Democratic Athens As an Experimental System: History and the Project of Political Theory

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Democratic Athens As an Experimental System: History and the Project of Political Theory Princeton/Stanford Working Papers in Classics Democratic Athens as an Experimental System: History and the Project of Political Theory. Version 1.0 November 2005 Josiah Ober Princeton University Abstract: Athens as a case study can be useful as an “exemplary narrative” for political science and normative political, on the analogy of the biologicial use of as certain animals (e.g. mice or zebrafish) as “model systems” subject to intensive study by many researchers. © Josiah Ober. [email protected] 1 What is a historical case study good for? Can the political history of classical Athens legitimately be regarded as a case study: an experimental system or exemplary narrative, useful for investigating various aspects of democracy and related phenomena? I hope to show that the answer to that question is yes, but first it seems necessary to pose an analytically prior question: What is the goal of the investigation? What precisely is the use-value of the case? What, in short, is the exemplary narrative supposed to be good for? Those questions may make a proper historian a bit queasy. She might reasonably ask: Need history be good for something other than historical knowledge itself? The point is that as soon as I say that the historical experience of (e.g.) classical Athens is an experimental system, I seem to have abandoned the historian’s tried and true ground of supposing that it is sufficient to say that Athenian history is worth studying for its own sake. I admit to a personal fondness for this sort of traditional historian’s propriety. So, as a preliminary gesture, let me plant a stake in the ground (in Greek terms: a horos) by saying that I actually do suppose that Athenian history is interesting for its own sake. I will try to advance the argument for the use-value of Athens as an exemplary narrative as far as possible beyond that marker. I may be forced to give some of the ground in front of the stake by the end of the day. But the stake of “Athens interesting for its own sake” is the point behind which I would not retreat without making a desperate stand.1 The most obvious answer to the “exemplary for what?” question is, I suppose, “exemplary for other periods of history.” Which is to say that the case of democratic Athens might usefully be deployed for comparative methods of argument in historiography because, via close attention to a range of similarities and differences, the history of Athenian political development might tell us something meaningful about other periods of human experimentation with democracy and related forms of political organization. I think that such a claim, carefully framed, could be supported. I am very much in favor of comparative arguments in history, and I have quite often made reference to “exemplary narratives” drawn from the history of early modern Europe (e.g.) in order make a point about antiquity – especially in seeking to extend the range of interpretive possibilities that might be considered by historians of antiquity.2 But I do not have anything new to say about the method of comparative history – the advantages and problems with the comparative approach have been a matter of discussion for a long time among historians (students of antiquity will be likely to think, for example, of Plutarch’s Parallel Lives), and I can see no very obvious way that the theory of “the case” would allow me to add anything fresh or original to those discussions.3 Is it reasonable, then, to look outside the discipline of history in seeking to establish a use-value for the Athenian case? On the face of it, yes. The use-value of a given biological “model system” is not de facto limited to a particular academic discipline. The mouse is used in experiments by both medical pathologists and behavioral psychologists. Drosophila have proved just as useful for evolutionary biologists investigating geographic diffusion of visible traits as they have for molecular biologists who analyze the structure of individual genes. Arguably, the conceptual category “model system” connotes interdisciplinary use-value. So, if the exemplary historical narrative qua experimental system is indeed analogous to a biological model system, its use-value should potentially exceed the disciplinary domain of history per se. I will return, at the 2 end of this essay, to similarities and differences between model and experimental systems. I propose, then, to ignore comparativism within the discipline of history, and to argue instead that “historical narratives” can be usefully exemplary, can serve as “experimental systems” outside the discipline of history as such. The most obvious extra- historical field for which the case of Athenian democracy might seem to have use-value is political sociology. Classical Athens offers an example of a fairly rare and yet analytically significant socio-political phenomenon: direct participatory democracy as the primary system of governance for a society that was fairly large (i.e. too big to be explained in terms of face-to-face interactions), quite complex (literate, socially differentiated), and politically independent (i.e. not subject to superior external or internal political authority).4 There has been at least sporadic interest among political scientists in classical Athens as a case study in direct democracy. Some of my own earlier work on Athens was aimed at convincing political scientists that the Athenian case challenges the universality of the so-called “Iron Law of Oligarchy,” which asserts that participatory democracy will inevitably degenerate into oligarchy for structural reasons involving leadership roles.5 But I propose leaving political sociology to one side for the time being in order to focus on the possibility that the historical case of democratic Athens may be usefully employed within a different academic field: ethical and political theory. That is to say, I want to argue that the Athenian case may be useful for normative thinking about problems of justice, rights, and obligations.6 I am quite aware that asserting that a particular historical case might usefully inform normative theory means confronting a familiar obstacle – and the obstacle may be regarded by some students of normative theory as simply impassible. The brick wall in question is defined by David Hume’s famous assertion that “one cannot derive an ‘ought’ from an ‘is’.”7 And so, presumably (perhaps a fortiori), not from a ‘was.’ An expansive interpretation of the scope of Hume’s dictum might, therefore, seem to write history out of ethical and political philosophy. Before exploring ways to get around the wall, we should ask whether there is any very good reason to want to get around it. After all, the experimental system must, by definition, model something that relevant disciplinary practitioners actually care to learn more about. If consideration of the historical case does not offer something needed (or anyway valued) by normative theory, it seems senseless to proceed with the endeavor of inviting political theorists to take cognizance of the case of classical Athens. It may come to seem akin to urging astrophysicists to begin experimenting with fruit-flies, on the grounds that experiments on drosophila have materially advanced other scientific fields.8 Claiming that experimenting with historical cases could usefully advance the project of normative theory is not, on the face of it, much easier to sell than fruit-flies to physicists. Political theorists are very interested in texts written in the historical past (by, e.g. Hobbes, Locke, and Mill), but they tend to regard past historical practice as irrelevant to their scholarly project and they have long tended to regard “historicism” as a gross methodological error.9 Theorists use the charge of “historicism” somewhat loosely and in ways very reminiscent of the ways some historians’ use the term “essentialism”: In each discipline-specific argumentative context, she who fails to defend herself against the damaging charge must regard her argument as effectively refuted. This casual and pervasive use by political theorists and historians of terminological short-hand to produce 3 knock-down methodological refutations has, I think, unnecessarily limited intellectual intercourse between political theorists and historians.10 By way of personal anecdote: When I first came to Princeton in 1990, I frequently attended meetings of the Political Philosophy Colloquium (which centered, then as now, on the general problem of liberalism and its critics) and meetings of the Davis History Seminar, then focused on imperialism and colonialism. I was graciously welcomed in both forums, but I quickly found that framing interventions in each venue, without leaving oneself open to knockout punches of “historicism” on the one hand, or “essentialism” on the other, was a severe challenge (even for someone professionally involved, as I was and am, in the study of rhetoric). Now, the strong Humean imagined above might say that “historicism” is not just a scare-term like “essentialism,” that it serves a function that is more serious than simply shoring up current canons of disciplinary taste. He might suggest that “historicism” for the political theorist is equivalent to the historian’s concern with “anachronism” – i.e. shorthand for a methodological error that is so basic as to render any claim infected by the error invalid a priori. For instance, in response to a historian’s charge of “essentialism” I might respond: “yes indeed, my argument does assume that some particular and modest aspects of human behavior are innate, rather than socially constructed and contingent, but I hope to convince you that making this sort of essentialist assumption will allow me to explain a fuller range of the historical phenomena we are seeking to understand.” I suppose that most historians would be willing to hear me out, judging the potential validity of my “essentialist” assumption on the basis of its explanatory power or lack thereof.
Recommended publications
  • Political Ideas and Movements That Created the Modern World
    harri+b.cov 27/5/03 4:15 pm Page 1 UNDERSTANDINGPOLITICS Understanding RITTEN with the A2 component of the GCE WGovernment and Politics A level in mind, this book is a comprehensive introduction to the political ideas and movements that created the modern world. Underpinned by the work of major thinkers such as Hobbes, Locke, Marx, Mill, Weber and others, the first half of the book looks at core political concepts including the British and European political issues state and sovereignty, the nation, democracy, representation and legitimacy, freedom, equality and rights, obligation and citizenship. The role of ideology in modern politics and society is also discussed. The second half of the book addresses established ideologies such as Conservatism, Liberalism, Socialism, Marxism and Nationalism, before moving on to more recent movements such as Environmentalism and Ecologism, Fascism, and Feminism. The subject is covered in a clear, accessible style, including Understanding a number of student-friendly features, such as chapter summaries, key points to consider, definitions and tips for further sources of information. There is a definite need for a text of this kind. It will be invaluable for students of Government and Politics on introductory courses, whether they be A level candidates or undergraduates. political ideas KEVIN HARRISON IS A LECTURER IN POLITICS AND HISTORY AT MANCHESTER COLLEGE OF ARTS AND TECHNOLOGY. HE IS ALSO AN ASSOCIATE McNAUGHTON LECTURER IN SOCIAL SCIENCES WITH THE OPEN UNIVERSITY. HE HAS WRITTEN ARTICLES ON POLITICS AND HISTORY AND IS JOINT AUTHOR, WITH TONY BOYD, OF THE BRITISH CONSTITUTION: EVOLUTION OR REVOLUTION? and TONY BOYD WAS FORMERLY HEAD OF GENERAL STUDIES AT XAVERIAN VI FORM COLLEGE, MANCHESTER, WHERE HE TAUGHT POLITICS AND HISTORY.
    [Show full text]
  • Michels's Iron Law of Oligarchy
    MICHELS’S IRON LAW OF OLIGARCHY Robert Michels ( 1876– 1936), was a young historian who had been unable to get a job in the German university system, despite the recommendation of Max Weber, because he was a member of the Social Democrats. Michels had participated extensively in party activities and had come to the conclusion that the Socialists did not live up to their own ideals. Although the party advocated democracy, it was not internally democratic itself. The revolutionary Marxism of the speeches at conventions and on the floor of the Reichstag was just a way of whipping up support among the workers, while the party leaders built a bureaucratic trade union and party machine to provide sinecures for themselves. Michels’s analysis appeared in 1911 in a book called Political Parties. The phenomenon of party oligarchy was quite general, stated Michels; if internal democracy could not be found in an organization that was avowedly democratic, it would certainly not exist in parties which did not claim to be democratic. This principle was called the Iron Law of Oligarchy, and it constitutes one of the great generalizations about the functioning of mass‐ membership organizations, as subsequent research has borne out. The Iron Law of Oligarchy works as follows: First of all, there is always a rather small number of persons in the organization who actually make decisions, even if the authority is formally vested in the body of the membership at large. The reason for this is purely functional and will be obvious to anyone who has attended a public meeting or even a large committee session.
    [Show full text]
  • Qt04h0308g.Pdf
    UC Berkeley Cabinet of the Muses: Rosenmeyer Festschrift Title Biography and Bibliography of T. G. Rosenmeyer (1920-2007) Permalink https://escholarship.org/uc/item/04h0308g Publication Date 2007-04-05 Peer reviewed eScholarship.org Powered by the California Digital Library University of California TOM ROSENMEYER IN MEMORIAM Saturday, April 7, 2007, 1 p.m. Heyns Room The Faculty Club University of California, Berkeley PROGRAM MUSICAL SELECTIONS OPENING REMARKS: Tony Long REMEMBRANCES Robert Alter Erich Gruen John Prausnitz Michelle Zerba Kathy Fabunan MUSICAL INTERLUDE REMEMBRANCES Patricia Rosenmeyer Benjamin Acosta-Hughes Donald Mastronarde Mark Griffith CLOSING REMARKS: Tony Long RECEPTION THOMAS GUSTAV ROSENMEYER APRIL 3, 1920–FEBRUARY 6, 2007 Tom Rosenmeyer, Professor Emeritus of Greek and Comparative Literature at the University of California at Berkeley, died at his home in Oakland on Tuesday, February 6, 2007. He was 86. Born in Hamburg, Germany, on April 3, 1920, and educated at the humanistic Johanneum Gymnasium in that city from 1930 to 1938, Tom fled to England in 1939 to avoid Nazi per- secution. He enrolled at the London School of Oriental Studies, intending to learn Sanskrit, but in 1940 the British, expecting a German invasion, interned all “enemy” aliens. He was sent on to an internment camp in Canada, where the residents formed their own impromptu “university,” studying Hebrew, Sanskrit, and Arabic as well as the classical languages together behind barbed wire. Among his colleagues in the camp were future classicist Martin Ostwald and Emil Fackenheim, who taught Tom Arabic and later became a prominent philosopher of the Shoah. Released from internment in 1942, Tom completed an undergraduate degree in Classics at McMaster University in Hamilton, Ontario, in 1944 and took an MA in Classics at the University of Toronto in 1945 before proceeding to Harvard for his doctoral studies.
    [Show full text]
  • The Iron Law of Oligarchy: a Tale of 14 Islands ∗
    The Iron Law of Oligarchy: A Tale of 14 Islands ∗ Christian Dippely Jean Paul Carvalhoz December 15, 2014 Abstract The great puzzle of Caribbean history in the mid-19th century is that this was a time of radical institutional change – with all but one of the long-established Caribbean parliaments voting themselves out of existence inside a twenty-year window – despite very stable conditions in the (exogenous) terms-of-trade and in the (endogenous) local plantation economy. This paper argues that the post-slavery change of the planter elite into a more creole and colored composition did not change the incentives of the coercive Caribbean plantation economy, but that it did undermine the elite’s ability to dominate the political process within the given set of formal institutions, i.e. the locally elected parliaments. The new elite needed a new set of formal institutions to maintain the existing coercive institutional bundle. The first argument is a version of the ”iron law of oligarchy” (Michels (1911)), the second a version of the ”seesaw of de jure and de facto institutions” (Acemoglu and Robinson (2008)). Guided by a model of elite coherence and institutional choice, we explore our two arguments in a combination of very rich micro-data on islands’ parliamentary politics and sugar plantations, as well as colony-level regression analysis. Keywords: Iron law of Oligarchy, Bankruptcy, de jure and de facto Institutions, Economic Development JEL Codes: F54, N26, O43, P16 ∗Financial support from UCLA’s Burkle Center, Center for Economic History and Price Center are gratefully acknowledged. yUniversity of California, Los Angeles, and NBER.
    [Show full text]
  • Swarthmore College Bulletin (December 2002)
    DECEMBER 2002 Photo Blitz: Student Visions ON THE COVER: B DAN FAIRCHILD’S [’03] PHOTOGRAPH OF PARRISH HALL MAILBOXES GRACES THE APRIL 2003 PAGE OF NEXT YEAR’S SWARTHMORE COLLEGE CALENDAR. IT IS ONE OF THOUSANDS OF PHOTOS SUBMITTED DURING THIS FALL’S “PHOTO BLITZ,” SPONSORED BY THE PUBLICATIONS OFFICE. FOR MORE STUDENT VISIONS OF SWARTHMORE, TURN TO PAGE 20. CONTENTS: HANG NGO ’05, ONE OF MORE THAN 360 STUDENTS WHO PARTICIPATED IN THE PHOTO BLITZ, SAID OF THIS PHOTO: “THE SHADOWS ARE [ONES] OF ME AND ... MY BEST FRIEND HERE, FRANCISCO CASTRO ’05 [LEFT].” DECEMBERDECEMBER 2002 2002 F e a t u r e s Cell Divisions 14 Swarthmore-educated scientists, ethicists, and legal scholars help Departments lead the stem-cell and cloning debate. L e t t e r s 3 Readers’ feedback By Tom Krattenmaker P r o f i l e s C o l l e c t i o n 4 Working Toward Through Student Current news a Better World 48 E y e s 2 0 Sam Ashelman ’37 hosted Bosnian A weeklong “Photo Blitz” reveals diplomats at Coolfont Resort.Resort students’ vision of Swarthmore. Alumni Digest 42 Connections and adventures By Elizabeth Redden ’05 By Jeffrey Lott ClassNotes 44 F o l l o w i n g Liberal Arts Correspondence from friends t h e W i n d 6 4 in a Conservative Jon Lyman ’77 enjoys the scenery L a n d 2 6 and sociability of ballooning. Two Swarthmoreans help start D e a t h s 5 3 a women’s college in Jeddah, Sympathy extended By Angela Doody Saudi Arabia.
    [Show full text]
  • How Political Parties Shape Democracy
    UC Irvine CSD Working Papers Title HOW POLITICAL PARTIES SHAPE DEMOCRACY Permalink https://escholarship.org/uc/item/17p1m0dx Author van Biezen, Ingrid Publication Date 2004-11-01 eScholarship.org Powered by the California Digital Library University of California CSD Center for the Study of Democracy An Organized Research Unit University of California, Irvine www.democ.uci.edu This paper assesses the relationship between the nature of political parties and varieties of democracy1. It is argued that the changing role of parties can be attributed to an ideational transformation by which parties have gradually come to be seen as necessary and desirable institutions for democracy, and that this has contributed to a changing conception of parties from voluntary private associations towards the political party as a ‘public utility’, i.e. the party as an essential public good for democracy. Recent cases of democratization, where parties were attributed a markedly privileged position within the democratic institutional framework, provide the most unequivocal testimony of such a conception of the relationship between parties and democracy. At the same time, however, fundamental disagreements persist about the meaning of democracy and the actual role of political parties within it. Regrettably, however, the literatures on parties and democratic theory have developed to a large degree in mutual isolation. This paper provides a preliminary attempt to move beyond the consensus which exists on the surface that modern democracy is unthinkable save in terms of parties by considering varieties of party and different conceptions of democracy. On the Paradox of Party As Schattschneider famously asserted more than half a century ago, ‘the political parties created democracy and modern democracy is unthinkable save in terms of the political parties’ (Schattschneider, 1942:1).
    [Show full text]
  • Front Matter, Table of Contents, Bibliography of T. G. Rosenmeyer
    UC Berkeley Cabinet of the Muses: Rosenmeyer Festschrift Title Front matter, Table of Contents, Bibliography of T. G. Rosenmeyer Permalink https://escholarship.org/uc/item/86t2b21j Authors Griffith, Mark Mastronarde, Donald J. Publication Date 1990-04-01 Peer reviewed eScholarship.org Powered by the California Digital Library University of California CABINET OF THE MUSES ESSAYS ON CLASSICAL AND COMPARATIVE LITERATURE IN HONOR OF THOMAS G. ROSENMEYER edited by Mark Griffith and Donald J. Mastronarde Scholars Press Atlanta, Georgia CABINET OF THE MUSES Essays on Classical and Comparative Literature in Honor of Thomas G. Rosenmeyer edited by Mark Griffith and Donald J. Mastronarde © 1990 Scholars Press Postprint digital edition © 2005 Department of Classics, University of California, Berkeleu Library of Congress Cataloging in Publication Data Cabinet of the muses : essays on classical and comparative literature in honor of Thomas G. Rosenmeyer / edited by Mark Griffith and Donald J. Mastronarde. p. cm. — (Homage series) ISBN 1-55540-408-1. -- ISBN 1-55540-409-X (pbk. : alk. paper) 1. Classical literature-History and criticism. 2. Literature. Comparative-Classical and modern. 3. Literature. Comparative- -Modern and classical. 4. Rosenmeyer, Thomas G. I. Rosenmeyer, Thomas G. II. Griffith, Mark. m. Mastronarde, Donald J. IV. Series. PA26.R68C3 1989 880'.09-dc20 89-10862 CIP Printed in the United States of America on acid-free paper CONTENTS Portrait of Thomas G. Rosenmeyer...................................................................
    [Show full text]
  • Extra-Party Neo-Anarchist Critiques AQ: Please
    Rapp, John A. "Extra-Party neo-anarchist critiques AQ: Please clarify whether you want this word to read critiques as in the running head and also that the same change can be carried out in the FM also. of the state in the PRC." Daoism and Anarchism: Critiques of State Autonomy in Ancient and Modern China. London: Continuum, 2012. 175–192. Contemporary Anarchist Studies. Bloomsbury Collections. Web. 29 Sep. 2021. <http://dx.doi.org/10.5040/9781501306778.ch-008>. Downloaded from Bloomsbury Collections, www.bloomsburycollections.com, 29 September 2021, 03:37 UTC. Copyright © John A. Rapp 2012. You may share this work for non-commercial purposes only, provided you give attribution to the copyright holder and the publisher, and provide a link to the Creative Commons licence. 8 Extra-Party neo-anarchist critiques of the state in the PRC Introduction This chapter and the succeeding one examine various “neo-anarchist” critiques of the Leninist state in the PRC, from the early years of the Cultural Revolution to the beginning of the Tiananmen protests. The label of neo-anarchist in this book refers not to self-proclaimed “post-modern” anarchist critiques but to anyone in China who criticizes the Leninist state using the simple, basic, but powerful view shared by all kinds of anarchists (contradictory as they might be on their own positive agendas), namely, that the state rules for itself when it can, not for classes, interest groups, a mass of individuals, or the whole community. The term “neo-anarchist” is adapted from analysts who apply the label “neo-Marxism” to those thinkers who fi nd the Marxist class paradigm useful without necessarily being Communists.
    [Show full text]
  • Princeton/Stanford Working Papers in Classics
    Princeton/Stanford Working Papers in Classics What the Ancient Greeks Can Tell Us About Democracy. Version 1.0 September 2007 Josiah Ober Stanford The question of what the ancient Greeks can tell us about democracy can be answered by reference to three fields that have traditionally been pursued with little reference to one another: ancient history, classical political theory, and political science. These fields have been coming into more fruitful contact over the last 20 years, as evidenced by a spate of interdisciplinary work. Historians, political theorists, and political scientists interested in classical Greek democracy are increasingly capable of leveraging results across disciplinary lines. As a result, the classical Greek experience has more to tell us about the origins and definition of democracy, and about the relationship between participatory democracy and formal institutions, rhetoric, civic identity, political values, political criticism, war, economy, culture, and religion. Fortcoming in Annual Reviews in Political Science 2007 © Josiah Ober. [email protected] 1 Who are “we”? It might appear, at first glance, that there is no coherent scholarly or academic “us” who might be told something of value by studies of the ancient Greeks. The political legacy of the Greeks is very important to three major branches of scholarship -- ancient history, political theory, and political science -- and at least of collateral importance to a good many others (for example anthropology, communications, and literary studies). Ancient Greek history, political theory, and political science are distinctly different intellectual traditions, with distinctive forms of expression. Very few theorists or political scientists, for example, assume that their audiences have a reading knowledge of ancient Greek; few theorists or historians assume a knowledge of mathematics, statistics, or game theory; few historians or political scientists are comfortable with the vocabulary of normative and evaluative philosophy.
    [Show full text]
  • Democracy Embattled Francis Fukuyama Ivan Krastev Yascha Mounk Marc F
    Thirtieth Anniversary Issue January 2020, Volume 31, Number 1 $15.00 Democracy Embattled Francis Fukuyama Ivan Krastev Yascha Mounk Marc F. Plattner Larry Diamond Alina Mungiu-Pippidi Michele Dunne Carl Gershman Steven Levitsky and Lucan Way Lilia Shevtsova Ladan Boroumand Christopher Walker, Shanthi Kalathil, and Jessica Ludwig Thomas Carothers Minxin Pei Ghia Nodia Andrew J. Nathan Sumit Ganguly Laura Rosenberger on This Is Not Propaganda DEMOCRACY’S INEVITABLE ELITES Ghia Nodia Ghia Nodia is director of the International School for Political Science and professor of political science at Ilia State University in Tbilisi. He is also chairman of the Caucasus Institute for Peace, Democracy and Development. For five months in 2016–17, he was a Reagan-Fas- cell Democracy Fellow at the National Endowment for Democracy in Washington, D.C. Commentators who analyze and criticize populism—two activities that frequently go hand-in-hand—tend to presume that there is no such thing as populist theory. One can have a theory about populism, these ana- lysts generally believe, but populism itself is not based on a rationally defensible vision. Populism is not a concept or an ideology, but rather an attitude, a predisposition, a discursive technique, a specific kind of resentment that demagogues exploit. A theoretical foundation for populism can be found, however, in Robert Michels’s classic work of political sociology, Political Par- ties: A Sociological Study of the Oligarchical Tendencies of Modern Democracy (1911).1 It is a text worth revisiting when democracy is— or at least is perceived to be—caught up in a crisis resulting from a backlash against the alleged elite appropriation of people’s power.
    [Show full text]
  • Deplorable Or Criminal”, Were in Fact So Recent. What Brings Us to Our Point
    defining the ideology of extremism deplorable or criminal”, were in fact so recent. What brings us to our point is the fact that “in spite of it, they replenished the century; one against the other, sustaining each other, they fabricated their material. Simultaneous- ly very powerful, very ephemeral and very ominous, how could they mo- bilise so much hope, or so much passion in so many individuals?” (Ibid.). Furet’s analysis brought forward an interpretation that in quite clear terms reveals the mechanisms of interdependence between fascism and bolshe- vism. Being adversaries, both ideologies and for some time also political systems needed each other. Still more, they were in a relation of complic- ity regarding their common enemy: “The heftiest secret of complicity be- tween bolshevism and fascism remains however the existence of their com- mon adversary, which the both hostile doctrines reduced or exorcised with an idea that it had been in agony, and which therefore constituted their soil: very simply, democracy” (Ibid.: p. 39). Maybe it is not so important that this interpretation, which in its minute scrutiny of both historical oc- currences maintains a constant awareness of their irreducible differences, makes possible to comprehend the turning points of history such as Hitler’s and Stalin‘s temporary alliance. From a theoretical point of view, it is more instructive that Furet’s interpretation in its retrospective insight demon- strates what could be called the vulnerability of democracy. Since the rep- resentative democracy as the formal political system does not offer much else, but the rule of the abstract Law, it maintains openness for a variety of different political alternatives and unfortunately for the anti-democrat- ic ones too.
    [Show full text]
  • Introduction SITING PLATO
    © Copyright, Princeton University Press. No part of this book may be distributed, posted, or reproduced in any form by digital or mechanical means without prior written permission of the publisher. Introduction SITING PLATO IN THIS BOOK I argue for a fundamental rethinking of the relationship between Plato's thought and the practice of democracy. I propose that the canonical view of Plato as a virulent antidemocrat is not sound.1 Rather, in his work, a searching consideration of the possibilities raised by some democratic ideals and institutions coexists alongside severe criticisms of democratic life and politics. Plato ®nds the lived experience and ideology of Athenian democracy repulsive and fascinating, troubling and intrigu- ing. He not only assails democratic practice but also weaves hesitations about the reach of that attack into the very presentation of his thought. A substantial measure of ambivalence, not unequivocal hostility, marks his attitude toward democracy as he knew it. This dimension of Plato's thought has remained largely unexplored for some time. This is in part because Plato has for centuries been cast as a founding ®gure in what has been called the ªantidemocratic tradition in Western thought.º2 But even when commentators have noted that state- 1 This view is longstanding and widely held, and thus I call it canonical. Typical are pas- sages such as the following: ªPlato's antipathy to democracy as he knew it thus emerges clearly in this section [the simile of the ship at Republic 487b±497a]. No doubt his anti- democratic attitude is a product of various complex factors, but what should interest us here is the philosophical ground for his condemnation of democracyº (R.
    [Show full text]