Nietzsche's Preface to Philosophy

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Nietzsche's Preface to Philosophy NIETZSCHE’S PREFACE TO PHILOSOPHY YONI MOLAD SUBMITTED IN TOTAL FULFILLMENT OF THE REQUIREMENTS OF THE DEGREE OF MASTER OF PHILOSOPHY M AY 2 0 1 4 SCHOOL OF SOCIAL AND POLITICAL SCIENCES THE UNIVERSITY OF MELBOURNE Thesis Abstract Nietzsche's philosophical practice is best understood as a set of practical exercises in preparation for the transformation of modern social life. Rather than providing pedagogical dogma or verifiable theses about the world, Nietzsche's life and work serve as an example of an attempt to abolish philosophy as an autonomous practice. His writings are examples of experiments and spiritual exercises with the aim of positing new tasks for his readers who are tasked with embarking on an adventure of subjective metamorphosis. As the title of this thesis asserts, Nietzsche’s work is best understood as a preface to a new philosophy, to which, after a thorough re-evaluation of the philosophical tradition, Nietzsche only provides some basic foundational co-ordinates. The thesis elaborates this by focusing on Nietzsche’s earliest philosophical writings, which serve as orienting guidelines to interpret his more mature re-elaborations of similar ideas, and hence as a foundation upon which to begin philosophizing in a different way. In addition, the thesis discusses Nietzsche’s own Prefaces to some of his books, in which he articulates his philosophical practice most clearly in order to re-affirm the experimental and provisional nature of most of his central ideas. The thesis itself is therefore also a preface to this future philosophy, and future inquiry, insofar as it highlights the preliminary and preparatory nature of Nietzsche’s philosophical practice. In this way the thesis both seeks to articulate the framework in which Nietzsche's philosophy becomes coherent and examines the ways in which Nietzsche's texts perform the redefinition and deconstruction of philosophy he attempted to complete by provoking a similar attempt in the reader. 2 Declaration This is to certify that: i the thesis comprises only my original work towards the MA except where indicated in the Preface, ii due acknowledgment has been made in the text to all other material used, iii the thesis is less than 40 000 words in length, exclusive of tables, maps, bibliographies and appendices 3 Acknowledgments: I would like to thank the following people for their support, concern and unwavering encouragement. At times, circumstances demanded that I test their patience and hospitality to the limit and this thesis would never have been completed without their commitment, insight and belief: My family: Omer and Erica. Yudit and Ami. Ori. Gershon and Anna. Leah. Chayim and Esther. My people: Scarlett Williams and Tyla Bear. Jason, Liza, Elijah and Rueben Freddi. Belinda and Larry. Firas and Stella. Seano. Milo, Steve Marmo. Stephen , Virgine, Nina and Elliot Pascoe. Nesim and Zephyra. Dr. Jessica Whyte. Dr. Justin Clemens. Michael Ascroft. David Mintern. Jasmine Chen. Audrey Samson I would also like to thank my supervisor Assoc Prof John Rundell for his wisdom, continuous support and perseverance. 4 Table of Contents Preface: 8-16 Introduction: Life is no argument! 17-25 Chapter One: The History of Overcoming. 26-52 Chapter Two: On the Uses and Disadvantages of Philosophy for Life. 54-63 Chapter Three: The Overcoming of History: Nietzsche's Prefaces. 65-89 Conclusion. 90-97 Bibliography. 98-103 5 ABBREVIATIONS OF NIETZSCHE'S TEXTS AC. The Antichrist, 1888 BGE. Beyond Good and Evil, 1886 BT. The Birth of Tragedy, 1872 D. Daybreak, 1881 DD. Dithyrambs of Dionysus, 1888 EH. Ecce Homo, 1880 GM. On the Genealogy of Morals, 1887 GS. The Gay Science, 1882 (Part Five, 1887) HH. Human, All too Human, 1878 T&L. On Truth and Lie in an Extra-Moral Sense, 1872 TI. Twilight of the Idols, 1888 UM. Untimely Meditations, 1873–76 WP. The Will to Power, 1968 (posthumous) Z. Thus Spoke Zarathustra, 1883–85 All editions and translations by Cambridge University Press except for: WP. trans., Walter Kaufmann and R. J. Hollingdale (Vintage Books, 1967). 6 7 Nietzsche's Preface to Philosophy 8 Preface ‘Perhaps it is only in a very restricted sense that philosophy starts with a question. It might be more correct to say that it tries to arrive at a question’ – Paul Von Tonregen . Nietzsche's philosophical project was never completed due to his untimely mental collapse and subsequent early death. Yet, his philosophy is unfinished not merely because he stopped writing as a result of his breakdown but also because it is a continuous attempt to bring to consciousness an ever developing and changing struggle that language is not always equipped to articulate – the process of life itself. Instead of developing an alternative philosophical system,1 Nietzsche struggles to extricate himself from all existing philosophical systems whilst attempting to live long enough to tell the tale. His writings therefore serve only as provisional and preparatory experiments, making way for the right type of people to bring about the transformation of the modern social relations and institutions dependent on and reproducing the philosophical tradition inherited from post-Socratic culture. Far from an example of a philosophical life ‘his whole philosophy, then, would be a preface to the experiment of life itself.’2 As the title of this thesis asserts, Nietzsche’s work is best understood as a preface to a future philosophy, to which, after a thorough re-evaluation of the philosophical tradition, Nietzsche only provides some basic foundational co-ordinates. The provisionality of his philosophy stems 1 It is common in the literature to claim that Nietzsche's thought comprises a system and that he even has an 'ontology'. This is partly due to the misreading of Nietzsche by Martin Heidegger. Heidegger's lectures on Nietzsche are fascinating and justly influential, but they no longer serve as important a purpose as when first conceived. Heidegger's ontologically reductive interpretation, aimed at salvaging Nietzsche from an equally reductive biologistic appropriation by the Nazis, is guided by his insistence that the task of an interpreter is to unveil the central 'teachings' and doctrines of every philosopher. In the case of Nietzsche this kind of reading is likely to obscure the more important experimental and practical intentions of his thought. See Martin Heidegger, Nietzsche, in four volumes ed. and trans., David Farrell Krell (Harper, 1991). For a contemporary approach that attempts to read Nietzsche as a systematic metaphysician see John Richardson, Nietzsche's System (OUP, 2002). 2 This striking and accurate description is provided by Paul Von Toneregen. See ‘‘‘Ich Bin Darin […] Ego Ipsissimus […], Ego Ipsissimum’’. Nietzsches Philosophische Experimente Mit Der Literarischen Form Der Vorrede,’ Nietzsche Studien, Nov 2012, Vol. 41, Issue 1, pp1-16). 9 from Nietzsche's diagnosis that our world is still living in the shadow of dead gods. In light of this situation, anything more than a provisional approach would pretend to have overcome the cultural habits of millennia in one fell swoop and, out of haste, risk re-establishing that which it is so eager to overcome. This thesis shares this modesty in its aims and is therefore also a preface to this future philosophy, and future inquiry, insofar as it highlights the preliminary and preparatory nature of Nietzsche’s philosophical practice. The thesis does this by focusing on Nietzsche’s earliest philosophical writings, which serve as orienting guidelines to interpret his more mature re- elaborations of similar ideas, and hence as a foundation upon which to begin philosophizing in a different way. In addition, the thesis discusses Nietzsche’s own Prefaces to some of his books, in which he articulates his philosophical practice most clearly, in order to re-affirm the experimental and provisional nature of most of his central ideas. In this way the thesis both seeks to articulate the framework in which Nietzsche's philosophy becomes coherent and examines the ways in which Nietzsche's texts perform the redefinition and deconstruction of philosophy he attempted to carry out by provoking a similar attempt in the reader. Nietzsche's philosophical project is best understood as a set of practical spiritual exercises in preparation for the transformation of modern social life. Rather than providing pedagogical dogma or verifiable theses on the world, Nietzsche's life and work serve as an example of an attempt to abolish philosophy as an autonomous practice. His writings are examples of experiments and spiritual exercises with the aim of promoting new tasks for his readers. These ‘philosophers of the future’ are tasked with embarking on an adventure of subjective metamorphosis through developing a tangible philosophical practice rather than a merely reflective art. In response to the untenability of traditional philosophical questioning, Nietzsche undertakes to make his own life an experiment on the uses and disadvantages of philosophy, with the aim of transmitting this experiment to his readers. Nietzsche makes a correlation between himself and the vast array of social and cultural problems he attempts to overcome in himself through his writings. ‘My writings speak only of my overcomings: ‘I’ am in them, together with everything 10 that was inimical to me, ego ipsissimus’ (HH II, Preface, § 1).3 He offers himself as a stand-in human being upon which the problems of the age are played out. In order to overcome those problems, Nietzsche has to overcome himself insofar as he is implicated and suffers from them. As Daniel Conway correctly observes, ‘In order to complete his critique of modernity, that is, he enlists himself to stand for humanity as a whole.’4 The example given by this literary experiment is not to be mistaken as a solely literary achievement but as testimony to the experiences of Nietzsche’s own life. Nietzsche’s philosophy is to be understood as a continuous experiment, performed on his own body, utilizing only his own physiological and intellectual resources (which for him are one and the same) in which the problems of the modern age seek resolution.
Recommended publications
  • The Use of Tactical Absurdity in (Post-)Conceptual Art Practice
    University of Southampton Faculty of Arts and Humanities Winchester School of Art The Use of Tactical Absurdity in (Post-)Conceptual Art Practice by Dave Ball Thesis for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy Sep 2020 1 University of Southampton Abstract Faculty of Arts and Humanities, Winchester School of Art The Use of Tactical Absurdity in (Post-)Conceptual Art Practice by Dave Ball The ‘tactical absurdity’ forwarded in this research emerged out of my own practice. I, like many other artists working in a conceptual tradition, was producing work that appeared to operate through some sort of absurdity, and with some sort of intentionality. There was, however, almost nothing in the literature that could account for this approach. The term ‘absurdity’ is deployed by artists, critics, and curators alike with little precision or consistency; usages borrowed from literature or existential philosophy sit alongside everyday understandings, and frequently fail to discriminate between absurdity as a formal device and absurdity as a subject-matter. Its meaning is treated as self-evident. Adopting an emergent and autoethnographic practice-based methodology, this research furnishes a practical and theoretical understanding of the operation of tactical absurdity deployed as a device in (post-)conceptual art practice. Over the course of the research, five objectives are achieved: (i) to define the concept of absurdity; (ii) to establish a context for the use of tactical absurdity in contemporary (post-)conceptual art practice; (iii) to develop a body of work that operates through tactical absurdity; (iv) to account for its emergence within a practice; and (v) to forward a theoretical analysis of its functionality and value modelled through notions of relativity, generativity, and criticality.
    [Show full text]
  • (Updated: 12/01/2020) Department of Philosophy SO
    MARINA PAOLA BANCHETTI CURRICULUM VITAE (Updated: 12/01/2020) Department of Philosophy SO 283 – P.O. Box 3091 Florida Atlantic University 777 Glades Road Boca Raton, Florida 33431-0991 [email protected] ________________________________________________________________________ EDUCATION Ph.D. Philosophy (1991) University of Miami Dissertation: “Edmund Husserl: Intentionality and Meaning” Master of Arts Philosophy (1990) University of Miami Bachelor of Arts English, Philosophy (1985) Minors: History, Chemistry University of Miami MAJOR FIELDS • Phenomenology • Philosophy of Science • Philosophy of Language • Philosophy of Mind • Philosophical Orientation: Analytico-Phenomenological 2 LANGUAGES • Italian (Native/bilingual speaking, reading, and writing proficiency) • French (Native/bilingual speaking, reading, and writing proficiency) • Spanish (Native/bilingual speaking, reading, and writing proficiency) • Portuguese (Full reading proficiency) PROFESSIONAL EXPERIENCE 2001- Associate Professor Present Department of Philosophy Florida Atlantic University 1995- Assistant Professor 2001 Department of Philosophy Florida Atlantic University 1993- Visiting Assistant Professor 1995 Department of Philosophy Florida Atlantic University Summer Adjunct Professor of Humanities 1993 Miami-Dade Community College 1992- Adjunct Professor of Philosophy 1993 Florida A&M University 1990- Instructor, Dept. of Philosophy 1991 University of Miami 1986- Teaching Assistant, Dept. of Philosophy 1989 University of Miami ADMINISTRATIVE EXPERIENCE 2017- Chair 2019 Department
    [Show full text]
  • The Reader and the Poet
    THE READER AND THE POET THE TRANSFORMATION OF LATIN POETRY IN THE FOURTH CENTURY A Dissertation Presented to the Faculty of the Graduate School of Cornell University in Partial Fulfillment of the Requirements for the Degree of Doctor of Philosophy by Aaron David Pelttari August 2012 i © 2012 Aaron David Pelttari ii The Reader and the Poet: The Transformation of Latin Poetry in the Fourth Century Aaron Pelttari, Ph.D. Cornell University 2012 In Late Antiquity, the figure of the reader came to play a central role in mediating the presence of the text. And, within the tradition of Latin poetry, the fourth century marks a turn towards writing that privileges the reader’s involvement in shaping the meaning of the text. Therefore, this dissertation addresses a set of problems related to the aesthetics of Late Antiquity, the reception of Classical Roman poetry, and the relation between author and reader. I begin with a chapter on contemporary methods of reading, in order to show the ways in which Late Antique authors draw attention to their own interpretations of authoritative texts and to their own creation of supplemental meaning. I show how such disparate authors as Jerome, Augustine, Servius, and Macrobius each privileges the work of secondary authorship. The second chapter considers the use of prefaces in Late Antique poetry. The imposition of paratextual borders dramatized the reader’s involvement in the text. In the third chapter, I apply Umberto Eco’s idea of the open text to the figural poetry of Optatianus Porphyrius, to the Psychomachia of Prudentius, and to the centos from Late Antiquity.
    [Show full text]
  • The Theater of the Absurd in Europe and America: Sartre, Beckett, Pinter, Albee and Drama Criticism Sheila O'brien Mcguckin University of New Hampshire, Durham
    University of New Hampshire University of New Hampshire Scholars' Repository Doctoral Dissertations Student Scholarship Spring 1996 The Theater of the Absurd in Europe and America: Sartre, Beckett, Pinter, Albee and drama criticism Sheila O'Brien McGuckin University of New Hampshire, Durham Follow this and additional works at: https://scholars.unh.edu/dissertation Recommended Citation McGuckin, Sheila O'Brien, "The Theater of the Absurd in Europe and America: Sartre, Beckett, Pinter, Albee and drama criticism" (1996). Doctoral Dissertations. 1895. https://scholars.unh.edu/dissertation/1895 This Dissertation is brought to you for free and open access by the Student Scholarship at University of New Hampshire Scholars' Repository. It has been accepted for inclusion in Doctoral Dissertations by an authorized administrator of University of New Hampshire Scholars' Repository. For more information, please contact [email protected]. INFORMATION TO USERS This manuscript has been reproduced from the microfilm master. UMI films the text directly from the original or copy submitted. Thus, some thesis and dissertation copies are in typewriter face, while others may be from any type of computer printer. The quality of this reproduction is dependent upon the quality of the copy submitted. Broken or indistinct print, colored or poor quality illustrations and photographs, print bleedthrough, substandard margins, and improper alignment can adversely affect reproduction. In the unlikely event that the author did not send UMI a complete manuscript and there are missing pages, these will be noted. Also, if unauthorized copyright material had to be removed, a note will indicate the deletion. Oversize materials (e.g., maps, drawings, charts) are reproduced by sectioning the original, beginning at the upper left-hand comer and continuing from left to right in equal sections with small overlaps.
    [Show full text]
  • Kierkegaard, Literature, and the Arts
    Kierke gaard, Literature, and the Arts Engraving, ca. 1837, by Carl Strahlheim showing the Gendarmenmarkt in Berlin, with what was then the Schauspielhaus, or Theater (center)— now the concert house of the Konzerthausorchester Berlin— flanked by the German Cathedral (left) and the French Cathedral (right). Pictured in the background to the immediate right of the theater is the building, still standing today, in which Kierkegaard lodged during his four stays in Berlin, in 1841– 42, 1843, 1845, and 1846. It was there, as noted by a plaque outside, that Kierkegaard wrote the first drafts of Either/Or, Repetition, and Fear and Trembling. Kierkegaard, Literature, and the Arts Edited by Eric Ziolkowski northwestern university press evanston, illinois Northwestern University Press www.nupress.northwestern.edu Copyright © 2018 by Northwestern University Press. Published 2018. All rights reserved. Printed in the United States of America 10 9 8 7 6 5 4 3 2 1 Library of Congress Cataloging- in- Publication Data Names: Ziolkowski, Eric Jozef, 1958– editor. Title: Kierkegaard, literature, and the arts / edited by Eric Ziolkowski. Description: Evanston, Illinois : Northwestern University Press, 2018. | Includes index. Identifiers: LCCN 2017029795 | ISBN 9780810135970 (cloth : alk. paper) | ISBN 9780810135963 (pbk. : alk. paper) | ISBN 9780810135987 (e-book) Subjects: LCSH: Kierkegaard, Søren, 1813–1855. | Kierkegaard, Søren, 1813– 1855—Aesthetics. | Literature—Philosophy. | Music and philosophy. | Art and philosophy. | Performing arts—Philosophy. Classification: LCC B4377 .K4558 2018 | DDC 198.9—dc23 LC record available at https://lccn.loc.gov/2017029795 Except where otherwise noted, this book is licensed under a Creative Commons Attribution-NonCommercial-NoDerivatives 4.0 International License. To view a copy of this license, visit http://creativecommons.org/licenses/by-nc-nd/4.0/.
    [Show full text]
  • Purity of Heart Is to Will One Thing by Sören Kierkegaard
    Purity of Heart Is to Will One Thing by Sören Kierkegaard This book was first published by Harper in 1938. It was translated from the Danish and contains an introductory essay by Douglas V. Steere. Prepared for Religion Online by Ted and Willie Brock. Translator’s Introduction by Douglas V. Steere A helpful summary of Kierketaard's basic positions, written by an outstanding scholar of his work. Douglass Steere was Professor of philosophy at Haverford College. Preface A woman doing needlework on an altar cloth does not want the work admired or criticized, but rather that the intent of the work is that it be seen for its higher purpose. Kierkegaard desires his writing receive the same attention. Chapter 1: Introduction: Man and the Eternal In relation to the eternal, a man ages neither in the sense of time nor in the sense of an accumulation of past events. There is something eternal in a man, and the eternal must be able to exist and to be grasped within every change. Chapter 2: Remorse, Repentance, Confession: Eternity’s Emissaries to Man Remorse is a guide that calls out to the wanderer that he should take care. In confession one becomes at one with himself. Chapter 3: Barriers to Willing One Thing: Variety and Great Moments Are Not One Thing To will one thing can only mean to will the good, because every other object is not a unity. The will that only wills that another object, therefore, must become double-minded. Chapter 4: Barriers to Willing One Thing: The Reward-Disease If a man can will one thing, then he must will the Good, for the Good alone is one.
    [Show full text]
  • Konturen VII (2015) 1 Introduction: Kierkegaard and German
    Konturen VII (2015) 1 Introduction: Kierkegaard and German Thought Michael Stern University of Oregon Moods, Voicing, and Anticipation Et Forord er Stemningen. At skrive et Forord er ligesom at hvæsse Leen, ligesom at stemme Guitaren, ligesom at snake med et Barn, ligesom at spytte af Vinduet. (Kierkegaard, SKS 4, 469) A preface is a mood. Writing a preface is like sharpening a scythe, like tuning a guitar, like talking with a child, like spitting out of the window.1 (Kierkegaard, Prefaces 5) If it would please you, dear reader, recall the vocabulary of the Kierkegaardian preface. Remember its lexicon, its love of secrets and self-effacements. Give heed to its masks, its pseudonymous authors who write pamphlets at their leisure, its editors who find manuscripts in secret compartments, its thieves in the night who copy diaries in anxious haste. Conjure up its sly seductions, its misdirections, its Chinese boxes, and its celebration of the chance occurrence. Bring to mind the aesthetics of a beginning that is never an origination for it is not possible for a thinker such as Kierkegaard to forward first principles or doctrines. Kierkegaard seemed to relish the activity of composing introductions so much that he once wrote a book consisting of nothing but prefaces, introductions introducing nothing at all. He published Forord (Prefaces) in 1844, on the same day as Begrebet Angest (The Concept of Anxiety)⎯the first book conveying empty promises and the second possibilities without discernable objects. In the very first of Forord’s (Prefaces) series of prefatory pieces, Kierkegaard’s pseudonym, Nicolaus Notabene explains that his young wife’s jealousy inspired the structure of the text.
    [Show full text]
  • ABSTRACT the Legitimacy of the Comic: Kierkegaard and The
    ABSTRACT The Legitimacy of the Comic: Kierkegaard and the Importance of the Comic for His Ethics and Theology Will Williams, Ph.D. Mentor: Paul Martens, Ph.D. While some consider the comic to be a trivial subject, fit mainly for amusement or distraction, Søren Kierkegaard disagrees. This dissertation examines Kierkegaard’s understanding of the nature of the comic and how he believes even the triviality of comic jest to be deeply tied to ethical and theological earnestness. First, I examine Kierkegaard’s understanding of the comic, irony, and humor, drawing primarily from Concluding Unscientific Postscript (1846). I argue that, for Kierkegaard, the comic is a contradiction or misrelation that is essentially though not absolutely painless, providing a “way out.” The comic is a contradiction between norms, suggesting that it springs from one’s perspective in a way that holds important implications for one’s ethical and theological worldview. Kierkegaard believes that subjective development is closely tied to one’s capacity to perceive the comic, making the comic both diagnostic of and formative for one’s subjective state. For him, the Christian is far from humorless, instead having the maximum human capacity to perceive the comic. Next, I show that the previously argued conception of the comic can be found in other works by Kierkegaard: Prefaces (1844), Upbuilding Discourses in Various Spirits (1847), and the Corsair affair (c.1845-1848). Then, I examine representatives of the Deconstructionist tradition of reading Kierkegaard, namely Louis Mackey, Roger Poole, Elsebet Jegstrup, and Mark C. Taylor. I argue that, while they accurately perceive the widespread irony in Kierkegaard’s corpus, they incorrectly conclude that such irony is a sign of his lack of earnest interest in philosophy and theology.
    [Show full text]
  • Chronology of Kierkegaard's Writings
    CHRONOLOGY OF KIERKEGAARD'S WRITINGS Because of the thematic nature of this essay, it might be helpful for the reader to note the chronology of Kierkegaard's writ­ ings at the outset of the investigation.1 I have listed biblio­ graphical information for the English texts used throughout the study, and have specified the way in which these works are indicated in the footnotes of the essay. Sept. 7, 1837 From the Papers of One Still Living (not translated) Sept. 16, 1841 The Concept of Irony, with Constant Refer­ ence to Socrates, trans. by Lee N. Capel, Bloomington: Indiana University Press, 1968. (The Concept of Irony) Feb.2o, 1843 Either-Or, vol. I trans. by David F. and Lil­ lian M. Swenson, vol. n trans. by W alter Lowrie, Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1971. (Either-Or, 1; Either-Or, n) May 16,1843 Two Edifying Discourses2 Oct. 16, 1843 Repetition, trans. by W alter Lowrie, New York: Harper T orchbooks, 1964. (Repeti- tion) Fear and Trembling, trans. by Waiter Lowrie, Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1970. (Fear and Trembling) 1 Howard and Edna Hong's table at the beginning of the first vol­ ume of their S;>ren Kierkegaard's fournals and Papers (Bloomington: Indiana University Press, 1967) has been helpful in arranging this list. 2 Kierkegaard's Edifying Discourses are collected in a four-volume series: Edifying Discourses, trans. by David F. and Lillian M. Swenson (Minneapolis: Augsburg Publishing House, 1943ff.). xi CHRONOLOGY Oct. r6, r843 Three Edifying Discourses Dec. 6, r843 Four Edifying Discourses March 5, 1844 Two Edifying Discourses June 8, r844 Three Edifying Discourses June 13, r844 Philosophical Fragments, trans.
    [Show full text]
  • The Actual Author of This Dissertation
    Henrik Jøker Bjerre The Actual Author of This Dissertation Groucho Marx once told an audience that before he would begin to speak, he had something important to say. On the face of it, this decla- ration describes rather precisely what it means to write a preface: You state some introductory or clarifying remarks before moving on to the actual subject at hand. Groucho’s expression has a certain comical efect, however, because it also postulates a rather paradoxical ability: being able to “say” something before, and thus without, “speaking”, as if there is a saying that is somehow qualitatively diferent from speak- ing. But how can you say anything without speaking? By miming it? And what does it mean for that which follows? Is speaking somehow less than saying something, or, on the contrary, the only case where anything really gets across at all? A preface contains a similarly asymmetric relation to the text it intro- duces. It states something that is not really part of the text itself, but has to be stated before the actual writing begins. Sometimes, a pref- ace can solemnly summarize a work’s world-historical signifcance, like when Wittgenstein in the preface of the Tractatus claimed to have “solved the problems of philosophy and shown how little was thereby 131 accomplished”1. At other times, it is the preface which is profane or immaterial, giving only dull information about the bureaucratic con- ditions of the appearance of the text. In any case, the expression “before I speak, I have something import- ant to say” shows something about an urgency of getting the opening right, of approaching the text in the right manner.
    [Show full text]
  • Theatrical Doubling and Rosencrantz and Guildenstern Are Dead
    W&M ScholarWorks Undergraduate Honors Theses Theses, Dissertations, & Master Projects 5-2011 The "Opposite of People": Theatrical Doubling and Rosencrantz and Guildenstern are Dead Megan Behm College of William and Mary Follow this and additional works at: https://scholarworks.wm.edu/honorstheses Part of the Theatre and Performance Studies Commons Recommended Citation Behm, Megan, "The "Opposite of People": Theatrical Doubling and Rosencrantz and Guildenstern are Dead" (2011). Undergraduate Honors Theses. Paper 360. https://scholarworks.wm.edu/honorstheses/360 This Honors Thesis is brought to you for free and open access by the Theses, Dissertations, & Master Projects at W&M ScholarWorks. It has been accepted for inclusion in Undergraduate Honors Theses by an authorized administrator of W&M ScholarWorks. For more information, please contact [email protected]. The “Opposite of People”: Theatrical Doubling and Rosencrantz and Guildenstern are Dead A thesis submitted in partial fulfillment of the requirement for the degree of Bachelors of Arts in Theatre from The College of William and Mary by Megan Behm Accepted for (Honors, High Honors, Highest Honors) Laurie Wolf, Director Elizabeth Wiley Dr. Richard Palmer Brett D. Wilson Williamsburg, VA April 15, 2011 Behm Page 2 Abstract Tom Stoppard is a modern playwright who is concerned with absurdism, metatheatricality, and language as tools to explore the nature and definitions of reality. Rosencrantz and Guildenstern are Dead, Stoppard‘s first major work, focuses on all of these themes—and is specifically one of Stoppard‘s most theatrical plays. Doubling is a longstanding theatrical tradition in which one actor portrays multiple characters within a dramatic work.
    [Show full text]
  • A Very Short Life of Kierkegaard by Charles K. Bellinger Søren Kierkegaard Was Born in 1813, in Copenhagen, Denmark, As the Seventh Child of a Wealthy Businessman
    A Very Short Life of Kierkegaard by Charles K. Bellinger Søren Kierkegaard was born in 1813, in Copenhagen, Denmark, as the seventh child of a wealthy businessman. His father was a self-educated man who had a brooding, deeply religious spirit. The father's pietism and philosophical interests had a great impact on his last son, Søren, who went on to become one of the most important figures in modern Christian thought. Kierkegaard was a bright student and he received a high quality private school education. By the time he was 17, he could read Hebrew, Greek, Latin, German, and French, as well as his native Danish. He entered the University, where his father hoped that he would study to become a pastor. Kierkegaard was more interested in studying literature and philosophy, however, and he adopted the carefree, expensive lifestyle of a prodigal son. He wrestled deeply with religious ideas, however, and at the age of 25 he had a profound conversion experience. He was reconciled with his father shortly before the latter's death, and he dedicated himself to the cause of Christian faith for the rest of his life. The Kierkegaard family was deeply touched by tragedy. By the time Søren was 25, 5 of his 6 siblings had died, as well as his mother and father. Søren himself did not expect to live past the age of thirty. (As it was, he died at the age of 42 in 1855.) He went on to complete the prerequisites for ordination in the Lutheran church, but he never did become ordained.
    [Show full text]