RESEARCH…RESEARCH…RESEARCH Answering the Questions of Society Utilizing the Sociological Research Methodology

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

RESEARCH…RESEARCH…RESEARCH Answering the Questions of Society Utilizing the Sociological Research Methodology RESEARCH…RESEARCH…RESEARCH Answering the Questions of Society Utilizing the Sociological Research Methodology Marshall High School Sociology Mr. Cline Unit Two AF * Can Sociology Be Considered a Science? • As we consider how to do Sociology, we have looked at it from the perspective of Sociology as a science. • But, as you could see as we went through how to do it, there are several elements of it, and a great deal of societal criticism of it, questioning it as such. • This then begs the question, can Sociology be considered a real science, or is it just a bunch of do gooder, social activists, attempting to foist their political views on people under the guise of science? • Before considering whether Sociology can be considered a science, we first have to try to understand what science is • And, this understanding must come from the question, “How do we acquire knowledge and determine truth?” * Can Sociology Be Considered a Science? • Epistemologists (those who study how knowledge is acquired) have recognized four sources of where mankind has acquired knowledge • The Authoritarian Model states that people acquired knowledge through it being relayed from a trusted source of authority such as the government, the church, parents, etc. • The Mystical Model states that people acquire knowledge through religious revelation and divine spiritual guidance • The Deductive Model posits that people acquire knowledge through the application of reasoned thought, such as in mathematics • The Empirical or Scientific Method is the youngest of the four models, having only come into full existence 300 years ago, and posits that knowledge can only be acquired through observation and rigorous testing of hypotheses. * Can Sociology Be Considered a Science? • Some epistemologists would argue that the scientific method has a claim to superiority because results can be tested and replicated by others, thus verifying their “truth.” • While philosophy and mathematics may also be “truth” their truths are not applicable or necessarily linked to the “real world” as different dimensions of time and space have different properties. • As discussed previously in the birth of Sociology, a group of scientific philosophers that included the father of Sociology, Auguste Comte, felt that all of the universe could be explained through the scientific method. • They are known as the Positivists * Can Sociology Be Considered a Science? • Positivists engage in a process of hypo-deductive reasoning to prove truth. • Hypo-Deductive reasoning entails developing a theory and inviting others to prove you wrong. • It is based on the concept that nothing can be proven 100% true but theories can be proven false. • For example, I would never be able to prove that I am going to live forever but others could quite easily prove I won’t by killing me. • It is reasoned that if many fail to prove a theory wrong it has an increased likelihood of being correct or true (but we will never be 100% sure.) * Can Sociology Be Considered a Science? • According to positivists for theories to be scientific they must be subject to falsifiability. • Falsifiability or Refutability is the property of a statement, hypothesis, or theory whereby it could be shown to be false if some conceivable observation were true. • In this sense, falsify is synonymous with nullify, meaning not "to commit fraud" but "show to be false". • Science must be falsifiable. • Logical and rational reasoning, such as that used in the Deductive Model, suggest that there is a firm truth that can be proven with evidence. * Can Sociology Be Considered a Science? • However, inductive reasoning counters this by saying that deductive reasoning suffers from two fallacies • Over Generalization about the properties of a class of objects based on a limited number of observations. • For example, if you have only ever seen white swans, a deductive argument would state that all swans are white. • Presupposition that a sequence of events in the future will occur as it always has in the past • For example, that the laws of physics will hold as they have always been observed to hold, which does not hold true because the so called Law of Gravity does not hold were I on the moon. • By the problem introduced by the process of induction, no number of confirming observations can verify a universal generalization, such as All swans are white. * Can Sociology Be Considered a Science? • Yet, it is logically possible to falsify it by observing a single black swan. • Thus, the term falsifiability is sometimes synonymous to testability. • The concern with falsifiability gained attention by way of philosopher of science Karl Popper. • Popper stressed that to distinguish the scientific from the unscientific, falsifiability has to be the demarcation, or dividing point, such that what is unfalsifiable is classified as unscientific, and the practice of declaring an unfalsifiable theory to be scientifically true is pseudoscience. • In falsificationism, an unfalsifiable and thus unscientific theory is not necessarily intrinsically false or inappropriate, since metaphysical theories might be true or contain truth, but one cannot know for sure. • Simply, to be scientific, a theory must entail at least one observation, which may or may not be the case. * Can Sociology Be Considered a Science? • Positivists believe that a scientifically backed theory is far more valid than one that is not backed up with quality evidence. • Positivists see the world as being full of concrete testable realities. • Positivists use quantitative methods to support their theories. • Interpretivists are very skeptical with regard to the positivists ‘scientific’ claims. • They see the world as mainly a socially constructed place. • By this they mean that reality as we understand it only exists because of agreed shared concepts • Or, in other words, knowledge itself is whatever we agree it to be. • For example most people would recognize a chair as something useful to sit on, but if you took it to a tribe who had been isolated from the rest of the world and were a very aggressive group they may view it as a shield with spikes on it. * Can Sociology Be Considered a Science? • Context is therefore a hugely important aspect of knowledge itself, and so context is really important when we are trying to understand/interpret a situation. • Interpretivists don’t think that scientific methodology is useful to the study of human interactions or sociology. • They see it as not valid because it often removes the context or interferes in some way with the subject matter. • Interpretivists use qualitative research techniques such as ethnographic techniques for example observations and unstructured interviews. WHICH OF THESE TWO DO YOU THINK IS THE POSITIVIST, AND WHICH THE INTERPRETIVIST? * Can Sociology Be Considered a Science? • Even among Positivists, however, there is disagreement about whether a theoretical subject such as Sociology can truly be considered a science. • To examine this controversy, we must look closer at what actually constitutes something being a science. • Epistemologists seem to agree that in order for a field to be considered a science it must meet the following criteria: • It must have testable concepts • It must rely on accurate gathering of information in order to obtain reliable measurable data • It must be able to make generalizations based on the research conducted to establish universal laws. We refer to this as being theoretical. • It must be objective (unbiased) • It must be based on practical investigations and empirical evidence, and • Research must be able to build on prior research, and thus the knowledge gained be cumulative * Can Sociology Be Considered a Science? • If we compare these criteria against the field of Sociology, we find that: • Sociology can be done empirically, meaning that theories can be tested and are verifiable by observation or experience • Durkheim’s Suicide study presented a theory that people commit suicide due to lack of involvement in a strong social support structure. • He was able to test this through the experience of those who had committed suicide as recorded in historical and governmental records • Sociology when done empirically, however, has a strong probability of not being falsifiable, or testable. • Testability means that the scientist must formulate a theory, and then test it. • However, in Durkheim’s Suicide study, he utilized the inductive method wherein he gathered data, and then developed a theory to test. * Can Sociology Be Considered a Science? • Sociology when done empirically, however, has a strong probability of not being falsifiable, or testable. • This would certainly seem to argue against Sociology’s claim to being a science, as • Sociology cannot use laboratory experiments to test theories • And, it cannot isolate the variables in a situation • However, this is true of other recognized “hard” sciences as well, such as • cosmology, • meteorology, • volcanology, and • animal behavior. • And, this does not stop theories being tested by observation within them • However, sociologists do claim that comparative methods allow for the testing of a result (triangulation) * Can Sociology Be Considered a Science? • Triangulation is when a study uses one method for its research, such as a survey, but then validates the results obtained from that method with results from another method such as secondary analysis. • Some sociologists see triangulation as a means by which to assess the validity and reliability of research
Recommended publications
  • The Political and Social Philosophy of Auguste Comte
    THE POLITICAL AND SOCIAL PHILOSOPHY OF AUGUSTE COMTE. BY HARRY ELMER BARNES. I. LIFE AND WORKS. IT was one hundred years in May of this year since Auguste Comte pubHshed the famous prospectus of his comprehensive social philosophy under the title of Plan dcs travaux scientifiques ncccssaires pour reorganiser la societe} In the century which has passed many one-sided philosophies of society have been proposed and many incomplete schemes of social reform propounded. Many writers in recent years have, however, tended to revert to the position of Comte that we must have a philosophy of society which includes a consideration of biological, psychological and historical factors, and a program of social reform which will provide for an increase both in technical efficiency and in social morale.- Further, there has also developed a wide-spread distrust of the "pure" democracy of the last century and a growing feeling that we must endeavor more and more to install in positions of political and social power that intellectual aristocracy in which Comte placed his faith as the desirable leaders in the reconstruction of European society.'' In the light of the above facts a brief analysis of the political and social philosophy of Comte may have practical as well as historical interest to students of philosophy and social science. Auguste Comte ws born in MontpelHer in 1798, and received his higher education at the Ecole Polytcchnique. During six years 1 See the brief article on this matter in the American Journal of Sociology, January, 1922, pp. 510-13. - See Publications of the American Sociological Society, 1920, pp.
    [Show full text]
  • Auguste Comte and Positivism 1 a Free Download From
    Auguste Comte and Positivism 1 A free download from http://manybooks.net PART I. PART II. Auguste Comte and Positivism Project Gutenberg's Auguste Comte and Positivism, by John-Stuart Mill This eBook is for the use of anyone anywhere at no cost and with almost no restrictions whatsoever. You may copy it, give it away or re-use it under the terms of the Project Gutenberg License included with this eBook or online at www.gutenberg.net Title: Auguste Comte and Positivism Author: John-Stuart Mill Release Date: October 9, 2005 [EBook #16833] PART I. 2 Language: English Character set encoding: ISO-8859-1 *** START OF THIS PROJECT GUTENBERG EBOOK AUGUSTE COMTE AND POSITIVISM *** Produced by Marc D'Hooghe AUGUSTE COMTE AND POSITIVISM BY JOHN STUART MILL 1865. * * * * * PART I. THE COURS DE PHILOSOPHIE POSITIVE. For some time much has been said, in England and on the Continent, concerning "Positivism" and "the Positive Philosophy." Those phrases, which during the life of the eminent thinker who introduced them had made their way into no writings or discussions but those of his very few direct disciples, have emerged from the depths and manifested themselves on the surface of the philosophy of the age. It is not very widely known what they represent, but it is understood that they represent something. They are symbols of a recognised mode of thought, and one of sufficient importance to induce almost all who now discuss the great problems of philosophy, or survey from any elevated point of view the opinions of the age, to take what is termed the Positivist view of things into serious consideration, and PART I.
    [Show full text]
  • Auguste Comte
    Module-2 AUGUSTE COMTE (1798-1857) Developed by: Dr. Subrata Chatterjee Associate Professor of Sociology Khejuri College P.O- Baratala, Purba Medinipur West Bengal, India AUGUSTE COMTE (1798-1857) Isidore-Auguste-Marie-François-Xavier Comte is regarded as the founders of Sociology. Comte’s father parents were strongly royalist and deeply sincere Roman Catholics. But their sympathies were at odds with the republicanism and skepticism that swept through France in the aftermath of the French Revolution. Comte resolved these conflicts at an early age by rejecting Roman Catholicism and royalism alike. Later on he was influenced by several important French political philosophers of the 18th century—such as Montesquieu, the Marquis de Condorcet, A.-R.-J. Turgot, and Joseph de Maistre. Comte’s most important acquaintance in Paris was Henri de Saint-Simon, a French social reformer and one of the founders of socialism, who was the first to clearly see the importance of economic organization in modern society. The major works of Auguste Comte are as follows: 1. The Course on Positive Philosophy (1830-1842) 2. Discourse on the Positive Sprit (1844) 3. A General View of Positivism (1848) 4. Religion of Humanity (1856) Theory of Positivism As a philosophical ideology and movement positivism first assumed its distinctive features in the work of the French philosopher Auguste Comte, who named the systematized science of sociology. It then developed through several stages known by various names, such as Empiriocriticism, Logical Positivism and Logical Empiricism and finally in the mid-20th century flowed into the movement known as Analytic and Linguistic philosophy.
    [Show full text]
  • Journal of Interdisciplinary History of Ideas, 16 | 2019 [Online], Online Since 31 December 2019, Connection on 30 July 2020
    Journal of Interdisciplinary History of Ideas 16 | 2019 Varia Electronic version URL: http://journals.openedition.org/jihi/276 ISSN: 2280-8574 Publisher GISI – UniTo Electronic reference Journal of Interdisciplinary History of Ideas, 16 | 2019 [Online], Online since 31 December 2019, connection on 30 July 2020. URL : http://journals.openedition.org/jihi/276 This text was automatically generated on 30 July 2020. Creative Commons Attribution-ShareAlike 4.0 International Public License 1 TABLE OF CONTENTS Éditorial Manuela Albertone and Enrico Pasini Articles Rendering Sociology. On the Utopian Positivism of Harriet Martineau and the ‘Mumbo Jumbo Club’ Matthew Wilson Individualism and Social Change An Unexpected Theoretical Dilemma in Marxian Analysis Vitantonio Gioia Notes Introduction to the Open Peer-Reviewed Section on DR2 Methodology Examples Guido Bonino, Paolo Tripodi and Enrico Pasini Exploring Knowledge Dynamics in the Humanities Two Science Mapping Experiments Eugenio Petrovich and Emiliano Tolusso Reading Wittgenstein Between the Texts Marco Santoro, Massimo Airoldi and Emanuela Riviera Two Quantitative Researches in the History of Philosophy Some Down-to-Earth and Haphazard Methodological Reflections Guido Bonino, Paolo Maffezioli and Paolo Tripodi Book Reviews Becoming a New Self: Practices of Belief in Early Modern Catholicism, Moshe Sluhovsky Lucia Delaini Journal of Interdisciplinary History of Ideas, 16 | 2019 2 Éditorial Manuela Albertone et Enrico Pasini 1 Le numéro qu’on va présenter à nos lecteurs donne deux expressions d’une histoire interdisciplinaire des idées, qui touche d’une façon différente à la dimension sociologique. Une nouvelle attention au jeune Marx est axée sur le rapport entre la formation de l’individualisme et le contexte historique, que l’orthodoxie marxiste a négligé, faute d’une connaissance directe des écrits de la période de la jeunesse du philosophe allemand.
    [Show full text]
  • The Science, Philosophy, and Politics of Auguste Comte
    Introduction The Significance of Auguste Comte Warren Schmaus, Mary Pickering, and Michel Bourdeau Despite Comte’s remarkable influence, there has been very little published in recent years on his thought, especially in English. Perhaps the best gen- eral overview in English of Comte’s entire philosophy is still the 1903 translation of Lucien Lévy-Bruhl’s The Philosophy of Auguste Comte. The present anthology aims to help correct this oversight. Such a volume is par- ticularly timely given the recent political turn in the philosophy of science. Philosophers of science such as Philip Kitcher and especially feminist philosophers of science such as Helen Longino have recently turned to questions of how science should be organized to better serve human needs. Kitcher envisions an enlightened public playing a larger role in science policy making, while Longino would like to democratize not just science policy but scientific decision making itself, permitting more different points of view to be expressed.1 At the same time, recent scholarship in the history of philosophy of science by Don Howard, George Reisch, and Thomas Uebel is revealing the political and social motivations of members of the Vienna Circle of logical positivists such as Otto Neurath, Rudolf Carnap, Hans Hahn, and Philipp Frank.2 Sarah Richardson, on the other hand, questions whether the logical positivists can serve as a model for a political philosophy of science today.3 The debate concerns whether the logical positivists just happened to be involved in the politics of their time 3 © 2018 University of Pittsburgh Press. All rights reserved. 4 Warren Schmaus, Mary Pickering, and Michel Bourdeau or whether there was any connection between their politics and their phi- losophy of science.
    [Show full text]
  • Auguste Comte and Consensus Formation in American Religious Thought—Part 2: Twilight of New England Comtism
    religions Article Auguste Comte and Consensus Formation in American Religious Thought—Part 2: Twilight of New England Comtism Kenneth S. Sacks ID Department of History, Brown University, Providence, RI 02912, USA; [email protected] Received: 19 June 2017; Accepted: 9 August 2017; Published: 15 August 2017 Abstract: Auguste Comte was the most influential sociologist and philosopher of science in the Nineteenth Century. Part 1 summarized his works and analyzed reactions to them by Transcendentalists and Unitarians from 1837 until just after the Civil War. Part 2 examines in detail the post-war Transcendentalist and liberal Unitarian institutions of the Free Religious Association and the Radical Club and their different approaches to spiritual faith based on intuitionalism and reliance on scientific proof. In the background to their disputes is the positivism of Auguste Comte, who served as an easy source of common criticism. But at the same time as they wrote against positivism, both intuitionalists and those who relied on science were significantly influenced by Comte. Once again, as in part 1, a community of discourse was formed through the need to create social bonds at the expense of careful evaluation of the philosophy they criticized. Keywords: Comte; positivism; intuitionalism; Unitarianism; Free Religious Association; Radical Club; Francis Ellingwood Abbot; Octavius Brooks Frothingham; Thomas Wentworth Higginson In part one, we saw how, mirroring its success in Great Britain, Comte’s Course was initially well-received in the United States by Transcendentalists and some liberal Unitarians who viewed positivism as both the appropriate approach to scientific discovery and a way of envisioning a progressive, ameliorative humanity.
    [Show full text]
  • Is Habitability a Falsifiable Concept?
    Is Habitability A Falsifiable Concept? Robin Wordsworth, Ringberg Castle, 21/11/2014 people.seas.harvard.edu/~rwordsworth/ Talk outline • Why should we care? • Is habitability a falsifiable concept? YES • Is the habitability of nearby exoplanets a maybe falsifiable concept in the next 20-30 years? not • Narrow vs. wide habitability definiMons • Habitability and coevoluMon • General discussion (Pop) Philosophy of Science I • Why do we care if a theory is falsifiable or not? • Historically, falsifiability was not regarded as a key criterion • PosiMvism: scienMfic theories should be verifiable. In extreme limit of this idea, all non-verifiable human knowledge is without value AUGUSTE COMTE • One problem: theories can appear verified and turn out not to be, someMmes centuries later (e.g. Newtonian gravity) hp://skepcism.org/meline/september-history/8576-death-philosopher-auguste-comte.html Philosophy of Science II • Popper: Falsifiability is the key to goodness of a scienMfic theory • Theories cannot be proven, only disproved • Most falsifiable / simplest theory that hasn’t been falsified by observa4on is the current best approximaon to the truth • By this yardsMck Einstein’s special relavity is a very good theory (it can be falsified). String theory is not (it can’t). • Some example scienMfic statements from planetary science: – ‘Venus has abundant surface liquid water’ KARL POPPER – ‘Mars had abundant surface water 3.8 Ga’ – ‘The interior of Europa is inhabited by microbes’ The meaning of ‘falsifiable’ in planetary science • For the most part, observaons of exisMng systems dominate (it’s hard to experiment on planets) • No neat division into ‘true’ and ‘false’ theories. ParMcularly for study of past events.
    [Show full text]
  • Notes and References
    Notes and References Chapter 1 1. Saint -Simon refers to posItive philosophy, negative principles and positive work at least as early as his Introduction aux travaux scientifiques du xixe siecle, 2 vols, 1807-8; see pp. 97 and 103 of the extracts translated by the editor in K. Taylor (1975). 2. An exception is Halfpenny (1982). See also Cohen (1980). There are well-considered, if undifferentiated, accounts of positivism in the 'Introduction' to Giddens (ed.) (1974); and in Keat & Urry (1975) and Benton (1977). 3. Habermas (1963-71) ch. 7. This chapter was first published in German in 1963. 4. It is particularly regrettable that limitations of space preclude discussion of positivism in the Marxist tradition. For a start on this topic, see Jordan (1967) and Wellmer (1969). Chapter 2 1. E. Durkheim, The Rules of Sociological Method (French edn, 1895; English edn, 1982) passim. This English edition by S. Lukes, translated by W. D. Hills, provides a superior translation to the 1938 edition by G. E. G. Catlin, translated by S. A. Solovay & J. H. Mueller. As the 1938 edition is so well known, however, comparative page references to it will be given. 2. There is no complete translation of the Cours. I always quote from H. Martineau (ed.), The Positive Philosophy of August Comte, 2 vols (1853). Martineau 'freely translated and condensed' the original and there can be no doubt that M. Clarke's translation for S. Andreski (ed.), The Essential Comte (1974) is superior. Unfortunately, it does not include all the passages I wish to quote and so, rather than confuse by using two translations of the same work, I have always gone back to Martineau.
    [Show full text]
  • The Positive Philosophy Auguste Comte Batoche Books
    The Positive Philosophy of Auguste Comte Freely Translated and Condensed by Harriet Martineau With an Introduction by Frederic Harrison In Three Volumes Vol. II Batoche Books Kitchener 2000 London, George Bell & Sons, 1896 Contents Book V: Biology................................................................................. 5 Chapter I: General View of Biology ................................................. 5 Chapter II: Anatomical Philosophy ................................................ 43 Chapter III: Biotaxic Philosophy ................................................... 53 Chapter IV: Organic or Votive Life................................................ 67 Chapter V: The Animal Life. ......................................................... 82 Chapter VI: Intellectual And Moral, or Cerebral Functions .......... 95 Book VI: Social Physics .................................................................116 Chapter I: Necessity and Opportuneness of this New Science ......116 Chapter II: Principal Philosophical Attempts to Constitute a Social System. .................................................................................... 162 Chapter III: Characteristics of the Positive Method in Its Application to Social Phenomena. .............................................................. 175 Chapter IV: Relation of Sociology to The Other Departments of Positive Philosophy ................................................................. 215 Chapter V: Social Statics; or, Theory of The Spontaneous Order of Human Society .......................................................................
    [Show full text]
  • Theory of Knowledge and Theory of Science in the Work of Auguste Comte
    lHEORY OF KNOWLEDGE AND lHEORY OF SCIENCE IN 1HE WORK OF AUGUSTE COMlE NOlE ON COMIE'S ORIGINALfIY «Au lieu de chercher aveuglement une sterile unite scientifique, aussi oppressive que chimerique, dans la vicieuse reduction de tous les phenomenes a un seul ordre de lois, l'esprit humain regardera finale­ ment les diverses classes d'evenements commeayant leurs lois speciales. » Auguste Comte. RESUME. Theorie de la connaissance et theorie des sciences chez Auguste Comte. Plut6t que de reduirel'ceuvre de Comte ason «positivisme », il est utiled'etablir une distinction entresa theorie de la connaissance et sa theorie des sciences. Si la theorie de la connaissance comtienne ne parait pas particulierement originale, sa theoriedessciences est ici consideree comme une innovationintellectuelle majeure: c'est une des toutespremieres theories historiques et differentielles. Elle a ete capi­ tale pour la formation de l'epistemologiefrancaise. The most common opinion on the work of Auguste Comte is that it can well be reduced to the issue of « positivism ». Comments generally indi­ cate that the sense of his writings may be recapitulated by this word, however trivial and however abominable the matter is considered today. Ever since the unfortunate polytechnicien presented his enterprise under the sign of « positive philosophy», his disciples and critics alike have associated his name with the « positivist )} doctrine. And especially in the social sciences, nothing is more evident than that Comte's intellectual significance resides in his positivism in all its manifestations (from his epistemology and sociology to the religion of humanity) 1. I. For a typical example see the introduction by Gertrud Lenzer, in Auguste Comte and Positivism.
    [Show full text]
  • Hungarian Philosophical Review
    HUNGARIAN PHILOSOPHICAL REVIEW VOL. 62. (2018/4) The Journal of the Philosophical Committee of the Hungarian Academy of Sciences Austrian Philosophy Edited by Gergely Ambrus and Friedrich Stadler Contents Foreword 5 UNITY AND TENSIONS IN AUSTRIAN PHILOSOPHY GUILLAUME FRÉCHETTE: Brentano on Perception 13 DENIS FISETTE: The Reception of Ernst Mach in the School of Brentano 34 CHRISTOPH LIMBECK-LILIENAU: The First Vienna Circle: Myth or Reality? 50 CHRISTIAN DAMBÖCK: Carnap’s Aufbau: A Case of Plagiarism? 66 THOMAS UEBEL: Overcoming Carnap’s Methodological Solipsism: Not As Easy As It Seems 81 GERGELY AMBRUS: Austrian Identity Theory and Russellian Monism: Schlick, Russell and Chalmers 97 FRIEDRICH STADLER: Austrian Philosophy: Outlines of a Discipline at the University of Vienna in the 20th Century 117 THE INFLUENCE OF AUSTRIAN PHILOSOPHY IN HUNGARY CSABA PLÉH: The Impact of Karl Bühler on Hungarian Psychology and Linguistics 135 MIKLÓS RÉDEI: Parallels and Divergencies: Gödel and von Neumann 168 PÉTER ANDRÁS VARGA: A Snapshot of Austrian Philosophy on the Eve of Franz Brentano’s Arrival: The Young Bernhard Alexander in Vienna in 1868–1871 182 DOCUMENT BARNABÁS SZEKÉR, BETTINA SZABADOS UND PÉTER ANDRÁS VARGA: Die Wiener Einträge 1869–1870 aus dem Tagebuch des ungarischen Philosophen Bernhard Alexander 209 Contributors 217 Summaries 219 Foreword This special issue of the Hungarian Philosophical Review presents papers resulting from current research on Austrian philosophy. The topics are mainly historical, however they provide an in-depth analytical reconstruction and interpretation of the views discussed. Part of the papers focus on lesser known aspects of and connections within the diverse strands of the Austrian philosophical tradition, others address some important influences of Austrian philosophy (including also philosophical aspects of psychology, linguistics and mathematics) on Hungarian intellectual life and academia.
    [Show full text]
  • A Seven-Minute Sketch of My Research Michael R
    University of Nebraska - Lincoln DigitalCommons@University of Nebraska - Lincoln Sociology Department, Faculty Publications Sociology, Department of 2006 A Seven-Minute Sketch Of My Research Michael R. Hill University of Nebraska-Lincoln, [email protected] Follow this and additional works at: http://digitalcommons.unl.edu/sociologyfacpub Part of the Family, Life Course, and Society Commons, and the Social Psychology and Interaction Commons Hill, Michael R., "A Seven-Minute Sketch Of My Research" (2006). Sociology Department, Faculty Publications. 353. http://digitalcommons.unl.edu/sociologyfacpub/353 This Article is brought to you for free and open access by the Sociology, Department of at DigitalCommons@University of Nebraska - Lincoln. It has been accepted for inclusion in Sociology Department, Faculty Publications by an authorized administrator of DigitalCommons@University of Nebraska - Lincoln. Hill, Michael R. 2006. “A Seven-Minute Sketch of My Research.” Invited presentation for Professor Constance L. Chapple’s course on Qualitative Research Methods, Department of Sociology, University of Nebraska-Lincoln, February 14. A SEVEN-MINUTE SKETCH OF MY RESEARCH1 MICHAEL R. HILL2 Editor, Sociological Origins Y CENTRAL PROJECT is to identify, explicate, and better understand the fundamental dimensions, consequences, and possibilities of human embodiment in the social world. This project is multi- Mfaceted and is continually evolving. Virtually all of my work contributes directly to this project, including my analyses of archives,
    [Show full text]