Democracy's Great Opponent: the Problem of Oligarchy in Ancient and Modern Political Thoucht
Total Page:16
File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb
DEMOCRACY'S GREAT OPPONENT: THE PROBLEM OF OLIGARCHY IN ANCIENT AND MODERN POLITICAL THOUCHT Jeffrey Sikkenga Submitted in partial fulllllment of the requinments lot the Doctor of Philosophy in Political Science, University of Toronto 14 March 2000 Nat ional Library Bibliothèque nationale l*l of Cat~da du Canada Acquisitions and Acquisitions et Bibliographie Services sentices bibliographiques 395 Wellington Street 395, me Wellington Ol(ewa0N K1AON4 OmwaON KlAW Canede Canada The author bas granted a non- L'auteur a accordé une licence non exclusive licence aüowing the exclusive permettant à la National Library of Canada to Bibliothèque nationale du Canada de reproduce, loan, distribute or seil reproduire, prêter, distribuer ou copies of this tbesis in microform, vendre des copies de cette thèse sous paper or electronic formats. la forme de microfiche/film, de reproduction sur papier ou sur format électronique. The author retains ownership of the L'auteur conseme la propriété du copyright in this thesis. Neither the droit d'auteur qui protège cette thèse. thesis nor substantial extracts firom it Ni la thèse ni des extraits substantiels may be printed or othenivise de celle-ci ne doivent être imprimés reproduced without the author's ou autrement reproduits sans son permission. autorisation. ACKNOWLEDGMENTS This work has been a long time coming. It could never have arrived without the help of a lot of people who deserve special thanks. First, to my cornmittee: my supervisor Thomas Pangle, who gave me the idea for this work and showed scholarship by example; Clifford Orwin, whose humor and support came ai a critical time; Sennifer Nedelsky, who graciously agreed to help. Also, to my colleagues at Ashland University: Peter Schramm, for tiikiiig a chance; Brid Thornpson, who stuck by; and David Foster, for a budding friends hip. Next, thanks go to my friends. To those from Toronto: Haig Patapan, for being my midwife; and Jim Alvey, a gentleman. And those from earlier days: James Ceaser, for indulging my theoretical vice. Also. to those who lent support at crucial moments dong the way: Richard and Susan Ilka, for the use of a computer and so much more; Paul and Martha Lawrence, for a summer study; and Robert Sirico. Kris Mauren, Greg Dunn, and Gregory Gronbacher, for putting me in the right place at the right time. Findly, to my family: Grams, whose unconditional kindness will never be forgotten; and lastly, my parents -- for an education only now understood. To Sharon For the Shape of Her Heart CONTENTS PREFACE: "Why and How We Should Study Oligarchy' ................... 1 CHAPTER ONE: LLInvestigatingMichelsy Iron Law" ........................ 10 CHAPTER TWO: 'LPlato on the Oligarchic Soul" ............................20 CHAPTER THREE: "Aristotle on Oligarchie Regimes" .....................43 CHAPTER FOUR: "Hobbes and Locke on Acquisi tiveness and Oligarc hy9'........... -76 CHAPTER FIVE: "Montesquieu on Oligarchie Republicanism" ........... 104 CHAPTER SIX: "The Federalist and Oligarchy in Americaw.............. 135 CHAPTER SEVEN: "Recovering Lost Insight" .............................160 WHY AND HOW WE SHOULD STUDY OLIGARCHY 1. Why We Should Study Oiigarchy a. Startirtg with Liberal Dernocmq This work seeks to address and clarify the problem of oligarchy. According to the Oxford English Dictionary, oligarchy is "govemment by the few" or "a form of govemment in which a few persons or families hold power" (OED 1989). But etymology does little to clarify the nature of oligarchy because it does not say who constitutes "the few", nor why those "few" desire to nile. nor whether they deserve to nile. More importantly. the word itself does not explain why contemporary political scientists should care what oligarchy is. As James Ceaser points out. "liberal democracy is home to most political scientists. and most political scientists make liberai democracy -- or some aspect of it -- the focus of their life's work" (Ceaser 1990, 1 ). As political scientists. understanding and improving liberal democracy are our most immediate concems. But Ceaser also notes that "to say that political science may assist liberal democracy in no way means that this task exhausts its purposes or constitutes its only or highest horizon" (Ceaser 1990.3). The purpose of political science is. in other words, not merel y poli tically salutary. Rather, as Christopher Bruel1 argues, political science at its most comprehensive seeks to gain a rational understanding of the political mathrmata. the most important of which is the idea of nobility embodied in justice (Bniell 1987. 105, 109). For justice is the one thing unique to political action and discourse. Rightly understood, then, political science is first and foremost the study of justice. As contemporary political scientists, therefore, Our first concern should be with investigating the principles of justice at the core of our liberal democratic regime! This engagement with liberal democracy is not simply parochial. According to the argument made As a number of contemporary commentators have pointed out. liberal democracy vies ta hide its "regime character" by burying the question of justice or the right way of life underneath a concern with life simply (see, for example, MacIntyre 1988; Beiner 1992; Fukuyama 1992). But as Michael Sandel observes, disputes over justice within liberal demoçracies cannot be limited to procedural matters. They inevitably raise substantive questions about what is right or just action, and thereby what is the nght or just way of life (Sandel 1982, ch. 1). prominent by Francis Fukuyama, it is demanded by the fact that while "the current wave of democratization has probably crested, and we will be in for a period of retrenchment over the next few years", nevertheless "al1 of the major systematic alternatives to liberal democracy have collapsed, one by one" (Fukuyama 1991, 664). According to these observers. "there are no serious ideological competitors left to liberal democracy" outside of the theocratic politics espoused in parts of the Islamic world (Fukuyama 1992, 21 1). Hence for many analysts like Fukuyama. modem liberal democracy is the dominant force shaping politics around the world. Oligarchy is dead. dong with the other opponents of liberal democracy -- from Filmer and the divine right of kings io Marx and scientific socidism. They have ali been defeated because of the appeal of liberal democracy's central ideas, the core of which is individual and collective self- government based on natural or human rights (cf. Fukuyama 1992, 21 1- 12). Given the apparent triumph of liberal democracy, why then should we study oligarchy, which seems to have gone the way of the dinosaur? b. The Retum of Oligarchy? There does indeed seem to have been a decline in the twentieth century of oligarchy as a political regime. The few "oligarchs" remaining in power in Latin America. Africa. Russia, and East Asia are nearly unanimous in their proclamations of allegiance to democratic principles (cf. Jackson & Rosberg 1982, 5-6; Lewin 1987, 25)? At their boldest, the contemporary proponents of undemocratic political systems (e.g. "Asian values" paternalisrn) argue that democracy must have a different fom in their countries, or that it must be realized in a more circumspect manner. They are forced to be hypocritical because no one today seriously claims that oligarchy is a better regime than democracy, liberal or otherwise. Thus while it may be true, as Spencer Wearst notes, that oligarchies are "a historically more numerous class of republics" than democracies, the unquestionable dominance of the democratic notion of justice makes oligarchy seem no longer threatening to democracy (Wearst 1998, 1). As a result. oligarchy no longer appean to deserve urgent study by those interested in contemporary liberal democracy or in politics generally.3 Yet this appearance is deceptive. As Frank Sorauf notes, an increasing number of observen now charge that recent trends have given rise to "a new plutocracy" or even an "oligarchy" within Western liberal dernocracies. especially in the United States (Sorauf 1994, 367). The The very refusa1 of contemporary "oligarchs"openly to assert the oligarchic basis of their authonty raises the question whether there are any real oligarchs left (cf. Lewin 1987.25). In contmt. the Greco-Roman thinkers recognized oligarchy as the great political challenger to democracy. Openly oligarchic revolutions were not uncornmon, as we learn from ancient writers such as Thucydides and Polybius (cf. Onvin 1994.7 1-72; Syme 1988,56-7). commentator Kevin Phillips daims, for example, that liberal democracy is veering away from its economic and politicai principles and becoming more oligarchic. In his view, "declining manufacturing competitiveness, stagnant real wages, and increased econornic polarization" translate into a growing division within liberal democratic societies between "haves" and "have- nots" (Phillips 1994. 17). John McClaughry womes that these economic divisions eventually will entail political divisions that will give rise to the nile of the few over the many, who will be "the prisoners of a parasitical class that exists to manipulate govemment to transfer wealih into the favored pockets of a few" (McClaughry 1998, 93). Michael Patrick Allen's study of wealth concentration and politicai influence purports to show that iiberai democracy is in fact increasingly marked by the presence of "a super-rich class" who "exert a pervasive influence in social and political affairs at both