Is Evolution Predictable? Quantitative Genetics Under Complex Genotype-Phenotype Maps

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Is Evolution Predictable? Quantitative Genetics Under Complex Genotype-Phenotype Maps bioRxiv preprint doi: https://doi.org/10.1101/578021; this version posted March 16, 2019. The copyright holder for this preprint (which was not certified by peer review) is the author/funder, who has granted bioRxiv a license to display the preprint in perpetuity. It is made available under aCC-BY 4.0 International license. 1 Title: Is evolution predictable? Quantitative genetics under complex genotype-phenotype maps *1 *1,2,3 2 Authors: Lisandro Milocco , Isaac Salazar-Ciudad 3 Affiliations: 4 1Institute of Biotechnology, University of Helsinki, 00014 Helsinki, Finland 5 2Centre de Recerca Matemàtica, 08193 Barcelona, Spain 6 3Genomics, Bioinformatics and Evolution. Departament de Genètica i Microbiologia, Universitat 7 Autònoma de Barcelona, 08193 Barcelona, Spain 8 *Correspondence to: 9 Isaac Salazar-Ciudad. Email: [email protected] Phone: +358 4148 26384 10 Lisandro Milocco, [email protected]. Phone: +358 4148 26384 11 1 bioRxiv preprint doi: https://doi.org/10.1101/578021; this version posted March 16, 2019. The copyright holder for this preprint (which was not certified by peer review) is the author/funder, who has granted bioRxiv a license to display the preprint in perpetuity. It is made available under aCC-BY 4.0 International license. 1 Abstract: A fundamental aim of post-genomic 21st century biology is to understand the 2 genotype-phenotype map (GPM) or how specific genetic variation relates to specific phenotypic 3 variation (1). Quantitative genetics approximates such maps using linear models, and has 4 developed methods to predict the response to selection in a population (2, 3). The other major 5 field of research concerned with the GPM, developmental evolutionary biology or evo-devo (1, 6 4–6), has found the GPM to be highly nonlinear and complex (4, 7). Here we quantify how the 7 predictions of quantitative genetics are affected by the complex, nonlinear maps found in 8 developmental biology. We combine a realistic development-based GPM model and a population 9 genetics model of recombination, mutation and natural selection. Each individual in the 10 population consists of a genotype and a multi-trait phenotype that arises through the 11 development model. We simulate evolution by applying natural selection on multiple traits per 12 individual. In addition, we estimate the quantitative genetics parameters required to predict the 13 response to selection. We found that the disagreements between predicted and observed 14 responses to selection are common, roughly in a third of generations, and are highly dependent 15 on the traits being selected. These disagreements are systematic and related to the nonlinear 16 nature of the genotype-phenotype map. Our results are a step towards integrating the fields 17 studying the GPM. 18 19 Introduction 20 A fundamental aim of post-genomic 21st century biology is to understand how genomic variation 21 relates to specific phenotypic variation. This relationship, called the genotype-phenotype map or 22 GPM, is considered by many researchers to be critical factor for understanding phenotypic 23 evolution (1). The GPM determines which phenotypic variation arises from which random 2 bioRxiv preprint doi: https://doi.org/10.1101/578021; this version posted March 16, 2019. The copyright holder for this preprint (which was not certified by peer review) is the author/funder, who has granted bioRxiv a license to display the preprint in perpetuity. It is made available under aCC-BY 4.0 International license. 1 genetic variation. Natural selection then acts on that realized phenotypic variation. Thus, natural 2 selection and the GPM jointly determine how traits change over evolutionary time. 3 Quantitative genetics uses a statistical approach to describe the GPM and predict 4 phenotypic change in evolution by natural selection. This approach has long made significant 5 contributions to plant and animal breeding (2,3). According to the breeder’s equation of 6 quantitative genetics (8, 9), the response to selection in a set of traits ( ), is the product of the 7 matrix of additive genetic variances and covariances between traits (the G-matrix) and the 8 selection gradient ( ), i.e. the direct strength of selection acting on each trait. 9 10 This is the canonical equation for inferring past selection and predicting future responses to 11 selection (10, 11). The G-matrix has been interpreted as a measure of genetic constraints on 12 future evolution (12), the diagonal elements of G measure the short-term readiness of a trait to 13 respond to selection while the off-diagonal elements measure how a trait evolution is slowed 14 down (or accelerated) by the evolution in other traits. 15 Developmental evolutionary biology or evo-devo (1, 4-6) is the other main field 16 concerned with the GPM. Evo-devo views the GPM as highly nonlinear and complex (4, 7). 17 Most evo-devo studies, however, do not consider the population level. At that level, it has been 18 suggested that the nonlinearities of the GPM will average out, and hence would not affect the 19 accuracy of quantitative genetics (13), at least in the short-term (14). 20 Our aim is to study how the predictions of the multivariate breeder’s equation are 21 affected when considering the complex and nonlinear GPMs found in the study of development. 22 For that purpose, we combine a computational GPM model that is based on current 23 understanding of developmental biology (15, 16) and a population genetics model with mutation, 3 bioRxiv preprint doi: https://doi.org/10.1101/578021; this version posted March 16, 2019. The copyright holder for this preprint (which was not certified by peer review) is the author/funder, who has granted bioRxiv a license to display the preprint in perpetuity. It is made available under aCC-BY 4.0 International license. 1 recombination, drift and natural selection. The developmental model has been shown to be able 2 to reproduce multivariate morphological variation at the population level (15). It includes a 3 network of gene regulatory interactions and cell and tissue biomechanical interactions. The 4 model’s parameters specify how strong or weak those interactions are. The value of each 5 individual’s parameter are determined additively by many loci. The developmental model 6 produces then, for each individual, a 3D morphological phenotype (see Fig. S1) on which a 7 number of traits are measured: the position of specific morphological landmarks. Individual 8 fitness is calculated as the distance between each of five traits in each individual and these same 9 traits in each simulation’s optimal morphology (see Supplementary Figs. 1, 2). The processes of 10 mutation, development and selection are iterated over generations to simulate trait evolution. At 11 the same time, we estimate G, P and s in each generation and use the multivariate breeder’s 12 equation to estimate the expected response to selection per generation. We then quantify the 13 difference between expected and observed trait changes in the simulations with a complex 14 development-based GPM (see Fig. S3). The difference we estimate should be regarded as the 15 minimal theoretically possible since we include no environmental noise (i.e. no environmental 16 variance) and G, P and s are estimated in each generation. 17 Results 18 We found that in many generations there is a significant discrepancy, or prediction error, 19 between the trait changes observed in the simulations and the trait changes predicted from the 20 multivariate breeder’s equations (see Fig. 1, Supplementary Video 1, 2, for two example 21 simulations). To study whether this prediction error is merely due to stochastic processes such as 22 drift, mutation or recombination, we re-simulated 40 times each generation of every simulation. 23 Since mutation, recombination and genetic drift are simulated as stochastic processes, different 4 bioRxiv preprint doi: https://doi.org/10.1101/578021; this version posted March 16, 2019. The copyright holder for this preprint (which was not certified by peer review) is the author/funder, who has granted bioRxiv a license to display the preprint in perpetuity. It is made available under aCC-BY 4.0 International license. 1 trait changes are observed in each of these 40 simulations (see the 99% confidence intervals 2 shown in a gray shade in Fig. 1). If the multivariate breeder’s equation is accurate, the expected 3 trait changes should not be statistically different from the the mean of these 40 observed changes. 4 However, as can be seen in the simulations in Fig. 1, the deviation is significant for a large 5 number of generations. There is, thus, a systematic prediction error that is not explainable from 6 stochastic processes. We refer to this systematic error as bias. For the simulation shown in Fig. 7 1A, the bias is large and significant between generations 15 and 55. 8 Bias was not exclusive to a single trait or simulation (see Fig. S4). Bias was common. 9 Fig. 2 shows the percentage of generations across all simulations that showed significant bias 10 with 99% confidence. For individual simulations the median was that 30% of the generations 11 showed significant bias in traits 2 and 4 (the x-position of each lateral cusps) and less so for the 12 three traits. Bias can be very large, see Fig. 2B. Considering all traits together, the prediction 13 error divided by the observed change per generation is at least 46% for half of the generations 14 exhibiting significant bias. 15 We found that in our simulations bias arises from nonlinearities in the GPM. Fig. 3 and 16 Fig. S5 show explanatory examples of how specific aspects of the developmental dynamics lead 17 to nonlinearities and then to bias. Bias correlates with measures of the linearity of the GPM 18 around the region of the parameter space where the population is distributed at a given 19 generation (see Fig.
Recommended publications
  • From Developmental Constraint to Evolvability
    From Developmental Constraint to Evolvability How Concepts Figure in Explanation and Disciplinary Identity Ingo Brigandt Department of Philosophy, University of Alberta 2-40 Assiniboia Hall, Edmonton, AB T6G2E7, Canada [email protected] Abstract The concept of developmental constraint was at the heart of develop- mental approaches to evolution of the 1980s. While this idea was widely used to criticize neo-Darwinian evolutionary theory, critique does not yield an alternative framework that offers evolutionary explanations. In current Evo-devo the concept of constraint is of minor importance, whereas notions as evolvability are at the center of attention. The latter clearly defines an explanatory agenda for evolution- ary research, so that one could view the historical shift from ‘developmental con- straint’ towards ‘evolvability’ as the move from a concept that is a mere tool of criticism to a concept that establishes a positive explanatory project. However, by taking a look at how the concept of constraint was employed in the 1980s, I argue that developmental constraint was not just seen as restricting possibilities (‘con- straining’), but also as facilitating morphological change in several ways. Ac- counting for macroevolutionary transformation and the origin of novel form was an aim of these developmental approaches to evolution. Thus, the concept of de- velopmental constraint was part of a positive explanatory agenda long before the advent of Evo-devo as a genuine scientific discipline. In the 1980s, despite the lack of a clear disciplinary identity, this concept coordinated research among pale- ontologists, morphologists, and developmentally inclined evolutionary biologists. I discuss the different functions that scientific concepts can have, highlighting that instead of classifying or explaining natural phenomena, concepts such as ‘devel- opmental constraint’ and ‘evolvability’ are more important in setting explanatory agendas so as to provide intellectual coherence to scientific approaches.
    [Show full text]
  • Why Call It Developmental Bias When It Is Just Development? Isaac Salazar-Ciudad1,2,3
    Salazar-Ciudad Biology Direct (2021) 16:3 https://doi.org/10.1186/s13062-020-00289-w OPINION Open Access Why call it developmental bias when it is just development? Isaac Salazar-Ciudad1,2,3 Abstract The concept of developmental constraints has been central to understand the role of development in morphological evolution. Developmental constraints are classically defined as biases imposed by development on the distribution of morphological variation. This opinion article argues that the concepts of developmental constraints and developmental biases do not accurately represent the role of development in evolution. The concept of developmental constraints was coined to oppose the view that natural selection is all-capable and to highlight the importance of development for understanding evolution. In the modern synthesis, natural selection was seen as the main factor determining the direction of morphological evolution. For that to be the case, morphological variation needs to be isotropic (i.e. equally possible in all directions). The proponents of the developmental constraint concept argued that development makes that some morphological variation is more likely than other (i.e. variation is not isotropic), and that, thus, development constraints evolution by precluding natural selection from being all-capable. This article adds to the idea that development is not compatible with the isotropic expectation by arguing that, in fact, it could not be otherwise: there is no actual reason to expect that development could lead to isotropic morphological variation. It is then argued that, since the isotropic expectation is untenable, the role of development in evolution should not be understood as a departure from such an expectation.
    [Show full text]
  • Getting to Evo-Devo: Concepts and Challenges for Students Learning Evolutionary Developmental Biology Anna Hiatt
    Bryn Mawr College Scholarship, Research, and Creative Work at Bryn Mawr College Biology Faculty Research and Scholarship Biology 2013 Getting to Evo-Devo: Concepts and Challenges for Students Learning Evolutionary Developmental Biology Anna Hiatt Gregory K. Davis Bryn Mawr College, [email protected] Caleb Trujillo Mark Terry Donald P. French See next page for additional authors Let us know how access to this document benefits ouy . Follow this and additional works at: http://repository.brynmawr.edu/bio_pubs Part of the Biology Commons Custom Citation Hiatt A, Davis GK, Trujillo C, Terry M, French DP, Price RM and Perez KE . "Getting to evo-devo: concepts and challenges for students learning evolutionary developmental biology". CBE-Life Sciences Education 12 (2013): 494-508. This paper is posted at Scholarship, Research, and Creative Work at Bryn Mawr College. http://repository.brynmawr.edu/bio_pubs/10 For more information, please contact [email protected]. Authors Anna Hiatt, Gregory K. Davis, Caleb Trujillo, Mark Terry, Donald P. French, Rebecca M. Price, and Kathryn E. Perez This article is available at Scholarship, Research, and Creative Work at Bryn Mawr College: http://repository.brynmawr.edu/ bio_pubs/10 CBE—Life Sciences Education Vol. 12, 494–508, Fall 2013 Article Getting to Evo-Devo: Concepts and Challenges for Students Learning Evolutionary Developmental Biology Anna Hiatt,*† Gregory K. Davis,‡ Caleb Trujillo,§ Mark Terry, Donald P. French,* Rebecca M. Price,¶ and Kathryn E. Perez** *Department of Zoology, Oklahoma
    [Show full text]
  • Evodevo: an Ongoing Revolution?
    philosophies Article EvoDevo: An Ongoing Revolution? Salvatore Ivan Amato Department of Cognitive Sciences, University of Messina, Via Concezione 8, 98121 Messina, Italy; [email protected] or [email protected] Received: 27 September 2020; Accepted: 2 November 2020; Published: 5 November 2020 Abstract: Since its appearance, Evolutionary Developmental Biology (EvoDevo) has been called an emerging research program, a new paradigm, a new interdisciplinary field, or even a revolution. Behind these formulas, there is the awareness that something is changing in biology. EvoDevo is characterized by a variety of accounts and by an expanding theoretical framework. From an epistemological point of view, what is the relationship between EvoDevo and previous biological tradition? Is EvoDevo the carrier of a new message about how to conceive evolution and development? Furthermore, is it necessary to rethink the way we look at both of these processes? EvoDevo represents the attempt to synthesize two logics, that of evolution and that of development, and the way we conceive one affects the other. This synthesis is far from being fulfilled, but an adequate theory of development may represent a further step towards this achievement. In this article, an epistemological analysis of EvoDevo is presented, with particular attention paid to the relations to the Extended Evolutionary Synthesis (EES) and the Standard Evolutionary Synthesis (SET). Keywords: evolutionary developmental biology; evolutionary extended synthesis; theory of development 1. Introduction: The House That Charles Built Evolutionary biology, as well as science in general, is characterized by a continuous genealogy of problems, i.e., “a kind of dialectical sequence” of problems that are “linked together in a continuous family tree” [1] (p.
    [Show full text]
  • A Release from Developmental Bias Accelerates Morphological Diversification in Butterfly Eyespots
    A release from developmental bias accelerates morphological diversification in butterfly eyespots Oskar Brattströma,b,1,2, Kwaku Aduse-Pokua,3, Erik van Bergena,4, Vernon Frenchc, and Paul M. Brakefielda,d aDepartment of Zoology, University of Cambridge, CB2 3EJ Cambridge, United Kingdom; bAfrican Butterfly Research Institute (ABRI), 0800 Nairobi, Kenya; cInstitute of Evolutionary Biology, University of Edinburgh, Edinburgh, EH9 3JT, United Kingdom; and dCambridge University Museum of Zoology, CB2 3EJ Cambridge, United Kingdom Edited by Sean B. Carroll, Howard Hughes Medical Institute, College Park, MD, and approved September 8, 2020 (received for review April 28, 2020) Development can bias the independent evolution of traits sharing cells releasing a signal (e.g., a diffusible morphogen) that spreads ontogenetic pathways, making certain evolutionary changes less out to form a circular concentration gradient (21, 26). The sur- likely. The eyespots commonly found on butterfly wings each have rounding cells have sensitivity thresholds that direct the color of the concentric rings of differing colors, and these serially repeated pigmented scales that are formed. Below a certain signal threshold, pattern elements have been a focus for evo–devo research. In the the cells do not respond and will continue to develop into the butterfly family Nymphalidae, eyespots have been shown to func- normal base color of the wing, effectively forming the outer edge tion in startling or deflecting predators and to be involved in sex- of the eyespot. Despite two decades of research gradually unrav- ual selection. Previous work on a model species of Mycalesina eling the genetic basis of the developmental processes of butterfly butterfly, Bicyclus anynana, has provided insights into the devel- eyespots, the exact nature of the focal signal remains unknown.
    [Show full text]
  • The Structure of Evolutionary Theory: Beyond Neo-Darwinism, Neo
    1 2 3 The structure of evolutionary theory: Beyond Neo-Darwinism, 4 Neo-Lamarckism and biased historical narratives about the 5 Modern Synthesis 6 7 8 9 10 Erik I. Svensson 11 12 Evolutionary Ecology Unit, Department of Biology, Lund University, SE-223 62 Lund, 13 SWEDEN 14 15 Correspondence: [email protected] 16 17 18 19 1 20 Abstract 21 The last decades have seen frequent calls for a more extended evolutionary synthesis (EES) that 22 will supposedly overcome the limitations in the current evolutionary framework with its 23 intellectual roots in the Modern Synthesis (MS). Some radical critics even want to entirely 24 abandon the current evolutionary framework, claiming that the MS (often erroneously labelled 25 “Neo-Darwinism”) is outdated, and will soon be replaced by an entirely new framework, such 26 as the Third Way of Evolution (TWE). Such criticisms are not new, but have repeatedly re- 27 surfaced every decade since the formation of the MS, and were particularly articulated by 28 developmental biologist Conrad Waddington and paleontologist Stephen Jay Gould. 29 Waddington, Gould and later critics argued that the MS was too narrowly focused on genes and 30 natural selection, and that it ignored developmental processes, epigenetics, paleontology and 31 macroevolutionary phenomena. More recent critics partly recycle these old arguments and 32 argue that non-genetic inheritance, niche construction, phenotypic plasticity and developmental 33 bias necessitate major revision of evolutionary theory. Here I discuss these supposed 34 challenges, taking a historical perspective and tracing these arguments back to Waddington and 35 Gould. I dissect the old arguments by Waddington, Gould and more recent critics that the MS 36 was excessively gene centric and became increasingly “hardened” over time and narrowly 37 focused on natural selection.
    [Show full text]
  • Phenotype Bias Determines How RNA Structures Occupy the Morphospace of All Possible Shapes
    bioRxiv preprint doi: https://doi.org/10.1101/2020.12.03.410605; this version posted December 3, 2020. The copyright holder for this preprint (which was not certified by peer review) is the author/funder, who has granted bioRxiv a license to display the preprint in perpetuity. It is made available under aCC-BY-NC-ND 4.0 International license. Phenotype bias determines how RNA structures occupy the morphospace of all possible shapes Kamaludin Dingle1, Fatme Ghaddar1, Petr Sulcˇ 2, Ard A. Louis3 1Centre for Applied Mathematics and Bioinformatics, Department of Mathematics and Natural Sciences, Gulf University for Science and Technology, Hawally 32093, Kuwait, 2School of Molecular Sciences and Center for Molecular Design and Biomimetics at the Biodesign Institute, Arizona State University, Tempe, AZ, USA 3Rudolf Peierls Centre for Theoretical Physics, University of Oxford, Parks Road, Oxford, OX1 3PU, United Kingdom (Dated: December 3, 2020) The relative prominence of developmental bias versus natural selection is a long standing con- troversy in evolutionary biology. Here we demonstrate quantitatively that developmental bias is the primary explanation for the occupation of the morphospace of RNA secondary structure (SS) shapes. By using the RNAshapes method to define coarse-grained SS classes, we can directly mea- sure the frequencies that non-coding RNA SS shapes appear in nature. Our main findings are, firstly, that only the most frequent structures appear in nature: The vast majority of possible struc- tures in the morphospace have not yet been explored. Secondly, and perhaps more surprisingly, these frequencies are accurately predicted by the likelihood that structures appear upon uniform random sampling of sequences.
    [Show full text]
  • Development Evolution 9. Phenotypic Plasticity Phenotypic Plasticity
    Development Evolution 9. Phenotypic plasticity 1. development 2. evolution The short version: 3. epigenetics 4. canalization 5. cryptic genetic variation / capacitance phenotype depends on the environment 6. genetic assimilation 7. evolvability 8. preadaptation 9. phenotypic plasticity 10. epistasis 11. modularity 12. developmental bias / constraint Phenotypic plasticity: long version Phenotypic plasticity • Gradual response to environmental gradient OR “When I use a word, it means just what I discrete switching between types choose it to mean – neither more nor less” • Fixed traits (eg size after metamorphosis) OR Humpty Dumpty labile traits (eg behavioral) • Change in the phenotypic mean (reaction norm) OR change in the phenotypic variance “When I make a word do a lot of work like that, • Response to a directional environmental shift OR I always pay it extra” response to residual environmental “noise” Humpty Dumpty • Adaptive, evolved response OR side effect of basic physiology How does phenotypic plasticity trait Spectrum adaptive tie in to other concepts? phenotypic plasticity Some contradictory (?) ideas: random preadapted • Genetic assimilation of plastic trait is loss not gain mutation cryptic variation of complexity, so genetic assimilation is irrelevant • Random variation unlikely to be adaptive to the evolution of novelty (Williams) • Very deleterious stuff weeded out • Canalization is the opposite of phenotypic • Revealed variation more likely to be adaptive plasticity (Goggy) • Trait needed briefly, then lost • Revelation of cryptic genetic variation in response • Easier to find it again in cryptic variation to stress is one kind of phenotypic plasticity • Frequent environmental switching ⇒ evolution of adaptive phenotypic plasticity (or reaction norm) • Environment stabilizes ⇒ genetic assimilation with loss of complexity 1 10.
    [Show full text]
  • Downloaded from Brill.Com09/24/2021 08:16:07PM Via Free Access 210 R.A
    Contributions to Zoology, 74 (1/2) 209-211 (2005) Short notes and reviews Combating footnote status in evolutionary theory Ronald A. Jenner Section of Evolution & Ecology, University of California, Davis, CA95616, USA (e-mail: rajenner@ucdavis. edu) Review of: Biased Embryos and Evolution, by empirical and theoretical information generated Wallace Arthur. Cambridge University Press, 2004, within the mushrooming discipline of evolutionary xiii + 233 pp. ISBN 0 521 54161 1 (Paperback). development biology, or, in short, evo-devo. De- pending on the reader’s background, they can then On 11 May 2004, Wallace Arthur presented a char- choose to flesh out Arthur’s conceptual framework acteristically engaging seminar at the Department with intellectually more taxing and empirically of Zoology of the University of Cambridge in or- more dense works such as Gerhart and Kirschner der to promote his new book Biased Embryos and (1997), Davidson (2001), Minelli (2003), and Wilkins Evolution. After the lecture the speaker and his au- (2002). dience adjourned to the University Museum of Zo- The core question in Arthur’s book is: what de- ology for the official launch of the book. There, termines the direction of evolutionary change? A amidst wine and canapés, the flocked friends and resounding “natural selection!” will certainly be collected colleagues were given the opportunity to the most common answer to this question from the purchase, with a considerable reduction in prize of educated layman to most professional biologists. course, the first copies of Arthur’s book, which the However, Arthur labels this expected answer as author dutifully signed in between his munching of “overly Darwinian” (p.
    [Show full text]
  • The Role of Developmental Bias In
    THE ROLE OF DEVELOPMENTAL BIAS IN A SIMULATED EVO-DEVO SYSTEM by SEAN THOMAS PSUJEK Submitted in partial fulfillments of the requirements For the degree of Doctor of Philosophy Department of Biology CASE WESTERN RESERVE UNIVERSITY May, 2009 CASE WESTERN RESERVE UNIVERSITY SCHOOL OF GRADUATE STUDIES We hereby approve the thesis/dissertation of _____________________________________________________ candidate for the ______________________degree *. (signed)_______________________________________________ (chair of the committee) ________________________________________________ ________________________________________________ ________________________________________________ ________________________________________________ ________________________________________________ (date) _______________________ *We also certify that written approval has been obtained for any proprietary material contained therein. Table of Contents Abstract .............................................................................................................................. 2 List of Figures ................................................................................................................... 4 Chapter 1 : Introduction ...................................................................................................... 6 Chapter 2 : Background .................................................................................................... 12 Modeling in Evo-devo ...............................................................................................
    [Show full text]
  • Evolution & Development
    Received: 28 March 2019 | Revised: 5 August 2019 | Accepted: 6 August 2019 DOI: 10.1111/ede.12312 RESEARCH Developmental bias in the fossil record Illiam S. C. Jackson Department of Biology, Lund University, Sweden Abstract The role of developmental bias and plasticity in evolution is a central research Correspondence interest in evolutionary biology. Studies of these concepts and related Illiam S. C. Jackson, Lund University, Sweden. processes are usually conducted on extant systems and have seen limited Email: [email protected] investigation in the fossil record. Here, I identify plasticity‐led evolution (PLE) as a form of developmental bias accessible through scrutiny of paleontological Funding information Knut och Alice Wallenbergs Stiftelse, material. I summarize the process of PLE and describe it in terms of the Grant/Award Number: KAW 2012.0155 environmentally mediated accumulation and release of cryptic genetic variation. Given this structure, I then predict its manifestation in the fossil record, discuss its similarity to quantum evolution and punctuated equili- brium, and argue that these describe macroevolutionary patterns concordant with PLE. Finally, I suggest methods and directions towards providing evidence of PLE in the fossil record and conclude that such endeavors are likely to be highly rewarding. KEYWORDS cryptic genetic variation, developmental bias, plasticity‐led evolution 1 | INTRODUCTION we might expect to result from PLE in the fossil record, anchor these patterns in historical work and suggest Developmental bias describes the manner in which methods and future directions for examining PLE using certain changes to development are more accessible to fossil data. evolution than others (Arthur, 2004). A key generator of developmental bias, and integral to understanding its role in evolution, is developmental plasticity, which 2 | CONSTRUCTIVE refers to an organism’s ability to adjust its phenotype in DEVELOPMENT response to environmental conditions (Laland et al., 2015; Schwab, Casasa, & Moczek, 2019).
    [Show full text]
  • Animal Learning As a Source of Developmental Bias
    1 2 3 4 5 Animal Learning as a Source of Developmental Bias 6 7 In: Developmental Bias in Evolution, 8 Special Edition of Evolution and Development 9 10 11 12 13 Kevin N Laland1, Wataru Toyokawa1,2,3 & Thomas Oudman1,4 14 15 1 School of Biology, University of St Andrews, St Andrews, UK 16 2 Department of Evolutionary Studies of Biosystems, SOKENDAI (The Graduate University for Advanced 17 Studies), Hayama, Kanagawa 240-0193, Japan 18 3 Current address: Department of Psychology, University of Konstanz, Germany 19 4 NIOZ Royal Netherlands Institute for Sea Research, Department of Coastal Systems, and Utrecht University, 20 The Netherlands 21 22 23 The authors declare that they have no relevant conflicts of interest. 24 25 Article: Laland, KN, Toyokawa, W & Oudman, T 2019, 'Animal learning as a source of 26 developmental bias' Evolution and Development, vol. Early View, 27 e12311. https://doi.org/10.1111/ede.12311 28 Pure ID: 260877183 29 30 Author accepted manuscript (accepted August 10 2019) 1 31 ABSTRACT. As a form of adaptive plasticity that allows organisms to shift their phenotype 32 toward the optimum, learning is inherently a source of developmental bias. Learning may be 33 of particular significance to the evolutionary biology community because it allows animals to 34 generate adaptively biased novel behavior tuned to the environment and, through social 35 learning, to propagate behavioral traits to other individuals, also in an adaptively biased 36 manner. We describe several types of developmental bias manifest in learning, including an 37 adaptive bias, historical bias, origination bias and transmission bias, stressing that these can 38 influence evolutionary dynamics through generating nonrandom phenotypic variation and/or 39 nonrandom environmental states.
    [Show full text]