Benjamin Steege Assistant Professor, Department of Music, Columbia University Brian Hulse – Outside Member Associate Professor, Department of Music, College of William and Mary This dissertation is accepted by the Graduate School Charles Taber Dean of the Graduate School ii Abstract of the Dissertation Discourses on Time in the European Avant-Garde by Aaron Allen Hayes Doctor of Philosophy in Music (Music History and Theory) Stony Brook University 2016 In the 1950s and 1960s, European composers, especially those interested in the development of serialism and electronic music, framed many of their aesthetic and compositional challenges as problems of time. This dissertation examines the writings and music of five notable composers from this era, and reconstructs the philosophical discourses that implicitly and explicitly provide the intellectual horizons for these temporal problems.
    [Show full text]
  • Running out of Space? Architecture and the Need for a Post-Copernican Geocentrism" February 23, 2017, Yale University
    Geocentrism 1 "Running out of Space? Architecture and The Need for a Post-Copernican Geocentrism" February 23, 2017, Yale University 1 For many years I taught a course called The Philosophy of Architecture. That I taught this course at all was the result of conversations with Kent Bloomer, who suggested, many years ago, that the undergraduate major could use such a course. Before then I had been teaching a course called The Philosophy of Modern Art. The Meaning of Modern Art, published in 1968, was the result of that course. That book was quite successful. After all these years it is still in print. But with its appearance I lost some of my interest in that course, and so I was quite ready to respond to Kent Bloomer’s invitation, especially so since my interest in architecture goes back to my childhood. That course, too, finally resulted in a Book, The Ethical Function of Architecture. It, too, has been successful. It was just honored with a second Festschrift. But, again, with the appearance of the book I lost some of my interest in the course, although I did teach it for one last time in the fall. But I have kept thinking and lecturing about architecture. Not that I have changed my position in any fundamental way. But circumstances have changed; the world has changed. More especially, the way we relate to space has changed and continues to change. Our understanding of space has changed; and since architecture may be understood as the art of bounding space that suggests that our understanding of architecture, too, will have changed.
    [Show full text]